The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind [online version ed.] 0199262616, 9780199262618

The study of the mind has always been one of the main preoccupations of philosophers, and has been a booming area of res

2,733 376 4MB

English Pages 815 [943] Year 2009

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Polecaj historie

The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind [online version ed.]
 0199262616, 9780199262618

  • Commentary
  • pdf from online version
Citation preview

[UNTITLED]

[UNTITLED]   The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy Online Publication Date: Sep 2009

(p. iv)

Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © the several contributors 2009 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2009 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,

Page 1 of 2

[UNTITLED] Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind / edited by Brain McLaughlin with Ansgar Beckermann and Sven Walter. p. cm.—(Oxford handbooks in philosophy) Includes index. ISBN 978–0–19–926261–8 1. Philosophy of mind. I. McLaughlin, Brain P. II. Beckermann, Ansgar, 1945–III. Walter, Sven. BD418.3.094 2008 128′.2—dc22 2008039119 ISBN 978–0–19–926261–8 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2

Page 2 of 2

Dedication

Dedication   The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy Online Publication Date: Sep 2009

Dedication (p. v)

For Bryant, Daniel, Kathryn, Will, Grace, and Megan

Page 1 of 1

Acknowledgements

Acknowledgements   The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy Online Publication Date: Sep 2009

(p. vi)

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Peter Momtchiloff for being an ideal editor—a wise counsel, ever patient, and ever encouraging. We would also like to thank Lena Kästner for her help in preparing the final version of the manuscript and Iris Oved and Nicole Troxler for prepar­ ing the index.

Page 1 of 1

List of Contributors

List of Contributors   The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy Online Publication Date: Sep 2009

(p. xi)

List of Contributors

Louise Antony: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 352 Bartlett Hall, Amherst, MA 01003–9269. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Anita Avramides: Fellow and Tutor, St. Hilda's College, University of Oxford, Cow­ ley Place, Oxford, OX4 1DY. United Kingdom.

Email: anita.avramides@st‐hildas.ox.ac.uk

Kent Bach: Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Department of Philosophy, San Fran­ cisco State University, 1600 Holloway Avenue, San Francisco, CA 94132. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Lynne Rudder Baker: Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philoso­ phy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 352 Bartlett Hall, Amherst, MA 01003– 9269. USA.

Page 1 of 10

List of Contributors Email: [email protected]

Katalin Balog: Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Yale University, 406B CT Hall, New Haven, CT 06520–8306. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Ansgar Beckermann: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Bielefeld, Postfach 100 131, 33501 Bielefeld. GERMANY.

Email: ansgar.beckermann@uni‐bielefeld.de

José Luis Bermúdez: Professor of Philosophy and Director, Program in Philosophy, Neuroscience and Psychology, Washington University in St Louis, Department of Phi­ losophy, Wilson Hall,Campus Box 1073, St. Louis, MO 63130–4899. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Andrew Brook: Chancellor's Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Institute of Cognitive Science, Department of Philosophy, Carleton University, 3A46 Paterson Hall, 1125 Colonel By Drive, Ottawa, Ontario, K1S 5B6. CANADA.

Email: [email protected]

Jessica Brown: Professor in Arché Philosophical Research Center for Logic, Lan­ guage, Metaphysics and Epistemology, Philosophy Departments, The University of St Andrews, Edgecliffe, The Scores, St Andrews, KY16 9AL. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: jab30@st‐andrews.ac.uk

Page 2 of 10

List of Contributors

Alex Byrne: Professor of Philosophy, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Depart­ ment of Linguistics and Philosophy, 77 Massachusetts Avenue, 32‐d808, Cambridge, MA 02139–4307. USA.

Email: [email protected]

John Campbell: Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of California at Berkeley, 314 Moses Hall #2390, Berkeley, CA 94720–2390. USA.

Email: [email protected]

David J. Chalmers: Professor of Philosophy Professor of and ARC Federation Fellow, Director of the Centre for Consciousness, Research School of Social Sciences, Aus­ tralian National University, Canberra ACT 0200. AUSTRALIA.

Email: [email protected]

Tim Crane: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University College London, Gower Street, London, WC1E 6BT. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Daniel Dennett: Co‐director of the Center for Cognitive Studies, Austin B. Fletcher Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Tufts University, Medford, MA 02155–7059. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Page 3 of 10

List of Contributors

Fred Dretske: Professor Emeritus, Stanford University. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Frances Egan: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey, 26 Nichol Avenue, New Brunswick, NJ 08901–2882. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Tamar Szabó Gendler: Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Department of Philosophy, Yale University, Connecticut Hall, New Haven, CT 06520–8306. USA.

Email: [email protected]

George Graham: A.C. Reid Professor of Philosophy, Wake Forest University, Depart­ ment of Philosophy, 1834 Wake Forest Road, Winston‐Salem, NC 27106. USA.

Email: [email protected]

John Heil: Professor of Philosophy, School of Philosophy and Bioethics, Building 11, Monash University VIC 3800. AUSTRALIA. And: Professor of Philosophy, Washington University in St Louis, Department of Philosophy, Wilson Hall, One Brookings Dr., Campus Box 1073, St. Louis, MO 63130–4899. USA.

Email: [email protected]; [email protected]

Page 4 of 10

List of Contributors Terence Horgan: Professor of Philosophy, University of Arizona, Department of Phi­ losophy, Tucson, AZ 85721–0027. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Jaegwon Kim: William Herbert Perry Faunce Professor, Department of Philosophy, Brown University, Box 1918, Providence, RI 02912. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Krista Lawlor: Associate Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Stan­ ford University, Stanford, CA 94305–2155. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Joseph Levine: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, 352 Bartlett Hall, Amherst, MA 01003–9269. USA.

Email: [email protected]

E. J. Lowe: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Durham University, 50 Old Elvet, DH1 3HN. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Cynthia Macdonald: Professor of Philosophy, School of Politics, International Stud­ ies and Philosophy, Queens University Belfast, 21 University Square, Belfast, BT7 1PA, Northern Ireland, United Kingdom

Page 5 of 10

List of Contributors

Email: [email protected]

Colin McGinn: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Mia­ mi, PO BOX 248054, Coral Gables, FL 33124–4670. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Robert J. Matthews: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey, 26 Nichol Avenue, New Brunswick, NJ 08901– 2882. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Brian P. McLaughlin: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey, 26 Nichol Avenue, New Brunswick, NJ 08901– 2882. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Alfred R. Mele: William H. and Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy, De­ partment of Philosophy, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL 32306–1500. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Ruth Garrett Millikan : Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Univer­ sity of Connecticut, Storrs, CT 06269–2054. USA.

Page 6 of 10

List of Contributors Email: [email protected]

Michelle Montague: Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, Oxford University, St John's College, Oxford OX1 3JP. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Barbara Montero: Associate Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy Program, The Graduate Center, City University of New York, 365 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10016–4309. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Adam Morton: Professor of Philosophy and Canada Research Chair in Epistemology and Decision Theory, Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta, 4–115 Humani­ ties Centre Edmonton, Alberta T6G 2E5. CANADA.

Email: [email protected]

David Papineau: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, King's College, London, Strand, London, WC2R 2LS. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Christopher Peacocke: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Colum­ bia University, 1150 Amsterdam Avenue, 708 Philosophy Hall, MC 4971, New York, NY10027. USA. And: Richard Wollheim Chair of Philosophy, Department of Philoso­ phy, University College, Gower Street, London WC1E 6BT. UNITED KINGDOM.

Page 7 of 10

List of Contributors Email: [email protected]

John Perry: Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside and Henry Waldgrave Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305–2155. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Jesse Prinz: John J. Rogers Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, CB # 3125, Caldwell Hall, Chapel Hill, NC 27599–3125. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Paul Raymont: Assistant Professor, Ryerson University, 350 Victoria Street, Toronto, Ontario M5B 2K3. CANADA.

Email: [email protected]

Howard Robinson: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Central Euro­ pean University, H 1051 Budapest, Nádor u.9. HUNGARY. And: Honarary Visiting Professor in Philosophy, University of York. UK.

Email: [email protected]

David M. Rosenthal: Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator of Cognitive Science, City University of New York, Graduate Center, 365 Fifth Avenue, Room 7–111, New York, NY 10016–4309. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Page 8 of 10

List of Contributors

William Seager: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Humanities (University of Toronto Scarborough) and Department of Philosophy (University of Toronto), 170 St. George Street, Toronto Ontario, M5R 2M8.

Email: [email protected]

Gabriel Segal: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London, WC2R 2LS. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Galen Strawson: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, The University of Reading, Reading RG6 6AA. UNITED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

John Tienson: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis, 327 Clement Hall, Memphis Tennessee 38152. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Michael Tye: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, The University of Texas at Austin, Austin, TX 78712. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Page 9 of 10

List of Contributors Robert Van Gulick: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Syracuse University, Syracuse, NY 13244–1170. USA.

Email: [email protected]

Sven Walter: Assistant Professor, Institute of Cognitive Science, University of Os­ nabrueck, Albrechtstraße 28, 49076 Osnabrueck. GERMANY.

Email: s.walter@philosophy‐online.de

Ralph Wedgwood: Professor of Philosophy, Merton College, Oxford OX1 4JD. UNIT­ ED KINGDOM.

Email: [email protected]

Julie Yoo: Visiting Assistant Professor, Department of Cognitive Science, Occidental College, Los Angeles, CA.

Email: [email protected]

(p. xvi)

Page 10 of 10

Introduction

Introduction   Brian P. McLaughlin The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0001

Abstract and Keywords The philosophy of mind is a core area of philosophy. It has roots tracing back to ancient Greece, where the idea that the soul is distinct from the body originated. Philosophy of mind flourished during much of the period from the publication in the seventeenth centu­ ry of René Descartes's magnificent works on the mind to the first quarter of the twentieth century, which closed with the publication of C. D. Broad's The Mind and Its Place in Na­ ture. With the rise of behaviourism in the second quarter of that century, however, philo­ sophical interest in the mind waned. Still, some mid-twentieth-century work stands out. With the fall of behaviourism in the late 1950s and early 1960s and the rise of cognitive science, interest in the mind and in its place in nature was renewed — and with enormous vigour. Since then research in the philosophy of mind has been booming. Keywords: philosophy of mind, body and soul, behaviourism, cognitive science, René Descartes, ancient Greece

THE philosophy of mind is a core area of philosophy. It has roots tracing back to ancient Greece, where the idea that the soul is distinct from the body originated. Philosophy of mind flourished during much of the period from the publication in the seventeenth centu­ ry of René Descartes's magnificent works on the mind to the first quarter of the twentieth century, which closed with the publication of C. D. Broad's The Mind and Its Place in Na­ ture (1925). With the rise of behaviourism in the second quarter of that century, however, philosophical interest in the mind waned. Still, some mid‐twentieth‐century work stands out; we think here especially of Gilbert Ryle's The Concept of Mind (1949), Herbert Feigl's ‘The “Mental” and the “Physical” ’ (1958), J. J. C. Smart's ‘Sensations and Brain Process­ es’ (1959), and the literature on Ludwig Wittgenstein's private‐language argument that appeared during this time period. With the fall of behaviourism in the late 1950s and ear­ ly 1960s and the rise of cognitive science, interest in the mind and in its place in nature was renewed—and with enormous vigour. Since then research in the philosophy of mind has been booming. It is our hope that this volume will serve not only as a sourcebook on philosophy of mind and a passageway into the vast contemporary literature, but also as a stimulus to research in the twenty‐first century.

Page 1 of 25

Introduction The abundance of philosophical riches in contemporary philosophy of mind presented the editors with a dilemma. On the one hand, the volume had to deserve its august title The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. On the other hand, the size of the volume had to be such that a normal human being could hold it in his or her hands. We thus had to de­ cide which of the very many candidate topics for inclusion in the volume to in fact in­ clude. The selection process began at a lunch several years ago at which Peter Momtchiloff approached Brian McLaughlin about editing the volume. At the lunch, the decision was made that a division of labour was called for. Philosophical issues concern­ ing the science of psychology (issues such as whether there are psychological laws, and the relationship of psychology to neuroscience) and issues in cognitive psychology (such as innateness, the bearing of evolution on psychological phenomena, the nature of our cognitive architecture, and the computational modelling of mental capacities) would be set aside for separate volumes, and the present volume would focus mainly on the core metaphysical and epistemological issues in the philosophy of mind—issues that make up the (p. 2) heart of the philosophy of mind. The Oxford Handbook of Evolutionary Psycholo­ gy appeared in 2007 (Dunbar and Barrett 2007). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Psychology (Prinz, forthcoming) and The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Sciences (Stich, Samuels, and Margolis, forthcoming) are now under construction. These volumes and the present one are companions that complement one another. Even within the focus of the present volume we have relied on a division of labour. The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (Kane 2002) rendered it unnecessary to include an essay on free will; The Oxford Handbook on Wittgenstein (McGinn, forthcoming), rendered it un­ necessary to include an essay on the private‐language argument; The Oxford Handbook of Rationality (Mele and Rawlings 2004) rendered it unnecessary to include an essay on ra­ tionality; The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (Kopp 2007) rendered it unnecessary to include an essay on moral psychology; and certain topics relevant to intentionality (e.g. rule following and interpretation) are covered in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (Lepore and Smith 2006). Still, even with all of this help, difficult editorial choices remained. Contributions to our understanding of the mind trace back to the work of Plato and Aristotle, and forward from them to the work of such giants as Augustine, Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Hobbes, Malebranche, Hume, Locke, Reid, and Kant. A number of the essays in the vol­ ume include historical discussion. But the volume contains no essays exclusively devoted to historical figures or to historical periods. Sweeping survey chapters treating the philos­ ophy of mind during various periods of history would have been out of line with the level of depth of the other chapters in the volume and, moreover, can be found elsewhere in the literature; and there was no space for a proper treatment of historical figures. Rele­ vant historical topics will be covered in future Oxford handbooks; for example, The Ox­ ford Handbook of Plato (Fine, forthcoming) will contain an essay entitled ‘Plato on the Soul’.

Page 2 of 25

Introduction Had modern humans evolved with the physical prowess of Neanderthals, Oxford would have allowed us to include more material. We are certain of that. As it is, Oxford allowed us a volume that a normal human being can hold in two hands, not constraining the heft of the volume to what can be held in a single hand alone. We are thus deeply grateful to the press for the enormously generous way in which it resolved our initial dilemma. We have a volume covering a cornucopia of core issues in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume addresses the cluster of issues that fall under the heading ‘the mind–body problem’, and much more. If your interest lies in the place of mind in nature, the nature of consciousness, the nature of intentionality, the relationship between consciousness and intentionality, subjectivity, mental causation, mental content, propositional attitudes, whether thought requires language, our epistemic access to our own and other minds, folk psychology, personal identity, the unity of consciousness, or the nature of the self, then you have come to the right Oxford handbook. Dualism, idealism, physicalism, func­ tionalism, and panpsychism are examined. So are the leading psychosemantic theories— the leading naturalistic theories of how the contents of mental states are determined. There are, moreover, essays focusing on mental abilities such as the ability to think, to re­ member, to imagine, to feel emotions, to focus our attention (p. 3) on perceived objects and properties, and to engage in intentional action. The topics covered comprise the heart of contemporary philosophy of mind. All of the essays in the volume are previously unpublished. The contributors were chosen both because of their expertise in the subject of their essay and because of the passion they bring to the subject. They include many of the leading figures in the philosophy of mind, as well as a number of rising stars. We are honoured to edit a volume with such dis­ tinguished contributors. The essays are long and substantive, engaging issues in depth. They aim not only to chart the terrain as concerns a philosophical issue, but also often to argue for particular posi­ tions. We encouraged the authors to indicate where they think the truth lies. In some cas­ es authors were asked to present and defend philosophical positions that originated with them. The authors, one and all, do philosophy, rather than simply reporting what contem­ porary philosophical work has been done on a particular topic. (There are currently many excellent encyclopedia and philosophical‐dictionary entries that provide such reports; in­ deed a wealth of such material is available for free on the web.) The essays are one and all contributions to the philosophy of mind. As editors are wont to do, we have sorted the essays into sections based on interrelated themes. But even given our broad section titles, it seemed in some cases an arbitrary de­ cision to place an essay in one section rather than in another. We hope, in any case, that the sections provide a useful guide to exploring the volume. We should note that the or­ der of essays in each section was decided entirely independently of considerations con­ cerning either the relative centrality of the topic covered to the philosophy of mind or any assessment of the closeness of the content of the essay to the truth. Order was decided solely by pedagogical considerations. But the essays can be profitably read in any order. Each essay stands entirely on its own. A reader can begin anywhere. And a reader can Page 3 of 25

Introduction skip around from one section to another following only the direction of his or her inter­ ests. To supplement the Table of Contents, we provide below a glimpse of the material in each of the essays. These strictly matter‐of‐fact summaries are self‐contained, and so they too can be read independently. Given that they are self‐contained, if one reads them in one sitting one will encounter some redundancy. But it is also the case that if one reads them in one sitting the relationships between various essays will become apparent. Virtually all of the essays note that one or another issue in the philosophy of mind re­ mains unresolved. Indeed, fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind remain unre­ solved. The heart of the philosophy of mind continues to beat to the drum of dialectical debate. This volume is testament to that. Positions defended in one essay are sometimes attacked in another; a presupposition of one essay is sometimes challenged in another; a problem presented as insuperable in one essay is sometimes claimed in another to be re­ solvable; in some cases there is an important question whether a position taken in one es­ say is in conflict with a position taken in another. We won't highlight these matters; high­ lighting is unnecessary, since they will leap from the page even in the brief matter‐of‐fact summaries below. Nor will we try to adjudicate any of the disputes or to indicate where we believe the truth lies. We (p. 4) refrain from doing so not only because it would be in­ appropriate in an introduction such as this one, but also because on a number of issues there is no consensus even among the editors. We leave the adjudication of these philo­ sophical disputes to the reader. One learns philosophy by doing philosophy. Engaging with the essays in this volume will take one to the cutting edge of debates that animate the heart of contemporary philosophy of mind.

I The Place of Mind in Nature 1. Jaegwon Kim's ‘Mental Causation’. As Kim points out, the problem of mental causation—the problem of how mental states and events can have causal effects—is essentially coeval with the mind–body problem. Descartes famously argued that mental substances are distinct from physical substances in that mental substances are not located in space. Given this substance dualism, the question arises as to how the mental and the physical are related. Descartes's answer was that they are causally related; specifically that minds and brains causally interact. Certain states of and changes in the brain cause states of and changes in a non‐spatial mental substance; and states of and changes in the mental substance cause certain states of and changes in the brain. In response, Princess Elisabeth wrote to Descartes: ‘I admit that it would be easier for me to concede matter and extension to the mind than it would be for me to concede the capacity to move a body and be moved by one to an immaterial thing’ (Garber 2001: 172). As Kim notes, this may well be the first statement of a causal case for physicalism. The debate over whether dualism can capture mental causation had begun.

Page 4 of 25

Introduction Kim argues that Cartesian substance‐dualist accounts of mental causation succumb to ‘a pairing problem’—the problem of linking mental events with their alleged causes and ef­ fects. He argues that the problem can be resolved only if causes and effects are located in a space–time framework, and hence that the problem of mental causation is insuperable for Cartesian substance dualism. Kim goes on to present a number ways in which the problem of mental causation arises even for various contemporary theories of mind that reject Cartesian substance dualism but that nevertheless maintain the property‐dualist view that mental properties are not identical with physical properties. He notes that Don­ ald Davidson's doctrine of anomalous monism faces the problem of how mental events can have causal effects in virtue of being instances of mental properties, given that causa­ tion, on Davidson's view, is subsumption under a strict physical law. In addition, Kim ar­ gues that the functionalist thesis that mental properties are functional properties that are realized by, though not identical to, physical properties cannot vindicate the view that in­ stances of mental properties have causal effects. Moreover, he discusses his own superve­ nience (or exclusion) argument for the claim that mental events are either reducible to physical events or else epiphenomena (devoid of causal effects). (p. 5) He defends his ar­ gument against a variety of objections that have been raised to it in the literature, includ­ ing the objections that the argument relies on assumptions that have the absurd conse­ quence that special‐science causation is impossible, that it relies on an untenable produc­ tive/generative conception of causation, and that it fails to rule out the possibility that mental causation involves a tenable form of overdetermination.

2. David Papineau's ‘The Causal Closure of the Physical and Natural­ ism’. Papineau presents the considerations in favour of the principle of the causal closure of the physical—roughly, the principle that every caused physical event has a sufficient physical cause—from a historical perspective, examines ways in which the thesis can be made more precise, and explores the connections between the principle and the issue of whether two varieties of naturalism are true. He points out that the causal‐closure princi­ ple is invoked in the causal argument for physicalism, the argument that anything with physical effects must in some sense be physical: it must either be identical with some­ thing physical or at least be metaphysically necessitated by something physical. Pap­ ineau, moreover, discusses the role of the principle of the causal closure of the physical in the defence of the philosophical doctrine of methodological naturalism—the doctrine that ‘philosophy uses the same methods of investigation as the natural sciences’—and in de­ fence of the doctrine of ontological naturalism, ‘which says that the subject matter of phi­ losophy coincides with that of the natural sciences’.

3. E. J. Lowe's ‘Dualism’. As Lowe points out, mental–physical dualism comes in two varieties: substance dualism and property dualism. He discusses both. He distinguishes Cartesian substance dualism— the view that mental substances are immaterial entities that bear only mental properties —from non‐Cartesian substance dualism, which claims that mental substances are the Page 5 of 25

Introduction bearers of mental properties but allows that they bear physical properties as well. Sub­ stance dualists claim that a person is not her body (or any part of it). Two traditional ar­ guments for this view are the conceivability argument and the indivisibility argument. The conceivability argument runs (roughly) as follows: I can conceive that I could exist without having a body; so I can exist without having a body; thus, I am not my body. The indivisibility argument runs: My body is divisible into parts; I am not so divisible; so I am not identical to my body. Lowe maintains that both arguments are wanting. But in his view there are two more promising arguments for substance dualism; namely, the re­ placement argument and the unity argument. The gist of the replacement argument is this: If all parts of a person's body were gradually replaced by artificial substitutes, the person would survive the procedure; neither her biological body nor any part of it would survive it; thus a person is (p. 6) not her body or any part of it. The central premises of the unity argument, which Lowe takes to be the more compelling of the two arguments, are that (1) I am the subject of all and only my own mental states, and that (2) neither my body as a whole nor any part of it could be the subject of all and only my own mental states. In his discussion of property dualism Lowe focuses mainly on the question of how, if property dualism is true, mental causation can be reconciled with the causal closure of the physical—the thesis that every caused physical event has a sufficient physical cause. The alleged tension between mental causation and the causal closure of the physical can be overcome, he argues, if we recognize that there is a distinction between fact causation and event causation. He maintains that a mental fact (a fact to the effect that someone is in a certain mental state) can cause a physical fact without a mental event causing a physical event.

4. Sven Walter's ‘Epiphenomenalism’. One response to the problem of mental causation is to deny a presupposition of the ques­ tion of how mental states and events have causal effects. The question of how they have effects presupposes that they have effects. Epiphenomenalism is the thesis that mental states and events have no causal effects. If epiphenomenalism is true, then although it ap­ pears that mental states and events causally contribute to the production of our behav­ iour, they are in fact devoid of behavioural effects, since they are devoid of any effects. Behaviour and mental states are, rather, dual effects of common physical causes in the brain. Walter discusses two prominent objections to epiphenomenalism. The first is the argument from evolution, according to which since epiphenomena cannot be selected for, and since the mind was selected for in the course of evolution, epiphenomenalism must be false. The second is the argument from other minds, according to which epiphenome­ nalism undermines any justification for our confidence that others enjoy a mental life. Walter also considers an issue that has so far been largely neglected in discussions of epiphenomenalism; namely, the issue of which account of causation would allow for a co­ herent formulation of the epiphenomenalist's position that mental events are caused by brain events but have no causal effects. He argues that on all the leading approaches to causation either brain events fail to cause mental events or mental events have causal ef­ fects; and so the epiphenomenalist's position may turn out to be incoherent. Page 6 of 25

Introduction

5. Julie Yoo's ‘Anomalous Monism’. The doctrine of anomalous monism was proposed and defended by Donald Davison. It is the doctrine that every particular mental event is identical to some particular physical event or other (token physicalism), but mental properties are not identical to physical properties (property dualism); and, moreover, there can be no strict psychophysical laws (psychophysical anomalism). Yoo presents Davidson's argument for token physicalism, and two of his main lines of argument for psychophysical (p. 7) anomalism. She also ad­ dresses two of the main concerns about the doctrine of anomalous monism. Given token physicalism, Davidson can maintain that mental events are causes since every mental event is identical with some physical event that has causal effects. One of the central premises of Davidson's argument for token physicalism, however, is that causation re­ quires subsumption under a strict physical law. This raises the concern that Davidson is committed to a kind of type or property epiphenomenalism, according to which events have causal effects only in virtue of falling under types (or instantiating properties) cited in strict physical laws, and so never in virtue of falling under mental types (or instantiat­ ing mental properties). Another concern about anomalous monism is that token physical­ ism is too weak to be a substantive form of physicalism since it is silent about whether mental properties are dependent on physical properties. Advocates of anomalous monism, including Davidson, however, hold that mental properties are dependent on physical prop­ erties in that they supervene on them: two events cannot differ in their mental properties without differing in their physical properties. But the supervenience thesis in question can be interpreted in a number of non‐equivalent ways, and it remains an issue whether there is a psychophysical‐supervenience thesis strong enough for anomalous monism to count as a substantive kind of physicalism yet weak enough to be consistent with psy­ chophysical anomalism.

6. Lynne Rudder Baker's ‘Non‐reductive Materialism’. According to Baker, non‐reductive materialism is the view that although every concrete particular is either microphysical or made up entirely of microphysical phenomena (so that there are no immaterial souls, entelechies, or the like), it is nevertheless the case that (1) there are mental properties that are distinct from any physical properties; that (2) mental properties depend on physical properties; and that (3) mental properties make a causal contribution to what happens. She points out that proponents of the doctrine face the issue of how to reconcile (3) with (1) and (2). She examines in detail the leading arguments that given the causal closure of the physical, (1) and (2) can be reconciled with (3) only by assuming a kind of untenable overdetermination of physical events by mental events. And she discusses her own version of non‐reductive materialism, the prop­ erty‐constitution view, according to which mental properties are constituted by physical properties. This version of non‐reductive materialism, she maintains, can accommodate the causal efficacy of mental properties and intention‐dependent properties in a way that is consistent with the causal closure of the physical and involves no untenable overdeter­ mination. Page 7 of 25

Introduction

7. Robert Van Gulick's ‘Functionalism’. Van Gulick discusses the historical roots of the functionalist approach to the mind and distinguishes a variety of versions of functionalism. These versions all have in common that types of mental states (events, processes) are to be understood in terms (p. 8) of the functional roles that their instances play in suitably organized systems. The roles in ques­ tion consist of relations to inputs to the system, outputs of the system, and to internal states of the system. On one version of functionalism the relevant functional roles are those specified by folk psychology; on another version they are the functional roles speci­ fied by scientific psychology. The notion of functional role, moreover, has been specified in a variety of ways—as computational role, as causal role, and as teleological role, or as some combination of these. Van Gulick also distinguishes ontological functionalism and analytical functionalism. Ontological functionalism concerns the nature of types of mental states (events, etc.). On one version, occupant functionalism, a type of mental state is tak­ en to be the occupant of a certain functional role; on another version, role functionalism, it is taken to be the higher‐order state of being in some state or other that occupies the functional role. Analytical functionalism is a claim about mental concepts; namely, that such concepts can be analysed in functional terms. Van Gulick also discusses arguments for and against the functionalist approach to the mind. He notes that the overall plausibil­ ity of the functionalist approach depends on how it comes to grips with ‘the three big C's’—content, causation, and consciousness. He maintains that with regard to content, functionalism comes off well since virtually all current major theories of mental content are in one way or another functionalist. As concerns causation, matters are more difficult, given that it has been argued that the price of functionalism is the causal impotence of the mental; but, van Gulick claims, this issue remains unresolved. Consciousness seems to be especially difficult for functionalism because of the apparent possibility of inverted and absent‐qualia scenarios. But even here, van Gulick argues, matters are not settled. He maintains that for opponents of functionalism to simply insist that any functional roles that may be specified by functionalists in the future will allow for inverted or absent qualia would beg the question against the functionalist programme. Van Gulick concludes that the objections that have been raised against functionalism are indecisive.

8. Ansgar Beckermann's ‘What is Property Physicalism?’. Much of the contemporary philosophical discussion of physicalism has focused on proper­ ty physicalism. But how, exactly, should the doctrine of property physicalism be formulat­ ed? Beckermann argues that in the end there are two rival answers to this question: iden­ tity theory and reductive‐explainability theory. According to the first, every mental prop­ erty is identical to a physical property. According to the second, every mental property is reductively explainable in terms of physical (and functional) properties. Beckermann ar­ gues that certain kinds of properties are candidates for identity theses—for example properties such as being water, being granite, and being a cloud—and he argues that cer­ tain other kinds of properties, properties such as transparency and water‐solubility, are candidates only for reductive explanation. Mental properties, he argues, are of the sec­ ond kind: they are candidates only for reductive explanation. He thus concludes that Page 8 of 25

Introduction property physicalists must maintain that mental properties are reductively explainable in terms of physical properties. (p. 9)

9. Barbara Montero's ‘What is the Physical?’.

Without an informative characterization of what it is for something to be physical, the doctrine that everything is physical lacks substantive content. Montero discusses and re­ jects some attempts to characterize the physical, including the suggestions that the physi­ cal is that which is relevantly similar to a class of prototypical physical objects and prop­ erties, that the physical is that which current physics posits, and that the physical is that which a true and complete physics would posit. Montero argues that rather than attempt­ ing to offer an informative characterization of the physical, it is more productive to for­ mulate the issues motivating the debate over physicalism as ones of whether certain kinds of phenomena, such as mental phenomena, numerical phenomena, and normative phenomena, are fundamental phenomena.

10. Howard Robinson's ‘Idealism’. As Robinson points out, idealism is not a theory about the nature of mind, but rather a theory about the nature of the physical world: idealists claim that the physical world is dependent on mind; indeed, they hold that mind is the ground of the physical world. There are, he notes, two main versions of this idea: (1) the physical world exists only as a complex feature of experience; and (2) the physical world itself is a mind, or consists of minds. He presents the two main lines of argument for idealism, one of which appeals to sensory qualities (such as colour, taste, etc.), and the other of which appeals to features of our conception of the world. The first line of argument is that there will be a vicious regress of dispositional powers unless such powers are ultimately grounded in intrinsic sensory qualities. The second line of argument is that our conception of the world, as manifested in our language about it, possesses certain features that cannot be under­ stood as representations of aspects of a concrete, mind‐independent reality, and so that our conception of the world is not a conception of a mind‐independent reality; indeed, even if anti‐idealists posit abstract entities such as universals, they cannot form any co­ herent conception of how a world might be in itself, independently of categories that are modes of understanding or interpretation. Robinson examines both of these lines of argu­ ments in great detail, offering responses to the leading attempts to rebut them. He con­ cludes that anti‐idealists have yet to show why these lines of argument fail.

11. William Seager's ‘Pansychism’. Panpsychism is the doctrine that mentality is ontologically fundamental and ubiquitous. It is fundamental in that it is irreducible. It is ubiquitous in that everything in space–time, even atoms and more elementary particles, has some form of mentality. Robinson presents a brief history of panpsychism from the Presocratic period, through Spinoza and Leibniz, to certain nineteenth‐century philosophers. He also compares and contrasts panpsychism with versions of dualism, physicalism, (p. 10) and emergence, pointing out Page 9 of 25

Introduction how certain theoretical considerations seem to favour pansychism. Further, he considers how panpsychists might respond to the leading lines of objection to their position. Pansy­ chism, Seager concludes, stands as a perennially interesting metaphysical doctrine that may yet turn out to offer the best way of understanding the fundamental nature of mind and matter.

II The Nature of Consciousness and the Place of Consciousness in Nature 12. John Perry's ‘Subjectivity’. Perry provides a detailed characterization of our subjective life within the framework of understanding the mind as an informational system. He maintains that all of our experi­ ences have both ‘feels’—‘what‐it‐is‐like for us as subjects’ aspects—and contents that can be satisfied or fail to be satisfied. He thus holds that bodily sensations such as aches and pains have contents as well as feels, and that even experiences of thinking something have feels as well as contents. He examines a number of basic metaphysical and episte­ mological issues concerning subjectivity. And he appeals to the different roles concepts can play in our information‐processing systems to argue that Frank Jackson's knowledge argument—an argument to the effect that one could in principle know all physical truths and yet not know what it is like to have certain experiences—fails to refute physicalism.

13. David M. Rosenthal's ‘Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness’. Rosenthal points out that higher‐order theories of consciousness are concerned with the problem of state consciousness; namely, the problem of what it is for a state to be a con­ scious state. The basic idea of higher‐order theories is that a state is conscious if one is conscious of the state in some suitable way. There is no circularity here since the mental state by which one is conscious of the state need not itself be a conscious state. There are two broad kinds of higher‐order theory. According to inner‐sense theories, the relevant way in which the subject must be conscious of the state is by sensing the state; according to higher‐order‐thought theories, the way in which the subject must be conscious of the state is by having in a certain way a thought that she is in the state. Rosenthal discusses both the considerations in favour of each of the two different kinds of higher‐order‐theo­ ries and the difficulties that each faces. He distinguishes two kinds of higher‐order‐ thought theories: dispositional (p. 11) higher‐order‐thought theories and intrinsic higher‐ order‐content theories. He concludes with a discussion of the central issue of how being conscious of a state with mental qualities can make the difference between there being something it is like for one to be in that state and there being nothing that it is like.

Page 10 of 25

Introduction

14. Michael Tye's ‘Representationalist Theories of Consciousness’. According to representationalist theories of consciousness, the qualitative aspect of a phenomenal state, its ‘what‐it‐is‐like for the subject’ aspect, just is (or at least supervenes upon) the representational content of the phenomenal state. Tye presents the leading considerations that have been advanced in favour of representationalist theories of con­ sciousness, and surveys various kinds of representationalist theories. Moreover, he ad­ dresses two of the most formidable arguments against representationalist theories; name­ ly, the inverted‐spectrum argument and the inverted‐earth argument.

15. Alex Byrne's ‘Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities’. Byrne claims that sensible qualities are qualities that we perceive, such as redness, roundness, sweetness, and motion. When we veridically perceive a red apple, we perceive not only the apple but also the redness of the apple, which seems to be a quality of the apple itself. Sensory qualities are supposed to be qualities of experiences, rather than of things that are experienced; other terms for sensory qualities, he says, are ‘qualia’ and ‘the phenomenal (or qualitative) character of an experience’. Sensational qualities, Byrne claims, are supposed to be qualities of mental entities that are the immediate objects of experience—sense data. Byrne claims that many historical figures, and some contempo­ rary ones, try to identify sensible qualities with sensory qualities or with dispositions to produce experiences with sensory qualities. He maintains, however, that although there are sensible qualities such as redness, sweetness, and the like, it should be controversial whether there are any sensory qualities. He further claims that if there are none, then a lot of the motivation for secondary‐quality theories of sensible qualities—theories of sensi­ ble qualities as dispositions to produce certain kinds of experiences or as the grounds of such dispositions—evaporates. Moreover, he says that the hard problem of consciousness —roughly, the problem of how to reductively explain the phenomenal character of con­ scious states—arguably presupposes that there are sensory qualities; and so if there are none, the problem dissolves. He recommends that we eschew positing sensory qualities and see how quickly—or indeed whether—we run into sand. (p. 12)

16. Joseph Levine's ‘The Explanatory Gap’.

The explanatory gap thesis is the claim that there is an unbridgeable explanatory gap be­ tween the qualitative aspects of experiences (their ‘what‐it‐is‐like for the subject’ aspects) and physical and functional properties. It thus entails that a reductive explanation of the qualitative aspects of experiences in terms of such properties is impossible. Levine expli­ cates the explanatory gap thesis, and discusses how it relates to certain arguments for dualism. He notes that materialists respond to the thesis either by maintaining that the explanatory gap is eliminable in that it can be bridged or else by arguing that although there is an unbridgeable explanatory gap, the gap can be adequately explained without assuming property dualism, and indeed in a way compatible with materialism. The cur­ rent leading strategy for reconciling materialism with an ineliminable explanatory gap is Page 11 of 25

Introduction to try to explain the explanatory gap as a conceptual gap, rather than an ontological gap, by appeal to the distinctive role of phenomenal concepts in our cognitive architecture. Some implementations of the strategy maintain that phenomenal concepts afford us an acquaintance with the qualitative characters of our experiences, and appeal to this ac­ quaintance relation to offer an epistemic explanation of the explanatory gap. Levine notes, however, that this faces the problem of how the relation of acquaintance itself can be accounted for in physicalist or functional terms. Moreover, he maintains that all of the extant implementations of the phenomenal‐concept strategy face formidable challenges that their proponents have yet to meet.

17. Katalin Balog's ‘Phenomenal Concepts’. Phenomenal concepts are supposed to be concepts that we can apply directly to our oc­ current experiences without any mediating mode of presentation of the properties in virtue of which they apply. The notion of a phenomenal concept figures prominently in re­ cent debates between physicalists and property dualists concerning consciousness. Dual­ ists tend to argue for their position by appeal to epistemological gaps between physical (and functional) truths and truths about the qualitative aspects of experience. Proponents of the phenomenal‐concept strategy argue that the existence of these epistemological gaps can be fully explained by appeal to some (physicalistically explicable) features of phenomenal concepts, and so without having to invoke property dualism. Balog examines in great detail the phenomenal‐concept strategy and its uses in defence of physicalism. She discusses as well both the various extant theories of phenomenal concepts and the challenges that remain for proponents of the strategy.

18. David J. Chalmers's ‘The Two‐dimensional Argument Against Ma­ terialism’. A number of the leading arguments for dualism concerning consciousness start from a premise about an epistemic gap between physical (or functional) truths and truths (p. 13) about consciousness, and then infer that there is an ontological gap between physical (and functional) phenomena and consciousness. These arguments include the knowledge argument and various conceivability arguments. One conceivability argument runs as fol­ lows: (1) it is conceivable that a physical duplicate of an individual who enjoys conscious­ ness could be devoid of consciousness (and so be ‘a zombie’); (2) given that this is con­ ceivable, it is metaphysically possible; (3) hence, it is metaphysically possible; (4) there­ fore, materialism (or physicalism) is false for consciousness. One leading materialist strat­ egy for responding to such arguments is to concede the epistemic gap but to deny that it entails ontological dualism. Thus, a materialist might accept (1) and yet reject (2). The framework of two‐dimensional semantics has been invoked to justify certain principles linking certain epistemic facts to modal facts concerning what is possible. According to two‐dimensionalism, terms (and on some versions concepts) have two intensions, a prima­ ry intension and a secondary intension; and the primary intension, but not the secondary intension, is relevant to matters of cognitive significance. It is claimed that this frame­ work can accommodate Kripkean cases of a posteriori necessity (such as that it is neces­ Page 12 of 25

Introduction sary yet a posteriori that water is identical with H20), and that it can do so without avail­ ing materialists of an avenue of response to the dualist arguments in question. Chalmers spells out in detail how the two‐dimensional framework can be invoked to try to justify certain principles linking the epistemic and the modal that can be appealed to in order to establish dualism concerning consciousness on the basis of certain epistemic facts.

III Intentionality and Theories of Mental Con­ tent 19. Daniel Dennett's ‘Intentional Systems Theory’. At the centre of Dennett's philosophy of mind is his theory of intentionality, intentional systems theory, according to which anything whose behaviour is usefully and voluminous­ ly predictable from the intentional stance is an intentional system. Dennett distinguishes the intentional stance from two other predictive stances, the physical stance and the de­ sign stance, and points out the usefulness and wide applicability of the intentional sys­ tems theory. He challenges the alleged distinction between original (‘real’) and derived (‘as if’) intentionality. Moreover, he responds to two objections to intentional systems the­ ory; namely, that it is instrumentalistic, and that it is too liberal in what it counts as an in­ tentional system.

20. Frances Egan's ‘Wide Content’. The idea that mental content is wide content is the idea that it is individuated at least in part by environmental factors or social factors. If mental content is wide, (p. 14) then two individuals can be exactly alike in every intrinsic physical respect, and yet have mental states with different contents. Egan discusses in detail the Twin Earth thought‐experi­ ments of Hilary Putnam and of Tyler Burge offered in support of different externalist the­ ories of mental content, which entail that mental content is wide. She also discusses an argument of Gareth Evans that certain thoughts have wide content in that they contain individuals as constituents. She examines various challenges to these externalist theses. She critically examines the idea that there are psychological contents that are narrow— that are determined by intrinsic properties of appropriate individuals. Moreover, she ad­ dresses a number of issues concerning wide content, including the issue of whether wide content is causally relevant to behaviour. She defends the view that wide contents are causally explanatory.

21. Gabriel Segal's ‘Narrow Content’. The idea that the content of a mental state is narrow is the idea that it is determined sole­ ly by intrinsic conditions of the individual in the state. If the content of a mental state is narrow, then two individuals exactly alike in every intrinsic respect would be such that the one is in a mental state with that content if and only if the other is. Twin Earth thought‐experiments developed by Hilary Putnam and Tyler Burge have been used by Page 13 of 25

Introduction them and others to argue that mental content is not narrow content, but rather wide con­ tent in that it is partly individuated by environmental or social factors. Segal discusses some theories according to which there is a kind of mental content that is narrow, and so a kind of mental content that an individual on Earth and the individual's doppelgänger on Twin Earth share. But he also presents a case that the various Twin Earth thought‐experi­ ments simply fail to show that the contents we ordinarily attribute to mental states using that‐clauses are wide, rather than narrow.

22. Fred Dretske's ‘Information‐theoretic Semantics’. Information‐theoretic semantics attempts to ground the meaning (or content) of mental states or natural‐language expressions in an objective, mind‐and‐language‐independent notion of information. It is a part of a larger philosophical effort to naturalize mental con­ tent, thereby contributing to the naturalization of mentality. If symbols are the bearers of meaning, then information‐theoretic semantics locates the primary source of this mean­ ing in certain naturalistic relations these symbols participate in. Dretske explicates the relevant notions of information and meaning, and spells out the information‐theoretic pro­ gramme in detail. He also discusses a number of problems that have been raised for this programme, including the disjunction problem (essentially the problem of whether the programme can capture misrepresentation, e.g. false belief), the grain problem (the prob­ lem of whether the programme can capture content as fine‐grained as mental content seems to be), and the issue of whether content is causally relevant to the explanation of behaviour (given its relational nature). (p. 15)

23. Ruth Garrett Millikan's ‘Biosemantics’.

Biosemantics is a kind of naturalistic, teleological theory of mental content. Biosemantics tries to explain how states have mental content by appealing to a teleological notion of function: what a mental state represents depends on the functions of the state in the sys­ tem that uses or produces it, where the notion of function is the notion of what something was selected for by natural selection or some other natural process of selection. As Mil­ likan points out, if the notion of function is anchored in natural selection, then a teleologi­ cal theory of mental content presupposes that mental representations can sometimes benefit an organism. What is needed is thus an account of how mental representation can be beneficial. The bulk of Millikan's essay is devoted to a discussion of three different kinds of representation—descriptive representations (representations that are designed to represent facts), directive representations (representations that tell what to do) and ‘pushmi‐pullyu’ representations (the most primitive and fundamental kind of representa­ tions)—and to showing exactly what role these kinds of representations play in her biose­ mantic account of the contents of mental representations.

Page 14 of 25

Introduction

24. Robert J. Matthews's ‘A Measurement‐theoretic Account of Propo­ sitional Attitudes’. The sentences by which we attribute propositional attitudes have a relational logical form. The main‐clause verb of sentences of the form ‘x believes (desires, etc.) that S’ ex­ presses a relation between the possessor of the propositional attitude and an abstract particular that is the referent of the that‐clause. According to a traditional view, the propositional‐attitude state attributed by such a sentence (the belief, or desire, etc.) con­ sists of the subject's bearing a certain relationship to the referent of the that‐clause. Matthews notes that it has proved notoriously difficult for this view to account for the psychological role of propositional‐attitudes states. And he rejects the view. In its place, he defends a measurement‐theoretic approach, according to which propositional‐attitude predicates such as ‘believes that S’ have a different function: they function like the nu­ merical‐measure predicates that we use to attribute physical magnitudes, predicates such as ‘has a mass of 5 kg’. The point is that although the sentences by which we attribute propositional attitudes are relational in form, the relations they express are not constitu­ tive of the propositional‐attitude states attributed. The state of an object's having a mass of 5 kg does not consist, even in part, in the object's bearing some relation to the number 5. Rather, the mass of the object is specified by a location on a mathematical scale. Simi­ larly, an individual's believing that S does not consist, even in part, in the individual's bearing a relation to the referent of ‘that S’. Rather, the abstract entities that are the ref­ erents of that‐clauses are used to represent, measurement‐theoretically, the belief state that is attributed. Matthews discusses in detail this measurement‐theoretic account and its philosophical implications. (p. 16)

25. Ralph Wedgwood's ‘The Normativity of the Intentional’.

It is often claimed in contemporary philosophy of mind that the intentional is normative— that intentional mental states (such as propositional attitudes) are normative. Wedgwood examines ways in which this claim has been understood. One way of understanding the claim is as a metaphysical claim concerning the nature or essence of intentional states; namely, that the nature or essence of such states includes normative factors. Wedgwood also examines in detail various lines of argument that have been advanced for the view that the intentional is normative. According to the entailment line of argument, there are some facts about our intentional states that entail normative facts, and so intentional states are essentially normative. Another line of argument presupposes an interpretation theory of intentional states. According to this interpretation line of argument, intentional states are normative in that the right way to interpret an intentional agent is the most charitable reading of his or her behavioural dispositions, the way that, consistent with other constraints, makes the agent's dispositions most rational and most sensitive to the norms that apply to intentional states. Yet another line of argument is to support the claim that the intentional is normative by arguing against the view that the nature of our intentional states is determined by features of our relevant dispositions that can be speci­ fied in wholly non‐normative terms. Wedgwood argues that all three of these lines of ar­ gument are wanting. He goes on to make a case that the intentional is normative by argu­ Page 15 of 25

Introduction ing that only a normative kind of dispositionalism can give an adequate account of the na­ ture of intentional mental states.

26. Christopher Peacocke's ‘Concepts and Possession Conditions’. As Peacocke points out, the nature of concepts is a controversial issue that interacts with the theory of thought, and with fundamental metaphysical and epistemological issues. He discusses the view that concepts are abstract objects, the view that they are mental rep­ resentations with syntactic and semantic properties, and the pleonastic view that they are grammatical fictions. He discusses Frege's principle of individuation of concepts, which he states as the principle that concept A is distinct from concept B if and only if a thinker can rationally judge some complete (truth‐evaluable) content containing the concept A without judging the corresponding content containing B. He discusses as well the prob­ lem of what distinguishes conceptual content from non‐conceptual content. Moreover, he explores a number of questions concerning concepts that remain open. Types of con­ cepts, he holds, typically have rationality profiles, and one open question is: Can all as­ pects of rationality specific to a given type of concept be explained in terms of the nature of that type of concept? Another open question is: How should we conceive of the relation between concepts and knowledge? Yet another is: What is the role of reference and truth in the individuation of concepts? A fourth open question is: Is (p. 17) there some unified explanation of the range of apparent characteristics of conceptual content? Do, for exam­ ple, all these characteristics flow from the idea of concepts individuated in part by rea­ sons for being in states involving them? Some concepts, he maintains, are individuated by external factors. And he cites yet another open question: What is the correct account of the relation between external individuation of mental states, epistemic norms for judging given conceptual content, and the identity of the concepts in that content? The task re­ mains, he notes, to integrate our metaphysics, epistemology, and theory of thought for the domain of concepts themselves.

27. José Luis Bermúdez's ‘The Distinction between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content’. Bermúdez points out that notions of non‐conceptual content have been invoked in discus­ sions of perceptual experience, of subpersonal computational states, and of the mental states of non‐linguistic animals and pre‐linguistic humans. Thus, it has been argued, for instance, that something can look F (e.g. right‐angled) to a visual perceiver who lacks the concept of F, and thus that a perceiver's visual experience can represent something as F without that involving any conceptualization of F by the perceiver. Also, it has been claimed that computational cognitive states have contents, but that the subpersonal‐level processes in which they participate do not consist of the exercise of concepts. And it has been claimed that higher non‐linguistic animals and pre‐linguistic humans have proposi­ tional attitudes despite lacking concepts. Bermúdez provides a detailed survey of these and a number of other theoretical discussions. Moreover, he examines a number of argu­ ments for and against the existence of non‐conceptual content. Maintaining that there is non‐conceptual content, he engages the fundamental issues of what non‐conceptual con­ Page 16 of 25

Introduction tent is, and how non‐conceptual content is different from conceptual content. Further, he sketches how Peacocke's notion of a scenario content, a kind of non‐conceptual visual content, could be developed with the help of his (Bermúdez's) notion of canonical object‐ properties to yield a more adequate account of non‐conceptual visual content.

28. Tim Crane's ‘Intentionalism’. Crane embraces Brentano's thesis that all mental phenomena are intentional. All mental states, not only states such as beliefs, desires, and intentions, but also emotions, percep­ tual experiences, and sensations are intentional in that they are about or directed upon or concern something. He explicates Brentano's thesis and presents various ways in which the thesis has been developed in the literature. Moreover, he compares and contrasts rep­ resentationalism with intentionalism. Representationalism is the position that the phe­ nomenal or qualitative character of a conscious mental state (its ‘what‐it‐is‐like for the subject’ aspect) is determined by its intentional (p. 18) content. Intentionalism is the view that the phenomenal character of a conscious mental state is determined by its entire in­ tentional nature. Crane argues that intentionalism is the superior of the two. He points out that there is a distinction between intentional content and intentional mode. The be­ lief that p and the hope that p have the same intentional content, but the states have dif­ ferent intentional modes: one is a belief, the other a hope. Perceptual experiences, too, can have different modes: the visual mode, the auditory mode, etc.; indeed, Crane main­ tains that all conscious states have intentional modes. According to intentionalism, the phenomenal character of a conscious mental state is determined by its content and its mode, rather than by its content alone. Thus, phenomenal character supervenes on the combination of intentional content and intentional mode: conscious states cannot differ in their phenomenal character without differing either in their intentional content or their intentional mode.

29. Michelle Montague's ‘The Content of Perceptual Experience’. Montague addresses the question: What is the content of a perceptual experience? She maintains that the answer is: Whatever is given to one in having the experience. She ar­ gues that the content of an experience includes more than the worldly state of affairs that it presents, the state of affairs that we express using a that‐clause when attributing the perceptual experience. She argues that the content includes as well the phenomenal character of the experience—the ‘what‐it‐is‐like for the subject’ aspect of the experience. She argues further that it also includes an awareness of the experience itself, even though this awareness is normally in the background, rather than in the foreground of at­ tention, since attention is normally focused on the environmental state of affairs that we are experiencing. Montague discusses this view of the content of perceptual experience in the context of a wide range of central debates: the debate over whether experience is phenomenologically transparent, the externalism versus internalism debate about inten­ tional content, the direct versus indirect‐realism debate, and the debate over whether

Page 17 of 25

Introduction there is a unified kind of experience common to perception and hallucination or whether instead disjunctivism is true.

30. George Graham, Terence Horgan, and John Tienson's ‘Phenome­ nology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind’. As Graham, Horgan, and Tienson note, we are both conscious beings and intentional be­ ings. We are conscious in that there is something it is like to be us; and we are intentional beings in that we occupy representational mental states. They note that the currently dominant view is that there are two independent features that a mental state can have: a mental state can have representational (intentional) content and (p. 19) it can have a phe­ nomenological character (a ‘what it‐is‐like for the subject’ aspect). They call the thesis that phenomenology and intentionality are mutually independent ‘separatism’. More specifically, separatism is the thesis that a mental state can have intentionality without having a phenomenal character and a mental state can have a phenomenal character without having intentionality. Separatists will typically claim, for example, that a belief state has intentionality but no phenomenal character, and that a feeling of pain has a phe­ nomenal character but no intentional content. Inseparatism is the thesis that phenome­ nology and intentionality are inseparable. Graham, Horgan, and Tienson advocate a the­ sis they call ‘moderate inseparatism’. They formulate the thesis as follows: mental states that uncontroversially have intentional content have phenomenal character, and mental states that uncontroversially possess phenomenal character have intentional content. They spell out the separatism/inseparatism debate, present a case for moderate insepa­ ratism, and address objections to it.

IV Self, Unity of Consciousness, and Personal Identity 31. Galen Strawson's ‘The Self’. Strawson claims that when used by a human being the word ‘I’ sometimes refers to the human being as a whole and that it sometimes refers instead to the self of the human be­ ing at the time in question. In Strawson's view, a self is a subject of experience, and it is not identical with a whole human being. The reason that selves are not identical to whole human beings is that a self exists only as long as it is consciously experiencing. Human beings, in contrast, can of course continue to exist when they have no experiences at all; for example, in periods of dreamless sleep. There is not a single self that is the subject of all of the experiences that a human being has over his or her lifetime. Rather, there are many, many selves, each of which lasts exactly as long as the conscious experience of which it is the subject. Strawson maintains, however, that selves, like whole human be­ ings, are physical objects or substances, and so rejects mental–physical substance dual­ ism.

Page 18 of 25

Introduction

32. Paul Raymont and Andrew Brook's ‘Unity of Consciousness’. Raymont and Brook discuss five varieties of unity of consciousness: (1) unified conscious­ ness of an individual object, (2) unified consciousness of the content of an experience, (3) unified consciousness of acts of experiencing, (4) unified consciousness of one's self, and (5) unity of focal attention. They point out that the first four ideas are found in Kant and the fifth in Wilhelm Wundt. They discuss how mental (p. 20) disorders such as dissocia­ tive‐identity disorder, severe schizophrenia, dysexecutive syndrome, and simultagnosia reveal how these ways in which consciousness is normally unified can break down. They discuss as well the disunity of the consciousness in individuals who have undergone com­ missurotomies.

33. Tamar Szabó Gendler's ‘Personal Identity and Metaphysics’. Issues concerning personal identity include: (1) Given a person X at a time t, with which past and future entities (if any) is X (numerically) identical? (2) Which facts determine the answer to (1)? (3) On what bases do we ordinarily make judgements about (1) and on what bases could we do so in principle? Gendler examines in detail John Locke's views on such issues, and poses problems for any Lockean approach. She also discusses in detail three contemporary approaches to issues of personal identity.

V A Variety of Mental Abilities 34. Colin McGinn's ‘Imagination’. Imagination, McGinn claims, is a basic faculty of the mind intimately connected to various mental capacities, including the creative capacities expressed in the arts and in science. He distinguishes two types of imagination: sensory imagination, the forming of a mental image, and conceptual imagination, entertaining a possibility in the conceptual style. He contrasts sensory imagination with sensory perception, arguing both against the Humean view that imagination is a kind of perception and against the Kantian view that percep­ tion is a kind of imagination. As concerns cognitive imagination, McGinn argues that imagining‐that is not a kind of believing‐that; unlike believing‐that, imagining‐that is sub­ ject to the will, requires attention, and does not purport to be knowledge of the world. He claims that imagining‐that gives us a (fallible) means to consider the merely possible, and therefore bears on linguistic meaning. As he puts it, understanding the meaning of a sen­ tence is the imaginative apprehension of the possibility expressed by it.

35. Louise Antony's ‘Thinking’. Antony examines a number of philosophical issues concerning the activity of thinking. Moreover, she draws on intuitive considerations about the nature of thought, marshalled by thinkers as apparently antagonistic as René Descartes and Alan Turing, to make a case for the account of thinking as computation: as consisting of the (p. 21) operation of struc­ Page 19 of 25

Introduction ture‐sensitive processes defined over the compositional structures of mental symbols pos­ sessing contents.

36. John Heil's ‘Language and Thought’. A number of contemporary philosophers hold that thinking, or at least higher‐order think­ ing (thinking about mental states), requires possession of a natural language. Heil argues against this view. Conscious thinking, he maintains, is imagistic, and the images used in thinking need not be linguistic images; they can be ‘pictorial’. He relies on the idea that representations only have a meaning when they are used by some agent to mean some­ thing. Thinking does not consist in the mere having of images, but rather in using those images in certain ways. The images so used need not be linguistic images. According to Heil, the correlation we find between the capacity for language and the capacity for thought is not due to one requiring the other, but rather to both having a common cause: a structure that enables a being to form and use representations in certain ways.

37. John Campbell's ‘Consciousness and Reference’. Campbell maintains that our ability to know the reference of our singular and general terms is based, ultimately, on our ability to focus our conscious attention on objects and properties. Consciousness of objects and of properties, he tells us, provides us, respec­ tively, with knowledge of the reference of our demonstrative singular terms and of the reference of certain of our general terms. In spelling out this thesis he relies on Russell's distinction between knowledge of truths and knowledge by acquaintance, and on Russell's idea that the latter is more basic than the former. Campbell discusses both con­ sciousness of objects and consciousness of properties within the context of G. E. Moore's idea of the transparency of conscious awareness. Campbell argues, among other things, that Russell's idea of conscious acquaintance with properties has been misunderstood in the literature. As concerns perceptual conscious awareness of objects, he argues, among other things, that it consists of a three‐place relation between a person, a standpoint, and the object: the person is conscious of an object from a standpoint. The standpoint will dif­ fer depending on the kind of sense modality in question. Campbell maintains that it is consciousness of the object demonstrated that provides us with knowledge of the refer­ ence of our demonstrative terms.

38. Krista Lawlor's ‘Memory’. Lawlor provides a wide‐ranging survey of recent work in the psychology and in the philos­ ophy of memory. She shows, moreover, the centrality of issues concerning memory in a wide range of core philosophical subjects. These include autonomous agency, self‐con­ sciousness, reference, mental content, and reasoning.

Page 20 of 25

Introduction (p. 22)

39. Jesse Prinz's ‘Emotions: Motivating Feelings’.

Prinz reviews the leading theories of emotions, and points out that those theories can be divided into two categories: cognitivist and non‐cognitivist. Cognitivists claim that emo­ tions are or require thoughts, while non‐cognivists deny this. He presents evidence in support of a non‐cognitivist approach that builds on the James/Lange theory, according to which emotions are feelings of changes in the body. He argues that emotions are an im­ portant source of information, even though they are bodily feelings. Emotions, he con­ tends, make a distinctive contribution to decision making since, unlike thoughts or judge­ ments, they present information in a way that motivates action.

40. Alfred R. Mele's ‘Intention and Intentional Action’. We have the ability to plan courses of action and to intentionally carry them out. What is the relationship between intentions and intentional actions? What is it to act intentionali­ ty? Intentions, Mele argues, differ from desires by their settledness. While one can desire to do something without being at all settled on doing it, to intend to do something is, in part, to be settled on doing it. Intentions are formed by decisions, and should cohere with one's beliefs. Also, Mele examines two analyses of what makes an action intentional. The first is that an agent S intentionally A‐ed if and only if S A‐ed the way S intended to A. The second is that an agent S intentionally A‐ed if and only if S A‐ed for a reason. He points out that both analyses face problems. How one responds to these problems depends in part, he maintains, on what aim one pursues as a philosopher of action: on whether one aims to analyse the folk concept of intentional action or to build an adequate theory of in­ tentional action. Mele addresses a third topic as well: the causalism versus anti‐causalism debate. According to Mele, standard causalism can be characterized by two theses: (1) An event's being an action depends on how it was caused; and (2) proper explanations of ac­ tions are causal explanations. Mele examines two objections to causalism—the problem of causal deviance and the problem of vanishing agents—and argues that neither is decisive.

VI Epistemic Issues 41. Adam Morton's ‘Folk Psychology’. Social life is based on our ability to ascribe mental states to other people and to predict and explain their behaviour in terms of such states. This ability is called ‘mind reading’ in the current literature. It has been claimed that this ability is based on knowledge of folk psychology. But what, exactly, are the resources we rely on in making such ascriptions and predictions? Two answers are much debated. Subtleties (p. 23) aside, the theory‐theo­ ry tells us that we rely on an explicit theory that tells us what mental states a person would be in in various circumstances, and what a person would do if she were in those states. The simulation theory holds that we rely on the ability to simulate what mental states we would be in various circumstances and what we would do. Morton maintains that in fact both simulation and theory play a role, and so finds Stephen Stich and Shaun Page 21 of 25

Introduction Nichol's distinction between information‐rich procedures and information‐poor proce­ dures more useful than the traditional theory‐theory/simulation theory distinction. Infor­ mation‐rich procedures involve heavy reliance on theory, while information‐poor proce­ dures require engagement in simulation. Morton maintains that our ability to ascribe mental states and to predict the behaviour of other people on the basis of such states re­ lies on three basic resources: (1) a mental‐category theory, our understanding of which is based in part on our linguistic abilities; (2) the capacity for simulation, which is based in part on our ability to engage in counterfactual thinking, and normally on the ability (man­ ifested very early in life) to track the gaze of other people; and (3) a how‐to manual, pro­ viding information about what kind of simulation works under which circumstances, what information about others is relevant in modelling their mental states, and so on. Morton argues that this account can be developed to handle questions about the phylogenetic evolution and ontogenetic development of folk psychology. However, he points out that many questions remain, including epistemological questions concerning the reliability of the procedures in question, and the justification of our mental attributions.

42. Anita Avramides's ‘Other Minds’. Avramides critically examines two would‐be solutions to the problem of other minds and defends another. The first is the argument from analogy. From my knowledge that I have a mind, a mind that causes certain behaviour, and from the observation that there are others who are physically similar to me and who behave similarly to me, I conclude that these other individuals have a mind. Several objections have been raised against this ar­ gument, including that the inference rests on an induction from a single case, and that it is impossible to check the conclusion. The second argument is the argument from best ex­ planation. The ascription of mental states to others provides the best explanation of their behaviour under certain circumstances. Avramides claims that both of these solutions are inadequate because they leave room for scepticism about other minds. According to Avramides, our belief that we are not alone in the universe, that there are other people who, for example, feel pain, is not a hypothesis; it is, rather, as Thomas Reid argued, a first principle that leaves no room for coherent doubt. It is deeply rooted in our concep­ tion of mind. Avramides claims that if we abandon the mistaken Cartesian conception of mind, we can come to see that the relation between mind and behaviour is not a contin­ gent one, but rather a necessary one. (p. 24)

43. Cynthia Macdonald's ‘Introspection’.

Macdonald argues for her own version of an introspectionist account of authoritative self‐ knowledge by comparing and contrasting it with alternative accounts. As she points out, introspectionist accounts of self‐knowledge fall within the broader domain of theories of self‐knowledge, understood as views about the nature of and basis for one's knowledge of one's own mental states and events, including one's beliefs, desires, conscious episodes of thinking, and sensations. Theories of self‐knowledge are motivated by the apparent need to account for a number of striking features of at least some such knowledge, which ordi­ nary empirical knowledge, including knowledge of the mental states of others, is typically Page 22 of 25

Introduction thought to lack. Knowledge of certain of one's mental states is said to be epistemically di­ rect or immediate in some sense (for example, in being non‐inferential and/or non‐evi­ dence‐based), and privileged and/or authoritative, perhaps in being incorrigible, or infalli­ ble, or transparent to oneself (or all three of these). Introspectionist theories attempt to account for some, or all, of these features by reference to a special method by which this knowledge is obtained. Macdonald argues that the main alternatives to her view account for some of these features at the expense of others, or suffer from additional problems that her account avoids.

44. Jessica Brown's ‘Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge’. According to semantic externalism, the contents of a subject's thoughts are at least partly individuated by factors in her environment. One of the main objections to semantic exter­ nalism is that it is incompatible with the fact that we normally have privileged access to our thoughts; privileged in the sense that we can normally know what we are thinking a priori; a priori in the sense that the knowledge is not based, directly or indirectly, upon in­ vestigation of the environment. Brown notes that there are two main problems that pro­ ponents of the view that semantic externalism and such privileged access are compatible must address: the achievement problem and the consequence problem. The achievement problem is that given semantic externalism it is difficult to see how a subject could achieve privileged access; for it seems that if a subject's thought contents are partly indi­ viduated by her environment, then the subject's knowledge of what she is thinking would have to be based, at least indirectly, on empirical information about her environment. The consequence problem is that the conjunction of semantic externalism and privileged ac­ cess seems to have the consequence that we can have a priori knowledge of facts about our environment that it patently seems could be known only a posteriori. Brown points out several promising avenues for compatibilists to explore to resolve the achievement problem. As concerns the consequence problem, she argues that it in fact does not follow from semantic externalism that there are a priori knowable entailments from the fact that one is having certain thoughts to contingent facts (p. 25) about the environment. She con­ cludes that semantic externalism may well be compatible with privileged access.

45. Kent Bach's ‘Self‐deception’. Bach examines the so‐called paradoxes of self‐deception as well as a wide variety of other issues concerning self‐deception. He notes that the view that being self‐deceived requires having intentionally deceived oneself seems to have paradoxical consequences. It seems to have the consequence that the self‐deceiver has succeeded in carrying out an intention to believe something that the self‐deceiver believes is false, while retaining the belief that it is false and knowledge of the stratagem. But how could one successfully carry out the stratagem in such a circumstance? And how could one believe that p and believe that not p at the same time? Some philosophers attempt to answer the first question by positing unconscious intentions; some claim instead that in self‐deception one part of a person in­ tentionally deceives another part of the person, so that the part that successfully carries out the stratagem is not the part that is taken in by it. Some philosophers attempt to an­ Page 23 of 25

Introduction swer the second question by distinguishing two kinds of beliefs, for example, central be­ liefs and avowed beliefs. Bach critically examines these various would‐be answers to the questions. He argues in favour of rejecting the idea that self‐deception requires intention­ ally deceiving oneself, and maintains instead that in self‐deception one unintentionally misleads oneself in certain ways. And he argues that rather than self‐deception requiring contradictory beliefs, in self‐deception one has a complex disposition to resist consciously thinking something that one believes (or at least takes there to be strong evidence for and normally would believe), and to affirmatively think something contrary to that propo­ sition. Moreover, he explores in detail the role of attention and inattention in the various activities by which a self‐deceiver unintentionally acquires and sustains the disposition in question, activities that include evasion, rationalization, and what he calls jamming. The last involves using one's imagination to conjure fanciful alternatives to the unwanted truth, and using the mere possibilities in question to support the case that the matter is unsettled. Bach discusses many other issues concerning self‐deception as well, including how self‐deception can be twisted. Typical cases of self‐deception involve wishful think­ ing. But in cases of twisted self‐deception a person is self‐deceived that p, yet wishes that p were not the case. Whereas the straight self‐deceiver cannot face up to some unpleas­ ant truth, and so evades it, the twisted self‐deceiver cannot get his mind off some unde­ sirable falsehood, and ends up disposed to affirmatively think it.

References Broad, C. D. (1925), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Dunbar, R., and Barrett, L. (2007) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Evolutionary Psycholo­ gy (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Feigl, H. (1958), ‘The “Mental” and the “Physical”’, Minnesota Studies in the Phi­ losophy of Science, 2: 370–497. (p. 26)

Fine, G. (forthcoming) (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Plato (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Garber, D. (2001), ‘Understanding Interaction: What Descartes Should Have Told Elisa­ beth’, in D. Garber (ed.), Descartes Embodied: Reading Cartesian Philosophy through Cartesian Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 168–88. Kane, R. (2002) (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Kopp, D. (2007) (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Lepore, E., and Smith, B. (2006) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Page 24 of 25

Introduction McGinn, C. (forthcoming) (ed.), The Oxford Handbook on Wittgenstein (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Mele, A. R., and Rawlings, P. (2004) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Prinz, J. (forthcoming) (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Psychology (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). Smart, J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56. Stich, S., Samuels, R., and Margolis, M. (forthcoming) (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Brian P. McLaughlin

Brian P. McLaughlin is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey.

Page 25 of 25

Mental Causation

Oxford Handbooks Online Mental Causation   Jaegwon Kim The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0002

Abstract and Keywords The problem of mental causation is essentially coeval with the mind–body problem. Descartes arguably invented the latter when, in Meditation 2, he asked ‘But what then am I?’ to which he replied ‘A thing which thinks’, and then went on to argue, in Meditation 6, that ‘it is certain that this I is entirely and absolutely distinct from my body, and can exist without it’. As every student of western philosophy knows, Descartes's view was that minds and bodies constitute two disjoint categories of substance: minds are immaterial substances whose essential nature is thinking, while bodies are material substances located in physical space whose essence consists in being extended in space. Presumably, substance dualism of this form was not startling news to anyone at the time. However, Descartes, alone among the great rationalists of his day, urged a further view: minds and bodies are in causal interaction with each other, minds influencing bodies in voluntary actions and bodies influencing minds in perception and sensation. Keywords: mental causation, mind–body problem, René Descartes, substance dualism, causal interaction, voluntary actions

Page 1 of 28

Mental Causation THE

problem of mental causation is essentially coeval with the mind–body problem.

Descartes arguably invented the latter when, in Meditation 2, he asked ‘But what then am I?’ to which he replied ‘A thing which thinks’, and then went on to argue, in Meditation 6, that ‘it is certain that this I is entirely and absolutely distinct from my body, and can exist without it’.1 As every student of western philosophy knows, Descartes's view was that minds and bodies constitute two disjoint categories of substance: minds are immaterial substances whose essential nature is thinking, while bodies are material substances located in physical space whose essence consists in being extended in space. Presumably, substance dualism of this form was not startling news to anyone at the time. However, Descartes, alone among the great rationalists of his day, urged a further view: minds and bodies are in causal interaction with each other, minds influencing bodies in voluntary actions and bodies influencing minds in perception and sensation. Leibniz famously denied causal relations between all monads; occasionalists like Malebranche allowed no causal relations anywhere in the created world, with God as the sole causal agent; and there probably was no room for genuine mind‐body causation in Spinoza's doctrine of a single substance with mind and body as its two parallel attributes. It is not surprising then that Descartes's contemporaries lost no time in contesting his interactionist thesis, which, to many of us today, is probably the most commonsensical and plausible of the doctrines that make up Descartes's theory of the mind. Among the prominent critics of the interactionist thesis were Pierre Gassendi, Antoine Arnauld, and (p. 30) Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia. The challenge posed to him was in essence this question: How can substances with such diverse natures, one with thinking as its essence and not even located in space and the other with extension and location in space, causally influence each other? Thus was the problem of mental causation born. Some commentators have attributed the fall of Cartesian dualism to Descartes's inability to come up with a satisfactory response to this challenge (Watson 1987). What is remarkable is the fact that the problem of mental causation didn't go away with the downfall of substance dualism. Although substance dualism has not totally vanished from the contemporary scene and there have recently been some attempts to resuscitate it, philosophy of mind since the mid‐twentieth century has been dominated by a strong physicalist outlook, and the agenda of the field has consisted largely in various physicalist/naturalist programmes—the projects of ‘naturalizing’ centrally important mental phenomena, such as intentionality, content, and consciousness. The re‐emergence of mental causation as a major problematic in the 1960s was occasioned by the reluctance on the part of most philosophers of mind to go all the way with physicalism. These philosophers reject the dualism of mental and material substances, recognizing only material things as the inhabitants of the world, and yet they are deeply committed to the preservation of mental properties and kinds as genuine but physically irreducible properties and kinds. And part of what makes mental properties ‘genuine’ properties is their possession of causal efficacy. That is to say, these property dualists hold the view that a mental property when possessed by a material thing endows it with distinctive causal powers, powers that are irreducible to those of physical properties. The question that has been raised concerning this combination of doctrines parallels the challenge Page 2 of 28

Mental Causation posed to Cartesian interactionist dualism: Given the irreducible diversity of the two domains of properties, mental and physical, how is it possible for an object's mental properties to have causal powers to affect, and be affected by, its physical properties? Just as the essential diversity in their natures turned out, for substance dualists, to be an insuperable obstacle to explaining causal relations between mental and material substances, the purported autonomy of mental properties vis‐à‐vis physical properties has proved, for physicalist property dualists, to be a seemingly intractable difficulty in accommodating mind‐body causation. Before we turn to the contemporary debate, it will be instructive to see wherein the real difficulties lie for substance dualism in accounting for mental causation.

1.1 Substance Dualism and Mental Causation In Meditation 2, Descartes writes: by a body I understand whatever has a determinable shape and a definable location and can occupy a space in such a way as to exclude any other body; it can be perceived by touch, sight, (p. 31) hearing, taste or smell, and can be moved in various ways, not by itself but by whatever else comes into contact with it. (Descartes 1641/1984: 17) This suggests that physical causation requires contact—the object that causally influences another must come into contact with it. In view of the transitivity of causation, the cause need not be in direct contact with the object in which a change is caused, but it is clear that, on Descartes's view, where there are causally related objects there must be objects in contact. And, evidently, the very idea of contact requires spatiality. Given this, Princess Elisabeth's request to Descartes, in her letter of May 1643, seems eminently natural and reasonable; she asked Descartes to explain

how the mind of a human being can determine the bodily spirits in producing voluntary actions, being only a thinking substance. For it appears that all determination of movement is produced by the pushing of the thing being moved, by the manner in which it is pushed by that which moves it, or else by the qualification and figure of the surface of the latter. Contact is required for the first two conditions, and extension for the third. [But] you entirely exclude the latter from the notion you have of the soul, and the former seems incompatible with an immaterial thing.2 Descartes's reply was that mind‐body causation must be understood through the idea of mind‐ body union, and that this is a primitive notion that is intelligible per se. Causation among material things is causation by contact; however, the issue of contact does not arise with respect to mind‐body union. I will comment on this approach later, but for now let us return to Princess Elisabeth. Apparently unsatisfied by Descartes's response, she writes back:

Page 3 of 28

Mental Causation And I admit that it would be easier for me to concede matter and extension to the mind than it would be for me to concede the capacity to move a body and be moved by one to an immaterial thing.3 I find this response remarkable—in fact, fascinating; it is, to my knowledge, the first causal argument for physicalism that I know. She would rather physicalize the mind (‘easier for me to concede matter and extension to the mind’) than accept causal relations between immaterial minds and material bodies.

Princess Elisabeth's difficulty with mental causation within the Cartesian setting depended on a particular conception of physical causation; namely, that physical causation requires contact between cause and effect, whether direct or mediated. But perhaps causation at a distance, without mediating chains of contiguous cause‐effect pairs, cannot be ruled out a priori. I believe, though, that it can be shown that the difficulties that beset causal relations involving immaterial, non‐spatial entities go deeper and do not depend on the assumption that physical causation requires contact or contiguity. They would arise even for causation, or action, at a distance (if such (p. 32) should exist). A plausible argument can be developed, at a more abstract and general level, that shows that causation is inseparable from spatiality, and that causal relations between immaterial souls—that is, mind‐mind causation—are just as problematic as mind‐ body causation and for the same reason. Here is the argument.4 Let us first consider an example of physical causation. A gun, call it A, is fired and this causes the death of a person, X. Another gun, B, is fired at the same time (say, in A’s vicinity—but the time and place are unimportant), and this results in the death of another person, Y. What makes it the case that the firing of A caused X’s death and the firing of B caused Y’s death, and not the other way around—that is, A’s firing causing Y’s death and B’s firing causing X’s death? That cannot be an unexplainable brute fact. There must be a relation R that grounds and explains the ‘cause‐effect pairings’, a relation that holds between A’s firing and X’s death and also between B’s firing and Y’s death, but not between A’s firing and Y’s death or between B’s firing and X’s death. What is this R, the ‘pairing relation’ as we might call it? We are not supposing at this point that there is a single such R for all cases of physical causation, only that some relation must ground the fact that a given cause is a cause of the particular effect that is caused by it. Two ideas immediately come to mind. The first is the idea of a causal chain: there is a continuous causal chain from A’s firing to X’s death, as there is from B’s firing to Y’s death, whereas no such chains link A’s firing with Y’s death or B’s firing with X’s death. The second idea is that each gun when it was fired was at an appropriate distance and in appropriate orientation relative to the person it killed, but not to the person it did not kill. That is, spatial relations do the job of pairing causes with their effects. A moment of reflection shows that the causal chain idea will not work as an independent solution to the problem. A causal chain, after all, is a chain of causally connected events, and interpolating more cause‐effect pairs will obviously not solve the pairing problem. It is plausible to think that spatial relations, and more broadly spatio‐temporal relations, must play a role in generating pairing relations. Intuitively, space seems to have nice Page 4 of 28

Mental Causation causal properties; for example, as distance increases, causal influence diminishes, and it is often possible to set up barriers, at intermediate points, to block or impede the propagation of causal influence. In any case, I can state my fundamental assumption in general terms, and it is this: It is metaphysically possible for there to be two distinct physical objects, a and b, with the same intrinsic properties and hence the same causal potential or powers; further, one of these, say a, causes a third object, c, to change in a certain way but object b has no causal effect on c. Now, the fact that a, but not b, causes c to change must be grounded in some fact about a, b, and c. Since a and b have the same intrinsic properties, it must be their relational properties with respect to c that provide an explanation of their different (p. 33) causal roles vis‐à‐vis c. What relational properties, or relations, can do this job? The only plausible answer seems to be that it is the spatial relation between a and c, and that between b and c, that are responsible for the causal difference between a and b vis‐à‐vis c (a was in the right spatial relation to c; b was ‘too far away’ from c to exert any influence). At least, there is no other possible explanation that comes to mind. Later I will give an explanation of what it is about spatial relations that enables them to serve as causal‐pairing relations. Now consider the possibility of immaterial souls, outside physical space, causally interacting with material objects in space. The following again should be a metaphysically possible situation: Two souls that have the same intrinsic properties5 act in a certain way at the same time, and as a result a certain material object undergoes a change. Moreover, it is the action of one of the souls, not that of the other, that is the cause of the physical change. What makes it the case that this is so? What pairing relation pairs the first soul, but not the second, with the physical object? Since souls, as immaterial substances, are outside physical space, it is not possible to invoke spatial relations to do the pairing. What possible relations could provide causal pairings across the two domains, one of spatially located material things and the other of immaterial minds outside space? Consider a variation on the foregoing example: There are two physical objects, P 1 and P 2, with the same intrinsic properties, and an action of an immaterial soul causally affects one of them, say P 1, but not P 2. How can we explain this? Since P 1 and P 2 have identical intrinsic properties, they must have the same causal capacity (‘passive’ as well as ‘active’ causal powers), and it would seem that the only way to make them discernible in a causal context is their spatial relations to other things. Doesn't that mean that any pairing relation that could do the job in this case must be a spatial relation? If so, the pairing problem for this case is unsolvable, since the soul is not in space and cannot bear spatial relations to anything. The soul cannot be any ‘nearer’ to, or ‘more properly oriented’ toward, one physical object than another. Nor can we say that there is a causal barrier ‘between’ the soul and one of the physical objects but not the other; for what can ‘between’ mean as applied to something in space and something outside it? It is a total mystery what non‐spatial relations there can be that might help distinguish, from the point of view of an immaterial soul, between two intrinsically indiscernible physical objects.

Page 5 of 28

Mental Causation According to Descartes, the pineal gland is where the soul and the body meet for mutual causal action. The soul of course cannot literally be in the pineal gland, though it was claimed to move the gland to and fro and thereby initiate the motion of animal spirits. One implicit assumption here is that my mind acts on my pineal gland, and your mind acts on yours. More generally, a person is a ‘union’, Descartes said, of an immaterial mind and a material body, and, as noted, he claimed the idea of mind‐body union to be a primitive, per se intelligible notion. It is possible to construe this (p. 34) as Descartes's answer to the pairing problem. That is, in our foregoing example, what distinguishes the two souls in their causal relationship to a material thing, when this is a human body, is that the first, not the second, forms a ‘union’ with it. Moreover, through this union relationship with a material body your soul can causally reach other material things, since spatial relations are now available to do the causal pairings between your body and material things around it. Something like this may well seem to the committed dualist like a reasonable way out, but we can hardly accept it as a solution to the problem at hand. The reason is that mind‐body causation is implicitly, and ineliminably, involved in the notion of a union of a mind and a body. A mind is united with that body with which it is in ‘direct’ causal relation, that is, without another body or mind serving as a causal intermediary. This pineal gland, not that one, counts as mine precisely because my mind is in direct causal contact with it and only with it. It is difficult to see what other explanation is possible. Unless we understand mind‐body causation, therefore, we do not understand mind‐body union. And we do not understand mind–body causation unless we have a solution to the pairing problem for minds and bodies. Simply declaring mind‐body union a primitive and yet intelligible notion, as Descartes apparently did, does not help. But could there be causal interactions among immaterial minds? Ruling out mind‐body causation does not in itself rule out the possibility of an autonomous domain of immaterial minds in which minds are in causal commerce with other minds. Perhaps that is the picture of a purely spiritual afterlife offered by some religions and theologies. Is that a possibility? The pairing problem makes such an idea a dubious proposition. Again, any substance dualist who wants causation in the immaterial realm must allow the possibility of there being three mental substances, M 1, M 2, and M 3, such that M 1 and M 2 have the same intrinsic properties, and hence the same causal powers, and yet an action by M 1, but not the same action by M 2 at the same time, is causally responsible for a change in M 3. In such a situation, what pairing relation could connect M 1, but not M 2, with M 3? If causation is to be possible within the mental domain, there must be an intelligible and motivated answer to this question. But what mental relations could serve this purpose? It is difficult to think of any; I don't think we even know where to begin. Consider what space does for physical causation. In the kind of picture envisaged, where a physical thing causally acts on only one of the two objects with identical intrinsic properties, what distinguishes these two objects is their spatial locations. Space provides a principle of individuation of material objects. Pure qualities and causal powers do not. And what enables space to serve this role is the fact that physical objects occupying exactly the same location in space at the same time are one and the same object.6 This is in effect the venerable principle of ‘impenetrability of matter’, which can be understood Page 6 of 28

Mental Causation as an exclusion principle for space: Material things (p. 35) compete for, and exclude one another from, spatial regions. From this it follows that if physical objects a and b bear exactly the same spatial relations to some object c, a and b are one and the same object. This principle is what enables space to individuate material things with identical intrinsic properties. The same goes for causation in the mental domain. What is needed to solve the pairing problem for immaterial minds is a kind of mental coordinate system, a ‘mental space’, in which minds are each given a unique ‘location’ at a time. Further, a principle of ‘impenetrability of minds’ must hold in this mental coordinate system; that is, minds that occupy the same ‘location’ in this space must be one and the same. I don't think we have any idea how a mental space of this kind could be constructed.7 Moreover, even if we could develop such a space for immaterial minds, that still would fall short of a complete solution to the pairing problem; to solve it for causal relations across the mental and the physical domains, we would need to somehow coordinate the two spaces to yield unitary pairing relations across the domains. I doubt that we have any idea how something like this could be done. No wonder Descartes claimed the mind‐body union to be an unexplainable primitive. I believe the foregoing considerations constitute a compelling argument against a dualist metaphysics of immaterial minds and material bodies. What is eminently commonsensical and plausible in Descartes's interactionist dualism is his interactionism; it is his dualism that makes trouble for interactionism and ultimately sinks the ship.

1.2 Anomalous Monism and the Threat of Epiphenomenalism It appears that the topic of mental causation soon lost its prominence after the debate occasioned by Descartes's interactionist dualism. During the three centuries between the early debate on this issue in the seventeenth century and its re‐emergence as a major philosophical problematic in the late twentieth century there seem to have been only two philosophical episodes of any significance to us that touched on the issue: the first is T. H. Huxley's doctrine of epiphenomenalism during the late nineteenth century; the second is the emergentist claim of ‘downward’ causation in the mid‐twentieth century.8 Huxley, an eminent biologist who was well versed in philosophy, claimed that in both animals and humans conscious states are caused by ‘molecular changes’ in the brain but they have no power to cause anything else (Huxley 1874). According to him, all animal and human behaviour can be explained purely mechanically, or physiologically, without adverting to mental states—consciousness, emotions, volitions, and the like. In a paper published in (p. 36) 1967 the distinguished neurophysiologist Roger W. Sperry claimed that consciousness, although it arises out of neural processes, can somehow loop back and causally influence the course of lower‐level neural occurrences from which it has emerged (Sperry 1969). Note that both Huxley and Sperry were primarily scientists; it

Page 7 of 28

Mental Causation appears that for over three hundred years no philosopher of great prominence took up the issue of minds’ causal powers as a major philosophical problem. But everything changed in 1970 with the publication of Donald Davidson's ‘Mental Events’. The current debate on mental causation is a continuation of the debates triggered by Davidson's influential paper. A centrepiece of this paper is his ingenious argument for ‘anomalous monism’, and this argument struck more than a few philosophers as having unmistakable epiphenomenalist implications for the mental. This is what touched off the debate on mental causation that has continued to this day. Davidson's argument begins with the following premises: 1. Nomological character of causality. If event c causes event e, there is a ‘strict’ law that subsumes c and e. 2. Mind‐body causation. Some mental events cause, and are caused by, physical events. 3. Anomalism of the mental. The mental is anomalous—that is, there are no ‘strict’ laws concerning mental phenomena—neither purely psychological laws nor psychophysical laws. What is a ‘strict’ law? Strict laws are exceptionless and not hedged by ceteris paribus clauses. And laws, unlike mere empirical generalizations, are able to ground subjunctives and counterfactuals and confirmable by observation of positive instances (that is, they are inductively projectible). There is also the suggestion that strict laws are part of a ‘comprehensive’ and ‘complete’ theory over some domain (Davidson 1970: 219); but a precise construal of ‘strict’ in ‘strict laws’ will not concern us here. Note that if we take the mental/ physical dichotomy to be exhaustive (as Davidson seems to do), the anomalism of the mental implies that if there are any strict laws they will all be physical laws.9

The position Davidson calls anomalous monism is a monistic physicalism claiming that all individual mental events are physical events. An event is mental (or physical) just in case a mental (or physical) description, or predicate, is true of it—or, as we might say, in case it falls under a mental (or physical) kind. Let c be a mental event; in accordance with Premise 2 above, let us suppose that c is a cause of some physical event e. By the nomological character of causality (Premise 1), it follows that some strict law L must subsume c and e. But the anomalism of the mental (Premise 3) says that L cannot be a psychophysical law or a purely psychological law. So L must be a purely physical law. Since c and e are subsumed by a physical law, each must fall under a physical kind (or there must be a true physical description of each)—whence it follows that c, the mental event, is a physical event. More generally, it follows that all mental events causally connected with physical events are themselves physical (p. 37) events; and, since causation is transitive, those mental events that are not directly causally related to physical events are likely to be so related through other mental events. That, Davidson thinks, should pretty much cover almost all mental events. In fact, Davidson's argument can be made more general, yielding a stronger conclusion: it is plain that Premises 1 and 3, the nomological character of causality and the anomalism of the mental, together entail the proposition that any event (of any kind) that enters into a causal relation with another

Page 8 of 28

Mental Causation event (of any kind) is a physical event. This leaves out only events that are both causeless and effectless, and it seems safe enough to disregard them.10 The conclusion, in any case, is a form of physical monism: all mental events are physical events. This is a causal argument for physicalism—or, more precisely, token physicalism. As such it is reminiscent of Princess Elisabeth's remark to Descartes quoted above, that she would rather ‘concede matter and extension’ to the mind—that is, take the mind as something material—than accept the thesis that immaterial minds and material bodies can causally influence each other. The core idea shared by Davidson and Elisabeth is that the possibility of mind‐body causation requires minds to be physical. For Davidson, even mental‐to‐mental causation requires both cause and effect to be physical events. A number of philosophers,11 independently of one another and in a surprising unanimity, reacted negatively to Davidson's argument; what concerned them was the argument's apparent epiphenomenal implications for mental properties and kinds. Consider an individual mental event m. It is a mental event in virtue of the fact that it falls under some mental kind M (or a mental description, M, is true of it). But under Davidson's anomalous monism the fact that m falls under M—namely, it is the kind of mental event it is—seems wholly irrelevant to what causal relations m enters into. Event m’s causal relations are determined fully and exclusively by m’s physical properties, or the physical kinds under which it falls, because causal relations require strict laws and all strict laws are physical laws. The consequence seems to be that mental properties and kinds are causally irrelevant. If we were to redistribute mental properties over the domain of individual events any way we please, that would not change a single causal relation between the events of this world. To use Brian McLaughlin's useful terms (1989), Davidson's anomalism, while it is not token epiphenomenalism (that is, epiphenomenalism of individual mental events), is a form of type epiphenomenalism, since it gives no causal role to mental types or kinds. Or so Davidson's critics argued. Davidson and his critics have had exchanges on this charge of epiphenomenalism;12 however, discussions of mental causation have largely moved away from Davidson's anomalous monism. The problem of mental causation confronting Davidson is in essence to answer this question: If the mental is anomalous (that is, there are no laws about the mental), then, given that causation requires laws, how can mental events (p. 38) be causes or effects? The ensuing discussion helped to bring the general issue of epiphenomenalism to prominence, and philosophers began exploring the causal status of mental properties in a broader context. As a result, the focus of discussion has shifted to such questions as how mental causation is possible given that the physical world is causally closed (the physical‐causal‐closure problem), whether purported mental causes of physical events are excluded by physical causes (the exclusion problem), whether events can be systematically overdetermined by having both a mental and a physical cause (the overdetermination problem), and so on. We turn to these issues in the sections to follow.

Page 9 of 28

Mental Causation

1.3 The Exclusion and Supervenience Arguments Ontological dualism positing immaterial minds as entities in their own right has not been a serious option for most philosophers in contemporary philosophy of mind. The latter‐ day dualists are ontological physicalists who embrace a dualism of physical and non‐ physical properties. They believe that complex physical systems wholly composed of bits of matter can have non‐physical properties, properties that are neither properties investigated in physics nor reducible to them. Many property dualists hold that special‐ science properties in general, such as biological and geological properties, are no more physically reducible than mental properties. The proprietary properties of each special science are claimed to form an autonomous domain vis‐à‐vis fundamental physical properties and the properties of other special sciences.13 This has the important consequence that much of what we will say about mental causation under property dualism applies to causation in the special sciences in general. Let us now see how the spectre of epiphenomenalism has returned to haunt property dualists. To begin, most ontological physicalists will accept the following closure principle: Causal closure of the physical domain. If a physical event has a cause at t, it has a sufficient physical cause at t. To deny this would imply that there might be non‐physical causal agents, outside the physical domain, injecting causal influences into it, and that there might be physical events whose explanations must invoke these non‐physical causal agents and forces. If this were the case, theoretical physics would be in principle incompletable. Note that physical causal closure understood this way does not exclude non‐physical causes of physical effects; the closure principle only says that if there are to be such causes, there must also be sufficient physical causes. No non‐physical cause of a physical event is essential, and there is no need to go outside the physical domain to give a causal explanation of any physical event. Nor does the closure principle imply (p. 39) that every physical event has a cause; there could be uncaused physical events. In this sense, the closure thesis is consistent with the failure of physical determinism. Further, as far as closure goes, there may be all sorts of non‐physical entities and events, perhaps including mental ones, and there may be all kinds of interesting and significant causal relations among them. The only thing that physical causal closure protects is the causal and explanatory self‐sufficiency of the physical domain.

The dualist component of property dualism finds expression in the following proposition: Anti‐reductionism. Mental properties are distinct from, and irreducible to, physical properties. We can consider this alongside the following plausible metaphysical thesis:

Page 10 of 28

Mental Causation Causal exclusion. No event can have more than one sufficient cause occurring at any given time—unless it is a genuine case of causal overdetermination. Given these propositions as premises, we can quickly show that property dualism runs into trouble with mental causation.

Suppose some mental event, say an instance of mental property M, is a cause of a physical event, an instance of physical property P. (For simplicity and uniformity, we take events as instances, or instantiations, of properties; a mental event is an instance of a mental property at a time, and similarly for physical events.) By physical causal closure, there is a physical event, say an instance of P*, that is a sufficient cause of the instance of P. Anti‐reductionism entails that M ≠ P*, whence it follows that the mental cause of the P‐ instance must be distinct from its physical cause. And we may stipulate that this is not a genuine case of overdetermination; to contest this would result in the seemingly absurd claim that all cases of mental‐to‐physical causation are cases of systematic overdetermination involving a sufficient physical cause as well as the mental cause. At this point the causal‐exclusion principle applies, and we must exclude either the mental cause or the physical cause. Excluding the physical cause will not do any good, since if we try to retain the mental cause, physical causal closure will kick in again and bring back the excluded physical cause. The mental cause, therefore, must be let go. That is the argument. It applies to all forms of property dualism that accept physical causal closure. It is often referred to as an ‘exclusion argument’ because its point is that any putative mental cause of a physical event is always ‘excluded’, or ‘screened off’, by a physical cause. Physical causal closure implies that any putative non‐physical cause of a physical event will face competition from a physical event for causal status. The exclusion principle comes into play at this point, yielding the conclusion that in such competition the physical cause always prevails. The overall implication of the argument, therefore, is that mental events—and, more generally, all events in the special sciences—are epiphenomenal with respect to physical events. Property dualists come in two groups: those who accept mind‐body supervenience and those who do not. At this time most property dualists belong to the former, and among them are the so‐called non‐reductive physicalists. Ontological physicalism—or the rejection of non‐physical stuff, like Cartesian mental substance—is the first step (p. 40) toward physicalism. It is usually thought, however, that this is not nearly enough for physicalism, and that any robust physicalist must accept a strong dependence of mental properties on physical properties. It is customary to explain this dependence relation in terms of supervenience: Mental properties supervene on physical properties. For our present purposes, we may state this thesis in the following way: Mind‐body supervenience. Whenever something has a mental property, M, at t, it does so in virtue of the fact that it has, at t, a physical base property, P, where P necessitates M (that is, necessarily anything that has P at t has M at t).

Page 11 of 28

Mental Causation According to supervenience in this sense, there are no mental events or states that float free from physical processes; every mental phenomenon must be grounded in, or anchored to, some underlying physical base (presumably, a neural state). This means that mental states can occur only in systems that can have physical properties; namely, physical systems. This precludes Cartesian souls as subjects of mentality. Moreover, supervenience entails that any two things that are physically identical must be identical in all mental respects—to put it another way, physical twins are necessarily psychological twins as well. This captures the idea that the physical nature of a being wholly determines its mental nature. In these ways, mind‐body supervenience, as a physicalist thesis, goes well beyond ontological physicalism.

As noted, the exclusion argument presented above applies to all forms of property dualism, including those that do not accept supervenience. For property dualists who accept supervenience, in particular non‐reductive physicalists, we can develop a second argument that reveals a further epiphenomenalist implication of their position. The exclusion argument has shown that property dualism has the consequence that mental‐to‐ physical causation is not possible. The argument to follow will show that property dualism plus mind‐body supervenience is committed to epiphenomenalism tout court; that is, mental events are not capable of causing other mental events any more than causing physical events. Here is the argument: Suppose that an instance of mental property M causes an instance of mental property M*. From mind‐body supervenience it follows that M* has a physical property, P*, as its supervenience base. This means that the instantiation of P* at t is necessarily sufficient for M* to be instantiated at t, no matter what happened before t— and, in particular, as long as P* is there, M* will be there even if the M*‐instance's putative cause, the M‐instance, had not been there at all. This puts the causal status of the M‐instance vis‐à‐vis the M*‐instance in jeopardy. The only way to salvage the M‐ instance's claim to be a cause of the M*‐instance appears to be this: we say that the M‐ instance caused M* to instantiate by causing its supervenience‐base property P* to instantiate. This involves mental‐to‐physical causation: For any M‐instance to cause an M*‐instance, it must first cause a P*‐instance, where P* is a physical supervenience base of M*. More generally, the argument shows that, under supervenience, same‐level causation implies ‘downward’ causation. We may call this the ‘supervenience’ argument.14 (p. 41)

To conclude, then, the exclusion argument has shown that mental‐to‐physical causation is not possible. The supervenience argument shows that mental‐to‐mental causation is possible only if mental‐to‐physical causation is possible. The two arguments together, therefore, show that neither mental‐to‐physical nor mental‐to‐mental causation is possible —that is, the mental is epiphenomenal tout court.

Page 12 of 28

Mental Causation

1.4 Responses to the Exclusion/Supervenience Arguments What the two arguments purport to show is that the following four propositions are together inconsistent: (i) The physical domain is causally closed. (ii) Mental properties supervene on physical properties. (iii) Mental properties, states, events, etc. are causally efficacious. (iv) Mental properties do not reduce to physical properties. If you are persuaded by the arguments, you will have to reject at least one of the four propositions, and your choice will determine, to a significant degree, the kind of position you will occupy as regards the mind–body problem.

Who might want to reject (i), the physical causal closure? Emergentism is a form of property dualism that does exactly that; for the emergentists typically believe in ‘downward’ causation—they claim that emergent phenomena, like consciousness, once they have emerged from their ‘basal’ physical/biological conditions, can causally loop downward on to their own physical emergence bases and influence the course of events at the lower level (Sperry 1969; for discussion see Kim 1999). This is in clear violation of the causal closure of the physical domain, since emergentism considers emergent phenomena to be irreducible to and distinct from the (physical) phenomena from which they emerge. Whether or not emergentism so conceived is a coherent position is a question that has received some attention (see e.g. Kim 1999, 2006; O'Connor and Wong 2005); however, this goes beyond the scope of the present chapter. There are perhaps other ontological physicalists who would reject (i); there seems nothing in ontological physicalism per se that commits the position to (i). As for the possibility of rejecting (ii), some contemporary emergentists appear to be moving in this direction—often as a response to the exclusion/supervenience arguments seen as presenting difficulties to the view that emergent properties have their own distinctive causal powers (see e.g. Humphreys 1997a, 1997b; O'Connor and Wong 2005). No matter how this neo‐emergentist programme works itself out, it should be noted that classical British emergentists, in particular C. D. Broad, accepted the supervenience of emergent properties on their basal conditions (Broad 1925: 61, 64). (p. 42)

As noted, non‐reductive physicalists accept mind–body supervenience. For us, that is true by definition; the point, though, is that there are a large number of physicalists who fit the definition. Moreover, these philosophers will not regard giving up physical causal closure as an option; their physicalist commitment is too deep for that. What this means is that if they want to remain non‐reductivists, they must accept epiphenomenalism. This

Page 13 of 28

Mental Causation is a consequence that dooms non‐reductive physicalism. It is no wonder then that challenges to the exclusion/supervenience arguments come, by and large, from non‐ reductive physicalists. (We will consider some of these challenges in the next section.) As for physicalists who have no antecedent commitment to anti‐reductionism, the moral of the exclusion/supervenience arguments is that they face a choice between reductionism and epiphenomenalism. We must not forget physicalists who embrace mental eliminativism or irrealism.15 These physicalists probably have the easiest time of all: since mentality, for them, is not a real phenomenon, they could discard the whole package of (ii), (iii), and (iv). (There are senses of supervenience in which mind‐body supervenience holds trivially under mental irrealism, but that doesn't mean supervenience is something the irrealists should care about.) But most physicalists are not eliminativists, and so they must choose between reductionism and epiphenomenalism. A whole‐sale adoption of epiphenomenalism may be practically indistinguishable from mental irrealism; as the leading British emergentist Samuel Alexander remarked, to deprive the mental of causal powers is in effect to deprive it of reality (1920: 8). One possible response that should not be neglected is a partial rejection of (iv) combined with a partial rejection of (iii). For we should not think that the mental as a totality is either reducible or irreducible; it may well be that part of the mental is reducible, though not all of it is. It may well be—I believe this to be the case—that intentional/cognitive states are physically reducible while phenomenal aspects of conscious experience, or ‘qualia’, are not so reducible. A position like this has been defended by David Chalmers (1996; also Kim 2005). A physicalist who embraces a position like this must accept epiphenomenalism for the physically irreducible mental residue.

1.5 Objections to the Exclusion/Supervenience Arguments The two arguments have by no means gone unchallenged. In fact, numerous attempts have been made to refute them or, at least, to mitigate their epiphenomenalist implications for non‐reductive physicalism. We will briefly canvass some of (p. 43) the more important objections and criticisms, indicating their sources; however, we will not offer detailed discussions or replies. (i) The generalization objection: the exclusion/supervenience arguments show too much, and therefore they must be incorrect. If these arguments are sound, they generalize and will show not only that there is no mental causation, but also that there is no biological causation, no chemical causation, and no geological causation, leaving physical causation as the only causation that exists. In fact, not all physical causation we normally accept is safe because causal relations between macro‐level objects and events, such as a baseball

Page 14 of 28

Mental Causation breaking the window and an overnight cold spell freezing the lake, will give way to microphysical causation at the level of fundamental physics. This is absurd; the exclusion/ supervenience arguments cannot be correct (Van Gulick 1992: 325; Block 2003). This objection is called the generalization argument (Kim 1998). There are some points to be considered in reply. First, and the most important, is the fact that the objection, if correct, could only add to the success of the exclusion/supervenience arguments. The reason is that the arguments can be seen in two ways: (1) as an attempt to demonstrate epiphenomenalism, and (2) as a reductio against one of the premises of the arguments. We can agree with the proponents of the generalization objection that epiphenomenalism is false—not only in regard to mental properties but also biological, chemical, geological, and other special science properties. But then one of the premises must be rejected. Which one? A committed physicalist has only one choice: the anti‐reductionist premise. Reductionism wins. So if you are a non‐reductive physicalist, you are ill‐advised to attack the exclusion/supervenience arguments by deriving further unpalatable consequences. Second, the generalization argument moves too quickly, failing to consider the question whether or not special‐science properties in biology, chemistry, geology, and so on are reducible to physical properties. There is a strong initial intuition, though derided by some, that mental properties, especially the phenomenal properties of conscious experience (qualia) and the ‘aboutness’ of thoughts, are physically irreducible. I don't believe we have such dualist intuitions about biological or chemical properties. We should examine carefully the assumption, often all too readily made, that the properties investigated in the special sciences, such as biology and geology, are irreducible as well. We should be cautious—in fact, suspicious—about quick and loose arguments invoking the so‐called multiple realizability of special‐science properties.16 Third, whether or not the exclusion/supervenience arguments generalize to certain properties of the special sciences is one question; whether or not they generalize to macrophysical properties is another. What the arguments show is that physically supervenient and yet irreducible properties are epiphenomenal. Do macrophysical properties supervene on microphysical properties? This is a somewhat complex question that we must set aside (see Kim 1998, 2003, 2005; Noordhof 1999; Gillett and Rives 2001; Bontly 2002; Block 2003). (p. 44)

(ii) The causal‐drainage argument: current physics does not rule out the possibility that there is no fundamental, ‘bottom’ level in microphysics; if there is no bottom level, causal powers will drain away, and there will be no causation anywhere (Block 2003). In a way, this is a continuation of the preceding objection. It contends that what the exclusion/supervenience arguments show is that causation at one level gives way to causation at the next, lower level. This means that if there is a fundamental microphysical level, with absolutely basic particles (true metaphysical atoms), all causation will seep

Page 15 of 28

Mental Causation down and get deposited at this level. That would mean that there is causation only at the most fundamental micro‐level. But if there is no fundamental level, then the seepage of causal powers cannot be stopped, with the result that there is no causation anywhere. Full discussion of this interesting argument cannot be given here (see Block 2003; Kim 2003, 2005). It should be noted, though, that this objection, like the previous one, can only play into the reductionist's hand. For what the objection does is to continue the exclusion/supervenience arguments and derive further unwelcome consequences, reinforcing the need for a reductio. The situation remains the same for physicalists: they must choose between reductionism and epiphenomenalism. (iii) The exclusion/supervenience arguments rely on a ‘thick,’ productive/generative concept of causation; however, no such concept is countenanced in contemporary fundamental physics, and there is no reason to think there are generative causal relations anywhere in the world. This line of argument has been forcefully developed by Barry Loewer (2002). It is appropriate to raise questions about the concept of causation operative in the exclusion/ supervenience arguments, and to consider, in particular, the question of what sorts of causal concepts are required to underwrite causal exclusion and physical causal closure. I believe Loewer is correct in saying that a robust notion of generation and production is involved in the concept of causation driving the arguments. This raises a host of substantive questions. To begin, is it really true that the notion of causation as generation/production is absent from theoretical physics? We must distinguish physics from the mathematical equations and formalisms taken to express fundamental physical laws. It could be argued that it is our understanding and interpretation of these formalisms, especially in the context of explanation and practical control, that is crucial to the question of what sorts of causal concepts are operative in physics. Moreover, the mere fact that a generative concept of causation is not present at the fundamental microphysical level does not mean that it cannot appear at higher levels (perhaps like the directionality of time). Further, we care about mental causation, it seems to me, chiefly because we care about human agency, and evidently agency involves a productive/generative notion of causation. An agent is someone who brings about a state of affairs for reasons. If there indeed are no productive causal relations in the world, that would effectively take away agency—and our worries about mental causation along with it. An approach to causation that is quite congenial to the productive/generative view of causation is the conserved‐quantity account—that is, causation as energy flow or momentum transfer (see Quine 1973: 5; Fair 1979; Dowe 2000). David (p. 45) Papineau claims that the thesis of physical causal closure (or what he calls the ‘completeness’ of physics, which is close enough), which he takes to have had a critical role in ushering in physicalism as the reigning world‐view of the twentieth century, was closely tied to the wide acceptance of conservation laws of energy and momentum (2001). Also, the manipulative theory of causation, which views the relation of causation in terms of what Page 16 of 28

Mental Causation can be manipulated to produce a given change, seems congenial to the productive/ generative notion of causation. This is not surprising, because the intuitive idea motivating the manipulative approach is the fact that our interest in causation is rooted in our status as agents in the world. (For a detailed development of this approach see Woodward 2003.) In any case, these are substantive and important issues deserving of further explorations.17 (iv) We can show that mental causation exists on the basis of the Humean regularity account, the nomological account, or the counterfactual account of causation. No one would take it seriously if anyone were to suggest that there is no problem for mental causation since causation, as Hume is sometimes thought to have shown, is only a matter of regularities (or ‘constant conjunctions’) and there surely are mental‐physical regularities. Things don't improve much if this suggestion is strengthened by adding that these regularities must be nomological, with a modal force appropriate for laws of nature, and be able to support counterfactuals, be projectible, and so on. The reason is that non‐ causal nomological regularities can be generated by underlying causal processes, in the way regularities governing medical symptoms are generated by the progress of an underlying pathology. The crucial question, therefore, is whether these mind‐body regularities represent not just laws but causal laws. There surely are interesting and useful laws and regularities in the special sciences. According to the exclusion/ supervenience arguments, these regularities are not causal regularities, although they may arise from genuine underlying causal regularities; mental‐mental regularities are no more causal than the regular connections seen in a series of shadows cast by a moving car. Some appeal to the counterfactual approach to causation to show that mind‐body causal relations are unproblematic (see Baker 1993; Loewer 2002). In a simple case the argument would run like this: We can see that Sally's desire to get to the airport caused her to hail a cab because we see that the counterfactual ‘If Sally had not wanted to go to the airport, she wouldn't have hailed a cab’ is true. Here again we need to ask what grounds the truth of counterfactuals of this kind, and whether their truth always provides sufficient grounds for the attribution of a causal connection (in an appropriate direction). The counterfactual approach to causation has been controversial, though influential. One point to keep in mind is that there appears to be a general consensus that whatever the virtues of the counterfactual theory of causation may be, it cannot give us a productive/ generative relation of causation. (Of course, some advocates of the counterfactual approach, like Loewer, will not consider that a liability.) (p. 46)

(v) Overdetermination is a feasible option. It has been suggested by some that we should accept mental‐physical overdetermination; that is, the position that in every case in which a mental event causes a physical event (or any kind of event) there is also a physical cause of it. This proposal is a bit bizarre, and it is unclear whether, even if it can be defended, it should count as a sufficient vindication of mental causal efficacy. However, Page 17 of 28

Mental Causation the approach has been seriously argued by a number of advocates (see Mellor 1995: 103– 5; Mills 1996; Garrett 1998). (Papineau (2001: 26–8) criticizes this approach; see also Bennett 2003.) For further objections to and discussions of the exclusion/supervenience arguments see Sabates (2001), Menzies (2003), and Raymont (2003).

1.6 Functionalism and Mental Causation The functionalist view of the mind is still the most widely accepted approach to the nature of mentality, and it will be useful to consider how mental properties as conceived under functionalism fare in respect of causal efficacy. This question is important because functionalism is arguably the ‘official’ philosophy of cognitive science, and the issue of the causal efficacy of functionally conceived mental properties can have direct implications for the status of cognitive and psychological sciences and, in particular, the nature of laws and explanations in these sciences. Functionalism takes mental properties to be functional properties—properties defined in terms of the causal work they are supposed to perform, or ‘causal roles’. A bit more exactly, we can say that a property, F, is a functional property if it can be characterized by a definition (call it a functional definition) of the following form: x has property F at t = def. there exists some property P such that x has P at t, and input of kind J applied to x causes P to instantiate in x and P's instantiation in turn causes x to emit an output of kind K. Both input and output can be complex—that is, input can be a combination of various stimulus conditions and other mental states, and output can include further mental states as well as behaviour and physical changes. J and K are the two parameters that fix the kind of property F is. As an example, something like the following could qualify as a functional definition of pain (or being in pain):

x is in pain at t = def. there exists some property P such that x has P at t, and tissue damage or trauma to x causes P to instantiate in x and P's instantiation causes x to wince and groan and to enter into a state of distress.

Page 18 of 28

Mental Causation A human is in pain in virtue of having his C‐fibres stimulated, and for him C‐fibre stimulation is the property that fills the causal role specified in the functional definition of pain. So we say that C‐fibre stimulation is a realizer of the functional property of being in pain—it is a realizer for humans. But, as Hilary Putnam famously argued (p. 47) (1967), pain's realizer in octopuses is probably entirely different; it may well be that octopuses don't even have C‐fibres. Let's say then that O‐fiber stimulation is the realizer of pain in octopuses. If there were sentient Martians, their pain realizer might be X‐fibre stimulation. There is no upper bound to the number of possible realizers of a functional property. According to functionalism, this phenomenon of multiple realizability is the hallmark of mental properties, and it is what makes reductionist physicalism false. This is so because mental properties, say pain, cannot be reductively identified with any single physical realizer, say C‐fibre stimulation. Rather, mental properties as functional properties are ‘second‐order’ properties, at a higher level of abstraction; pain as functionally conceived abstracts away the physical/physiological details of its diverse multiple realizers, and focuses instead on the role it plays in the psychological economy of organisms. What all instances of pain have in common is not some single physical property or mechanism; it is the causal role they play in the psychologies of the organisms and systems endowed with ‘tissue damage detectors’.

Given this conception of a mental property, what can we say about its causal efficacy? Let us first note the following two evident points:18 (1) A given instance of pain has the same causal powers as the instance of its physical realizer. In general, the causal powers of an instance of a functional property F are identical with (or perhaps a subset of) the causal powers of its realizer. To put it another way, instances of a functional property ‘inherit’ their causal powers from their realizers. (This is sometimes called the causal‐inheritance principle.) (2) P1 and P2 count as diverse realizers because they are causally (and nomologically) diverse. If P1 and P2 have identical, or largely identical, causal powers, they should count as one property and one realizer (the principle of causal individuation of properties and kinds).

Page 19 of 28

Mental Causation From these two points it follows that pain, as a functional property, is highly heterogeneous as a causal type—as heterogeneous as its diverse physical realizers. Here we must count all nomologically possible realizers of pain, not just its actual realizers. Given this, it is difficult to believe that instances of pain—that is, all possible as well as actual instances—can have anything causally in common beyond the causal role definitive of pain; namely, their being caused by certain input conditions and their causing certain outputs. That is to say, pain as a causal category is in danger of losing its scientific interest, for it is unlikely to enter into any significant contingent lawlike regularities. The only general causal truth about all instances of pain may well be the analytic one that directly follows from its functional definition. To be sure, there may be interesting and significant regularities about human pains, or mammalian pains, or octopus pains; but that would be because humans, mammals, or octopuses each share the same, or similar, pain realizers, and there are likely to be significant empirical laws about each such realizer. This means that there is virtually no likelihood that there can be a scientific theory of pain as such, a theory that applies to all actual and (p. 48) nomologically possible pains. The same goes for the possibility of a theory of perception as such, of learning and memory as such, and so forth. What there can be—and what seems sufficient—is a theory of human pains, of octopus pains, and so on; and a theory of human learning and memory, of octopus learning and memory, of Martian learning and memory, and so on. If there are commonalities in the theory of human learning and the theory of octopus learning, that must be due to the shared features of the physical/biological realizers of learning in the two species (which in turn could be the results of parallel evolution in shared environments).

Another consequence of (1) and (2) worthy of note is this: psychological properties conceived as functional properties do not bring with them any new causal powers. All the causal powers they represent are those of their realizers. We do not have to say that this makes them epiphenomenal; it's only that no new and novel causal powers magically materialize at the psychological level, as the emergentists envisaged. Some have touted functionalism about the mental as a form—in fact, the principal form—of non‐reductive physicalism, a position that protects the autonomy of psychology—and other special sciences. But our results show that the autonomy purchased with functionalism does not amount to much: there is a good chance that psychology will be sundered into many psychologies along the lines dividing its many physical realizers, and these ‘local’ or ‘realizer‐specific’ psychologies are arguably reducible to the physical/biological theories of the underlying realizer states and processes.19

Page 20 of 28

Mental Causation

1.7 Further Issues Computationalism, the dominant ideology underlying much of cognitive‐science research today, views cognition as information processing, which in turn is construed as computation over mental representations. It has been pointed out, most forcefully by John Searle (1980), that computation is driven by the syntax of the representations, not their semantics—that is, by the shapes of the symbols over which computation takes place, not by what these symbols mean or represent. You feed the computer a string of 0s and 1s as input and the subsequent computation will return to you another string of 0s and 1s as output. This computation process is wholly insensitive to what the initial string of 0s and 1s represents—it could be the social‐security numbers of a group of people or it could be the weather conditions at the local airport—whereas we normally think of cognitive processes as dependent on the meanings, or representational contents, of the states involved. So if mental/cognitive processes are driven by semantics and computational processes are driven not by semantics but by syntax alone, how could mental/cognitive processes be computational processes? How could meaning and intentionality be generated by purely syntactic processes? (p. 49)

Essentially the same question arises when we think about how our propositional attitudes —states with contents (usually specified by declarative sentences)—can serve as causes. My belief that my turn is coming up for a dive from the high platform causes my muscles to go tense. My belief that I've just pulled off an excellent dive makes me sigh with relief. The two beliefs cause what they cause because of their contents. For the physicalist, what ultimately cause these events, the sighing and the onset of muscle tension, are neural events and states. As physicalists, we think of states of the brain as carrying contents— that is, as representing certain states of affairs—and it is now widely accepted that what particular content a given belief—that is, a given brain state—carries depends crucially on the causal/cognitive/historical relations that the subject bears to his external environment. This is content externalism. But, just like computational processes, brain processes—successions of causally connected mental states—seem entirely insensitive to what these states represent; they depend solely on the physical/biological configurations of these states. How one brain state causes another depends, it seems, only on the local physical/biological properties of these states, not at all on what these states might or might not represent. In particular, if content externalism is true, what the states represent is determined, at least in part but crucially, by the historical and environmental circumstances in which the subject has been embedded. But neural causation strikes us as being entirely local; that is, it depends only on what is here and now physically and biologically.

Page 21 of 28

Mental Causation So the problem is how to explain the causal efficacy of content. This is a complex problem; although there have been important and valuable contributions in this area, it is still essentially an open problem. I must conclude by listing some of the more significant works in this area: Allen (1995); Baker (1995); Crane (1988); Drestke (1988, 1998); Fodor (1987, 1989); Jacob (1997); Segal and Sober (1991); Yablo (1997).

References Alexander, S. (1920), Space, Time, and Deity, II (London: Macmillan). Allen, C. (1995), ‘It Isn't What You Think: A New Idea about Intentional Causation’, Noûs, 29: 115–26. Baker, L. (1993), ‘Metaphysics and Mental Causation’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 75–95. —— (1995), Explaining Attitudes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Bennett, K. (2003), ‘Why the Exclusion Problem Seems Intractable and How, Just Maybe, to Tract It’, Noûs, 37: 471–97. Bickle, J. (1998), Psychoneural Reduction (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Block, N. (1990), ‘Can the Mind Change the World?’, in G. Boolos (ed.), Meaning and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 137–70. —— (2003), ‘Do Causal Powers Drain Away?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67: 133–50. Bontly, T. D. (2002), ‘The Supervenience Argument Generalizes’, Philosophical Studies, 109: 75–96. Broad, C. D. (1925), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Campbell, D. (1974), ‘“Downward” Causation in Hierarchically Organized Biological Systems’, in F. J. Ayala and T. Dobzhansky (eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology (Berkley and Los Angeles, Calif.: University of California Press), 179–86. (p. 50)

Chalmers, D. J. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Churchland, P. M. (1981), ‘Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes’, Journal of Philosophy, 78: 67–90. Crane, T. (1998), ‘The Efficacy of Content: A Functionalist Theory’, in J. Bransen and S. E. Cuypers (eds.), Human Action, Deliberation and Causation (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 199–225.

Page 22 of 28

Mental Causation Davidson, D. (1970), ‘Mental Events’, in L. Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (Amherst, Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press), 79–101; repr. in Davidson, D. Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 207–25. —— (1993), ‘Thinking Causes’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3–17. Dennett, D. C. (1988), ‘Quining Qualia’, in A. J. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Contemporary Science (Oxford, Oxford University Press), 42–77. Descartes, R. (1641/1984), Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ii, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–398. —— (1931), The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1931). Dowe, P. (2000), Physical Causation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behaviour (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1998), ‘Minds, Machines, and Money: What Really Explains Behaviour’, in J. Bransen and S. E. Cuypers (eds.), Human Action, Deliberation and Causation (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 157–73. Fain, H. (1963), ‘Some Problems of Causal Explanation’, Mind, 72: 519–32. Fair, D. (1979), ‘Causation and the Flow of Energy’, Erkenntnis, 14: 219–50. Fodor, J. (1974), ‘Special Sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, Synthese, 28: 97–115. —— (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1989), ‘Making Mind Matter More’ Philosophical Topics, 17: 59–79. Foster, J. (1968), ‘Psychophysical Causal Relations’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 5: 64–70. —— (1989), ‘A Defence of Dualism’, in J. R. Smythies and J. Beloff (eds.), The Case for Dualism (Charlottesville, Va: University Press of Virginia). Garber, D. (2001), ‘Understanding Interaction: What Descartes Should Have Told Elisabeth’, in D. Garber (ed.), Descartes Embodied: Reading Cartesian Philosophy through Cartesian Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 168–88.

Page 23 of 28

Mental Causation Garrett, B. J. (1998), ‘Pluralism, Causation, and Overdetermination’, Synthese, 116: 355– 78. Gillett, C., and Rives, B. (2001), Does the Argument from Realization Generalize? Responses to Kim’, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39: 79–98. Hall, N. (2004), ‘Two concepts of causation’, in J. Collins, N. Hall, and L. A. Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 225–76. Humphreys, P. (1997a), ‘How Properties Emerge’, Philosophy of Science, 64: 1–17. —— (1997b), ‘Emergence, not Supervenience’, Philosophy of Science, 64: S337–45. Huxley, T. H. (1874), ‘On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and Its History’, Fortnightly Review, 16: 555–80; repr. in Huxley, Collected Essays, i (London: Macmillan, 1904), 199–250. (p. 51)

Jacob, P. (1997), What Minds Can Do (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Kim, J. (1973), ‘Causation, Nomic Subsumption, and the Concept of Event’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 217–36. —— (1992), ‘Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52: 1–26. —— (1993), ‘Can Supervenience and Non‐strict Laws Save Anomalous Monism?’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 19–26. —— (1998), Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind–Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1999), ‘Making Sense of Emergence’, Philosophical Studies, 95: 3–36. —— (2001), ‘Lonely Souls: Causality and Substance Dualism’, in K. Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 30–43. —— (2003), ‘Blocking Causal Drainage and Other Maintenance Chores with Mental Causation’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67: 128–53. —— (2005), Physicalism, or Something Near Enough (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). —— (2006), ‘Emergence: Core Ideas and Issues’, Synthese, 151: 547–59. Lepore, E., and Loewer, B. (1987), ‘Mind Matters’, Journal of Philosophy, 84: 630–42.

Page 24 of 28

Mental Causation Loewer, B. (2002), ‘Comments on Jaegwon Kim's Mind and the Physical World’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 655–62. McLaughlin, B. (1989), ‘Type Epiphenomenalism, Type Dualism, and the Causal Priority of the Physical’, Philosophical Perspectives, 3: 109–35. —— (1993), ‘On Davidson's Reply to the Charge of Epiphenomenalism’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 27–40. Mellor, D. H. (1995), The Facts of Causation (London: Routledge). Menzies, P. (2003), ‘The Causal Efficacy of Mental States’, in S. Walter and H.‐D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation (Exeter: Imprint Academic), 195– 223. Mills, E. (1996), ‘Interactionism and Overdetermination’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 33: 105–17. Noordhof, P. (1999), ‘Micro‐based Properties and the Supervenience Argument’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99: 109–14. O'Connor, T., and Wong, H. J. (2005), ‘The Metaphysics of Emergence’, Noûs, 39: 658–78. Papineau, D. (2001), ‘The Rise of Physicalism’, in C. Gillett and B. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 3–36. Polger, T. (2004), Natural Minds (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Putnam, H. (1967), ‘Psychological Predicates’, repr. as ‘The nature of mental states’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), 429–40. Quine, W. V. (1973), The Roots of Reference (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court). Raymont, P. (2003), ‘Kim on Closure, Exclusion and Non‐reductive Physicalism’, in S. Walter and H.‐D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation (Exeter: Imprint Academic), 225–42. Sabates, M. (2001), ‘Varieties of Exclusion’, Theoria, 16: 13–42. Searle, J. R. (1980), ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3: 417–24. Segal, G., and Sober, E. (1991), ‘The Causal Efficacy of Content’, Philosophical Studies, 63: 1–30. Shapiro, L. A. (2004), The Mind Incarnate (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Page 25 of 28

Mental Causation Sosa, E. (1993), ‘Davidson's Thinking Causes’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3–17. Sperry, R. W. (1969), ‘A Modified Concept of Consciousness’, Psychological Review, 76: 532–6. (p. 52)

Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Stoutland, F. (1980), ‘Oblique Causation and Reasons for Action’, Synthese, 43: 351–67. Van Gulick, R. (1992), ‘Three Bad Arguments for Intentional Property Epiphenomenalism’, Erkenntnis, 36: 311–32. Watson, R. A. (1987), The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities). Woodward, J. (2003), Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Yablo, S. (1992), ‘Mental Causation’, Philosophical Review, 101: 245–80. —— (1997), ‘Wide Causation’, Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 251–81.

Notes: (1) Descartes (1641/1984). The quotations are taken from The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1931). (2) This and other quotations from the correspondence between Princess Elisabeth and Descartes are taken from Garber (2001). The present quotation is from p. 172 (except for a correction of an apparent typo: in the last sentence ‘body’ has been replaced with ‘soul’). (3) Princess Elisabeth to Descartes, June 1643 (ibid.). (4) I will give only a brief sketch of the argument; for a fuller discussion see Kim (2001) or Kim (2005: ch. 3). I first discussed the pairing problem in Kim (1973). My reflections were prompted by Foster (1968). Foster was the first to discuss the pairing problem, but he believes that a substance dualist can live with it: see Foster (1989). Haskell Fain discussed a similar problem in Fain (1963). (5) If you are inclined to invoke the identity of intrinsic indiscernibles for souls to dissipate the issue, the next situation we will consider involves only one soul and the supposed remedy does not apply. Moreover, the pairing problem can be generated

Page 26 of 28

Mental Causation without assuming that there can be distinct intrinsic indiscernibles. This assumption, however, helps present the problem in a simple and compelling way. (6) There is the familiar problem of coincident objects—e.g. the statue and the bronze. Some claim that although these occupy the same region of space and coincide in many of their properties, they are distinct objects. I must set this problem aside, but it should be noted, though some will dispute this, that coincident objects share the same causal powers, except perhaps those associated with coming into being and going out of existence. (7) It will not help to try to bring souls into physical space and give them physical locations. For details see Kim (2001) or Kim (2005: ch. 3). (8) The term ‘downward causation’ is due to the biologist Donald Campbell, who introduced it in Campbell (1974). (9) In a later paper (1993) Davidson says that strict laws are found only in ‘developed physics’. (10) This amounts to the suggestion that Davidson's second premise be replaced by the statement that every mental event has either a cause or an effect. (11) Beginning with Stoutland (1980). (12) For a defence of Davidson see Lepore and Loewer (1987); for Davidson's own reply see Davidson (1993); for rejoinders and further discussion see Kim (1993), McLaughlin (1993), and Sosa (1993). (13) Thus, ‘property pluralism’ is a better name for this position than ‘property dualism’. (14) In many places I have combined the two arguments as one and called it the ‘supervenience’ argument. This combined argument is also called the ‘exclusion’ argument in the literature. See Kim (1998) and Kim (2005). I believe that the usage I am suggesting here is an improvement—more apt and clarifying. See also Yablo (1992). (15) Mental eliminativism in regard to intentional states is represented in, e.g., Churchland (1981) and Stich (1983). Dennett (1988) is probably the best‐known source of mental irrealism regarding qualitative consciousness. (16) On multiple realization and reduction see Fodor (1974); Kim (1992); Bickle (1998); Polger (2004); Shapiro (2004). (17) Hall (2004) is a useful discussion in thinking about these issues. (18) I discussed these points and related issues in Kim (1992). (19) For further discussion of functionalism and mental causation see Block (1990).

Page 27 of 28

Mental Causation

Jaegwon Kim

Jaegwon Kim is William Herbert Perry Faunce Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Brown University.

Page 28 of 28

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism

Oxford Handbooks Online The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism   David Papineau The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0003

Abstract and Keywords Over the latter half of the last century English-speaking philosophy became increasingly committed to naturalistic doctrines. Much of this naturalistic turn can be attributed to the widespread acceptance of the thesis that the physical realm is causally closed. This article contains four sections. The first section offers an initial formulation of the thesis that physics is causally closed and explains its immediate implications. The second section then discusses the evidence for the thesis from a historical perspective. The third section considers ways of making the thesis properly precise. Finally, the fourth section explores the connections between the thesis and the more general issue of naturalism. Keywords: naturalistic doctrines, physics, causal relation, naturalism, causal closure, causal–closure thesis

Introduction OVER

the latter half of the last century English‐speaking philosophy became increasingly

committed to naturalistic doctrines. Much of this naturalistic turn can be attributed to the widespread acceptance of the thesis that the physical realm is causally closed. This chapter will contain four sections. Section 2.1 offers an initial formulation of the thesis that physics is causally closed and explains its immediate implications. Section 2.2 then discusses the evidence for the thesis from a historical perspective. Section 2.3 considers ways of making the thesis properly precise. Finally, Section 2.4 explores the connections between the thesis and the more general issue of naturalism.

Page 1 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism

2.1 Causal Closure and its Immediate Implications At first pass the causal closure of physics says that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause. If this thesis is true, it distinguishes physics from all other subject (p. 54) domains. The biological realm, for example, is not causally closed in this sense, since biological effects often have non‐biological causes, as when the impact of a meteorite precipitated the extinction of the dinosaurs. Again, meteorology is not causally closed: the burning of carbon fuels—a non‐meteorological event—is causing global warming. Nor, importantly, is the mental realm causally closed: a mental pain can be caused by sitting on a physical drawing pin, or a train of thought can be interrupted by a loud noise. Physics, by contrast, does seem to be causally closed. If you consider any physical effect, then there will arguably always be some prior sufficient physical cause: we expect to be able to account for physical effects without leaving the physical realm itself. In particular, this seems to hold even for physical effects which take place within the bodies of conscious beings. When the muscle fibres in my arm contract, this is presumably due to electrochemical activity in my nerves, which is due to prior physical activity in my motor cortex, and so on. In principle, it would seem possible to account for this entire sequence solely in terms of the resources offered by physics itself, and without making any essential appeal to any other subject matter. (Isn't the causal closure of physics undermined by quantum‐mechanical indeterminism? Well, quantum mechanics does call for a more careful formulation of the causal‐closure thesis, but this doesn't matter for the philosophical implications. Let us shelve this complication until Section 2.3.) The causal closure of physics is solely a claim about how things go within physics itself. It does not assert that everything is physical, but only that those things that are physical have a physical cause. So it does not rule out realms of reality that are quite distinct from the physical realm. It is entirely consistent with the causal closure of physics that there should be self‐sufficient realms that operate quite independently of physical goings‐on (a realm of ghostly spirits, say). The causal closure of the physical says only that when we are within the physical realm we will find that every physical effect has a physical cause. Even so, the causal closure of the physical does give rise to a powerful argument for reducing many prima facie non‐physical realms to physics: for it indicates that anything that has a causal impact on the physical realm must itself be physical. This is because the causal closure of the physical seems to leave no room for anything non‐physical to make a causal difference to the physical realm, since it specifies that every physical effect already has a physical cause. To see the significance of this point, note that many prima facie non‐physical realms— such as the biological, meteorological, and mental realms—certainly do seem to have physical effects. Not only are these realms causally affected by physical events, as noted Page 2 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism above, but they in turn exert a causal influence on the physical realm. An infection (biological) can cause a physical rise in temperature; a hurricane (meteorological) can destroy physical houses; my current thoughts (mental) can give rise to physical movements of my fingers on a keyboard. However, the causal closure of the physical says that these physical effects must already have physical causes: the rise in temperature will be caused by cellular‐level chemical processes; the houses' destruction by fast‐moving gases; the movements of my fingers by neuronal activity (p. 55) in my brain. How then can the infection, the hurricane, and my thoughts also make a causal difference? The causal closure of the physical would seem to leave no room for these prima facie non‐ physical causes to matter to the physical effects. Unless, that is, we identify the prima facie non‐physical causes with the physical causes. If we equate the infection, hurricane, and thoughts with the cell‐level activity, fast‐moving gases, and neuronal activity respectively, then their causal efficacy will be respected. The biological, meteorological, and mental causes won't be eclipsed by the physical causes, simply because they will be one and the same as the physical causes—they will be ‘non‐physical’ only in the sense that they are normally referred to using specialist (biological, meteorological, mental) terminology, and not because they are ontologically different. The thesis of the causal closure of the physical thus argues that many prima facie non‐ physical occurrences—all those that exert an influence on the physical realm—must themselves in fact be physical. For otherwise it is hard to see how they could have any physical effects.

2.2 A Historical Perspective on the Evidence for the Causal Closure of Physics Why should we believe in the causal closure of physics (which for the moment I shall regard as the simple claim that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause)? It doesn't look as if this is an a priori matter—there is nothing conceptually contradictory in the idea that physical phenomena may be affected by non‐physical causes, as Descartes supposed, for example. So the causal closure of physics, if true, must somehow follow from the findings of science. But exactly which findings? Which part of science, if any, argues that the physical is causally closed? At first sight it might seem as if causal closure follows from the presence of conservation laws in physics: if there are laws specifying that important physical quantities stay constant over time, won't this show that the later values of physical quantities must be determined by earlier values? However, it depends on what conservation laws you have. Not any set of physical‐conservation laws rules out non‐physical causes for physical effects.

Page 3 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism Consider Descartes's early seventeenth‐century physics. This was based on a conservation law, but nevertheless allowed the non‐physical mind to affect the physical brain. The central principle of Descartes's physics was the conservation of amount of motion, which Descartes took to be the product of the masses of all bodies and their scalar speeds. (So amount of motion is different from momentum, which is the product of mass and vectorial velocity: a car going round a bend at a constant speed conserves amount of motion but not momentum.) In line with Descartes's mind–body interactionism, the conservation of amount of motion leaves plenty of (p. 56) room for non‐physical causes to intrude on the physical realm. In particular, if mental causes (operating in the pineal gland?) cause particles of matter to change their direction (but not their speed), then this will not in any way violate the conservation of amount of motion. Descartes's physics might allow an independent mind to affect the brain, but Descartes's physics is wrong. Later in the seventeenth century Leibniz replaced Descartes's law of the conservation of ‘motion’ with the two modern laws of conservation of (vectorial) momentum and of (scalar) kinetic energy, and thereby arrived at what we now regard as the correct laws governing impacts. Now, Leibniz's physics, unlike Descartes's, did indeed imply that the later values of all physical quantities are determined by their earlier values, and therewith the causal closure of the physical. Leibniz thus faced the argument outlined in my first section above: How can a non‐physical mind have physical effects, given that the causal closure of the physical seems to leave no room for anything non‐ physical to make a causal difference to the physical realm (see Woolhouse 1985)? However, Leibniz did not draw the modern physicalist conclusion that the mind must therefore be identical to the brain. Rather, he denied that the mind in fact has any physical effects. Since it seemed incontrovertible to him that mind and brain must be ontologically separate, he instead inferred from the causal closure of the physical that the mind is impotent to affect the physical world. (It only appears to do so because of the ‘pre‐established harmony’ with which God has arranged both the mental and physical worlds.) While Leibniz's physics implies the causal closure of the physical, this is not true of the Newtonian system of physics that replaced it at the end of the seventeenth century. The crucial difference is that, where Leibniz upheld the central principle of the ‘mechanical philosophy’ and maintained that all changes of velocity are due to impacts between material particles, Newton allowed that accelerations can also be caused by disembodied forces, such as the force of gravity. Moreover, Newton's system was quite open‐ended about the range of different forces that exist. In addition to gravity, Newton and his followers came to recognize magnetic forces, chemical forces, forces of adhesion—and indeed vital and mental forces, which arose specifically in living bodies and sentient brains respectively. If we count vital and mental forces as ‘non‐physical’ (we shall return to this point in the next section), then the admission of such forces undermines the causal closure of the physical. For it means that physical effects, in the form of accelerations of particles of matter, will sometimes be due to the operation of non‐physical vital or mental

Page 4 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism causes. Given this, Newtonian science once more allowed that a non‐physical mind can influence the physical world. Doesn't Newtonian physics coincide with Leibniz's at least to the extent of upholding the conservation of momentum and energy? So why don't these principles imply the causal closure of the physical, as they did for Leibniz? The answer is that Newton's physics differs from Leibniz's in the way the conservation of energy must be understood. Leibniz upheld the conservation of kinetic energy. However, the existence of Newtonian force fields means that this quantity is not always conserved: for example, two bodies receding from each other will slow down due to their mutual gravitational (p. 57) attraction, and so lose kinetic energy. Newtonian energy conservation specifies rather that the sum of kinetic and potential energy is constant. Potential energy is the latent energy stored when bodies are ‘in tension’ in force fields, as when two receding gravitating bodies cease to move apart and are about to accelerate together again. The notion of potential energy was not prominent in early Newtonian physics, but by the middle of the nineteenth century physicists concluded that all forces operated so as to conserve the sum of potential and kinetic energy—any loss of kinetic energy would mean a rise in potential energy, and vice versa. The emergence of this modern version of the ‘conservation of energy’ placed strong restrictions on what kinds of forces can exist, but it by no means rules out vital and mental forces. Provided that the fields of these forces store in latent form any losses of kinetic energy they occasion (cf. the notion of ‘nervous energy’), the presence of non‐ physical forces will be perfectly consistent with the conservation of kinetic plus potential energy. True, the conservation of kinetic plus potential energy does apparently imply that all forces must be governed by deterministic force laws (otherwise what would ensure that they always ‘paid back’ any kinetic energy they ‘borrowed’?) and this greatly exercised many Victorian thinkers, especially given that nothing in early Newtonian physics had ruled out spontaneously arising mental forces. But, even so, the Newtonian conservation of energy does not stop deterministic vital and mental forces affecting the physical realm. Nevertheless, during the late nineteenth and the twentieth centuries an increasing number of scientists have come to doubt the existence of vital and mental forces. The most significant evidence seems to have come directly from physiology and molecular biology, rather than from physics. Over the last hundred and fifty years a great deal has come to be known about the workings of biological systems (including brains), and there has been no indication that anything other than basic physical forces is needed to account for their operation. In particular, the twentieth century has seen an explosion of knowledge about processes occurring within cells, and here too there is no evidence of anything other than familiar physical chemistry. The result has been that the overwhelming majority of scientists now reject vital and mental forces, and accept the causal closure of the physical realm (see Papineau 2002: app.; see also McLaughlin 1992).

Page 5 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism

2.3 The Causal‐Closure Thesis Refined The causal‐closure thesis presupposes some prior concept of the physical realm. Some commentators argue that the unclarity of this concept empties the causal‐closure thesis of content (Crane and Mellor 1990). At first sight it might seem that ‘physical’ can be defined by reference to the fundamental categories of physical theory. However, this strategy generates an awkward dilemma for advocates of the causal‐closure thesis (Hempel 1980). On the one hand, they can equate ‘physical’ with the category of phenomena recognized by current (p. 58) physical theory. But then it seems implausible that ‘physics’ in this sense is closed: past form suggests very strongly that physics will in time come to posit various new fundamental causal categories. Alternatively, advocates of causal closure might wish to equate ‘physical’ with the ontology of some ideal future physical theory. But then it is hard to see how the causal closure of the ‘physical’ could have any current philosophical significance, given that we are as yet quite ignorant of exactly what this ideal future physical theory will include. However, this dilemma is by no means inescapable. True, neither current physics nor ideal future physics gives us a suitable notion of ‘physics’ for framing the causal‐closure thesis. But this does not mean there are no other notions of ‘physics’ that will serve this purpose. Indeed there are arguably a number of different ways of understanding ‘physics’ that will yield a well‐evidenced and contentful causal‐closure thesis (Jackson 1998: 7–8). For a start, we could simply define ‘physical’ as not sui generis mental or biological. This understanding of ‘physical’ was in effect assumed at the end of the last section, in the argument that the non‐existence of vital or mental forces establishes the causal closure of physics. Note that nothing in that argument assumed a definitive list of fundamental physical categories; rather the thought was simply that this list would not include any sui generis mental or vital entities. This is a relatively inclusive understanding of ‘physical’: it counts as a ‘physical’ cause anything that isn't mental or vital, and to this extent renders the causal closure of the physical a relatively weak thesis. But even so it remains a thesis of much philosophical interest, since it still argues that any mental or vital causes of physical effects must be identical to causes that are not themselves sui generis mental or vital. A rather stronger reading of ‘physical’ would take it to cover any categories of the same general kind as are recognized by current physical theory. The idea here is to understand ‘physical’ as referring to some mathematically characterizable set of primary qualities, recognizably descended from the categories of modern physics, even if not identical to them. On this reading the list of fundamental ‘physical’ categories will be taken to include not just anything non‐vital‐or‐mental, but more specifically items that display the same kind of simplicity as the categories of contemporary physics. Again, there seems good

Page 6 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism reason to suppose that ‘physics’ in this sense is casually closed, and therefore that anything which in this sense has ‘physical’ effects must itself be ‘physical’. Finally, and even more specifically, there is the option of equating ‘physical’ with microscopic. Modern physical theory characteristically deals with fundamental entities that are very small. Given this, we might define ‘physical’ as referring to anything that is composed of entities below a certain size (Pettit 1993). The causal‐closure thesis will then hold that every effect that is microscopically constituted must have a cause that is similarly microscopically constituted. Again, this thesis seems plausible, and argues that everything that has microscopically constituted effects must itself be microscopically constituted. (p. 59)

Apart from worries about the meaning of ‘physical’, there are various other complications with the causal‐closure thesis. So far this thesis has been presented fairly informally. A more careful formulation would be this: Every physical effect has an immediate sufficient physical cause, in so far as it has a sufficient physical cause at all. Consider first the requirement that the physical cause be ‘immediate’. This is needed to rule out the possibility of physical causes which produce their physical effects only via non‐physical intermediaries. Imagine, for example, that every bodily movement is indeed fully determined by some prior brain state, but that these brain states only produce the bodily movements indirectly, by first producing some sui generis mental effect, which then affects the nervous system, and so on (see Lowe 2000). This set‐up would ensure that every bodily movement had some (indirect) sufficient physical cause—namely, the prior brain state—but intuitively it wouldn't ensure the causal closure of physics, since it wouldn't require that the direct causes of physical effects must be physical, and therefore wouldn't ensure that every physical effect had a purely physical prior history. The requirement that every physical effect have an immediate physical cause will rule out any mixed physical/mental/physical histories of this kind, since it ensures that any physical effect has an immediately prior physical cause, which in turn has an immediately prior physical cause, and so on.

Now consider the requirement that the physical cause be ‘sufficient’. This is needed to ensure that it causes the physical effect by itself, and not solely in virtue of its conjunction with some sui generis non‐physical cause. Imagine, for example, that some neuronal activity is caused by the conjunction of some chemical state and some sui generis mental cause. Then that neuronal activity would have a physical cause (the chemical state), but this cause would not have sufficed on its own, in the absence of the sui generis mental factor. This is clearly less than we need for a philosophically significant closure thesis. To make sure we have the right kind of closure thesis, we thus need to require that every physical effect have a physical cause that suffices on its own. However, this last requirement now highlights the need for the final qualification entered above—that every physical effect has a sufficient immediate physical cause ‘in so far as it

Page 7 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism has a sufficient immediate cause at all’. The reason for this latter qualification is to accommodate the indeterminism of modern quantum mechanics, which tells us that certain physical effects are random, without any sufficient determining cause. At first sight it might seem as if this qualification will empty the causal‐closure thesis of any interest, and in particular prevent it from implying that everything with physical effects must itself be physical. For it might seem that quantum indeterminism creates room for sui generis non‐physical causes (operations of the will, perhaps) to exert a ‘downwards’ influence on the physical realm, by influencing whether or not random quantum events occur. However, this appearance is illusory. Quantum mechanics still specifies that random physical effects have their probabilities fixed by sufficient immediate physical causes. If we understand the causal closure of the physical as covering this kind of physical determination of physical probabilities, (p. 60) then it will once more rule out any sui generis non‐physical cause for a physical effect. For any such sui generis cause would have to make a difference to the probability of the relevant physical effect, and this would once more run counter to the causal‐closure thesis, understood now as implying that this probability is already fixed by some sufficient immediate physical cause.

2.4 Causal Closure and Naturalism At its most general, philosophical naturalism is the view that philosophy is continuous with the natural sciences. This view can usefully be divided into two parts: methodological naturalism, which asserts that philosophy uses the same methods of investigation as the natural sciences, and ontological naturalism, which says that the subject matter of philosophy coincides with that of the natural sciences. The thesis that physics is causally closed bears on both these aspects of naturalism. In this section I shall first comment briefly on the relation between causal closure and methodological naturalism; after that I shall turn to its connection with ontological naturalism. The most immediate way in which causal closure bears on methodological naturalism is by itself providing an important illustration of the methodological thesis. Recall how Section 2.2 showed the causal‐closure thesis to be a highly empirical claim, whose acceptance derives from detailed empirical evidence about the causes of physical effects. This clearly does not stop the causal‐closure thesis from having substantial philosophical consequences for the nature of mind and other philosophically interesting categories. Methodological naturalists will say that this is a prime example of the way that philosophical results, just like scientific results, characteristically depend on empirical findings. The causal closure of physics also promises to bring philosophy into close contact with science at a more detailed level. The causal‐closure thesis promises to show that the general run of prima facie non‐physical entities are in fact physical. If this is right, then Page 8 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism we can expect specific scientific findings to illuminate many familiar subjects of philosophical enquiry. To the extent that philosophically interesting categories are physically constituted, we can look to scientific investigation to uncover their underlying physical natures. Exactly how far scientific investigation will be able illuminate such categories, however, will depend on whether the causal‐closure thesis really does show them to be physically constituted, and if so in what precise sense. So far we have not looked very closely at the argument from causal closure to physical constitution. There is plenty of room for debate about the range of items to which this argument applies, and about the precise sense in which it shows these items to be physical. This now brings us to the bearing of the causal‐ closure thesis on ontological naturalism. In the rest of this final section I shall examine exactly what the causal‐closure thesis implies about the physical constitution of reality. (p. 61)

It will be convenient to proceed in two stages. First I shall consider those items to which the causal‐closure thesis applies directly; namely, those entities that have physical effects. After that I shall consider whether the causal‐closure thesis has any implications for entities that are not themselves physically efficacious. Take some prima facie non‐physical cause that has a physical effect. According to the causal‐closure thesis, this physical effect already has a sufficient physical cause. So, on pain of deeming this effect to have two independent causes, we need somehow to collapse the non‐physical cause into the physical cause. But what exactly does this require? There are different views about what is needed to render the two causes indistinct. A minimum requirement is that the two causes be token identical, in the sense that they both involve the same spatio‐temporal particulars. If some thought and some brain state are both to be counted as the cause of my fingers moving over the keyboard, say, then it seems clear that these causes cannot involve spatio‐temporally divergent particulars. If they did, then we would have a substantial dualism of causes, a pair of causes involving different particular substances. Still, it is generally agreed that token identity on its own is not enough to rule out a divergence of causes. It may rule out ‘substance dualism’, but it does not yet exclude ‘property dualism’. To see why, note that token identity is a very weak doctrine, since it does not imply any relationship at all between the properties involved in the physical and non‐physical causes—it is enough that the same particular entity should possess both these properties. In this sense, my height is token identical with my weight, since these properties are both possessed by the same particular; namely, me. Yet it seems wrong to conclude on this account that my height causes what my weight causes. Similarly, it seems unwarranted to conclude that my thoughts cause what my brain states cause, simply on the grounds that these causes must involve the same particulars. Causes are in

Page 9 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism some sense property‐involving, and any claim that two causes coincide will require that the properties they involve are in some sense also coincident. So much is widely agreed by contemporary philosophers of mind. At this point, however, consensus ends. One school holds that the causal argument requires type identity, the strict identity of the relevant properties of the non‐physical cause with some physical properties of the physical cause. They are opposed by those who say that it is enough if the non‐physical properties metaphysically supervene on the physical ones. Type identity is the most obvious way to ensure that non‐physical and physical causes do not comprise two distinct causes: if exactly the same particulars and properties comprise a non‐physical and a physical cause, the two causes will certainly themselves be fully identical. Still, type identity is a very strong doctrine. Type identity about thoughts, for example, would imply that the property of thinking about the square root of two is identical with some physical property. And this seems highly implausible. Even if all human beings with this thought must be distinguished by some common physical property of their brains—which itself seems highly unlikely—there remains the argument that other life forms, or intelligent androids, (p. 62) will also be able to think about the square root of two, even though their brains may share no significant physical properties with ours. This ‘variable realization’ argument has led many philosophers to seek an alternative way of reconciling the efficacy of non‐physical causes with the causal‐closure thesis, one which does not require the strict identity of non‐physical and physical properties. They suggest that it is enough if the non‐physical properties metaphysically supervene on the physical ones. According to this doctrine, a being's physical properties will fix its non‐ physical properties, in the sense that any two beings who share physical properties will necessarily share the same non‐physical properties, even though the physical properties which so ‘realize’ the non‐physical ones can be different in different beings. This arguably ensures that nothing more is required for any specific instantiation of a non‐physical property than its physical realization—even God could not have created my brain states without thereby creating my thoughts—yet avoids any reductive identification of non‐ physical properties with physical ones. (Those who hold that non‐physical properties generally supervene on physical ones are therefore called ‘non‐reductive physicalists’. For discussion of this position, see the essays in Kim 1993.) It is clear that the causal‐closure thesis requires at least metaphysical supervenience. If non‐physical properties do not so much as metaphysically supervene on physical properties, then non‐physical causes will be manifestly independent of physical causes. (For example, my thoughts will be genuinely extra to my brain states, in the sense that my brain states could possibly have existed without my thoughts.) And, given the causal‐ closure thesis, this would mean that any physical effects of non‐physical causes would have two quite independent causes, the non‐supervenient non‐physical cause, as well as the physical cause guaranteed by the causal‐closure thesis. Such rampant overdetermination seems absurd. Sometimes specific events are overdetermined by two Page 10 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism independent causes, each of which would have sufficed on its own—as when someone dies because they are shot and struck by lightning simultaneously. But it seems quite wrong to hold that all the physical effects of non‐physical causes are similarly overdetermined by two independent causes. Still, is metaphysical supervenience enough to avoid an implication of unacceptable overdetermination? Advocates of type identity insist that it is not. If non‐physical properties merely supervene on physical properties, they are not the same properties, and the causes which involve these properties cannot be identical. If two beings can both be thinking about the square root of two, even though they share no physical properties, then their so thinking cannot be identical to their possession of any physical property. Advocates of type identity thus argue that supervenience without identity still leaves the physical effect of any non‐physical cause with two distinct causes, the physical cause guaranteed by the causal‐closure thesis, and the distinct non‐physical cause, and this itself is unacceptable (see Kim 1993). The issue here hinges on the acceptability of different kinds of overdetermination. All can agree that ‘strong overdetermination’ is absurd—the physical effects of non‐physical causes surely don't always have two quite independent causes—and (p. 63) thus that causal closure implies at least the metaphysical supervenience of the non‐physical on the physical cause. But this leaves open the possibility of ‘weak overdetermination’, with the relevant physical effects always having both a physical cause and a supervenient but distinguishable non‐physical cause. Opinions differ on the acceptability of weak overdetermination. Advocates of type identity argue that this is just as absurd as strong overdetermination. (What difference can the non‐physical cause make, once the physical cause has done its work?) Friends of supervenience counter that there is nothing wrong with weak overdetermination. (In particular, it doesn't seem to carry the unhappy implication that the result would have occurred anyway, even if one of the causes had been absent—for the supervenience relation seems tight enough to ensure that both causes would have been absent if either were; see Bennett 2003.) Given the plausibility of the arguments for variable realization, the majority of contemporary philosophers probably favour supervenience over type identity. Note how this considerably dilutes the ontological implications of the causal‐closure thesis. It is one thing to hold that any causally efficacious non‐physical property must be type identical with some physical property. It is far weaker to claim that any such non‐physical property must supervene on physical properties. A wide range of different kinds of non‐physical properties arguably satisfy the latter requirement. In particular, to return briefly to the methodological aspect of naturalism, it is by no means obvious that any property that supervenes on physical properties must be the kind of property that is open to scientific investigation. True, the most familiar kind of supervenient properties are functional properties, properties which are constituted by the role they play in some system of scientific laws, and these by their nature are appropriate objects of scientific investigation. But functional properties are by no means the only kind of properties that

Page 11 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism can be held to supervene on physical properties. For example, various kinds of properties that are constituted by normative facts are widely held to supervene on the physical, and it is doubtful that these are appropriate objects of scientific investigation. Let me now turn to properties that are not themselves physically efficacious, and so escape the immediate impact of the causal‐closure thesis. As observed in section 4.1, the causal closure of physics itself leaves it quite open that there should be non‐physical realms which are causally isolated from the physical—a realm of ghostly spirits, perhaps. The argument from causal closure bites only on those items that do have physical effects, implying that they can only have those effects if they are themselves physical. This now opens the possibility that there are features of reality that do not even supervene on the physical realm, notwithstanding the causal closure of physics. There are two philosophically significant options to consider under this heading: first, epiphenomenal mental kinds; second, commonsensically non‐causal kinds like mathematics, modality, and morality. The first option relates specifically to conscious mental states. Pretheoretically, these might be supposed to have physical effects (most obviously of a behavioural kind) and therefore to supervene on the physical realm. But many philosophers feel that (p. 64) there are compelling reasons to deny that conscious properties are metaphysically supervenient on the physical. (Aren't zombies metaphysically possible—beings who share all your physical states yet have no conscious life at all?) Given causal closure, this non‐ supervenience threatens to imply strong overdetermination of all the physical effects of conscious causes—unless, that is, we conclude that conscious causes don't have physical effects after all. This epiphenomenalism option has been explored by various contemporary philosophers. Persuaded that conscious properties can't possibly be physical, they conclude that conscious states must be causal ‘danglers’, causal upshots of brain processes, but without any effects themselves (see Jackson 1982; Chalmers 1996). (Other philosophers, perhaps the majority, run the argument the other way, sticking to the claim that conscious properties have behavioural effects, and concluding that they must therefore supervene on the physical, despite initial philosophical impressions to the contrary.) Now consider mathematical, modal, and moral facts. Here there is plenty of room from the start to doubt that they have physical effects. Mathematical entities are abstract, outside space and time; modal facts concern realms of possibility other than the actual; moral facts seem to transcend any natural facts. If it follows from such considerations that these facts have no physical effects, then they escape the argument for physicalism. Causal closure argues that anything with a physical effect must itself be physical. But this carries no immediate implications for mathematical, modal, or moral facts, if they lack physical effects. For all that has been argued so far, they need have no particular relation to the physical world at all.

Page 12 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism The idea of facts without physical effects does face other difficulties, however. In particular, there are obvious epistemological queries about such facts. If mathematical, modal, and moral facts—or, for that matter, epiphenomenal conscious facts—lack any physical effects, then how can we possibly know about them? The standard route to knowledge of the actual world is via perception, or at least via some kind of causal interaction between our cognitive systems and the facts known about. And since our cognitive systems are physically realized, this would seem to require that the facts known about have physical effects. This makes it hard to see how we can know about realms of reality which lack physical effects. This argument is not conclusive. There remains the option that we can know about these realms a priori, or in some other way that does not require causal interaction. A number of contemporary philosophers defend theories along these lines. Still, it is not always obvious that such non‐causal epistemologies can be made to work. An alternative response to the epistemological difficulties is to conclude that the putative non‐causal entities do not really exist, and that our discourse about them is no more than a useful fiction. In addition, there remains the option of insisting that the problematic area is metaphysically supervenient on the physical after all, and so capable of interacting physically with our cognitive systems. Let me conclude by summing up this final section. The causal‐closure thesis argues that anything with physical effects must in some sense be physical. There may be room in reality for non‐physical things that lack physical effects, but it is not obvious that we can have knowledge of such things. However, even if our knowledge (p. 65) is restricted to physical things, the requirement of physicality is not necessarily as demanding as it may seem. Some take it to require type identity between physical and prima facie non‐physical properties. But as many hold that it only requires the metaphysical supervenience of the prima facie non‐physical on the physical, and this is a far weaker requirement.

References Bennett, K. (2003), ‘Why the Exclusion Problem Seems Intractable, and How, Just Maybe, to Tract It’, Noûs, 37: 471–97. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: in Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Crane, T., and Mellor, D. (1990), ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’, Mind, 99: 185– 206. Hempel, C. (1980), ‘Comments on Goodman's Ways of Worldmaking’, Synthese, 45: 193– 99. Jackson, F. (1982), ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36.

Page 13 of 14

The Causal Closure of the Physical and Naturalism —— (1998), From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Kim, J. (1993), Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Lowe, E. (2000), ‘Causal Closure Principles and Emergentism’, Philosophy, 75: 571–85. McLaughlin, B. (1992), ‘The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism’, in A. Beckerman, H. Flohr, and J. Kim (eds.), Emergence or Reduction (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 49–93). Papineau, D. (2002), Thinking About Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Pettit, P. (1993), ‘A Definition of Physicalism’, Analysis, 53: 213–23. Woolhouse, R. (1985), ‘Leibniz's Reaction to Cartesian Interaction’, Procedings of the Aristotelian Society, 86: 69–82.

David Papineau

David Papineau is a professor of Philosophy at King's College, University of London.

Page 14 of 14

Dualism

Oxford Handbooks Online Dualism   E. J. Lowe The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, History of Western Philosophy (Post-Classical), Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0004

Abstract and Keywords Dualism in contemporary philosophy of mind comes in many different varieties, but following long-standing tradition is normally divided into two main kinds: substance dualism and property dualism, the former maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical substances and the latter maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical properties. By a substance, in this context, is standardly meant an individual object, or bearer of properties, not a kind of stuff. However, much of the contemporary debate concerning dualism in fact focuses on the relationship between mental and physical events or states, largely because it is these that are commonly supposed to be the relata of causal relations and causal considerations play a very important role in that debate. This might lead one to suppose that a third main kind of dualism should be recognized, namely event or state dualism, maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical events or states. Keywords: dualism, contemporary philosophy, substance dualism, property dualism, mental substances, individual object

Page 1 of 21

Dualism DUALISM

in contemporary philosophy of mind comes in many different varieties, but

following long‐standing tradition is normally divided into two main kinds: substance dualism and property dualism, the former maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical substances and the latter maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical properties. By a substance, in this context, is standardly meant an individual object, or bearer of properties, not a kind of stuff. However, much of the contemporary debate concerning dualism in fact focuses on the relationship between mental and physical events or states, largely because it is these that are commonly supposed to be the relata of causal relations and causal considerations play a very important role in that debate. This might lead one to suppose that a third main kind of dualism should be recognized, namely event or state dualism, maintaining the distinctness of mental and physical events or states. The reason why no such third kind of dualism is generally recognized is that it is generally assumed that events and states do not comprise a fundamental ontological category, because an event or state just consists in the possession of a property (in some cases, a relational property) by a substance at a time (see especially Kim 1980). That assumption has not gone entirely unquestioned, however, and there are some philosophers who maintain that events do comprise a fundamental category of entities, on a par with—or even in place of—that of substances or objects (see further Lowe 2002: ch. 13). In what follows I shall try as far as possible not to take sides on this issue when I discuss the relationship between mental and physical events or states. I shall also continue to gloss over any distinction that might be thought to obtain between events and states themselves, such as that events involve change while states do not. Substance dualism, I have just said, maintains that mental and physical substances are distinct. But what are we to understand by a mental or physical substance in this context? I have already explained that by a substance, here, we are to understand (p. 67) an individual object or bearer of properties. By a mental substance, then, we are to understand a bearer of mental or psychological properties, and by a physical substance we are to understand a bearer of physical properties. So, by this account at least, we can see that, whether we are talking about substance dualism or property dualism in the philosophy of mind, the fundamental distinction in play is the distinction between mental and physical properties. The property dualist holds that mental and physical properties are distinct, while the substance dualist additionally holds that the bearers of those properties are distinct. This being so, what is crucially needed at this point is a precise and defensible account of the notion of a mental property, on the one hand, and that of a physical property, on the other. These are, it seems clear, distinct notions, although whether the properties of which they are notions are themselves distinct is, of course, one of the main points at issue. However, it is one thing to say that these notions are distinct —which would, I think, be almost universally accepted—and quite another to provide an account of that notional distinction that would be to everyone's satisfaction. In fact, it has proved remarkably difficult to produce an uncontentious characterization of either notion. Some, but by no means all, philosophers have been happy to adopt Brentano's contention that intentionality is the mark of the mental, for example (see Brentano 1874/1995 and, for a modern defence, Crane 2001). Similarly, the proposal that physical properties are Page 2 of 21

Dualism those that form the subject matter of the science of physics (whether contemporary physics, or an ideal or ‘completed’ physics)—or which, at least, depend ontologically upon the properties studied by physics—is controversial, even if widely espoused. (For doubts see Crane and Mellor 1990.) Fortunately, it is much easier to provide paradigm examples of mental and physical properties which almost all parties to the debate will be happy to accept as such. For instance, pain and desire are universally recognized as being mental properties, while mass and velocity are universally recognized as being physical properties. In what follows I shall take it for granted that the notional distinction now at issue is a genuine one and that for practical purposes it can be captured by appeal to such paradigm examples. This accepted, let us return to the topic of substance dualism. The adherents of substance dualism, as I have so far characterized it, contend that the bearers of mental properties, such as pain and desire, are distinct from—that is, are not to be identified with—the bearers of physical properties, such as mass and velocity. What are these ‘bearers’, though? Well, the bearers of mental properties might be called, quite generally, subjects of experience—understanding ‘experience’ here in a broad sense, to include not just sensory and perceptual experience, but also introspective and cognitive states (‘inner’ awareness and thought) (see further Lowe 1996: ch. 1). Human persons—we ourselves— provide prime examples of subjects of experience, but no doubt we should also include examples drawn from the ‘higher’ reaches of the non‐human animal domain. I am not insisting, then, that a subject of experience be capable of reason or self‐reflection, even though possession of these capacities is very arguably a necessary condition of personhood. Nonetheless, in what follows I shall normally be assuming that we are talking about subjects of experience like ourselves; that is, persons. As for the bearers of physical properties, for the purposes of (p. 68) the present discussion I shall mostly be referring to bodies, or parts of bodies—on the understanding that what we are talking about here are not mere lumps or masses of matter, but organized bodies and their parts, the paradigm examples being the human body and its organic parts, such as the brain and the neurons and other kinds of cell making up the brain and central nervous system. In these terms, then, the substance dualist may be construed as holding that a person is not to be identified with his or her body, nor with any part of it, such as the brain. On this view, a person—not the person's body or brain—feels pain and has desires, even if it is true to say that a person feels pain or has desires only because his or her body or brain is in a certain physical state. The physical state in question—a certain pattern of excitation in nerve cells, say—is not to be identified with the pain or desire consequently experienced by the person, according to the substance dualist. A property dualist could and no doubt would agree with this latter claim, however, while not accepting the further claim that the person experiencing the pain or desire is distinct from that person's body or any part of it. For the time being I shall focus on this further claim that is distinctive of substance dualism, and return later to the common ground between substance and property dualism. For, clearly, no argument to the effect that mental events or states

Page 3 of 21

Dualism cannot be identified with physical events or states can suffice to establish the truth of substance dualism, as opposed to the weaker doctrine of property dualism. At this point I need to draw a distinction, for which I have not so far catered, between two types of substance dualism. An apparent implication of what I have said so far concerning substance dualism may be that, according to it, a bearer of mental properties—a subject of experience—only bears mental properties, just as a bearer of physical properties, such as a human body or brain, only bears physical properties. This was indeed the view of the most famous substance dualist of all, René Descartes, for whom the human self or ego is an immaterial substance (see Descartes 1641/1984 and, for prominent modern sympathizers, Swinburne 1986 and Foster 1991). However, even if I am distinct from—not to be identified with—my body or any part of it, as Descartes held, it does not automatically follow that I can have only mental, not physical, properties. And, indeed, there is a modern form of substance dualism—which may be called, aptly enough, non‐ Cartesian substance dualism—which differs from Cartesian substance dualism precisely over this point. According to non‐Cartesian substance dualism, it is I, and not my body nor any part of it, who am the bearer of mental properties, just as Descartes maintained. However, unlike Descartes, the non‐Cartesian substance dualist does not make the further claim that I am not the bearer of any physical properties whatsoever. This sort of substance dualist may maintain that I possess certain physical properties in virtue of possessing a body that possesses those properties: that, for instance, I have a certain shape and size for this reason, and that for this reason I have a certain velocity when my body moves (see Lowe 1996: ch. 2 and also Baker 2000). It doesn't follow that such a substance dualist should allow that every physical property possessed by my body is also possessed by me, however, for some of these properties may entail that the thing possessing them is a body—and the non‐Cartesian substance dualist wants to deny, of course, (p. 69) that I am a body. One such property, for instance, would appear to be the property of being wholly composed of bodily parts, which is possessed by my body but presumably not by me. Prescinding, for the time being, from the distinction between Cartesian and non‐ Cartesian substance dualism, what sorts of arguments can be advanced in favour of such dualism, and how good are they? Some of the best‐known arguments have been inherited from Descartes himself and hence their contemporary versions may be described as ‘neo‐ Cartesian’. Two neo‐Cartesian arguments in particular are worthy of consideration: an argument from the conceivability of disembodiment and an argument from the indivisibility of the self. For brevity's sake, I shall call them the conceivability argument and the indivisibility argument respectively. The conceivability argument has both a strong and weak version, the difference in strength being a difference in the strength of their premises—that is to say, the premises of the strong version of the argument entail those of the weak version, but not vice versa. That being so, one might suppose that the weak version is to be preferred, because it assumes less. The weak version may be constructed as follows:

Page 4 of 21

Dualism (1) It is clearly and distinctly conceivable that I should exist without possessing a body. (2) What is clearly and distinctly conceivable is possible. Hence (3) It is possible that I should exist without possessing a body. (4) If it is possible that I should exist without possessing a body, then I must be distinct from my body. Therefore (5) I am distinct from my body. The strong version of the argument replaces premise (1) by

(1*) It is clearly and distinctly conceivable that I should exist without any body whatever existing. which clearly entails (1) (see Meixner 2004: ch. 3). The historical source of (1*) is, of course, Cartesian doubt about the very existence of the physical world in its entirety—a doubt which at least appears to be coherent and therefore to describe a possible state of affairs. As I say, one might suppose the weak version of the argument to be preferable to the strong version because it assumes less. However, it could be contended that (1) is only plausible, or at least is most plausible, in the context of (1*), on the grounds that it is difficult to conceive of oneself as existing in a disembodied state save under the hypothesis that the existence of the entire physical world is an illusion.

Whether we consider the strong or the weak version of the conceivability argument, it presents certain difficulties. First, in order to be valid it needs to be supplemented by a further premise; namely, (4+) My body is necessarily a body. Why? Because, clearly, if my body is not necessarily a body, then I cannot assume that a possible world in which I exist without possessing a body is one in which I am distinct from my body: for in that world my body might still exist and be identical (p. 70) with me, without being a body (see Merricks 1994). However, (4+) should not be regarded as particularly controversial, I think. This is because it is very plausible to maintain that it is an essential property of any entity that it belongs to a certain ontological category, such as the category of bodies. To suppose that my body might not have been a body is rather like supposing that the number 2 might not have been a number, and seemingly absurd for the same reason.

Much more controversial is premise (2), that what is clearly and distinctly conceivable is possible. (For well‐informed discussion see Gendler and Hawthorne 2002.) Let us grant the truth of premise (1*), that it is clearly and distinctly conceivable that I should exist without any body whatever existing, basing this claim on the coherence of Cartesian doubt about the existence of the physical world. The content of such doubt is something like this: Perhaps, for all that I know, the entire physical world as it seems to be presented to me in perception is non‐existent and that perception is wholly illusory. This is a doubt about the nature of the actual world, amounting to a surmise that the actual world contains no physical objects although it does contain me and my mental states. I am inclined to think that the surmise is at least a coherent, or logically consistent, one. But the question is whether this is enough to establish that there is a possible world in which I and my mental states exist but no physical objects exist. Of course, if the surmise is correct, then the actual world is just such a world. But we are not given that the surmise Page 5 of 21

Dualism is correct, only that it is coherent. To this it may be replied that it suffices that the surmise could be correct—it doesn't have actually to be correct. But the trouble, I think, is that we simply don’t know whether or not it could be correct, because there may, for all we know, be some reason why it couldn't be correct—a reason that we haven't yet thought of. For instance, it might be that there simply couldn't be a world containing no physical objects, whether or not it also contained me and my mental states. We might sum up this response to the conceivability argument by saying that the trouble with premise (2) is that it illicitly conflates ‘real’ or metaphysical possibility with mere epistemic possibility. That is to say, (2) together with either (1) or (1*) does not serve to ground the truth of (3), that it is possible that I should exist without possessing a body, in the requisite sense of ‘possible’. The most that can be established by these means is that I might actually exist without possessing a body, in an epistemic sense of ‘might’. This is the sense of ‘might’ in which we can say, for instance, that there might be an even number greater than 2 which is not the sum of two prime numbers, because we don't know whether or not Goldbach's conjecture is true. But in the metaphysical sense of ‘necessary’, it is either necessarily the case or else necessarily not the case that every even number greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers, so the matter is not in this sense a contingent one. Likewise, then, we cannot assume that it is a contingent matter whether or not I possess a body just because it is true that, in the epistemic sense, I might or might not possess a body. Let me pass on now to the indivisibility argument. This may be constructed as follows.

(p. 71)

(6) I contain no parts into which I am divisible. (7) My body, being spatially extended, is necessarily divisible into parts. Therefore (5) I am distinct from my body. In this case both premises are open to question, although (7) less obviously so than (6). With regard to (7), although it is indeed plausible to say that any extended region of space is divisible into smaller subregions, it is not self‐evident that any object exactly occupying that larger region must as a consequence be composed of parts occupying the smaller subregions. Of course, if the object in question were wholly composed of homogeneous and infinitely divisible matter, this would indeed be a consequence. But modern physics does not support the supposition that matter of this kind exists. Indeed, it would appear that the so‐called fundamental particles postulated by modern physics, such as the electron, are neither point‐like (since that would imply that they possessed an infinite energy‐density) nor composed of anything smaller. So it would seem that they provide actual counter‐examples to the assumption underlying premise (7). Even so, whether or not that questionable assumption is correct, it seems evident enough that my body is in fact divisible into parts of which it is composed—and so for the purposes of the indivisibility argument we can replace the contentious (7) by the uncontentious

(7*) My body is composed of parts.

Page 6 of 21

Dualism As for premise (6), however, it may now appear to be straightforwardly question‐begging, since it simply denies that I possess a property that (7*) uncontentiously attributes to my body— namely, the property of being a composite entity—and hence, it may be said, already presumes the truth of the conclusion, (5), that I and my body are distinct. Certainly, if the indivisibility argument is to acquire any persuasive force, an independent reason needs to be advanced in support of premise (6).

My own view, I should say, is that premise (6) is indeed true, but that the most plausible argument for its truth requires (5) as a premise, so that (6) cannot without circularity be appealed to in an argument for the truth of (5). If (5) is to be successfully argued for, then, we need to look elsewhere than to the indivisibility argument. I shall suggest an alternative shortly. As for my chief reason for thinking (6) to be true—that is, for holding the self to be a simple or non‐composite entity—it is that I consider the following argument (and note that its first premise includes (5) as a conjunct) to be not just valid but sound. (For a fuller account see Lowe 2001.) (8) I am not identical with my body nor with any part of it. (9) If I am composed of parts, all of those parts must be parts of my (10) Anything that is wholly composed of parts of my body must either itself be a part of my body or else be identical with my body as a whole. Hence (11) I am a simple entity, not composed of any parts, which is another way of expressing (6). The crucial premise here is, of course, (8), to which I shall return in a moment. As for premise (9), this should be uncontentious (p. 72) in the context of a debate between substance dualism and its physicalist opponents, since they will naturally agree with (9), holding as they do that I am identical with my body or some part of it, such as my brain. Premise (10) seems equally uncontentious—but more of that in a moment. I should acknowledge, however, that not all substance dualists will be happy to assert premise (9). Some, for instance, adopt the following view of the self: they hold that I am distinct from—not identical with—my body, but am composed of it and another, immaterial, entity: my soul. On this view I am a body–soul composite. (For discussion and criticism see Olson 2001 and Kim 2001.) Such a composite is still a ‘substance’—that is, an individual object or property‐bearer—but one which, in violation of premise (9), contains both parts of my body and something else, my soul, as parts. Indeed, Descartes himself sometimes writes as if he endorses this view. I can only say that I find it implausible and unattractive myself.

Another kind of substance dualist will reject premise (10), holding that I am wholly composed of parts of my body and yet am not identical with any part of it nor with my body as a whole. This kind of substance dualist sees the relation between me and my body as being analogous to that between a bronze statue and the lump of bronze of which it is made. On this view I am constituted by, but not identical with, my body (see especially Baker 2000). And, indeed, the example of the bronze statue may be seen as posing a threat to a generalized version of (10). For doesn't it show that it simply isn’t true that anything that is wholly composed of parts of an object x must either itself be a part of x or else be identical with x as a whole? For the bronze statue, it may be said, is wholly composed of parts of the lump of bronze and yet is neither itself a part of the lump of bronze nor identical with the lump of bronze as a whole. However, here a great deal turns on the question of how, precisely, we are to understand the assertion that the bronze Page 7 of 21

Dualism statue is ‘wholly composed of parts of the lump of bronze’. If the assertion is taken to mean that we can decompose the statue into parts all of which, without remainder, were parts of the lump of bronze, then it is certainly true. For we can decompose the statue into bronze particles, all of which were parts of the lump. But if, instead, the assertion is taken to mean that all of the parts of the statue are also parts of the lump of bronze— which is, mutatis mutandis, the interpretation that I was assuming in proposing premise (10)—then it is far from evident that it is true. For example: the head of the statue— assuming it to be a statue of a man—is a part of the statue and yet is not, plausibly, a part of the lump of bronze (see further Lowe 2001). However, is it not open to the constitution theorist to agree, now, with premise (10), interpreted in the manner I intend and instead reject premise (9), although not for the same reason that this was rejected by the proponent of the body–soul‐composite theory? Cannot the constitution theorist say that, just as the statue has parts, such as its head, that are not parts of the lump of bronze, so I have parts that are not parts of my body— but not because I have any immaterial part or parts, any more than the statue has. In principle, I agree, the constitution theorist could say this. However, I simply don't see what these ‘additional’ parts could at all plausibly be. The reason why the statue has parts that are not parts of the lump of bronze is that it (p. 73) has parts—such as its head —that are, like the statue, constituted by, but not identical with, a portion of bronze. If, analogously, I were to have parts that are not parts of my body, they would have to be parts that are constituted by, but not identical with, parts of my body—just as, according to the constitution theorist, I am constituted by my body as a whole. But there are, surely, no such parts of me—no parts of me that are related to parts of my body in the way that I am related to my body as a whole. As a self or subject of experience I do not, for example, have lesser or subordinate selves or subjects as parts of me, each of them associated with different parts of my body—as though I were a kind of collective or corporate self, on the model of a company or club. (For more on the latter notion see Scruton 1989.) At least, it certainly doesn't seem that way to me! Now I need to return to unfinished business—the search for a plausible argument in favour of the main claim of substance dualism, that I am not identical with my body nor with any part of it. This was premise (8) of my argument for the simplicity of the self. We have seen that neither the conceivability argument nor the indivisibility argument is satisfactory for the present purpose. I believe, however, that a much more compelling consideration in favour of (8) is this: (12) My identity‐conditions differ from those of my body or any part of it.

Page 8 of 21

Dualism Entities possessing different identity‐conditions cannot be identified with one another, on pain of contradiction (see further Lowe 1989: ch. 4). But what are ‘identity‐conditions’? Speaking quite generally, the identity‐conditions of entities of a kind K are the conditions whose satisfaction is necessary and sufficient for an entity x of kind K and an entity y of kind K to be identical; that is, for them to be one and the same K. Thus, for example, the identity‐conditions of sets are these: a set x and a set y are one and the same set if and only if x and y have exactly the same members. In the case of things that persist through time, their identity‐conditions will also provide their persistence‐conditions, since a thing persists through time just in case that same thing exists at every succeeding moment during some interval of time. Now, there are, of course, notorious difficulties attaching to the question of personal identity, and particularly to the question of what conditions are necessary and sufficient for the identity of the self over time. However, even without being able to settle this question, we may well be in a position to determine that the identity‐conditions of the self, whatever they may be, are different from those of the body or any part of it, such as the brain.

Here is one sort of consideration that seems quite compelling in this respect. We know already that parts of the human body can be replaced by artificial substitutes which serve the same function more or less equally well, as far as the person possessing that body is concerned. For example, a ‘bionic’ arm can replace a natural arm and serve the person who owns it pretty much as well as the original did. And, indeed, it seems perfectly possible in principle that every part of a person's biological body should, bit by bit, be replaced in this fashion, with nerve cells gradually being replaced by, say, electronic circuits mimicking their natural function (see Lowe 1989: 120; Baker 2000: 122–3). If such a procedure were carried out completely, as it seems it (p. 74) could be, the person whose biological body had been replaced by an entirely artificial one would, very plausibly, survive the procedure and so still exist at the end of it. And yet, clearly, neither that biological body nor any part of it would have survived and still exist. If correct, this shows that the persistence‐conditions of human persons are different from those of their biological bodies and their various parts, such as their biological brains, and hence that such persons—we ourselves—are not identical with those bodies nor with any of their parts. In short, it establishes the truth of (8), the main claim of substance dualism. (I should emphasize, however, that the cogency of claim (12) and the consequent support that it provides for (8) do not stand or fall with the success of the preceding argument, since there may be many other ways to show that my identity‐conditions differ from those of my body or any part of it.) Notice, however, that the foregoing argument for substance dualism—the replacement argument, as we may call it—while it serves the purposes of non‐Cartesian substance dualism well enough, is not sufficient to establish the truth of Cartesian substance dualism, since the latter maintains that the self possesses only mental properties, not any physical ones. For the replacement argument doesn't show that the self could survive in a completely disembodied state and hence doesn't show that the self might exist even in circumstances in which no physical properties whatever, such as shape or mass, could possibly be attributed to it. The conceivability argument does purport to show this, of course, but has been found wanting in persuasive force. As for the indivisibility argument,

Page 9 of 21

Dualism it, like the replacement argument, cannot be used specifically in support of Cartesian dualism, even setting aside the other difficulties that attach to it—for its conclusion is only that I am distinct from my body, not that I lack, or could lack, any physical properties whatever. Although, as we have seen, the indivisibility argument is unsatisfactory, there is another argument that is in some ways reminiscent of it but which, I think, deserves considerably more respect. I also think that it is even more compelling than the replacement argument, since it does not depend upon speculations which at present, it might be said, belong only to the realm of science fiction. I shall call this the unity argument—the unity in question being the unity of the self as the unique subject of all and only its own experiences. The first premise of the unity argument is (13) I am the subject of all and only my own mental states, which is surely a self‐evident truth.

The second premise is (14) Neither my body as a whole nor any part of it could be the subject of all and only my own mental states. The conclusion is, once again,

(8) I am not identical with my body nor with any part of it. Of course, (14) is the crucial premise, so let us see how it might be defended. First, then, observe that my body as a whole does not need to exist in order for me to have each and every one of the mental states that I do in fact have. If, for instance, I were to lack the tip of one of my little fingers, I might as a consequence lack some of (p. 75) the mental states that I do in fact have, but surely not all of them. I might perhaps lack a certain mildly painful sensation in the fingertip—a sensation that I do in fact have—but many of my other mental states could surely be exactly the same as they actually are, such as the thoughts that I am in fact having in composing this essay. Indeed, I could still even have that sensation ‘in my fingertip’, because the phenomenon of ‘phantom’ pain is a well‐attested one. However, I venture to affirm that no entity can qualify as the subject of certain mental states if those mental states could exist in the absence of that entity. After all, I certainly qualify as the subject of my mental states, as (13) asserts, but for that very reason those mental states could not exist in my absence. Mental states must always have a subject—some being whose mental states they are—and the mental states that in fact belong to one subject could not have belonged to another, let alone to no subject at all (see further Strawson 1959: ch. 3; Lowe 1996: ch. 2). But, as we have just seen, many and quite possibly all of my own mental states could exist even if my body as a whole were not to exist—that is to say, even if certain parts that my body actually possesses were not to exist. This, I suggest, indicates that my body as a whole cannot qualify as the subject of all and only my own mental states and so cannot be identified with me.

Now, many physicalists may agree with my reasoning so far but draw the conclusion that, rather than being identical with my body as a whole, I am identical with some part of it, the most obvious candidate being my brain. However, it is easy to see that the foregoing reasoning can now just be repeated, replacing ‘my body as a whole’ by ‘my brain as a whole’ throughout. For it seems clear that, although I may well need to have a brain in Page 10 of 21

Dualism order to have mental states, neither my brain as a whole nor any distinguished part of it is such that it needs to exist in order for me to have each and every one of the mental states that I do in fact have. Indeed, even if each and every one of my mental states depends upon some part of my brain, it by no means follows, of course, that there is some part of my brain upon which each and every one of my mental states depends. (To suppose that this does follow would be to commit a so‐called quantifier‐shift fallacy.) And yet I, being the subject of all and only my own mental states, am such that each and every one of those mental states does depend upon me. Hence, we may conclude, neither my brain as a whole nor any part of it can qualify as the subject of all and only my mental states and so be identical with me. Putting together the two stages of this train of reasoning, we may thus infer that (14) is true and from that and (13) infer the truth of (8), the main claim of substance dualism. However, here it may be objected that the foregoing defence of premise (14) depends upon an illicit assumption; namely, that if my body as a whole were to lack a certain part, such as the tip of one of my little fingers, then it—my body as a whole—would not exist. This assumption is unwarranted because it presupposes, questionably, that every part of my body is an essential part of it, without which it could not exist. As it stands, this may be a fair objection—although it should be acknowledged there are some philosophers who do hold that every part of a composite object is essential to it (see e.g. Chisholm 1976: ch. 3). However, I think that the reasoning in favour of premise (14) can in fact be formulated slightly (p. 76) differently, so as to make it independent of the truth of this assumption. The initial insight still seems to be perfectly correct—that, as I put it, my body as a whole does not need to exist in order for me to have each and every one of the mental states that I do in fact have. Thus, to repeat, the thoughts that I am having in composing this essay plausibly do not depend upon my body including as a part the tip of one of my little fingers. Call these thoughts T. Consider, then, that object which consists of my body as a whole minus that fingertip. Call this object O and call my body as a whole B. (It should be conceded here that there are some philosophers who would deny that any such object as O exists—see e.g. van Inwagen 1981—but that is, to say the least, a controversial claim.) Suppose, now, that it is proposed that I am identical with B, and hence that B is the subject of the thoughts T. Then we can ask: On what grounds can B be regarded as the subject of T in preference to O, given that T do not depend upon B's including the part— the fingertip—that O does not include? Isn't the material difference between B and O simply irrelevant to the case that can be made in favour of either of them qualifying as the subject of T? But in that case we must either say that both B and O are subjects of T, or else that neither of them is. We cannot say the former, however, because B and O are numerically distinct objects, whereas the thoughts T have just one subject—myself. We may conclude, hence, that neither B nor O is a subject of T and thus that I, who am the subject of T, am identical with neither of them. This sort of reasoning can then be repeated, as before, with respect to any specific part of B, such as my brain.

Page 11 of 21

Dualism However we exactly formulate the defence of premise (14), the basic point of the unity argument, as I call it, is that my mental states do not all depend on my body as a whole or on any part of it in the unified way in which they all depend upon me as their subject. This point, it seems to me, is a good one. Indeed, between them, the unity argument and the replacement argument provide, I think, very compelling grounds for belief in the truth of non‐Cartesian substance dualism. Moreover, if this form of dualism is true then so, a fortiori, is property dualism, in its guise as a dualism of mental and physical events or states—on the widely accepted assumption, at least, that events or states consist in the possession of properties by substances at times. For if a mental event or state, such as a thought or a sensation, always and only consists in the possession of a mental property by a subject at a time, and a subject cannot be identified with its physical body or any part of it, then it follows that such an event or state cannot be identified with any physical event or state which consists in the possession of a physical property by that body or any part of it. For, on this account of the identity‐conditions of events or states, events or states are individuated in part by the objects in whose possession of properties at times they consist (see further Lowe 2002: ch. 12). It is interesting—and perhaps even surprising—that we should be able to arrive at this conclusion without entering at all into the question of how, exactly, mental and physical properties are themselves related. But I think that we can indeed do so. However, compelling though the unity and replacement arguments seem to be to me, I recognize that there are many other philosophers whom they will fail to convince. So at this point I want to turn to the doctrine of property dualism in its own (p. 77) right, rather than as an adjunct of non‐Cartesian substance dualism. For there are independent considerations in favour of property dualism which have little or nothing to do with any arguments in favour of, or indeed against, substance dualism. In fact, as I have already indicated, property dualism is typically advanced not as a consequence of substance dualism, but as a supposedly more defensible alternative to it. Perhaps the most intuitively persuasive case that can be made for property dualism in its own right is by appeal to the apparently irreducible character of the properties of phenomenal consciousness, or ‘qualia’, as revealed to us by introspection. It is hard, perhaps, to see how mental qualities such as the perceived redness of a rose, tasted bitterness of a lemon, or the felt sharpness of a pain could simply be physical properties of the brain or nervous system, manifested in complex patterns of neuronal activity. There seems to be an unbridgeable ‘explanatory gap’ between such sensory qualia and the neurophysiological properties that appear to be correlated with them, which prevents us from either simply identifying these properties or even somehow ‘reducing’ the former to the latter (see further Levine 2001; Chalmers 1996: ch. 4). However, physicalists may urge that this is just because our access to our own mental properties is radically different from our access to the physical properties of other things, being via introspection rather than via our sensory organs, so that these properties appear to be different to us, when in some cases they could very easily be the same (see Papineau 2002). After all, it may be said, if sensory qualia were neurophysiological properties of the brain, one would hardly expect the appearance of such properties to be the same for the Page 12 of 21

Dualism subject possessing them as for another person looking at the brain in question. Even if A's pain, for example, just is a neurophysiological property of A's brain, the appearance of A's pain to another person, B, who is looking at the relevant part of A's brain, will be determined by the character of B's own visual qualia, which will presumably be quite different neurophysiological properties of B's brain. However, the idea that we may distinguish in such a way between ‘appearance’ and ‘reality’, where mental properties such as pain are concerned, is open to question, for the following reason (see Kripke 1980: 144–55). Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the mental property of pain just is a certain neurophysiological property, such as the firing of C‐fibres, by analogy with the empirically confirmed fact that the property of heat in a gas just is the kinetic activity of gas molecules—where the ‘is’ is understood as being the ‘is’ of identity. Saul Kripke has famously argued that any such identity, if it obtains, must obtain necessarily, not merely contingently. So, for example, given that heat in a gas just is the kinetic activity of gas molecules, it could not have been anything else. It must be conceded, however, that the identity seems contingent—and this is something that needs to be explained. Here we may appeal to the fact that we can, of course, imagine that heat in a gas might have been something else, explaining this in turn by the fact that there could have been a different kind of physical activity which had the same appearance as heat; that is, which gave rise to the same phenomenal experience as the kinetic activity of gas molecules gives rise to in us. This, then, is why the identity, despite being necessary, seems contingent. But the putative identity of pain with the firing of C‐fibres—or any other (p. 78) neurophysiological property—seems equally contingent, a fact which ought to be similarly explicable, one might think, if the identity really does obtain. This, however, is precisely where the intended analogy with the identity between heat and the kinetic activity of gas molecules appears to break down. For if pain just is the firing of C‐ fibres, say, then the analogy requires us to explain the seeming contingency of this identity by saying that there could be a kind of physical activity that has the appearance of pain without being pain, just as there could be a kind of physical activity which has the appearance of heat without being heat. And yet it seems evident that there is no such possibility in the case of pain, because whatever seems like pain is pain, even if not everything that seems like heat is heat. But I think that this line of argument is vulnerable to the following riposte. If pain just is the firing of C‐fibres, then, indeed, the seeming contingency of this identity needs to be explained, and it can't be explained in the foregoing fashion, because it is very plausibly true that whatever seems like pain is pain. Notice, however, that the reverse is not at all obviously true—that whatever is pain seems like pain. I have already indicated why this may not be the case. When B looks at the firing of C‐fibres in A's brain, how that neurophysiological property seems to B is determined by the character of B's own visual qualia, which are very different from the pain qualia that B would experience if his own C‐ fibres were firing. It is, very arguably, this difference between B's visual qualia and his pain qualia that makes it seem to B that the firing of C‐fibres is different from pain and hence that their identity, if it obtains, is merely a contingent one. In this case pain in A does not seem like pain to B, but this is quite consistent with the claim that whatever Page 13 of 21

Dualism seems to B like pain in B is pain in B. For this reason, I am not convinced that qualia‐ based arguments for property dualism are nearly so compelling as their advocates suppose. This is not to say that we should simply accede at once to the physicalists’ claim that phenomenal properties are indeed identical with, or reducible to, neurophysiological properties. The failure of an argument against a certain claim does not constitute any sort of argument in favour of that claim. Indeed, the burden of proof clearly lies with the physicalist to provide a positive argument in favour of the present claim, since it must still be conceded that phenomenal properties do not seem to be identical with neurophysiological properties, even if we have seen that this fact is not incompatible with their identity. A positive argument is always required in support of a claim that reality is, in some respect, not as it seems to be. This is the point at which causal considerations come to the fore in the debate between dualism and its opponents. Perhaps the most powerful argument against interactive dualism is the so‐called causal‐closure argument. (For further background see Lowe 2000a: ch. 2.) By interactive dualism I mean the doctrine that mental events or states are not only distinct from physical events or states, but are also included amongst the causes and effects of physical events or states. Of course, the causal‐closure argument can have no force against either epiphenomenalist or non‐interactive‐parallelist dualism, but since even the first and more credible of these positions has relatively few modern advocates (see e.g. Robinson 2004) I shall not consider them here. In any case, even those who do support them would presumably (p. 79) concede that they would prefer to endorse interactive dualism if they thought that it could meet the physicalists’ objections, so let us concentrate on seeing how those objections can indeed be met, focusing on the causal‐ closure argument. The key premise of the causal‐closure argument against interactive dualism is the principle of the causal closure of the physical domain. This principle has received a number of different formulations—some of which are really too weak for the physicalist's purposes (see further Lowe 2000b)—but the relatively strong version of the principle that I shall chiefly consider here is this: (15) No chain of event causation can lead backwards from a purely physical effect to antecedent causes some of which are non‐physical in character. (See Kim 1993.) It may be objected on behalf of interactive dualism that (15) is simply question‐begging, because it rules out by fiat the possibility of there being non‐physical mental causes of some physical effects. However, as we shall see, (15) does not in fact rule out this possibility. Dialectically, it is in the dualist's interests to concede to the physicalist a version of the causal‐closure principle that is as strong as possible—provided that it still falls short of entailing the falsehood of interactive dualism—because if the causal‐closure argument in its strongest non‐question‐ begging form can be convincingly defeated, the physicalist will be left with no effective reply. Weaker versions of the causal‐closure principle can, of course, be countered by interactive dualists relatively easily, but tend to be countered by them in implausible ways which leave the physicalist with a telling response.

Page 14 of 21

Dualism To illustrate the latter point, consider the following widely advocated version of the causal‐closure principle: (16) Every physical effect of a mental cause has a sufficient physical cause. An interactive dualist may accommodate (16) by, for example, espousing the doctrine of interactive parallelism, which maintains that there is a one‐to‐one correlation between the mental and physical causes of any physical event that has a mental cause, such that both the mental and the physical causes of any such event are sufficient causes of it. (For an exposition and defence see Meixner 2004: ch. 8.) (By a sufficient cause of a given event I mean an event or conjunction of events that causally necessitates the event in question.) The physicalist may object that this doctrine has the highly implausible implication that every physical effect of a mental cause is causally overdetermined by that mental cause and the physical cause that is, supposedly, one‐to‐one correlated with it. To this the interactive parallelist may reply that such causal overdetermination is no mere accident but, rather, the upshot of psychophysical laws, so that the fact that it occurs is a matter of nomic or natural necessity. However, it may nonetheless appear surprising to the impartial bystander that psychophysical laws of this character should be thought to govern the causal interactions of mind and body, when so many other possibilities are compatible with interactive dualism. The non‐interactive parallelist has, it seems, much better reason to suppose that there is a one‐to‐one correlation between the apparent mental causes of physical events and their actual physical causes, because (traditionally, at least) he sees this as (p. 80) being the upshot of a divinely instituted pre‐established harmony between the mental and physical domains. Equally, the physicalist has a perfectly good reason to suppose that there is a one‐to‐one correlation between the mental and physical causes of physical events, because he identifies those causes, and identity is a one‐to‐one relation par excellence. But the interactive parallelist, it seems, must simply regard it as a brute fact that psychophysical laws sustain such a one‐to‐one correlation—a fact that is all the more remarkable because so many other arrangements are consistent with the truth of interactive dualism. Neutral parties to the debate could be forgiven for suspecting that the interactive parallelist postulates the one‐to‐one correlation of mental and physical causes simply in mimicry of the physicalist's position, with a view to denying the physicalist recourse to any empirical evidence of a causal character that could discriminate between the two positions. For wherever the physicalist claims to find evidence of one and the same cause of a certain physical effect—a single cause that is both mental and physical—the interactive parallelist will be able to reply that we in fact have two distinct but correlated causes, one of them mental and the other physical.

Let us now consider a version of the causal‐closure argument against interactive dualism that appeals to the very strong formulation of the causal‐closure principle embodied in premise (15)—that no chain of event causation can lead backwards from a purely physical effect to antecedent causes some of which are non‐physical in character. Two additional premises are needed. First, (17) Some purely physical effects have mental causes. —which the interactive dualist accepts as true, of course. Second,

(18) Any cause of a purely physical effect must belong to a chain of event causation that leads backwards from that effect. These three premises entail the conclusion

Page 15 of 21

Dualism (19) All of the mental causes of purely physical effects are themselves physical in character. which contradicts the defining thesis of interactive dualism. My defence of interactive dualism will rest upon a challenge to premise (18). Moreover, it will endorse a version of interactive dualism which combines it with the sort of non‐Cartesian substance dualism defended earlier.

What seems plausible is that if we were to trace the purely bodily causes of any bodily event, such as the movement of my arm on a given occasion, backwards indefinitely far, we would find that those causes ramify, like the branches of a tree, into a complex maze of antecedent events in my brain and nervous system—these neural events being widely distributed across large areas of those parts of my body and having no single focus anywhere, the causal chains to which they belong possessing, moreover, no distinct beginnings (see further Lowe 1996: ch. 3 see Fig. 3.1 below). And yet, my mental act of decision or choice to move my arm seems, from an introspective point of view, to be a singular and unitary occurrence which somehow initiated my action of raising my arm. How, if at all, can we reconcile these two apparent (p. 81) facts? It seems impossible to identify my act of choice with any neural event, or even with any combination of neural events, because it and they seem to have such different causal features or profiles. The act of choice seems to be unitary and to have, all by itself, an ‘initiating’ role, whereas the neural events seem to be thoroughly disunified and merely to contribute in different ways to a host of different ongoing causal chains, many of which lead independently of one another to the eventual arm movement. (For a response to doubts about the ‘initiating’ role of acts of choice, founded on the well‐known experiments of Benjamin Libet 1985, see Lowe (2008: ch. 4).) Non‐Cartesian substance dualism—henceforth, NCSD—can, I believe, enable us to see how both of these causal perspectives on physical action can be correct, without one being reducible to the other and without any sort of rivalry between the two. The act of choice is attributable to the person or self—to me, in this case—whereas the neural events are attributable to parts of the body: and self and body are distinct things, even if they are not separable things. Moreover, the act of choice causally explains the bodily movement— the movement of my arm—in a different way from the way in which the neural events explain it. The neural events explain why the arm moved in the particular way that it did— at such‐and‐such a speed and in such‐and‐such a direction. By contrast, the act of choice explains why a movement of that general kind—say, a rising of my arm—occurred around about the time that it did (see Lowe 1999). It did so because shortly beforehand I decided to raise my arm. My decision certainly did not determine the precise speed, direction, and timing of my arm's movement, only that a movement of that general sort would occur. The difference between the two kinds of causal explanation reveals itself clearly when one contemplates their respective counterfactual implications. If I had not decided to raise my arm, there wouldn't have been an arm movement of that kind at all—my arm would either have remained at rest or, if I had decided to make another movement instead, it would have moved in a quite different way. It doesn't seem, however, that one can isolate any neural event, or any set of neural events, whose non‐occurrence would have had exactly the same consequences as the non‐occurrence of my decision. Rather, the most that one Page 16 of 21

Dualism can say is that if this or that neural event, or set of neural events, had not occurred, the arm movement might have proceeded in a somewhat different manner—more jerkily, perhaps, or more quickly—not that my arm would have remained at rest, or would instead have moved in a quite different kind of way. (In other words, in the ‘closest’ possible worlds in which the relevant neural events do not occur, it's not the case that an arm movement of the given kind does not occur at all, because in those worlds other neural events occur which give rise to a similar arm movement. They do so because in all of these worlds the agent has the same intention to move his arm in a certain way and succeeds in doing so, albeit in a slightly different way in (p. 82)

Fig. 3.1 A maze of neural causes

different worlds.)

Mental causation is intentional causation—it is the causation of an intended effect of a certain kind. Bodily causation is not like this. Both kinds of causation need to be invoked to give a full explanation of human action, and NCSD seems best equipped to accommodate this fact. The very logic of intentional causation differs from the logic of bodily causation. Intentional causation is fact causation, while bodily causation is event causation (see Lowe 1996: 67–8 and, for the distinction between fact causation and event causation, see Bennett 1988: 21 ff.). That is to say, a choice or decision to move one's body in a certain way is causally responsible for the fact that a bodily movement of a certain kind occurs, whereas a neural event, or set of neural events, is causally responsible for a particular bodily movement, which is a particular event. Merely to know why a particular event of a certain kind occurred is not necessarily yet to know why an event of that kind occurred, as opposed to an event of some other kind. Intentional causation can provide the latter type of explanation in cases in which bodily causation cannot. More specifically: an event, such as a particular bodily movement, which may appear to be merely coincidental from a purely physiological point of view—inasmuch as it is the upshot of a host of independent neural events preceding it—will by no means appear to be merely coincidental from an intentional point of view, since it was an event of a kind that the agent intended to produce. It may be asked: But what about the causes of my act of decision or choice? Are these bodily, or mental, or both? My own opinion is that an act of decision or choice is free, in the ‘libertarian’ sense—that is to say, it is uncaused (see further Lowe 2003a). This is not to say that decisions are simply inexplicable, only that they demand explanations of a non‐ causal sort. Decisions are explicable in terms of reasons, not causes. That is to say, if we want to know why an agent decided to act as he did, we need to enquire into the reasons in the light of which he chose so to act. Since decisions are, according to NCSD,

Page 17 of 21

Dualism attributable to the self and not to the body or any part of it, there is no implication here that any bodily event is uncaused. It may now be wondered: How is it really possible for mental acts of decision to explain anything in the physical domain, if that domain is causally closed, in the sense defined earlier? Let us recall how, precisely, we defined the causal closure of the physical domain. According to the principle of physical causal closure, I said, no chain of event causation can lead backwards from a purely physical effect to antecedent causes some of which are non‐physical in character. This was premise (15) above. But intentional causation on the NCSD model, as I have described it, does not violate the principle of physical causal closure, since it does not postulate that mental acts of decision or choice are events mediating between bodily events in chains of event causation leading to purely physical effects: it does not postulate that there are ‘gaps’ in chains of physical causation that are ‘filled’ by mental events (see Lowe 1996: 82). (p. 83) Thus, it is consistent with premise (15) of the causal‐closure argument and avoids the conclusion of that argument by repudiating, instead, premise (18). On the NCSD model, a decision can explain the fact that a bodily movement of a certain kind occurred on a given occasion, but not the particular movement that occurred. Even so, it may be protested, if physical causation is deterministic, then there is really no scope for intentional causation on the NCSD model to explain anything physical, because the relevant counterfactuals will all be false. It will be false, for instance, to say that if I had not decided to raise my arm, a rising of my arm would not have occurred; for precisely the same bodily movement would still have occurred, caused by the same physical events that actually caused it. Maybe so. But we know that physical causation is not in fact deterministic, so the objection is an idle one. The NCSD model of intentional causation may nonetheless seem puzzling to many philosophers. I suggest that that is because they are still in the grip of an unduly simple conception of causation—one which admits only of the causation of one event by one or more antecedent events belonging to one or more chains of causation which stretch back indefinitely far in time. Since this is the only sort of causation recognized by the physical sciences, intentional causation on the NCSD model is bound to be invisible from the perspective of such a science (see Lowe 2003b). To a physicalist, this invisibility will seem like a reason to dismiss the notion of intentional causation as spurious, because ‘non‐ scientific’. To more broad‐minded philosophers, I hope, it will seem like a reason to discern no conflict between explanation in the physical sciences and another, more humanistic, way of explaining our intentional actions.

References Baker, L. R. (2000), Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Page 18 of 21

Dualism Bennett, J. (1988), Events and Their Names (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett). Brentano, F. (1874/1995), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (London: Routledge). Chalmers, D. J. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Chisholm, R. M. (1976), Person and Object: A Metaphysical Study (London: George Allen & Unwin). Crane, T. (2001), Elements of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Crane, T., and Mellor, D. H. (1990), ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’, Mind, 99: 185– 206. Descartes, R. (1641/1984), Meditations on First Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ii, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–398. Foster, J. (1991), The Immaterial Self: A Defence of the Cartesian Dualist Conception of the Mind (London: Routledge). Gendler, T. S., and Hawthorne, J. (2002) (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Clarendon). Kim, J. (1980), ‘Events as Property Exemplifications’, in M. Brand and D. Walton (eds.), Action Theory (Dordrecht: Reidel), 159–77. Kim, J. (1993), ‘The Non‐reductivist's Troubles with Mental Causation’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 189–210. (p. 84)

—— (2001), ‘Lonely Souls: Causality and Substance Dualism’, in K. Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 30–43. Kripke, S. A. (1980), Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press). Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Libet, B. (1985), ‘Unconscious Cerebral Initiative and the Role of Conscious Will in Voluntary Action’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8: 529–66. Lowe, E. J. (1989), Kinds of Being: A Study of Individuation, Identity and the Logic of Sortal Terms (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1996), Subjects of Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Page 19 of 21

Dualism —— (1999), ‘Self, Agency, and Mental Causation’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6: 225–39. —— (2000a), An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2000b), ‘Causal Closure Principles and Emergentism’, Philosophy, 75: 571–85. —— (2001), ‘Identity, Composition, and the Simplicity of the Self’, in K. Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 139–58. —— (2002), A Survey of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2003a), ‘Personal Agency’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Minds and Persons (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 211–28. —— (2003b), ‘Physical Causal Closure and the Invisibility of Mental Causation’, in S. Walter and H.‐D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action (Exeter: Imprint Academic), 137–54. —— (2008), Personal Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Meixner, U. (2004), The Two Sides of Being: A Reassessment of Psycho‐physical Dualism (Paderborn: Mentis). Merricks, T. (1994), ‘A New Objection to A Priori Arguments for Dualism’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 31: 80–5. Olson, E. T. (2001), ‘A Compound of Two Substances’, in K. Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 73–88. Papineau, D. (2002), Thinking About Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Robinson, W. S. (2004), Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Scruton, R. (1989), ‘Corporate persons’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 63: 239–66. Strawson, P. F. (1959), Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Methuen). Swinburne, R. (1986), The Evolution of the Soul (Oxford: Clarendon). Van Inwagen, P. (1981), ‘The Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62: 123–37.

Page 20 of 21

Dualism

E. J. Lowe

E. J. Lowe is Professor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at Durham University.

Page 21 of 21

Epiphenomenalism

Oxford Handbooks Online Epiphenomenalism   Sven Walter The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0005

Abstract and Keywords Epiphenomenalism is not only at odds with our intuitive conception of ourselves as autonomous agents. It also faces a whole series of theoretical difficulties. Among other things, it appears to undermine freedom of the will, the possibility of an evolutionary account of the mind, our conviction that others enjoy a mental life similar to ours, the application of epistemic norms like justification, warrant, or reasonableness to processes of belief formation, the distinction between reasons for an action and the reasons for which it was performed, and our ability to refer to, have knowledge of, and have memories about mental states. This article briefly sketches two of the most important of them, saying why the epiphenomenalist's standard response to them appears unsatisfactory. Then it considers an issue that has so far been mostly neglected; namely, the question of which account of causation would allow for a coherent formulation of the epiphenomenalist's position. Finally, it suggests an alternative version of epiphenomenalism, which, though not free from problems, may be superior to the traditional version. Keywords: epiphenomenalism, epistemic norms, mental life, justification, warrant, causation

THE

idea that our mental states can causally affect our bodily behaviour, and thus

indirectly affect our environment, is an integral part of what one could, following Wilfrid Sellars (1962), call our ‘manifest image of the world’. We are, it seems, agents who act because of our beliefs, desires, sensations, intentions, perceptions, etc.: a headache makes us frown, the intention to make a bid at an auction causes us to raise our hand, and the desire to hear a loved one's voice leads us to make a phone call. That our mental life is causally effective is hard to deny. How it can be so, however, is far from clear. Four centuries have passed since Descartes's pioneering discussion of the problem of mental causation, but we still lack a satisfying account of how our mental life fits into the causal structure of the world. Our failure to understand the how of mental causation may be a Page 1 of 12

Epiphenomenalism reason to reconsider Thomas Huxley's (1874) suggestion that our mental life is a mere epiphenomenon—a by‐product of the neurophysiological causes of behaviour that does not itself contribute anything to ‘the go’ of the world. However, epiphenomenalism is not only at odds with our intuitive conception of ourselves as autonomous agents. It also faces a whole series of theoretical difficulties. Among other things, it appears to undermine freedom of the will, the possibility of an evolutionary account of the mind, our conviction that others enjoy a mental life similar to ours, the application of epistemic norms like justification, warrant, or reasonableness to processes of belief formation, the distinction between reasons for an action and the reasons for which it was performed, and our ability to refer to, have knowledge of, and have memories about mental states. In this short chapter there is no room for a comprehensive discussion of all these objections to the view that mental phenomena are epiphenomena (see Walter 2007a, 2008a). I will only briefly sketch two of the most important of them below, saying why the epiphenomenalist's standard response to them appears unsatisfactory. Then I consider an issue that has so far been mostly neglected; namely, the question of which account of causation (p. 86) would allow for a coherent formulation of the epiphenomenalist's position. Finally, I will suggest an alternative version of epiphenomenalism, which, though not free from problems, may be superior to the traditional version.

4.1 Epiphenomenalism Epiphenomenalists typically maintain that every mental event has a complete physical, in particular neurophysiological, cause, while no mental event is ever a complete or even a partial cause of any other event. It seems as if our behaviour is caused, or causally influenced, by our beliefs, desires, sensations, etc., but in fact the regular succession of mental and physical events—our headache being followed by our frowning, our desire to call a loved one being followed by our making a phone call, etc.—is the result of causal processes at the underlying neurophysiological level. Epiphenomenalism evolved in the late eighteenth and the nineteenth century as a consequence of two apparently discordant beliefs about the world: (1) the growing scientific confidence that our world is a world of purely physical causes governed by physical laws and driven by physical forces only, and (2) a decidedly dualistic trust in the distinctness of mind and brain. Epiphenomenalism managed to reconcile these two conflicting convictions. The view that modern science allows only for physical causation is compatible with dualism if the mental has no causal impact upon the physical. Traditional epiphenomenalism can thus be characterized by the three claims of irreducibility, causal dependence, and causal impotence:

Page 2 of 12

Epiphenomenalism (IR) No mental event is identical with or reducible to a physical event. [irreducibility] (CD) Every mental event that has a cause has a (set of) physical event(s) as its complete cause. [causal dependence]1 (CI) No mental event is a complete or even a partial cause of any other event. [causal impotence] Thesis (CD) plays a pivotal role in the epiphenomenalist's typical response to standard objections. (CD) ensures that whenever the epiphenomenalist's opponent appeals to a mental cause m in order to explain some phenomenon, there is a physical event p, namely, m's physical cause, which, the epiphenomenalist can claim, actually plays the causal role her opponent attributes to m (see sections 4.2 and 4.3 for examples of this strategy). Nor, obviously, can the epiphenomenalist give up (CI) and remain an epiphenomenalist. Finally, something like (IR) is accepted by most philosophers of mind, and there would be little or no reason to endorse epiphenomenalism in the first place, if mental events were identical with or reducible to physical events. Arguably then, (IR), (CD), and (CI) form the core of traditional (p. 87) epiphenomenalism. Yet we will see in Section 4.4 how they may cause trouble for the epiphenomenalist. First, however, let us consider two of the most prominent objections against the view that the mental is a mere epiphenomenon.

4.2 The Objection from Evolution One leading line of objection to epiphenomenalism goes as follows: The human mind seems to be the result of a process of evolution by natural selection. But in order for natural selection to get a hold on a trait, that trait must make a causal difference to an organism's fitness. Since epiphenomena cannot be selected for, and since the mind was selected for in the course of evolution, epiphenomenalism must be false (see e.g. Popper 1978). The standard response on behalf of epiphenomenalism is that natural selection can propagate a trait that does not increase (or even decreases) an organism's fitness, as long as it is correlated with a sufficiently beneficiary trait. To take Jackson's standard analogy (1982: 134), a polar bear's having a heavy coat decreases its fitness, since it slows it down, thereby making it vulnerable. Nevertheless, a polar bear's having a heavy coat is the result of a process of natural selection, since having a warm coat increases the bear's fitness, and a polar bear cannot have a warm coat without having a heavy coat. There was selection of a heavy coat, but only because there was selection for a warm coat and the latter was impossible without the former. Analogously, it is said, our mind, although it is an epiphenomenon, may have developed because it was a by‐product of certain fitness‐ enhancing neurophysiological structures: for the epiphenomenalist, what is selected for in evolution are the neurophysiological structures of which our mind, which has no survival value of its own, is an effect.

Page 3 of 12

Epiphenomenalism Usually that is all the epiphenomenalist has to say in response to the objection from evolution (Two laudable exceptions are Robinson (2007) and Corabi 2007.) However, that response seems wanting for several reasons. First, suppose a university's admissions office proclaimed that an applicant's religion has no influence upon her chances of being accepted, but it turned out that all accepted students have the same religion. That would cry out for an explanation, and the same holds if it is claimed that our mind is an epiphenomenon but that as a matter of (brute) fact evolution has seen to it that any (healthy) brain of sufficient complexity is accompanied by a conscious mind. Second, the usual analogies show that evolution can propagate a trait that is neutral or detrimental for an organism's fitness. They do not show, however, that evolution can propagate a trait that does not make any causal difference whatsoever. (After all, the polar bear's heavy coat affects its behaviour: it slows it down.) The mind, it seems, would be the only co‐evolved trait which has no effect at all. Third, we understand perfectly well why a selection pressure for a warm coat has led to a heavy coat—the insulatory properties of a polar bear's coat depend upon its thickness, and the thicker the coat is, the heavier it is. In contrast, we do not have (p. 88) the slightest idea why a selection pressure for certain neurophysiological structures should necessarily have led to a conscious mind (due, of course, in part to what Joe Levine calls the ‘explanatory gap’; see Ch. 16 below). This does not show that the epiphenomenalist's standard response is irreparably flawed, but it shows that the typical analogies alone are an insufficient response to the objection from evolution. Although this is not the place to go into the details, let me suggest the outline of a different rejoinder. Our mind is no doubt the result of a process of evolution (we have one, but we have ancestors that did not have one). That does not entail, however, that our mind is the result of a process of natural selection. Natural selection is one of the mechanisms behind evolution (the change of allele frequencies within populations), but not the only one. That point was made by Gould and Lewontin (1979), and has recently been backed up by researchers in evolutionary development (so‐called ‘evo‐devo’), who argue that factors in the embryonic development of an organism can affect evolution without there being any specific selection pressures, for instance because there is not enough variation in the gene pool for natural selection to be effective (e.g. Carroll 2005). This of course falls short of establishing that our mind is not a result of natural selection, but it shows that a crucial premise of the objection from evolution—that natural selection is the only mechanism that could explain the evolution of our mind—needs more support than it is usually given.

Page 4 of 12

Epiphenomenalism

4.3 The Objection from other Minds Another important objection is that epiphenomenalism undermines any justification for our confidence that others enjoy a conscious mental life similar to ours (see Benecke 1901; Jackson 1982: 134–5). The problem is that the typical solution of the so‐called other‐minds problem—that we are justified in believing in other minds since we can observe others' similar behaviour and can infer from their similar behaviour similar underlying mental causes (see Ch. 42 below, by Anita Avramides)—is not available to the epiphenomenalist, since she denies that the mental plays any causal role in the production of behaviour. The standard response on behalf of epiphenomenalism is that instead of inferring a similar mental life that serves as the cause of behaviour, we can infer similar neurophysiological causes of behaviour, and then conclude that these similar neurophysiological causes are accompanied by a similar mental life as a further effect. That is, instead of inferring similar mental causes directly from similar behavioural effects, the epiphenomenalist first infers similar neurophysiological causes, and then in a second step similar mental effects from them. Again, however, this is unsatisfactory. First, the epiphenomenalist's version is phenomenologically much less adequate than her opponent's story: it is obvious that the attribution of mental states to others depends upon their behaviour, but it is not at all obvious that it depends upon the assumption of a similar neurophysiological make‐up (see e.g. Dennett 1987: 17–25). (p. 89)

Second, the epiphenomenalist's response is once again backed up by misleading analogies. According to Jackson (1982: 134), the epiphenomenalist's solution to the other‐ minds problem is analogous to the following uncontroversial inference: My reading in The Times that Spurs won justifies my belief that the Telegraph has also reported on Spurs's victory, because from the report in The Times I can infer that Spurs won, and from that I can infer that the Telegraph has reported on Spurs's victory. However, what justifies the inference from the inferred cause (Spurs's victory) to the inferred effect (the report in the Telegraph) is no doubt the fact that we have frequently observed events similar to the former followed by events similar to the latter. That is where the analogy fails, however. For how often have we observed that neurophysiological states similar to ours were followed by mental states similar to ours? At best, we could observe such correlations in our own case, but even there few if any of us have done it. Third, since the epiphenomenalist's story contains one more inference than her opponent's, namely, the one from a similar neurophysiological make‐up to a similar mental life, and since this inference is not at all obvious, her alternative line of justification is epistemically less secure. Everyone must hold that the inference from behaviour to the underlying causes is justified. But the epiphenomenalist must also hold Page 5 of 12

Epiphenomenalism that the inference to similar mental states as further effects is justified, and that seems risky, especially since we have little idea of why neurophysiological states should be accompanied by mental states at all. Hence, the epiphenomenalist's appeal to apparently uncontroversial cases where we infer one effect from another via a joint cause does not show that her alternative solution to the other‐minds problem is satisfactory. This and the preceding section have shown how important (CD) is for the epiphenomenalist. (CD) ensures that for any mental event there is a physical event of which the epiphenomenalist can claim that it actually plays the causal role usually attributed to the mental event in question (enhancing our fitness, causing our behaviour, etc.). And, as stated in Section 4.1, (CI) and (IR) are essential for the epiphenomenalist. Yet, Section 4.4 will show that the combination of (CD), (CI), and (IR) can lead to some unexpected problems concerning the epiphenomenalist's account of causation.

4.4 Epiphenomenalism and Causation Apart from theses (IR), (CD), and (CI), the epiphenomenalist must endorse a principle of physical closure like the following: (PC) Every physical event which has a cause has a (set of) physical event(s) as its complete cause. [physical closure]2 If there is at least one caused physical event, (PC) entails physical‐to‐physical causation. Moreover, if there is at least one caused mental event, (CD) entails physical‐to‐mental causation. Since the epiphenomenalist is making these causal claims, she thus ought to have some theory of causation, even though she maintains that mental‐to‐physical and mental‐to‐mental causation are impossible. What has gone largely unnoticed so far in discussions of epiphenomenalism (but see Lachs 1963) is that it is far from clear what conception of causation could account for the causal transactions posited in (PC) and (CD), while at the same time also respecting (CI). Given the limited space, it is impossible to consider each and every account of causation in detail, but the following should at least illustrate the nature and force of the problem for the epiphenomenalist. (p. 90)

Obviously, adopting a simple regularity account of causation which dispenses with any kind of causal necessity and analyses causes as sufficient conditions of their effects will not do for the epiphenomenalist (a point already noted by Broad 1925). Roughly, the idea would be that if c and e are distinct events (and c is earlier than e), c causes e iff there are event types C and E such that c is of type C, e is of type E, and events of type C are regularly followed by events of type E. Yet according to the epiphenomenalist, a mental event m will regularly be followed by a behavioural event b; since m and b have a common neurophysiological cause p, p will be regularly followed by both m and b, so that m will be regularly followed by b, too. Hence, if the epiphenomenalist invokes a regularity conception of causation to account for physical‐to‐physical and physical‐to‐mental causation, she is thereby violating (CI).

Page 6 of 12

Epiphenomenalism The same holds for Mackie's INUS account (1974), according to which causes are insufficient but non‐redundant parts of an unnecessary but sufficient condition. My belief that I have left my laptop behind at the check‐in counter may not by itself be sufficient for my returning to the check‐in counter (I may be convinced that catching my flight is more important), but only in combination with other conditions, where in addition I would not have returned to the check‐in counter under these conditions had I not believed that I had left my laptop there. My belief would then be an INUS condition of my return to the check‐in counter. Hence, if the epiphenomenalist invokes an INUS conception of causation to account for physical‐to‐physical and physical‐to‐mental causation, she is once again violating (CI). Counterfactual accounts of causation typically treat causes as necessary conditions of their effects. Roughly, c is a cause of e iff, if c had not occurred, e would not have occurred.3 Consider thus the counterfactual ‘¬m ¬b’, where m and b are again a mental and a behavioural effect of a common neurophysiological cause p. Given (CD), had m not occurred, its cause p would not have occurred, and since p caused b, b would apparently not have occurred either (ceteris paribus). Had I not believed that I had left my laptop at the check‐in counter, then, in the circumstances given, my belief's neurophysiological cause that according to the epiphenomenalist made (p. 91) me return to the check‐in counter would have been absent as well, so that, ceteris paribus, I would not have returned, had I not believed that I had left my laptop there. Thus, if the epiphenomenalist invokes a counterfactual conception of causation to account for physical‐to‐physical and physical‐to‐mental causation, she is again violating (CI).4 Finally, the idea behind so‐called conserved‐quantity accounts of causation is that causation is best understood as essentially involving the transfer of some conserved physical quantity like energy or momentum. (For more on this and the role of such accounts for the debate about mental causation see Jaegwon Kim's contribution to this volume and Walter 2008b.) Such an account may seem attractive to the epiphenomenalist, since, in contrast to the other approaches above, it nicely accounts for (CI). For if one accepts (IR) and conceives of the mental as something which is completely distinct from the physical, it is hard to see how mental entities could even be the kinds of things which are able to transfer a physical quantity like energy or momentum to physical entities. On the other hand, however, if it is unintelligible how the mental could transfer energy or momentum to the physical, then for the very same reason it is also unintelligible how the physical could transfer energy or momentum to the mental, so that the kind of physical‐ to‐mental causation required by (CD) would be impossible, too. Hence, if the epiphenomenalist invokes a conserved‐quantity conception of causation to account for the impossibility of mental‐to‐physical and mental‐to‐mental causation, she is violating (CD). Apart from that, (CI) and (CD) together entail the existence of ‘causal dead ends’— unidirectional causal chains leading from the physical to the mental, but not back again to the physical. Hence, if causation consisted in the transfer of some physical magnitude,

Page 7 of 12

Epiphenomenalism then (CI) and (CD) would apparently lead to a ‘drainage’ of energy, momentum, etc. that would violate physical conservation laws. Although these brief remarks are far from exhaustive or conclusive, they show that it is unclear how a coherent overall account of the various causal claims to which the epiphenomenalist is committed would look. This objection goes deeper than the usual ones which purport to demonstrate that epiphenomenalism is incompatible with some apparently undeniable feature of our manifest image of the world. If correct, it shows that epiphenomenalism cannot even be coherently formulated—not, at least, by adopting one of the currently leading accounts of causation. If epiphenomenalism is to have any chance of being credible, then—regardless of how it fares (p. 92) with regard to other objections —much more attention has to be paid than hitherto to explaining what exactly according to the epiphenomenalist causation is supposed to be.

4.5 Epiphenomenalism: An Alternative Conception The claim that the mental depends upon the physical is important for the epiphenomenalist. Traditionally that claim is spelled out as (CD); that is, as the claim that the mental is causally dependent upon the physical. In the light of the difficulties raised in the previous section, however, it may be legitimate to ask why the kind of dependence in question must be causal. What matters to the epiphenomenalist is not that the physical causally necessitates the mental, but that it necessitates it (so that selection for complex brains leads to a selection of conscious minds, and we can infer the presence of a similar mental life in others from the inferred similar neurophysiological causes of their behaviour, etc.). The idea that the mental non‐causally depends upon the physical is familiar in the philosophy of mind, where it has been discussed under the label of ‘supervenience’ or ‘realization’ in recent decades. Hence, why not replace (CD) by some principle that relies on a kind of non‐causal determination like realization? (NCD) Every mental event is realized by a (set of) physical event(s). [non‐causal dependence]5

Page 8 of 12

Epiphenomenalism The position spanned by (IR), (CI), (NCD), and (PC) avoids any problematic ‘causal dead ends’. Although there still is a unidirectional dependency of the mental upon the physical, that dependency is non‐causal, so that (NCD) and (CI) do not violate physical conservation laws if a conserved‐quantity conception of causation is adopted. Moreover, adopting such a conception still accounts for the truth of (CI), but once (CD) is replaced by (NCD) it no longer conflicts with alleged cases of physical‐to‐mental causation, for there aren't any. Finally, if a conserved‐ quantity conception of causation works at all, it arguably works best for the kind of physical‐to‐ physical causation posited by (PC). Hence, if the epiphenomenalist could defend a conserved‐ quantity account of causation (which is admittedly no easy task, but not unprecedented either; see e.g. Kistler 1998, Hall 2004), replacing (CD) by (NCD) would make (p. 93) her position consistent. Moreover, it seems that there would not be any disadvantage. The standard strategy for dealing with objections remains unaffected, as seen above (although it is still not altogether convincing; see, for example, Sections 4.2 and 4.3), and, since realization is standardly taken to be compatible with a broadly physicalistic attitude, a general dismissal of dualism does not do as an objection against this alternative version of epiphenomenalism.

However, why would one adopt such a position? If one is prepared to accept that the mental is realized by the physical, and thus in some broad (non‐reductive) sense part of the physical, then why would one still hold that it is an epiphenomenon? Generally speaking, the motivation for adopting the alternative version of epiphenomenalism is the same as the motivation for adopting traditional epiphenomenalism. On the one hand, there is the intuition that the mental and the physical are in some robust sense distinct; on the alternative version of epiphenomenalism that intuition is accounted for by (NCD) and (IR).6 On the other hand, there is the intuition that as far as causation is concerned, the primacy is with the physical; on the alternative version of epiphenomenalism that intuition is accounted for by the conserved‐quantity account of causation, which arguably restricts causation to the (fundamental) physical level. As a consequence, it seems that the mental cannot contribute anything to ‘the go’ of the universe; that is, mental events cause neither physical nor mental events. One will be led to such a position if one thinks that traditional epiphenomenalism is untenable (for instance for the reason stated in Section 4.4) but also finds the various accounts of mental causation that have been offered by so‐called non‐reductive physicalists unconvincing. It is a position for all those who (like me) are reluctant to endorse traditional epiphenomenalism, and instead replace its unabashedly dualistic world‐view with a more naturalistic view according to which the mental is realized by the physical, but at the same time find mental causation problematic because they just cannot see how an adequate account of mental causation would go.7 , 8

References Benecke, E. (1901), ‘On the Aspect Theory of the Relation of Mind to Body’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1: 18–44. Broad, C. D. (1925), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge). Carroll, S. (2005), Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo Devo and the Making of the Animal Kingdom (New York: Norton). Page 9 of 12

Epiphenomenalism Corabi, J. (2007), ‘Evolutionary Arguments and the Mind–Body Problem’, (Ph.D thesis, Rutgers University, 2007). (p. 94)

Dennett, D. (1987), ‘True Believers’, in Dennett, The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 13–35. Gould, S., and Lewontin, R. (1979), ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’, Proceedings of the Royal Society London, B205: 581–98. Hall, N. (2004), ‘Two Concepts of Causation’, in J. Collins, N. Hall, and L. A. Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 225–76. Huxley, T. (1874), ‘On the Hypothesis that Animals are Automata, and Its History’, Fortnightly Review, 22: 555–80. Jackson, F. (1982), ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36. Kistler, M. (1998), ‘Reducing Causality to Transmission’, Erkenntnis, 48: 1–24. Lachs, J. (1963), ‘Epiphenomenalism and the Notion of Cause’, Journal of Philosophy, 60: 141–5. Lewis, D. (1973), ‘Causation’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 556–67. —— (1979), ‘Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow’, Noûs, 13: 455–76. —— (1986), Philosophical Papers, ii (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Mackie, J. (1974), The Cement of the Universe (Oxford: Clarendon). Popper, K. (1978), ‘Natural Selection and the Emergence of Mind’, Dialectica, 32: 339–55. Robinson, W. (2007), ‘Evolution and Epiphenomenalism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14: 27–42. Sellars, W. (1962), ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’, in R. Colodny (ed.), Frontiers of Science and Philosophy (Pittsburgh, Pa: University of Pittsburgh Press), 33– 78. Shoemaker, S. (2001), ‘Realization and Mental Causation’, in C. Gillett and B. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 74–98. Walter, S. (2005), ‘Program Explanations and Mental Causation’, Acta Analytica, 20: 32– 47. —— (2007a), ‘Epiphenomenalism’, in J. Fieser and B. Dowden (eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy , accessed 2008. Page 10 of 12

Epiphenomenalism —— (2007b), ‘The Epistemological Approach to Mental Causation’, Erkenntnis, 67: 273– 87. —— (2007c), ‘Determinables, Determinates, and Causal Relevance’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 37: 217–44. —— (2008a), ‘Ist der Epiphänomenalismus absurd? Ein neuer Blick auf eine tot geglaubte Position’, Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 62: 415–32. —— (2008b), ‘The Supervenience Argument, Overdetermination, and Causal Drainage: Assessing Kim's Master Argument’, Philosophical Psychology, 21(1): 671–94.

Notes: (1) (CD) allows for the possibility of uncaused mental events. Epiphenomenalism is thus compatible with mental events that are not causally grounded in physical events, as long as they have no effects. (2) Given (CI), no mental event is a complete or even a partial cause of a physical event; hence, if a physical event has a cause at all, it must have a physical cause. (3) ‘Roughly’ because since counterfactuals are not in general transitive, causation should not be defined as counterfactual dependence per se, but rather as a chain of counterfactual dependencies (see Lewis 1973). (4) There is a lot more to say on this issue though. Lewis has argued that if m and b are effects of a common cause p, ‘¬m ¬b’ is false (see Lewis 1979 and the postscripts to his 1973 and 1979 in Lewis 1986). According to Lewis, p is not sufficient for m in the relevant possible worlds. When assessing similarity across worlds we must weigh up the degree to which there are violations in the fundamental laws against the degree of departure from particular matters of fact. Lewis argues that a possible world in which m does not occur but (due to a minor miracle) p occurs and causes b is closer to the actual world than any possible world in which m and p are both absent and we have to change the entire causal history of the world in question. These are contested issues, however. Suffice it to say that if the epiphenomenalist adopts a counterfactual account of causation, she at least owes us a detailed explanation for why counterfactuals like ‘¬m ¬b’ are supposed to be false. (5) Of course, being a realizer here cannot mean being a filler of a causal role, as a functionalist would usually hold, for the mental has no causal role to play according to the epiphenomenalist. An epiphenomenalist account of realization would have to comprise, at a minimum, the claim that realization is a relation between properties such that a property G (a set of properties G 1,…,G n) realizes a property F only if the instantiation of G in an object o (of G 1,…,G n in objects o 1,…,o n) is sufficient for the instantiation of F in an object o′, but not vice versa. (See, for instance, Shoemaker's subset model of

Page 11 of 12

Epiphenomenalism realization (2001) according to which G is realized by any property individuated by a set of (conditional) causal powers that includes the (conditional) causal powers bestowed by G.) (6) Indeed, on a plausible understanding of (NCD) it entails (IR), since realization is arguably a non‐reductive relation. (7) See Walter (2005) for an argument against Jackson and Pettit's attempt to ground mental causation in the mental's ability to figure in so‐called program explanations, Walter (2007b) for an argument against Lynne Baker's attempt to ground mental causation in the mental's special explanatory status, and Walter (2007c) for an argument against Stephen Yablo's appeal to the determinable/determinate distinction in the attempt to prevent a pre‐emption of the mental by the physical. (8) I'm indebted to Brian McLaughlin for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper and to Lena Kästner and Nicole Troxler.

Sven Walter

Sven Walter is Assistant Professor, Institute of Cognitive Science, University of Osnabrueck.

Page 12 of 12

Anomalous Monism

Oxford Handbooks Online Anomalous Monism   Julie Yoo The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0006

Abstract and Keywords Anomalous monism is a view about the relationship between the mind and the body, which attempts to strike a delicate balance between the thesis of materialism, on the one hand, and the irreducibility of the mental, on the other. Its current formulation is found in Donald Davidson's landmark paper, ‘Mental Events’, and concerns only intentional states — contentful mental states, such as the belief that p, the desire that q, and other propositional attitudes. Anomalous monism consists of two theses, one concerning monism, the other concerning anomalism. The ‘monism’ part of anomalous monism is the claim that all events, including the mental ones, essentially fall under one class; namely, the class of physical events. Keywords: anomalous monism, mind–body relation, thesis of materialism, intentional states, propositional attitudes, physical events

ANOMALOUS

monism is a view about the relationship between the mind and the body, which

attempts to strike a delicate balance between the thesis of materialism, on the one hand, and the irreducibility of the mental, on the other. Its current formulation is found in Donald Davidson's landmark paper, ‘Mental Events’ (1970), and concerns only intentional states—contentful mental states, such as the belief that p, the desire that q, and other propositional attitudes. Anomalous monism consists of two theses, one concerning monism, the other concerning anomalism. The ‘monism’ part of anomalous monism is the claim that all events, including the mental ones, essentially fall under one class; namely, the class of physical events. To say that an event is physical is to say that there is a physical description that correctly picks out the event; alternatively, one can say that an event is physical if it exemplifies a physical property (mutatis mutandis) for mental events). While Davidson prefers to formulate his views in terms of the application of predicates rather than the instantiation

Page 1 of 17

Anomalous Monism of properties, the majority of contemporary philosophers of mind readily appeal to the notion of properties when discussing anomalous monism, a practice that will be adopted in this entry. Anomalous monism, then, asserts that every mental event aside from having its mental property also has a physical property. For this reason the monistic part of anomalous monism is also known as token physicalism: the idea that every mental event is numerically identical with a physical event, though not the converse, as there are events, such as hurricanes, that are physical but not mental. The following example illustrates the idea of token identity for events. It is uncontroversial that physical events can exemplify more than one property: the sinking of the Titanic, say, can be the same event as the greatest maritime disaster. Here being a sinking (p. 96) and being a maritime disaster are the distinct properties or types that belong to one and the same event. Likewise, believing that it is raining (a mental property) and being a certain neural occurrence (a physical property) can belong to one and the same event. The idea of token physicalism, then, is the idea that all mental events also exemplify a physical property, which is to say that mental events, qua events, are reductively identifiable with physical events. The thesis that expresses the ‘anomalous’ part of anomalous monism is that there are no strict lawful regularities that govern how someone will think or act, exceptionless regularities that constitute a closed and comprehensive theory, which is essentially a fundamental theory of all natural phenomena that physics is thought to provide. It encompasses psychological anomalism—the denial of strict regularities that would connect only mental events with other mental events—and psychophysical anomalism— the denial of strict regularities that would connect mental events with physical events. The thesis of psychological anomalism is directed against the possibility of regimenting folk psychology into a closed and comprehensive theory in its own right, and the thesis of psychophysical anomalism is directed against the requisite inter‐theoretic bridge principles that could facilitate a reduction of folk psychology to physics. Davidson's thesis of anomalous monism has had far‐reaching implications. It revived concerns over the possibility of mental causation, it introduced the idea of applying the concept of supervenience to mental and physical properties, and it has challenged the possibility of a scientific psychology using the vocabulary of folk psychology. Though widely criticized on all of these fronts, anomalous monism has been one of the most influential theses in contemporary philosophy of mind.

5.1 Argument for Monism Monism is the view that there is only one kind of thing. It is typically contrasted with dualism, the view that there are two mutually irreducible kinds of things, the mental and the physical. Monism can, in principle, be construed as endorsing the view that Page 2 of 17

Anomalous Monism everything is ultimately mental (called ‘idealism’ or ‘phenomenalism’) or that everything is ultimately physical (variously called ‘physicalism’, ‘materialism’, and ‘naturalism’). The monism of anomalous monism comes down on the side of physicalism. The physicalism of anomalous monism is a very modest one, for while it endorses the claim that mental events are reductively identifiable with physical events—the thesis known as token physicalism—it resolutely denies that mental properties are reducible to physical properties. Davidson's argument for token physicalism relies upon the claim that a mental event is causally efficacious in virtue of its token identity with an efficacious physical event. The argument consists of three principles. The first is that mental causation really happens; one's desire to stay dry in the rain, for instance, can cause one to use an umbrella. The second is that strict laws are necessary for causation. And the (p. 97) third is that there are no strict psychological laws or psychophysical laws. Here are Davidson's formulations of the principles (1970: 208): Principle of Causal Interaction: [A]t least some mental events interact causally with physical events. Principle of the Nomological Character of Causality: [W]here there is causality, there must be a law: events related as cause and effect fall under strict deterministic laws. Anomalism of the Mental: [T]here are no strict deterministic laws on the basis of which mental events can be predicted and explained. The argument for token physicalism proceeds thus. According to the anomalism of the mental, no mental event m can cause a physical event p (or any other event, for that matter) on account of its governance under a psychological law or psychophysical law, as no such laws are properly strict (if there are any such laws at all). By the principle of the nomological character of causality, all causal relations must be covered by a strict law. Such strict laws are found only in the domain of fundamental physics, meaning that only physical events—events exemplifying physical properties—can enter into causal transactions. Thus, if m causes p, as the principle of causal interaction affirms, it is because m has a physical property, from which it follows that m is a physical event.

The main objections to the argument are these. The most prominent is that it ends up precluding the possibility of mental causation, not grounding its possibility (this is discussed in Section 5.5). A different criticism is that mental events cannot be individuated into discrete tokens, on account of their holistic interrelations with other mental events, so that it is impossible to identify mental events with discretely individuated physical events (Lurie 1978; Antony 1989; Child 1993). A third criticism is that there is no unique physical token with which a mental token can be identified at a time, but rather an array of different possible candidates, undermining the idea that there is a unique token identity that can be established (Hornsby 1980; Horgan and Tye 1985).

Page 3 of 17

Anomalous Monism

5.2 Strict and Non‐strict Laws Davidson's argument for psychological and psychophysical anomalism turns upon his insistence that there are no strict laws involving the mental. The notion of a strict law, therefore, requires clarification. As McLaughlin (1985) has explained, a law of nature, on Davidson's account, is a true generalization that is confirmable by its positive instances and is capable of supporting counterfactuals. Some laws of nature have exceptions: they are observed to hold only under conditions where everything else is equal. To indicate the dependence upon the presence of optimal conditions, such laws are modified by ceteris paribus clauses and are not strict. Laws that are strict, on the other hand, hold without exception—they do not depend upon the presence of optimal conditions for their holding. To be strict, however, exceptionlessness is still not enough. The (p. 98) generalization ‘All men are mortal’, for instance, holds without exception, but it does not count as a strict law in the sense Davidson has in mind. In addition to exceptionlessness, the law must belong to a fundamental scientific theory, fundamental in the sense that it has the capacity to explain all natural phenomena, ranging from the microphysical to the most ordinary macrophysical. This is to say that a theory of this kind describes a closed and comprehensive system— closed in that there are no occurrences whose causal origin goes beyond the laws of the theory, and comprehensive in that its laws fully suffice to encompass the course of all natural occurrences. Let us say that T is a theory that consists of a body of laws. An event is a T‐event just in case a law of T governs its occurrence. T, then, is closed if and only if a T‐event is caused by only other T‐events; that is, if and only if there are no foreign non‐T‐ events causing a T‐event. T is comprehensive if and only if the laws of T fully suffice to govern the occurrence of all T‐events; that is, if and only if there are no T‐events whose occurrence escapes the jurisdiction of the laws of T. Although Davidson adds that strict laws covering causal relations must be deterministic, it could turn out that the laws of T are not deterministic. But being probabilistic does not mean having exceptions; a probabilistic law can still be strict in that it has no need of being qualified by ceteris paribus conditions. (In fact, our best current physics points in this direction.) Where do we look for a closed and comprehensive theory? Fundamental physics is thought to be the only viable candidate—not the one we currently have, which is incomplete and probably false in places, but a true and completed theory to be had in the future (if we're lucky). Non‐strict laws, on the other hand, belong to theories that are neither closed nor comprehensive, paradigmatic examples being laws in the special sciences such as chemistry, biology, geology, and meteorology. Generalizations belonging to these theories may support causal claims concerning the occurrence of natural events. Thus, a generalization like ‘Tall parents have tall offspring’, may have what it takes to support causal claims. But if the theory of biology cannot be reduced to the closed and comprehensive theory via the appropriate bridge laws, then none of its generalizations Page 4 of 17

Anomalous Monism can be rendered strict and exceptionless if we stick only to its proprietary home vocabulary. In such a case, according to Davidson, a non‐strict law, at best, provides evidence that some strict law or other is at work in securing the causal relation between the events.

5.3 Psychological Anomalism The primary target of psychological anomalism is generalizations that purport to capture strict mental‐to‐mental relations, both causal and non‐causal. Davidson is not alone in his scepticism about the possibility of strict psychological laws. Indeed, it has a long tradition going back to the Verstehen approach upheld by William Dray (1957), the Wittgensteinians such as Elizabeth Anscombe (1957), and, more recently, proponents of the simulation theory of mind, such as Jane Heal (1995). (p. 99)

To appreciate the thesis of psychological anomalism, let us consider some well‐worn folk‐ psychological generalizations: A. If an agent dearly wants X, but discovers that not‐X, then the agent will be disappointed that not‐X. B. If an agent believes that Y and that Y entails Z, then the agent believes that Z. C. If an agent fears X, then the agent wants it to be the case that not‐X. These familiar generalizations go a long way in supporting many of our explanations and predictions about our thoughts and actions, but we could never say of any of them that they are strict. Take, for instance, (B); there are all sorts of defeaters that may obstruct an agent from making the inference—distraction, inattention, fatigue, and so on. This is true for all generalizations of folk psychology. While good at serving as rules of thumb, none of them is immune to contravention.

Is there a way of refining the generalizations of folk psychology so that they may be turned into strict laws? For there to be strict psychological laws, psychology needs to be either closed and comprehensive, or reducible to, or transmutable into, such a theory. As Davidson argues, this is not possible. It isn't closed, because non‐physical events affect the mental (consider distal physical causes of perceptions), nor is it comprehensive, as mental events do not constitute the full scope of natural phenomena (such as short circuits and hurricanes). And it isn't reducible to fundamental physics, the theory designated as closed and comprehensive, because there are no bridge principles connecting mental predicates (properties) with physical predicates (properties) to effect the reduction—principles that connect terms or properties of the reduced theory with those of the reducing theory so that the reducing theory can incorporate the phenomena explained by the reduced theory. (This is the thesis of psychophysical anomalism, covered more fully in the next section.)

Page 5 of 17

Anomalous Monism It needs to be acknowledged that there are two interpretations of Davidson's psychological‐anomalism thesis. On one interpretation the absence of strict laws of folk psychology is still consistent with the claim that there are laws of folk psychology—they are just not strict. The special sciences are full of non‐strict laws, and folk psychology would just be another special science. Several philosophers keen on this idea have taken this to be the moral of Davidson's psychological anomalism, so that statements like (A), (B), and (C), though not expressions of strict laws of nature, still have nomic status (Lepore and Loewer 1987; Fodor 1989; McLaughlin 1989). The other interpretation makes the stronger claim that there are no laws of folk psychology, strict or non‐strict. Instead, they have the status of normative principles rather than non‐normative, lawlike, regularities (McDowell 1984; Kim 1985; Child 1993).

5.4 Psychophysical Anomalism The psychophysical‐anomalism thesis is a thesis that asserts the irreducibility of the mental. The primary target of psychophysical anomalism is generalizations linking (p. 100) mental properties with physical properties, or types of mental events with types of physical events, along the lines of the following schema: D. An agent has a mental property M if and only if the agent has a physical property P. The psychophysical‐anomalism thesis is that there are no reductive bridge principles conforming to schema (D), but it is also directed at the weaker one‐way conditionals along the lines of (E):

E. If an agent has a physical property P, then the agent has a mental property M. Since (D) entails (E), arguments directed against (E) will automatically count as arguments directed against (D). For the rest of this discussion, we will only concern ourselves with (E). Davidson's claim is not merely that psychophysical correlations have not yet been discovered; his is an a priori pronouncement against their possibility.

Although the argument for psychophysical anomalism is still thought to be sketchy in places, there are two prominent reconstructions of it, each of which relies upon the following two principles: I. Rationality of the mental: To have a mind is to have a network of propositional attitudes that is, for the most part, rationally coherent. II. Holism of the mental: The content of a propositional attitude is holistically determined.

Page 6 of 17

Anomalous Monism The holism assumption is that a propositional attitude derives the content that it has by playing its unique inferential role(s) within the network of the agent's total propositional attitudes. And the rationality assumption is that we must interpret the content of a belief, say, by placing it within a larger pattern of beliefs (desires and actions) whose contents rationally cohere with the content of the belief we ascribe. None of this is to deny that mentally endowed agents falter in their rationality. Instances of local irrationality have to be acknowledged by any adequate theory of mind. The point is that an agent's beliefs, desires, and other propositional attitudes cannot be systematically and globally irrational, for then the attributions no longer count as mental attributions. Let us now turn to the reconstructions.

Page 7 of 17

Anomalous Monism

5.4.1 Reconstruction 1 On this reconstruction, devised by Jaegwon Kim (1985), there can be no psychophysical laws along the lines of (E) because such laws would risk compromising the principle of the rationality of the mental. This reconstruction appeals to the idea that there are different rules—what Davidson calls ‘constitutive principles’—essential to the attribution of intentional states and physical states (Davidson 1970, 1974). The constitutive principles that govern the attribution of physical states are distinctly non‐rational, which is to say that physical properties are not attributed in a way that makes them rationally coherent with other physical attributions. This is obvious: physical things, such as travelling (p. 101) along an elliptical orbit, weighing 50 lb, or having negative charge, are not, as a categorical matter, the kinds of things that have rational bearing. Things are different when it comes to the attribution of propositional attitudes. The constitutive principles governing the attribution of intentional states are rationality‐preserving. These ‘constitutive principles of rationality’ enjoin us to attribute attitudes that, for the most part, rationally cohere with the ones ascribed. So while physical things and their relations to other physical things have no bearing, our thoughts about physical (and other) things do have rational bearing. The fact of this disparity constitutes one of the premises of Kim's reconstruction. The other crucial premise is a novel spin on the nature of inter‐theoretic reductive bridge laws. Kim suggests that we think of bridge laws as having the capacity to ‘transmit’ constitutive principles. More specifically, the constitutive principles governing the attribution of the reducing property get transmitted to the one reduced. Taking ‘(x) (Px → Mx)’ to represent the form of psychophysical laws, Kim's idea is that the non‐rational constitutive principles governing P will carry over to M, so that the attribution of M will then be governed by distinctly non‐rational constitutive principles. Suppose, then, the usual method of attributing mental properties according to principles of rationality leads to the attribution of M for an agent on a certain occasion. As the attribution of M would also be governed by non‐rational constitutive principles of the physical, it is possible that the psychophysical law covering M enjoins us to make a different attribution. If this is possible, then psychophysical laws invite predication conflict. Worse, they run the risk of compromising the nature of mind, which is that it is rational. As Davidson has often stressed, something is a mind only if it consists of a network of propositional attitudes that rationally cohere with each other. If all the attitudes were to be attributed by appealing to psychophysical laws, so that only non‐rational constitutive principles come to govern the attribution of mental properties, we could end up with attitude attributions that are rationally incoherent, undermining the very nature of mind itself. This reconstruction, while provocative, has been resisted. Tiffany (2001), along with McLaughlin (1985) and Latham (1999), has argued that attributing intentional states in a way that has no regard for their rational interconnections does not ineluctably lead to Page 8 of 17

Anomalous Monism systematically non‐rational attributions. For all we know, psychophysical laws may successfully preserve the rational interconnections between the attitudes, in spite of their being attributed according to non‐rational constitutive principles. Sure, we may wonder how this could happen, but we cannot assume that it can't. An argument that could demonstrate this consequence would certainly justify scepticism concerning psychophysical laws, but, as it is, Kim's reconstruction fails to accomplish this.

5.4.2 Reconstruction 2 This reconstruction, offered by William Child (1993), is based upon the claim that the constitutive principles of rationality are ‘uncodifiable’. This means that the principles of rationality—such as ‘If you believe that p and that p entails q, then you (p. 102) ought to believe that q’, ‘If you desire p, and believe that doing q is the best way of getting p, then you ought to do q’, and so on—cannot be agglomerated into a complete system of rules that uniquely determines what an agent ought to think or do. Take the first principle: suppose the agent discovers, on independent evidence, that q is not true. The agent then has two options: either drop your belief that p or drop your belief that p entails q. The original principle does not tell you which of these two options to take, and therefore underdetermines which attitude you are to attribute. Such indeterminacies are true of all applications of principles of rationality. As a consequence, there can be no psychophysical laws, since mental properties cannot be uniquely fixed by physical properties. Again, while this reconstruction is provocative, it is by no means conclusive, for the uncodifiability thesis is highly contentious. Some have argued that even if the principles of rationality are uncodifiable, psychophysical anomalism still does not necessarily follow (Tiffany 2001). More common is the objection that while we have not yet achieved a codification of all the principles of rationality, some subsystems of rationality—decision theory, confirmation theory, game theory—are well on their way to codification. At any rate, Child does not give sufficient evidence for the impossibility of their codification (see also Yalowitz 1997).

5.5 Anomalous Monism and Mental Causation

Page 9 of 17

Anomalous Monism One of the desiderata of anomalous monism was to establish a framework that can demonstrate how mental causation is possible. Because anomalous monism embraces the token‐identity thesis, a mental event is causally relevant on account of its token identity with a causally relevant physical event. If one accepts the token‐identity thesis, establishing the causal efficacy of a mental event is easy: because physical events unproblematically enter into causal relations and mental events simply are physical events, mental events are causally efficacious. But mere token identity is still insufficient for establishing the possibility of mental causation, because we need further assurance that the mental event is efficacious in virtue of its mental property. Many argue that the causal relevance of mental properties is what really matters for an account of mental causation. One of the most damning objections to Davidson's argument for anomalous monism is that while it may successfully establish the causal efficacy of mental events, it precludes the causal relevance of mental properties. To see the difference between the causal efficacy of an event, on the one hand, and the causal relevance of a property of an event, on the other, consider an explosion that causes a fire. Suppose the explosion was also the loudest sound that happened in Smith's cellar. If they are token‐identical events, then it is also true that the loudest sound in Smith's cellar caused the fire. However, surely the cause was not causally (p. 103) efficacious in virtue of it's having the property of being the loudest sound in Smith's cellar. Rather, it was the fact that the cause was an explosion. According to the critics, mental properties, under the rubric of Davidson's anomalous monism, are as causally irrelevant to behaviour as loudness is to the fire. Contrary to what we want in a demonstration of the possibility of mental causation, anomalous monism entails that mental events cause other events in virtue of their physical properties, not in virtue of their mental properties. To use a different locution among certain critics, mental events are efficacious qua physical event, not qua mental event.

Page 10 of 17

Anomalous Monism

5.5.1 The Charge of Epiphenomenalism Such a view is what McLaughlin (1989) has called type epiphenomenalism, the idea that the type or property satisfied by the event is causally irrelevant. The reasoning goes as follows. Recall Davidson's requirement that causal relations must be backed by strict laws. According to this requirement, events can enter into a causal relation only if they are subsumed by a strict law. Only physical laws have what it takes to be strict, so this means that events can enter into causal relations only in virtue of their physical properties. It follows that what secures the causal relation between a mental event and a physical event is the mental event's instantiation of the relevant physical property, not the instantiation of its intentional property. Therefore, the critics conclude, the fact that the mental event has the mental property (propositional content) it has, makes no causal difference to whether or not the behavioural reaction occurs. By the very lights of the premises of the argument for anomalous monism, the critics argue, it is not the instantiation of a mental property, but rather the instantiation of a physical property, that brings about the effect. If this is right, then there is no support for mental counterfactuals: if the content of a thought were altered or deleted altogether, this would not affect a mental event's causal status as long as its physical properties remained intact, because in the end it is the physical properties that fix all causal relations. A number of responses have been given to the charge of type epiphenomenalism. McLaughlin, for instance, has argued that being efficacious in virtue of the event's physical properties does not entail being efficacious only in virtue of the physical properties. Consequently, it is possible that mental events have their effects in virtue of mental properties while, and only as long as, the events have their effects in virtue of physical properties. Another response appeals to the idea that while mental events may be efficacious in virtue of their physical properties, mental properties can still be causally relevant in so far as there are true mentalistic counterfactuals, counterfactuals supported by non‐strict psychological laws (Lepore and Loewer 1987).

5.5.2 Davidson's Response to the Charge of Epiphenomenalism Davidson's response challenges the very idea that there are properties in virtue of which events bring about their effects (1993). Davidson, contra his critics, insists that (p. 104) the idea that events are causes in virtue of some fact about the events is a feature of causal explanations, an intensional relation between predicates or descriptions. It is not a feature of causation, an extensional relation between events simpliciter, and so holds no matter how the causes and effects are described. Consequently, the problem of epiphenomenalism is based upon conflating causation with causal explanation. Davidson's displacement of the ‘in virtue of’ locution from the domain of causation to the domain of explanation is motivated by his particular views about the different logical properties of causal statements as opposed to those of explanatory statements (1967). Page 11 of 17

Anomalous Monism Explanations of the form, ‘—— because ——’ create an intensional context where the ‘because’ typically relates statements or facts. Causal statements of the form, ‘—— causes ——’, on the other hand, are extensional, where the blanks are filled in with nominalized descriptions of events. With respect to causal claims, as long as the events are described by some appropriate event name, such as perfect nominals or definite descriptions, redescriptions along these lines are intersubstitutible. Davidson's contention is that when event names are modified by the ‘in virtue of’ idiom, or any of its cognates, the name gets transformed into a fact description or a statement so that intersubstitution fails, turning the extensional context into an intensional one. This leaves us with one of two options with respect to the favoured phrase of the critics, ‘c qua F causes e qua G’. Either we regard it as an explanatory statement disguised as a causal claim, or we drop the qua modifiers along with the properties they highlight if we want the phrase to convey its intended causal meaning. Whatever the choice, Davidson argues, we're left with the more simple ‘c causes e’. In response to Davidson's analyses of causation and explanation, McLaughlin has defended the use of the ‘in virtue of’ expression in claims about causal relations. Consider again the contested claim, ‘c qua F causes e qua G’. There are two ways of interpreting this: (a) the fact that c has F is what causes the fact that e has G; or (b) c causes e in virtue of some fact (namely, that c has F and e has G, and F and G are suitably related). Davidson has argued against the reading offered by (a), the idea that facts could count as proper causal relata, maintaining that facts belong only within an intensional context, and thus could only serve as explicanda at best. But, as McLaughlin points out, the reading offered by (b) does not appeal to facts as the relata of the causal relation. The idea behind (b) is that the holding of a causal relation can be explained by some fact. The important thing to appreciate is that specifying that a relation holds in virtue of some fact does not mean that the relata of the relation are themselves facts; so anyone who wished to embrace (b) as the proper interpretation need not be committed to (a). On McLaughlin's diagnosis of the dispute between Davidson and his critics, Davidson conflates (a) with (b), and while (a) may be questionable, (b) certainly is not. As McLaughlin explains, to violate extensionality, the ‘in virtue of’ qualification in (b) would have to make the cause of an event essentially description‐dependent, but this qualifier doesn't play that kind of role. This is (p. 105) because what makes it the case that a collection of particulars are related in a certain way does not involve the need to cite what descriptions are true of the particulars.

5.6 Anomalous Monism and Supervenience A crucial motivation for anomalous monism, recall, was to formulate a convincing form of non‐reductive materialism. The commitment to materialism is satisfied by token physicalism, but token physicalism is too minimal to capture a substantive and interesting Page 12 of 17

Anomalous Monism formulation of physicalism or a substantive and interesting formulation of the psychophysical relation. The reason is that token physicalism is silent about the nature of the relationship between mental and physical properties. Enter supervenience. The relation of supervenience promises to capture a relationship of dependence between mental properties and physical properties strong enough to convey the ontological primacy of the physical by articulating the idea that the way things are physically determines how things are in all other respects—the mental, included—but not too strong so that it is reductive. Supervenience is intended to express a relation of dependence in the following way. How things are mentally is just a manifestation of how things are physically, in that once we fix the distribution of physical properties, the distribution of mental properties is thereby fixed. Here is an intuitive example. Consider the relationship between the distribution of ink dots and the shape of a figure emerging from the ink‐dot distribution. Once the distribution of ink dots is fixed, the shape of the figure is thereby fixed; different figure, different ink‐dot distribution. In such a case, we say that the figure's shape supervenes upon the distribution of ink dots. Davidson's preferred formulation of psychophysical supervenience is what Kim (1989) calls weak supervenience. Kim broadly distinguishes between three different supervenience relations: weak supervenience (WS), strong supervenience (SS), and global supervenience (GS). The relata of the relation can range from truths to facts to predicates, but the most common specification of the relata appeals to families of properties. Let us say that F* comprises the family of properties F 1,F 2,…,F n, and that G* comprises the family of properties G 1,G 2,…,G n: (WS) F* weakly supervenes upon G* if and only if necessarily for any world w and individuals x and y, if x and y are indiscernible with respect to G* in w, then x and y are indiscernible with respect to F* in w. (SS) F* strongly supervenes upon G* if and only if necessarily for any worlds w 1 and w 2 and any individuals x and y, if x in w 1 and y in w 2 are indiscernible with respect to G*, then x in w 1 and y in w 2 are indiscernible with respect to F*. (GS) F* globally supervenes upon G* if and only if worlds w 1 and w 2 indiscernible with respect to G* are indiscernible with respect to F*.

Page 13 of 17

Anomalous Monism Briefly, the differences between the three supervenience theses comes down to this (see McLaughlin 1995). Weak supervenience is a claim about the distribution of properties pertaining to individuals within a given world. When applied to the family of mental properties and physical properties, saying that mental properties weakly supervene upon physical properties amounts to the claim that if two individuals are physically alike, then they are also mentally alike. The thesis is weak in that the consequence follows with no modal force, as it allows for physical twins each lodged in different worlds to be mentally different. Strong supervenience, on the other hand, is a modally stronger claim, because it is about the distribution of properties pertaining to individuals across worlds. To say that mental properties strongly supervene upon physical properties is to say that two individuals who are physically alike must be mentally alike. This rules out cross‐world physical twins having different mental properties. Finally, global supervenience is about worlds in their entirety, not about individuals within or across worlds. According to global supervenience, worlds that have the same distribution of physical properties must have the same distribution of mental properties. While consistent with the failure of weak supervenience, if unqualified, it still has modal significance, as the idea is that physically identical worlds must also be mentally the same. (p. 106)

As stated before, Davidson appeals to weak supervenience to supplement his theory of anomalous monism. Several philosophers, however, have worried that it is too weak to express an interesting form of dependence of the mental upon the physical (McLaughlin 1985). Consider the physical twins Abe and Babe. While they think the same thoughts within a given world, placing each in diverse worlds allows for them to entertain different thoughts. One might think that this is a virtue of weak supervenience, as it is consistent with the externalist theory of content individuation, where facts about one's physical environment and social linguistic conventions partly determine the content of an attitude (Putnam 1975; Burge 1986). While this is certainly a feature of weak supervenience one may exploit, the worry about the weakness of weak supervenience is that it allows for physically identical twins lodged in physically identical environments to have differing thoughts, something more radical than the psychophysical relations entailed by content externalism. Strong supervenience, on the other hand, imposes exact similarity in what Abe and Babe are thinking as each occupies a different world. But here there is the worry that it may be too strong to be consistent with Davidson's considerations for psychophysical anomalism (Kim 1993). Strong supervenience implies that for any member of the supervening family there exists some member or members of the base family that necessitates the supervening member, where the nature of the necessitation is either nomological or metaphysical. This follows if we assume that physical properties are closed under complementation—that not having a certain physical property is itself a physical property —so that for any given mental state there will exist some physical state that strictly necessitates the mental state. Such a possibility looks like it compromises Davidson's psychophysical‐anomalism thesis. But this issue is complicated. Depending upon what, exactly, we require of a law, it is possible to read Davidson's psychophysical‐anomalism thesis as being (p. 107) consistent with strong supervenience (Child 1993). On this reading, psychophysical‐necessitation relations generated by strong supervenience could be so highly specific that they are Page 14 of 17

Anomalous Monism instantiated only once in a world. Laws of nature, on the other hand, have to have greater generality, which is what makes it possible for them to be confirmable by their positive instances. If there is no positive instance of a psychophysical‐supervenience relation other than the one time it occurs, then strong supervenience may not threaten the psychophysical‐anomalism thesis after all. But then it would carry very little significance.

5.7 The Influence of Anomalous Monism Anomalous monism has faced many objections on a number of different fronts: that it leads to epiphenomenalism; that its arguments for psychophysical and psychological anomalism are underdeveloped; over its possible inconsistency with strong supervenience; and over its difficulty establishing token physicalism. At the same time, it has been critical for many productive research programmes in philosophy of mind. Had it not been for Davidson's argument for anomalous monism—its supporting principles, and the consequences it has been thought to entail—major areas of current research might not have come about. These include the surge of interest in mental causation, in supervenience, and in the status of folk psychology as a scientifically explanatory theory.

References Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957), Intention (Oxford: Blackwell). Antony, L. (1989), ‘Anomalous Monism and the Problem of Explanatory Force’, Philosophical Review, 98: 153–87. Burge, T. (1986), ‘Individualism and Psychology’, Philosophical Review, 95: 3–46. Child, T. W. (1993), ‘Anomalism, Uncodifiability, and Psychophysical Relations’, Philosophical Review, 102: 215–45. Davidson, D. (1967), ‘Causal Relations’, in Davidson, Essays on Action and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 149–62. —— (1970), ‘Mental Events’, in Davidson, Essays on Action and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 207–25. —— (1974), ‘Psychology as Philosophy’, in Davidson, Essays on Action and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 229–39. —— (1993), ‘Thinking Causes’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3–17. Dray, W. (1957), Laws and Explanation in History (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Page 15 of 17

Anomalous Monism Fodor, J. (1989), ‘Making Mind Matter More’, Philosophical Topics, 17: 59–80. Heal, J. (1995), ‘Simulation, Theory, and Content’, in P. Carruthers and P. K. Smith (eds.), Theories of Theory of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 75–89. Horgan, T., and Tye, M. (1985), ‘Against the Token Identity Theory’, in E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell), 427–43. (p. 108)

Hornsby, J. (1980), ‘Which Physical Events are Mental Events?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 55: 73–92. Kim, J. (1985), ‘Psychophysical Laws’, in E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell), 369–86. —— (1989), ‘Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept’, Metaphilosophy, 21: 1–27. —— (1993), ‘Can Supervenience and “Non‐strict Laws” Save Anomalous Monism?’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 19–26. Latham, N. (1999), ‘Davidson and Kim on Psychophysical Laws’, Synthese, 118: 121–44. Lepore, E., and Loewer, B. (1987), ‘Mind Matters’, Journal of Philosophy, 84: 630–42. Lurie, Y. (1978), ‘Correlating Brain States with Psychological Phenomena’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 56: 135–44. McDowell, J. (1985), ‘Functionalism and Anomolous Monism’, in E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell), 387–98. McLaughlin, B. P. (1985), ‘Anomalous Monism and the Irreducibility of the Mental’, in E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell), 331–68. —— (1989), ‘Type Epiphenomenalism, Type Dualism, and the Causal Priority of the Physical’, Philosophical Perspectives, 3: 109–35. —— (1995), ‘Varieties of supervenience’, in E. Savellos and U. Yalçin (eds.), Supervenience: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 16–59. Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “meaning”’, in Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 215–71. Tiffany, E. C. (2001), ‘The Rational Character of Belief and the Argument for Mental Anomalism’, Philosophical Studies, 103: 285–314. Yalowitz, S. (1997), ‘Rationality and the Argument for Anomalous Monism’, Philosophical Studies, 87: 235–58. Page 16 of 17

Anomalous Monism

Julie Yoo

Julie Yoo is Visiting Assistant Professor, Department of Cognitive Science, Occidental College, Los Angeles, CA.

Page 17 of 17

Non‐Reductive Materialism

Oxford Handbooks Online Non‐Reductive Materialism   Lynne Rudder Baker The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0007

Abstract and Keywords The expression ‘non-reductive materialism’ refers to a variety of positions whose roots lie in attempts to solve the mind–body problem. Proponents of non-reductive materialism hold that the mental is ontologically part of the material world; yet mental properties are causally efficacious without being reducible to physical properties. After setting out a minimal schema for non-reductive materialism (NRM) as an ontological position, this article canvasses some classical arguments in favour of NRM. Then it discusses the major challenge facing any construal of NRM: the problem of mental causation, pressed by Jaegwon Kim. Finally, it offers a new solution to the problem of mental causation. Keywords: non-reductive materialism, material world, mental properties, ontology, mental causation, Jaegwon Kim

Page 1 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism

6.1 Introduction THE

expression ‘non‐reductive materialism’ refers to a variety of positions whose roots lie

in attempts to solve the mind–body problem. Proponents of non‐reductive materialism hold that the mental is ontologically part of the material world; yet mental properties are causally efficacious without being reducible to physical properties. After setting out a minimal schema for non‐reductive materialism (NRM) as an ontological position, I'll canvass some classical arguments in favour of NRM.1 Then I'll discuss the major challenge facing any construal of NRM: the problem of mental causation, pressed by Jaegwon Kim. Finally, I'll offer a new solution to the problem of mental causation. First, a word about terminology. Unfortunately, non‐reductive materialists do not share a standard terminology; indeed, they often use the same words (e.g. ‘realized by’) for different relations. I shall speak of mental properties and their instances (or instantiations). Following Kim's construal of events as states of affairs at a time, I take mental states (or events) to be mental properties instantiated at a time. As I am using these terms, mental events are to mental properties as tokens are to types.

6.2 A Schema for Non‐reductive Materialism (p. 110)

For present purposes I consider non‐reductive and reductive materialism to be ontological positions.2 All forms of materialism, reductive and non‐reductive, disavow immaterial souls, vital spirits, entelechies, and the like. According to any materialist, every concrete particular is made up entirely of microphysical items. Non‐reductionists part company with reductionists, however, with respect to identity or non‐identity of various kinds or types. The non‐reductionist distinguishes mental kinds from physical kinds, where the mental includes sensation and thought, and the physical is roughly the domain of the physical sciences, including neurophysiology. Even after three and a half centuries we still cast discussion of the mind/body problem in blatantly Cartesian terms, albeit now with a materialistic twist: sensation and thought turn out to be part of the material world. It is just assumed by most parties to the dispute that there is an antecedent unproblematic pretheoretical distinction between the physical and the mental. Although I believe that this initial ‘mental/physical’ distinction itself needs scrutiny, I'll follow the mainstream and take for granted the (unexamined) distinction between the mental and the physical. Reductionists in the philosophy of mind (e.g. Kim 1998; Lewis 1999; recently Heil 2003) hold that there are no properties that are distinctively mental properties. There are mental predicates, of course. There are distinct levels of explanation. We have different Page 2 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism vocabularies in which to explain phenomena at different conceptual levels, but there is no corresponding irreducible difference in level among the phenomena themselves. According to reductionists, levels of description do not indicate levels among what is described. So reductionists hold that if mental predicates designate any properties at all, they designate physical properties. By contrast, all non‐reductive materialists hold: (1) There are mental properties that are distinct from any physical properties. However, (1) is compatible not only with materialism, but also with substance dualism and neutral monism; hence, (1) does not suffice for non‐reductive materialism. So we need to add another thesis to yield non‐reductive materialism. Typically, non‐reductive materialists hold that the mental depends on the physical. The kind of dependence at issue is usually a relation of determination—some kind of supervenience relation. Since the kind of dependence differs in different versions of non‐reductive materialism, I'll formulate the thesis in the most general (and imprecise) way:

(2) Mental properties depend on physical properties. Non‐reductionists may elucidate thesis (2) in more or less strict ways, but, as materialists, they agree that mental properties do not depend on anything other than physical properties. Finally, non‐reductive materialists eschew epiphenomenalism about mental properties: mental properties make a causal difference (whether or not there are any properties that are epiphenomenal). Different non‐reductive views construe the causal difference that mental properties make in different ways, but for all of them (p. 111)

(3) Mental properties make a causal contribution to what happens. I take the conjunction of theses (1)–(3) to be a minimal schema for any variety of NRM. However, the conjunction of theses (1)–(3) remains incomplete in several ways.

The conjunction of (1)–(3) yields only a schema because different versions of NRM result from different elucidations of ‘depend on’ in thesis (2) and ‘make a causal contribution to’ in thesis (3). For example, ‘depend on’ in thesis (2) may be understood variously as: ‘weakly supervene on’ (e.g. Davidson 1980), ‘strongly supervene on’ (e.g. Kim (1998), or ‘globally supervene on’ (e.g. Van Gulick 1993). Any of these kinds of dependence may be invoked by proponents of NRM who hold that mental properties are realized by physical properties. And ‘make a causal contribution’ in thesis (3) may be understood as nomological sufficiency (e.g. Kim 1998) or counterfactual dependence (e.g. Lewis 1973), or something else. The schema defined by the conjunction of theses (1)–(3) is only minimal, because different versions result from supplementing (1)–(3) by various further theses. For example, some non‐reductive materialists (e.g. Horgan 1993; Antony 1999) hold that mental properties must be fully explainable and predictable in principle in the vocabulary proper to the physical sciences. But others (e.g. Davidson 1980; Baker 1993; Burge 1993) hold the negation: mental properties cannot be both fully explained and predicted, even in principle, in the vocabulary proper to the physical sciences.3 And many materialists (e.g.

Page 3 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Lepore and Loewer 1989; Kim 1998) supplement (1)–(3) with a thesis of the causal closure of the physical: Every physical event has a complete physical cause.

6.3 Classical Arguments for NRM: Putnam, Fodor, Davidson NRM is supported (i) by Putnam's (and Fodor's) focus on multiple realizability, (ii) by Fodor's work on the special sciences, and (iii) by Davidson's anomalous monism (see Putnam 1975; Fodor 1974, 1975; Davidson 1980). (p. 112)

(i) Multiple Realizability. A property G is realized by a property F only if G supervenes on F. An instance of F necessitates (in some sense) an instance of G. Mental properties are realized by indefinitely many different kinds of neural properties. For example, consider being hungry. Although a mammal and an octopus may both be hungry, hunger in a human being may well not even be ‘correlated’ with the same physical‐chemical property as hunger in an octopus. Since hunger is realized by one physical state in a mammal and a distinct physical state in an octopus, there is no physical‐chemical or neural property with which to identify hunger (Putnam 1975: 436).4 Hence, there is no physical property with which hunger can be identified. Nor is there even a physical property that is necessary for hunger; different instances of hunger are realized in different kinds of physical states. Thus, the phenomenon of multiple realizability supports thesis (1) of NRM, and is seemingly neutral with respect to theses (2) and (3).

Page 4 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism

(ii) Special Sciences. The special sciences (e.g. psychology) appeal to mental properties that are neither identical to physical properties nor reducible to physical properties. A science like psychology is reducible to a science like neurophysiology only if the laws of psychology are reducible to laws of neurophysiology by means of biconditional bridge laws containing predicates of both psychology and neurophysiology (Fodor 1974).5 Bridge laws would connect the kinds to which psychology appeals to the kinds to which neurophysiology appeals. But because of multiple realizability, a psychological kind is not correlated with a single neurophysiological kind, but with a vast range of disjoint neurophysiological kinds. Moreover, the same issues surrounding the reduction of mental to neurophysiological properties also arise for the reduction of neurophysiological properties to cellular properties: neurophysiological properties are multiply realized at the cellular level.6 (So (ii) is a special case of (i) that also supports thesis (1).) Further, events recognized by the special sciences supervene on events recognized by microphysics. (This point supports thesis (2).) Nevertheless, lawlike, counterfactual‐ supporting generalizations of the special sciences are causal: If someone is thirsty, and believes that the bottle has water in it, then ceteris paribus, he will drink. (This point supports thesis (3).)

(iii) Anomalous Monism. According to Davidson, there are no strict psychophysical laws at all. Mental and physical predicates are not made for each other. Correct application of mental language is constrained by holism and normativity that have no place in correct (p. 113) application of physical language. (This point supports a Davidsonian analogue of thesis (1). Davidson appeals to predicates or descriptions, instead of to properties.) Furthermore, Davidson holds that the mental weakly supervenes on the physical in that there is no mental change without a physical change. (This point supports a version of thesis (2).) Davidson endorses a token‐identity theory. All events are physical events, but some physical events are described in mental terms (namely, in the vocabulary of propositional attitudes). The difference between mental and physical events is merely a difference in how they are described. Since causation is a relation between events no matter how they are described, mental events (i.e. physical events described in mental language) can cause physical events. (This point supports a version of thesis (3).) Since explananda are events only as described, mental events cannot be given purely physical explanations. Davidson argues that mental events weakly supervene on physical events. Modifying theses (1)–(3) for Davidson's appeal to descriptions instead of properties, anomalous monism supports NMR.

Page 5 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism

6.4 The Problem of Mental Causation NRM faces a serious difficulty. It is unclear whether (1)–(2) can be jointly satisfied in a way that avoids epiphenomenalism. For example, according to Davidson's anomalous monism, mental events—i.e. physical events with mental descriptions—figure in causal explanations of action. But the laws in virtue of which mental events have their effects are physical laws; the fact that some events have mental descriptions is irrelevant to what events they cause (see part I of Heil and Mele 1993 and Ch. 5, on anomalous monism in this volume). The mental is causally efficacious only in virtue of being physical. Being mental contributes nothing to what a mental event causes. (The causal contribution of mental events, on Davidson's view, is to causal explanation, not to causal relations.) Hence, although Davidson can satisfy both (1) and (2), his view does not avoid epiphenomenalism of the mental. In the past fifteen or so years Jaegwon Kim has mounted a sustained attack on various versions of NRM in numerous articles. Unless mental properties are reducible to physical properties, he argues, they are causally inert or else there is massive (and implausible) overdetermination. In Kim (1998: ch. 2) he pressed his objections from several directions. I shall focus on two arguments against NRM: the overdetermination argument, which I'll sketch briefly, and the ‘downward‐causation’ argument, which I'll set out in detail. Both arguments need recourse to the idea of higher‐level properties, which Kim roughly takes to be this: P2 is a higher‐level property than P1 iff the entities where P2 makes its ‘first appearance’ have ‘an exhaustive decomposition, without remainder, into entities belonging to the lower levels’ (1998: 15). Each of Kim's arguments against NRM relies on one or more of the following metaphysical assumptions: 1. The physical‐realization thesis: A higher‐level property is instantiated only if it is realized by a physical property. If P realizes M, then P is nomologically sufficient for M, and M supervenes on P (Kim 1993a: 200). (p. 114)

2. The nomological‐sufficiency conception of causation: Causation as nomological sufficiency (Kim 1993a: 204). 3. The causal‐realization principle: If an instance of S occurs by being realized by an instance of Q, then any cause of this instance of S must be a cause of this instance of Q (and of course any cause of this instance of Q is a cause of this instance of S) (Kim 1993a: 205–6; see also Kim 2000: 310). 4. The causal‐inheritance principle: If an instance of a mental property M occurs by being realized by an instance of a physical‐realization base P, the causal powers of this instance of M are identical with the causal powers of P (Kim 1992: 326). 5. The causal‐closure principle: Any physical event that has a cause at t has a complete physical cause at t (Kim 1993b: 43).

Page 6 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism 6. The principle of causal/explanatory exclusion: There is no more than one complete and independent cause (or causal explanation) of any event (Kim 1989: 89).

The Overdetermination Argument Assume that mental events are realized by physical events (in the sense of the physical‐ realization thesis), and hence that mental events supervene on physical events. If one mental event, M, caused another, M*, then there would be a physical event P* that realized M*, and M* would supervene on P*. On the assumption that the physical is causally closed, P* has a complete physical cause. Since M* supervenes on P*, the complete physical cause of P* is also a cause of M*. In that case, M* is overdetermined— by M and by the complete physical cause of P*. So if mental properties are not identical with physical properties, and mental events have physical effects, then these physical effects are overdetermined: All mentally caused events have complete physical causes as well as mental causes. But it is implausible, claims Kim, that every event with a mental cause is causally overdetermined. To bolster his case Kim bids us consider an example of overdetermination. Suppose that there are two assassins acting independently who shoot a politician at the same time. As Kim says, it is not plausible that all events with mental causes are overdetermined in that way. However, as Barry Loewer points out (Loewer 2001, 2002), in contrast to the case of the two assassins, a mental event and a physical realizer of it are not independent; they are metaphysically connected. So the analogy misfires. A number of philosophers reply to the overdetermination argument by arguing that if there is any overdetermination of mentally caused physical effects, it is harmless (see e.g. Thomasson 1998; Crisp and Warfield 2001; Loewer 2002; Pereboom 2002). The mental and physical causes are not in competition, since mental properties supervene on the physical properties. Such philosophers can concede that non‐identity of mental and physical properties leads to overdetermination, but can also maintain that the overdetermination involved is quite plausible.

(p. 115)

The Downward‐Causation Argument

There is a single argument that can be reconstructed from Kim's writings that, I believe, is his most forceful and sweeping assault on NRM. After stating the overall argument (as I–IV below), I'll give it in greater detail. Each of the premises in the overall argument is defended by one of the sub‐arguments (1–3, 4–7, 8–13, respectively). Say that a higher‐level property is irreducible if there is no lower‐level property to which it is identical. Then Kim's overall argument against NRM is this:

Page 7 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism I. If higher‐level properties are both irreducible and causally efficacious, then there is downward causation by irreducible higher‐level properties. II. If there is downward causation by irreducible higher‐level properties, then there are two distinct nomologically sufficient conditions of a single event. III. There are not two distinct nomologically sufficient conditions of a single event. ∴ IV. Higher‐level properties are not both irreducible and causally efficacious. Now turn to the arguments for Premises I–III. If mental states are causally efficacious, as NRM holds, then one irreducible and causally efficacious mental state may cause another mental state. Suppose that M and M* are mental states realized by physical states P and P* respectively, and that M ≠ P and M* ≠ P*.

Argument for Premise I: 1. M causes M*. [supposition for reductio] 2. If M causes M*, then M causes P*. [causal‐realization principle] ∴ 3. M causes P*. [1, 2 modus ponens] Argument for Premise II:

4. If M causes P*, then M is nomologically sufficient for P*. [Kim's nomological conception of causation] 5. M is nomologically sufficient for P*. [3, 4 modus ponens] 6. P is nomologically sufficient for P*. [causal‐closure principle + Kim's nomological conception of causation] ∴ 7. M and P are distinct nomologically sufficient conditions for P*. [5, 6 conjunction + assumption that M ≠ P] Argument for Premise III:

8. P is nomologically sufficient for M. [physical‐realization thesis] 9. If 7 & 8, then P is the only genuine cause of P*. [causal‐closure principle + principle of causal/explanatory exclusion] ∴ 10. P is the only genuine cause of P*. 11. If P is the only genuine cause of P* and M ≠ P, then M does not cause P*. [conceptual truth] 12. If M does not cause P*, then M does not cause M*. [causal‐realization principle] ∴ 13. M does not cause M*. [10–12 modus ponens twice] Hence, the supposition that M causes M* leads to a contradiction (1 and 13). The only causally efficacious properties are microphysical (or micro‐based macrophysical properties that are mereological aggregates of subatomic properties—see next section). Therefore, it appears that if NRM is correct, mental states are causally inert, and epiphenomenalism carries the day. I shall respond to the downward‐causation argument by proposing another model of NRM that satisfies the schema for NRM given in Section 6.2. If my model is correct, then the downward‐ causation argument is unsound. (In particular, lines (2) and (8) are false.) Before proposing my own model, however, I want to revisit an old controversy about the scope of Kim's conclusion. (p. 116)

Page 8 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism

6.5 Does Kim's Argument against Non‐ reductive Mental Causation Generalize? The downward‐causation argument has an extremely strong conclusion. It applies not just to mental properties, but to any putatively irreducible macrophysical property. If Kim's argument is sound, then there may be no macrophysical properties that are both irreducible and causally efficacious.7 Kim gave a two‐pronged reply to the charge that his argument against mental causation generalizes to threaten all macro‐causation (Kim 1998): (i) The first prong introduces a distinction between micro‐based macroproperties and others; (ii) the second prong introduces a distinction between levels and orders. (i) Kim's first prong: Micro‐based (or microstructural) macroproperties are properties of macro‐objects that can be characterized in terms of microstructure: ‘P is a micro‐based property just in case P is the property of being completely decomposable into nonoverlapping property parts, a1, a2, …, an, such that P1(a1), P2(a2), …, Pn(an), and R(a1, …, an)’, (1998: 84). For example, being a water molecule is a micro‐based property: it is the property of having two hydrogen atoms and one oxygen atom in a certain bonding relationship. Micro‐based properties, Kim argues, are both macroproperties and causally efficacious.8 For example, my table's having a mass of 10 kg is a micro‐based property: it is the property of being completely decomposable into 10 non‐overlapping parts each weighing 1 kg. Having a mass of 10 kg is a property of the table that is causally efficacious (it makes the pointer on the scale read ‘10 kg’) and is not a property of the table's proper parts. Hence, says Kim, we were mistaken to suppose that all macrophysical properties fall to the argument against non‐reductive mental causation. Micro‐based macroproperties are causally efficacious. (p. 117)

(ii) Kim's second prong: Mental properties and their realizers are on the same level. All properties of a single bearer are at a single level. So my property of intending to lock the door is at the same level as my property of having microparts with such‐and‐such microproperties and related in a certain way. So the competition between mental and physical properties is intralevel. Belief properties and the neural properties that realize them are at the same level; I have both. So a belief is a second‐order functional property: the property of having a first‐order property that plays a certain causal role. The distinction between first‐ and second‐order properties should be distinguished from the micro‐macro hierarchy of levels: ‘the realization relation does not track the micro‐macro relation’ (Kim 1998: 82). Neural properties are the first‐order properties—the realizers— that play the causal role. Mental and neural properties are at the same level, and neural properties have the causal powers.

Page 9 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism On Kim's view, a property can have a realizer only if it can be ‘functionalized’–that is, only if it can be construed ‘as a property defined by its causal/nomic relations to other properties, specifically properties in the reduction base’ (1999: 10).9 Kim ties realization to supervenience: If P realizes M, then M supervenes on P (1993a: esp. 196–7). The functional property and its realizers—the supervening property and its base—are on the same level. In short, says Kim, the problem of mental causation does not generalize to cross‐level causation, because mental and neural properties are at the same level, and micro‐based properties are macroproperties that are not susceptible to an analogue of the problem of mental causation. Let me respond to Kim's argument. Even if we accept everything that Kim says, there remains a huge class of important properties that Kim's view will render epiphenomenal (and hence, by Alexander's Dictum, non‐existent). These are properties mentioned in causal explanations of psychology, economics, and political science, as well as in everyday life. They are properties without which we cannot begin to make sense of the world that we encounter. I shall coin the term ‘intention‐dependent’, or ID for short, for such properties. They are properties that cannot be instantiated in a world without beings with propositional attitudes; for example, being in debt, being a driver's licence, being a delegate. Nobody can be in debt and nothing can be a driver's license in a world without beings with propositional attitudes. Call any property either that is a propositional‐attitude property (like believing, desiring, or intending) or whose instances presuppose that there are beings with beliefs, desires, and/or intentions an ID property.10 These are properties, non‐ mental as well as mental, whose instances depend on there being creatures with intentionality. ID properties that we are familiar with include being a wedding, being a carrot scraper, being a treaty, and so on. Other communities may be familiar with other kinds of ID properties; but all communities (p. 118) recognize many kinds of ID properties —as well as other ID objects like pianos and pay‐cheques, and ID phenomena like conventions and obligations.11 All artefacts and works of art and most human activities (getting a job, going out to dinner, etc.) are ID phenomena: They could not exist or occur in a world without beliefs, desires, and intentions. ID properties are not plausibly construed as micro‐based properties. However, ID properties are causal properties. By ‘causal properties’ I mean roughly the properties in virtue of which an object can have some effect: Property P is a causal property of x iff it's possible that there is some event E such that x causes E in virtue of having P. Without ID properties we could explain almost nothing that happens in the world—a president's ordering an invasion; a dean's cutting the departmental budget; a person's arrest on charges of fraud. It is highly unlikely that on Kim's account ID properties would turn out to be causally efficacious. In order to take ID properties to be causally efficacious Kim would have to construe them as functional properties, whose causal powers are just the causal powers of their non‐intentional realizers. Consider the property of being a payment of a debt. Page 10 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Your payment of a debt confers on you the causal power of clearing your name, and putting an end to harassing phone calls from your creditor. So payment of a debt is causally efficacious. Can Kim's view count payment of a debt as causally efficacious? The answer is affirmative only if three conditions are met. The first condition, on Kim's view, is that the property must be ‘functionalized’. It is not at all clear to me that the property of being payment of a debt has a single causal role, or even how to determine whether it does or not. The second condition is that the causal powers of an instance of paying a debt reside in its non‐intentional realizer. It is difficult even to find a candidate to be a non‐intentional realizer of a payment of a debt. Here's why. Kim ties realization to supervenience: If P realizes M, then P and M are members of families of properties, A and B respectively, such that B supervenes on A. So an instance of the property of being payment of a debt supervenes on the instances of its non‐ intentional realizers. Thus, given a non‐intentional realizer of an instance of the property of being a payment of a debt, necessarily the property of being a payment of a debt is instantiated. But the non‐intentional properties on which any instance of being a payment of a debt supervenes are not locally instantiated. That is, the non‐intentional base properties must be instantiated long before and far away from the instance of being a payment of a debt. Nothing would count as a payment of a debt without properties like ownership and borrowing. But ownership and borrowing are also ID properties. We have no idea what the base properties are on which being a payment of a debt supervenes. Yet if Kim is right, the causal efficacy of the payment of the debt resides in the non‐ intentional realizer (whatever that is). So Kim's view would have us transform a causal connection that we all understand, and that we can (p. 119) predict—the causal connection between Jones's payment of his debt and his putting an end to harassing phone calls from his creditor—into a causal connection between we know not what. The third condition is to find a theory at the base level that explains how the realizers of the higher‐level property can instantiate the functional specification. Since we have no idea of the identity of any non‐intentional realizers, we are in no position to find such a theory. Thus, it is highly unlikely the property of paying a debt can be functionalized. So it is unlikely that Kim's reductive approach can rescue ID properties as causally efficacious. An objector may be tempted to brush aside my argument that Kim's conditions cannot be met by ID properties, on the grounds that it is merely epistemological. The fact that we do not know how to carry out the reduction, as we are reminded often, does not imply that there is no reduction to be carried out (see Antony and Levine 1997). To such an objector I reply that if one advocates a particular strategy to meet a challenge, one should give reason to think that the strategy can succeed. If we have no idea of what a reduction would look like, we are in no position to claim that it can be carried out in principle. Without the ‘merely epistemological’, one has little reason to believe the loftily metaphysical.

Page 11 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Finally, even if Kim's conditions for functionalization were met, ID properties like being the payment of a debt would violate Kim's causal‐realization principle. The causal‐ realization principle, you recall, is this: If an instance of S occurs by being realized by an instance of Q, then any cause of this instance of S must be a cause of this instance of Q (and of course any cause of this instance of Q is a cause of this instance of S). So any cause of ending the harassing phone calls must bring about the non‐intentional realizer of the instance of the property of putting an end to harassing phone calls. Hence, if Jones's payment of his debt is to have the effect of putting an end to harassing phone calls, it must bring about the non‐intentional realizer. But the non‐intentional realizer, as we have just seen, includes all the properties on which this instance of putting an end to harrassing phone calls supervenes, and these include properties far beyond any individual's control today. So if Kim is correct, there may well be no intentional causation whatever. Not only is mental causation at stake, but all causation by objects' having properties whose instances depend on there being things with propositional attitudes; for example, being written in Dutch, being in debt, being a delegate. If we are realists about causal explanation (as Kim and I both are), then without ID properties we would have no causal explanations of, say, the president's vetoing a spending bill—or of any other historical, political, economic, social, and legal phenomena. So the problem of mental causation may not generalize to all macroproperties, but it does seem to generalize to a great swath of macroproperties that we cannot do without. Not only does Kim's reductionism lead to epiphenomenalism regarding ID properties generally, but even some versions of non‐reductive materialism leave us with no recognition of the causal efficacy of ID properties generally. Versions of NRM that hold that instances of mental properties confer (or are) causal powers and are intrinsic to their bearers (Clapp 2001; Pereboom 2002; Shoemaker 2003) will not (p. 120) generalize to account for other ID properties like the property of being written in Dutch or the property of being a delegate—putative properties whose realizations may have nothing in common. If predicates like ‘having a credit card’ or ‘being a felon’ do not designate properties, then we have no idea of any causal explanations of ordinary phenomena like being able to buy things without cash or of losing certain rights. Many ordinary phenomena are ID phenomena whose causal explanations appeal to ID properties.

6.6 Another Version of NRM I take it to be a condition of adequacy on an account of NRM that it allow that ID properties generally are causally efficacious. I want to propose a new version of non‐ reductive materialism—I'll call it the ‘PC view’; ‘PC’ for ‘property‐constitution’12— and to suggest that it refutes Kim's arguments against non‐reductive mental causation. Moreover, it accommodates ID properties, of which propositional attitudes are a special

Page 12 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism case, as causal properties. There are three elements of the PC view to be explained: the ideas of properties at different ontological levels, of property constitution, and of independent causal efficacy. First, consider the notion of properties at different ontological levels. Properties in general confer causal powers on their bearers (Shoemaker 2003). I use the term ‘causal power’ in a rough‐and‐ready way. Without endorsing Shoemaker's whole theory of properties, I follow him in holding that for something to have a causal power ‘is for it to be such that its presence in circumstances of a particular sort will have certain effects’ (Shoemaker 2003: 211).13 For any causal power C that an object has, there is some property P that the object has in virtue of which the object has that causal power C. There are distinct ontological levels: atoms (and aggregations of atoms) are on a lower level than are credit cards or passports.14 Every object is of some primary kind or other (see Baker 2000). An object's primary‐kind property determines its level and confers on it causal powers that cannot be manifested at lower levels. But an object also has other causal powers at lower levels, as well as at the level of its primary‐kind property. For example, a bronze statue has some causal powers in virtue of being a statue and some causal powers at a lower level in virtue of being made of bronze. (So I reject Kim's conception of levels according to which all properties with a single (p. 121) bearer are on the same level.) An ordinary woman has causal powers at a personal level (she can make her friends feel good), as well as at a sub‐personal level (she can rearrange air molecules when she dives into the pool). Although there is much more to be said about levels, I have said enough to state the first thesis of my view: Mental properties are distinct from physical properties, because they confer causal powers at different levels. The PC view thus satisfies thesis (1) of NRM: There are mental properties that are distinct from physical properties. Second, consider the notion of property constitution: Property instances are constituted by other property instances at a lower level.15 A property's constituter on a given occasion may be a proper part of a supervenience base for the property, but the constituting instance (e.g. being an extension of an arm out of a car window) does not suffice for the constituted instance (e.g. being a left‐turn signal). Property constitution is much weaker than supervenience: Whether or not one property instance constitutes another depends on circumstances. For example, raising one's hand in certain circumstances constitutes voting; one's hand's going up in certain circumstances constitutes raising one's hand; certain muscles' contracting in certain circumstances constitutes one's hand's going up; certain molecular motions in certain circumstances constitutes the muscles' contracting; and so on.16 Even the relation of atomic properties to molecular properties requires that the atomic‐property instantiations be in certain circumstances: Instances of being a sodium atom and being a chlorine atom do not constitute anything unless they are in circumstances of bonding.17

Page 13 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Although I can only be brief here, let me informally introduce another term needed for a schema for property constitution:18 ‘G‐favourable circumstances’. G‐favourable circumstances are the milieu in which something can have the property of being a G. The G‐favourable circumstances are conditions such that the addition of an appropriate F‐ instance makes it the case that there is a G‐instance, but not so comprehensive that just anything in G‐favourable circumstances guarantees that there is a G‐instance. Then, when a suitable F‐instance is in G‐favourable circumstances, it comes to constitute a G‐ instance. (To be suitable, an F‐instance cannot cease to be an F‐instance when put in G‐ favourable circumstances.) G‐favourable circumstances may be characterized by open sentences which are satisfied by an appropriate F‐instance. G‐favourable circumstances are conditions that are necessary but not (p. 122) sufficient for a G‐instance. If an F‐ instance is in G‐favourable circumstances, then ipso facto there is a G‐instance. For example, if a hand raising is in vote‐favourable circumstances, then ipso facto there is a vote. Here is a schema for property constitution: (PC) x's having F at t constitutes x's having G at t =df (a) x has F at t and x has G at t; & (b) x is in G‐favourable circumstances at t; & (c) It is necessary that: ∀z[(z has F at t & z is in G‐favourable circumstances at t) → z has G at t]; & (d) It is possible that: x has F at t & x lacks G at t.19 The potential constituters of an instance of G may have nothing in common, other than their suitability to constitute an instance of G in various circumstances.20 For example, a single instance of the property of voting may be constituted by an electronic signal, a mark on paper, a hole in paper, or something else.21 There is no general answer to the question of how much latitude there is among potential lower‐level property instances that may constitute a single higher‐level property instance. My only point is that there is some latitude: a constituted property instance may have any of a variety of different kinds of non‐intentional constituters, and there may be no physical similarities among the potential constituters.

The definition (PC) is too broad. It allows that, say, an instance of having mass constitutes an instance of being a passport. To remedy that, we may define ‘direct property constitution’ as follows: (DPC) x's having F at t directly constitutes x's having G at t =df (a) x's having F at t constitutes x's having G at t, & (b) There is no H such that x's having F at t constitutes x's having H at t and x's having H at t constitutes x's having G at t. Although an instance of having mass at t may constitute an instance of being a passport at t, there are intermediate constituters (e.g. being an aggregate of paper, plastic, and ink.) So the instance of having mass at t does not directly constitute the instance of being a passport at t. (p. 123)

Wherein, then, lies the dependence of the mental on the physical, or, more generally, of the constituted property instances on their constituters? Although constitution is not itself a supervenience relation, where there is constitution, there is a supervenience Page 14 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism relation in the neighbourhood. A constituted property instance supervenes ultimately on its subatomic constituters together with the microphysical supervenience base of all the circumstances in which the instance of the constitution relation obtains. The supervenience base will be very broad—too broad to be specified or to be useful in explanation—but it will be metaphysically sufficient for the constituted property instance. The PC view separates constitution from supervenience: Constitution is contingent and highly context‐dependent; supervenience is necessary and independent of context. However, supervenience supplies the dependence of the constituted property instances on their constitutors; constitution supplies the causal properties referred to in causal explanations. The PC view thus satisfies thesis (2) of NRM: Mental properties depend on physical properties. Third, consider the notion of independent causal efficacy. Constituted property instances confer causal powers that are ‘over and above’ the causal powers of their constituters. Some non‐reductionists hold that a property instance has independent causal efficacy if and only if it would have had its effect even if its constituter had been different.22 I would add that the causal powers of the constituted properties are not determined by those of the constituter alone. The G‐favourable circumstances are required for the constituted property to be instantiated. So (IC) A property instance has independent causal efficacy if and only if (i) it would have had its effect even if its constituting property instance had been different, and (ii) it confers causal powers that could not have been conferred by its constituting property instance alone. Any property whose instances have independent causal efficacy is a genuine causal property. My thesis, then, is this: ID properties generally (with mental properties as a special case) are causal properties because their instances have independent causal efficacy. Consider an example.

Let V be Jones's voting against Smith at t. P be Jones's hand going up at t. V* be Smith's getting angry at Jones at t′. P* be Smith's neural state at t′. C be circumstances that obtain at t in which a vote is taken by raising hands (‘vote‐ favourable circumstances'). The causal powers conferred by the constituted property instance (Jones's voting against Smith) are independent of the causal powers conferred by the constituter (Jones's hand’ going up). The causal powers conferred by Jones's hand going up include the power to move air molecules. The causal powers conferred by Jones's voting against Smith include the power to anger Smith—no matter how the vote was cast. In short, the causal efficacy of constituted property instances—of mental (p. 124) property instances and of instances of intention‐dependent properties generally —is independent of the causal efficacy of their constitutors. The PC view thus satisfies thesis (3) of NRM: Mental properties make a causal contribution to what happens.

Thus, the PC view satisfies the schema for NRM given in Section 6.2. The PC view, I believe, vindicates non‐reductive mental causation.

Page 15 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism

6.7 Saving Non‐reductive Materialism Now I shall apply this new version of non‐reductive materialism to the metaphysical principles underlying Kim's arguments against non‐reductive mental causation. Any non‐ reductive materialist, I believe, will have to reject three of Kim's principles: (a) The physical‐realization thesis, which guarantees that a putatively higher‐level property can be instantiated only if it is reducible to lower‐level properties; (b) The causal‐realization principle, which guarantees that no irreducible higher‐level property can be causally efficacious (by requiring that the cause of any higher‐level property must bring about its supervenience base); and (c) The causal‐inheritance principle, which guarantees that no higher‐level property instance confers on its bearer any new causal powers. Since each of these principles precludes irreducible, higher‐level, causally efficacious properties, each should be disavowed by any non‐reductionist. Indeed, the PC view provides the resources to justify rejection of each: if the PC view is correct, then each is false. The physical‐realization thesis and the causal‐realization principle were both needed for Kim's downward‐causation argument; the causal‐inheritance principle ensures that higher‐level properties have no independent causal efficacy. Hence, the PC view, if correct, renders Kim's argument unsound. (Conversely, of course, if Kim's argument is sound, then the three principles are true, and the PC view is incorrect.) My aim, however, is only to show that there is a coherent version of NRM that vindicates intentional causation and that justifies discarding these three principles. No non‐reductionist of any stripe can accept the three principles, and the availability of the PC view provides the grounds for rejecting them. Finally, note that the PC view does not violate the causal‐closure principle. The causal‐ closure principle says, roughly, that any physical event that has a cause at t has a complete physical cause at t (Kim 1993b: 280).23 On my view, all property instances are physical in this respect: any property instance is either identical to or ultimately constituted by microphysical property instances. ID properties thus are physical properties. So their causal efficacy does not violate the causal‐closure principle. Someone may object that ID properties as I have construed them are not really physical properties: the only physical properties are microphysical, or micro‐based (p. 125) properties that are just aggregates of microphysical properties (see Kim 1998: 114). Even so, the PC view would not violate the causal‐closure principle. Consider a case of basic action: Suppose that Jane is going through the security gate at a US airport, and she is instructed by a federal agent to raise her arms, so that the agent can ‘wand’ her. Jane wills24 to raise her arms (M) and she raises them (M*). Suppose that her willing to raise her arms causes her to raise them. Let MP be the microphysical constituter of Jane's willing to raise her arms and let MP* be the microphysical constituter of Jane's raising

Page 16 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism her arms. (Note that the relation between MP and M, on the one hand, and MP* and M*, on the other hand, is not Kim's realization relation but my constitution relation.) On the PC view, MP is not a complete cause of MP*. The causal‐closure principle requires only that MP* have a complete microphysical cause, not that MP be that complete cause of MP*. MP is only a proper part of a larger aggregate of microproperties that is nomologically sufficient for MP*.25 There is no difficulty for the property‐constitution view in saying: (i) Jane's willing to raise her arms causes her to raise her arms; (ii) Jane's willing to raise her arms is constituted by MP; (iii) Jane's raising her arms is constituted by MP*; but (iv) MP does not cause MP*. If the microphysical state of one sizable spatio‐ temporal region that ends at the time of Jane's willing caused the microphysical state of that slightly later sizable region that begins at the time of Jane's raising her arms, then the causal‐closure principle is honoured.26 So although the PC view does not require MP to be causally sufficient for MP*, it nevertheless does not violate the causal‐closure principle.27 There remains overdetermination, which, I suggested earlier, is benign. Better than benign, however: the possibility of overdetermination can be deployed in defence of NRM. For all we know, there is no fundamental level (see Schaffer 2003). If it turns out that there is no fundamental microphysical level, we cannot deny overdetermination, lest all the causal powers drain away. So we may have to countenance overdetermination in any case. Overdetermination resulting from ‘infinite descent’ would falsify reductionism but not NRM. So we have good reason to prefer NRM.

6.8 Conclusion Non‐reductive materialism is the most promising metaphysical view for understanding the world as we encounter it—the world filled with ordinary things like people (p. 126) and artefacts and works of art. Non‐reductive materialism alone offers a metaphysics that takes ordinary things and their interactions at face value and makes them intelligible; and it alone respects a common‐sense conception of reality in the context of a broadly scientific outlook.28

References Antony, L. (1999), ‘Making Room for the Mental: Comments on Kim's ‘Making Sense of Emergence’, Philosophical Studies, 95: 37–44. Antony, L., and Levine, J. (1997), ‘Reduction With Autonomy’, Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 83–106.

Page 17 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Baker, L. (1993), ‘Metaphysics and Mental Causation’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 75–96. —— (2000), Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View: (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Block, N. (1997), ‘Anti‐reductionism Slaps Back’, Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 107–32. Boyd, R. (1999), ‘Kinds, complexity and multiple realization’, Philosophical Studies, 95: 67–98. Burge, T. (1993), ‘Mind‐body Causation and Explanatory Practice’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 97–120. Clapp, L. (2001), ‘Disjunctive Properties: Multiple Realization’, Journal of Philosophy, 98: 111–36. Crisp, T., and Warfield, T. (2001), ‘Kim's Master Argument’, Noûs, 35: 304–16. Davidson, D. (1980), Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon). Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Fodor, J. (1974), ‘Special Sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, Synthese, 28: 97–115. —— (1975), The Language of Thought (New York: Crowell). Heil, J. (2003), From an Ontological Point of View (Oxford: Clarendon). Heil, J., and Mele, A. (1993) (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Horgan, T. (1993), ‘From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World’, Mind, 102: 555–86. Kim, J. (1989), ‘Mechanism, Purpose, and Explanatory Exclusion,’ Philosophical Perspectives, 3: 77–108; repr. in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 237–64. —— (1992), ‘Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52: 1–26; repr. in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 309–35. —— (1993a) ‘The nonreductivist's troubles with mental causation,’ in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 189–210;

Page 18 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism repr. in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 336–57. —— (1993b), ‘The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism’, APA Proceedings, 63 (1989): 31– 47; repr. in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1993), 265–84. —— (1998), Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind‐Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). (p. 127)

—— (1999), ‘Making Sense of Emergence,’ Philosophical Studies, 95: 3–36.

—— (2000), ‘Making Sense of Downward Causation,’ in P. Bogh Andersen et al. (eds.), Downward Causation (Aarhus: Aarhus University Press), 305–21. Lepore, E., and Loewer, B. (1989), ‘More on Making Mind Matter’, Philosophical Topics, 17: 175–91. Lewis, D. (1973), ‘Causation’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 556–67; repr in Lewis, Philosophical Papers, ii. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 159–72. —— (1999), ‘Reduction of Mind’, in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 412–31; repr in Lewis, Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1999, 291–324. Loewer, B. (2001), review of J. Kim, Mind in a Physical World, Journal of Philosophy, 98: 315–24. —— (2002), ‘Comments on Jaegwon Kim's Mind in a Physical World’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 655–62. McKitrick, J. (2003), ‘A Case for Extrinsic Dispositions’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81: 155–74. Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World). Noordhof, P. (1999), ‘Causation By Content’, Mind and Language, 14: 291–320. Pereboom, D. (2002), ‘Robust Nonreductive Materialism’, Journal of Philosophy, 99: 499– 531. Pereboom, D., and Kornblith, H. (1991), ‘The Metaphysics of Irreducibility’, Philosophical Studies, 63: 125–45.

Page 19 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 429–40. Schaffer, J. (2003), ‘Is There a Fundamental Level?’, Noûs, 37: 498–517. Searle, J. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Segal, G., and Sober, E. (1991), ‘The Causal Efficacy of Content’, Philosophical Studies, 63: 1–30. Shoemaker, S. (2003), ‘Causality and Properties’, in P. van Inwagen (ed.), Time and Cause (Dordrecht Reidel, 1980), 109–35; repr. in Shoemaker, Identity, Cause and Mind, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Clarendon 2003), 206– 34. Thomasson, A. (1998), ‘A Nonreductivist Solution to Mental Causation’, Philosophical Studies, 89: 181–95. Tuomela, R. (1998), ‘A defence of Mental Causation’, Philosophical Studies, 90: 1–34. Van Gulick, R. (1993), ‘Who's In Charge Here?’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.) Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 233–58.

Notes: (1) I take non‐reductive materialism to concern the causal efficacy of intentional phenomena—e.g. beliefs, desires, and intentions. Because of limited space, I shall omit specific consideration of qualia—e.g. the smell of garlic, or the sound of trumpets. (2) Historically reduction has been taken to be a relation between theories. According to Ernest Nagel's theory reduction, theory T2 is reduced to theory T1 just in case there are ‘bridge laws’ connecting the predicates of T2 and T1, and T2 is deducible from T1 together with the bridge laws (see Nagel 1961). (3) There is also room to hold that mental properties are predictable, but not explainable, in the vocabulary of the physical sciences. (4) There is an enormous literature on multiple realization (see e.g. Block 1997). (5) For a different non‐reductive conception of the special sciences see Boyd (1999). (6) Since the special sciences include all the sciences above the level of microphysics, if all the special sciences were reduced to microphysics there would be no macro‐causation at all. I'll return to this matter in Section. 6.5. (7) See Baker (1993), Burge (1993) and Van Gulick (1993) for arguments that Kim's claims against mental causation generalize to all macroscopic properties. Page 20 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism (8) Note that micro‐based properties are not irreducible, however. (9) Kim argues that functional properties are reducible to the bases that realize them. He gives a procedure for property reduction. To reduce E to a reduction base B, first, give a functional definition of E in terms of its causal relations to other properties (properties in reduction base B); second, find the physical realizers of E in B; third, find a theory at the level of B that explains how realizers of E fulfil the causal role specified in the definition. (10) Thanks to Gary Matthews for the label. (11) In other places I've used the expression ‘intentional property’ to refer to ID properties, and, less fortunately, ‘intentional object’ to refer to ID objects. Although I characterized what I meant by ‘intentional object’ carefully, I am now resorting to the technical term ‘ID object’ in order to avoid confusion with uses of ‘intentional object’ associated with Brentano and Meinong. (12) Pereboom and Kornblith (1991) Clapp (2001), and Pereboom (2002) all use the term ‘constitution’, but my view differs significantly from each of theirs. (13) Powers ‘can be thought of as functions from circumstances to causal effects’ (Shoemaker 2003: 212). I am not assuming Shoemaker's view in general. For example, Shoemaker takes properties to be non‐dispositional, and holds that ‘the word “power” refers only to intrinsic powers’. (2003: 221) I take properties to include dispositional properties, and I take powers to include extrinsic powers. (See McKitrick 2003.) (14) Kim defines levels mereologically: objects having properties at one level become parts of objects having properties at higher levels. (15) I say ‘property constitution’ for convenience. What is constituted are property instances, not properties themselves. Property constitution is analogous to the idea that I developed in Baker (2000) for understanding material objects in terms of what I simply called ‘constitution’. (16) Pace Kim (1998), I take the voter to be the bearer of all the properties at the different levels. (17) I individuate property instances in such a way that the same property instance could have occurred in different circumstances. Any G‐instance must be in G‐favourable circumstances, but if a G‐instance is constituted by an F‐instance, the F‐instance (which in fact is in G‐favourable circumstances) could have occurred in non‐G‐favourable circumstances. (18) The schema for constitution of properties differs from the one for constitution of particulars given in Baker (2000) and elsewhere. In the schema for constitution of particulars, F and G are x's and y's primary‐kind properties, respectively, and x and y are

Page 21 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism guaranteed to be non‐identical. In the schema for constitution of property instances, F and G are any properties, and although F and G are guaranteed to be non‐identical, there may be a single bearer of the properties F and G. (19) x has F but lacks G at t if the F‐instance is not in G‐favourable circumstances. X's having the property of being a salt molecule is constituted by x's having the compound property of being a sodium atom and being a chlorine atom—but only in salt‐favourable circumstances. If the properties of being a sodium atom and being a chlorine atom were instantiated in circumstances that prevented bonding, there would be no salt molecule. But necessarily when the chlorine and sodium atoms are in salt‐favourable circumstances, there is a salt molecule. The necessity here is metaphysical necessity. (20) This feature distinguishes my idea of property constitution from ideas of constitution found in Pereboom (2002), and from Clapp (2001). (21) For a defence of this claim see Pereboom and Kornblith (1991); see also Pereboom (2002). My view differs from Pereboom's in the latter article in several important ways. Most significantly: (i) Pereboom sets aside ‘any fundamentally relational causal powers’. (ii) Pereboom takes the relation between levels to be realization, where a realizer is nomologically sufficient for the realized property. (iii) Pereboom takes the causal powers of the realized property to be determined by (‘constituted by’) those of the realizer. I differ on all scores: (i) Assuming that causal powers derive from properties in virtue of which something has an effect, I take almost all intentional causal powers to be relational. (ii) I take the relation between levels to be constitution, where a constituter is not nomologically sufficient for the constituted property. (iii) I take the causal efficacy of ID properties not to be determined by their constituters. (22) Pereboom (2002) and Pereboom and Kornblith (1991) explain this point fully and persuasively. (23) This principle is important, says Kim, because to deny it ‘is to accept the Cartesian idea that some physical events have only nonphysical causes’ (1993b: 280). (24) I am using ‘will’ as an all‐purpose term that covers choosing, deciding, forming an intention for the immediate future. ‘Will’ carries no metaphysical weight here. (25) See Noordhof (1999) and Segal and Sober (1991). I discovered these articles after I had written the paragraph to which this note is appended. (26) There is much more to be said about the causal‐closure principle. Kim holds that physicalism ‘need not be, and should not be, identified with micro‐physicalism’ (Kim 1998: 117). In that case, if we disentangle the causal‐closure principle from the thesis of mereological supervenience, my own non‐reductive view satisfies the causal‐closure principle (see Kim 1998: 117).

Page 22 of 23

Non‐Reductive Materialism (27) We may still have a harmless kind of overdetermination. But note that the overdetermination is generated by the whole supervenience base, not by the constituter. (28) I am grateful to Gareth B. Matthews, Hilary Kornblith, and Jonathan Schaffer for reading drafts of this paper and making helpful suggestions.

Lynne Rudder Baker

Lynne Rudder Baker is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

Page 23 of 23

Functionalism

Oxford Handbooks Online Functionalism   Robert Van Gulick The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0008

Abstract and Keywords Functionalism at its core is the thesis that minds and mental kinds are to be understood in terms of the roles or functions that specific states and processes play within suitably organized systems. From a functionalist perspective, minds differ from non-minds not in any distinctive substance or fundamental substrate, but in their systemic organization and the roles played by their parts and sub-parts within it. A minded system is simply one that is organized in the right sort of way, though just which ways those are is a difficult and disputed matter. Functionalists classify states or processes largely, if not solely, in terms of the relevant roles or functions that they play in some such system. Keywords: substrate, functionalism, systemic organization, behaviourism, mental states, brain processes

FUNCTIONALISM

at its core is the thesis that minds and mental kinds are to be understood in

terms of the roles or functions that specific states and processes play within suitably organized systems. From a functionalist perspective, minds differ from non‐minds not in any distinctive substance or fundamental substrate, but in their systemic organization and the roles played by their parts and sub‐parts within it. A minded system is simply one that is organized in the right sort of way, though just which ways those are is a difficult and disputed matter. Functionalists classify states or processes largely, if not solely, in terms of the relevant roles or functions that they play in some such system. A process is treated as one of perceiving, remembering, or desiring in virtue of its systemic role, and so too are specific states such as believing that the climate has changed, intending to buy a tuna sandwich, or hearing the wind in the pines. Mental types and kinds are to be understood in term of their associated roles. The underlying substrate of mind matters only in so far as it supports and affects its system's organization and operation and the roles thus realized within it. From a functionalist perspective, mental differences are primarily differences in

Page 1 of 28

Functionalism function or role, and substrate variations that do not alter role thus do not matter mentally. Functionalism per se is not a specific thesis but more a general perspective on the mental. Particular functionalist theories and models share that basic view but differ greatly in how they develop it and what they take its import to be. Thus, in discussing functionalism, one must be clear about just what claim is at issue.

7.1 History Though functionalism no doubt has some historical antecedents, it is basically a contemporary view that originated in the 1960s and early 1970s. According to one (p. 129) standard and oft‐repeated history (Block 1980a), functionalism arose in response to the problems confronting the two main versions of physicalism then extant: logical behaviourism and the psychophysical type‐type identity theory. Logical behaviourism aimed to explicate ordinary mental terms or concepts such as belief, desire, and pain solely in terms of behavioural criteria involving actual or dispositional behaviour (Hempel 1949; Ryle 1949). According to such a behaviourist, the truthmakers for statements attributing such states to people are solely facts about the person's actual behaviour or about how she would behave under various other conditions. To want a cup of coffee is in part to be disposed to accept and drink one if it becomes available. Other facts may be relevant as well—for example having a disposition to walk to Starbucks if one has the time—but they are all facts about actual or counterfactual behaviour. Behaviourism had many supporters but confronted many objections, of which some concerning sufficiency and holism may have played a role in the origin of functionalism. Various examples were raised to challenge the sufficiency of the behaviourist analyses. Imagined examples appealing to perfect actors or super‐Spartans were alleged to show that all the relevant behavioural facts and dispositions might be true of a person who nonetheless lacked the relevant mental state. A perfect actor who was not in any actual pain might nonetheless be disposed to behave in every pain‐relevant way in all the relevant situations, and a super‐Spartan (Putnam 1965), stoically trained to never show pain, might conversely have no dispositions to behave in any pain‐related ways despite really being in pain. The behavioural and dispositional facts in such cases would not suffice to fix the mental facts. Others alleged that the holism of the mental made behaviourism viciously circular, at least in so far as it was intended as a reductive proposal for explaining the mental in terms of the non‐mental. The difficulty was with the antecedents of the conditional dispositions that figured in the behaviourist analyses. Wanting some coffee will lead one to drink a cup one is offered, but only if one believes that the cup contains coffee and has Page 2 of 28

Functionalism no contrary desires such as avoiding insomnia. Thus, to specify the dispositions associated with any given mental state one will typically need to include other mental states under which the dispositions will be activated. Given this holistic interdependence among mental states, the behaviourist would seem unable to break out of the circle of the mental or analyse the mental in term of the non‐mental (Grice 1975). The psychophysical type–type identity theory aimed to identify mental properties or states with specific neuroscientific properties (Place 1956; Smart 1959). Just as water turned out to be H2O and heat to be kinetic energy, so too it was supposed that pain might turn out to be simply C‐fibre firing or some other type of event described by neuroscience. Mental properties on such a model find a home in the physical world in the most direct way, by simply being identical with particular physical properties picked out by some non‐mental physical science; most probably, neuroscience. The evidence for such identifications might include observed correlations between first‐person reported mental states and the brain states observed by third‐person (p. 130) empirical means. The simplest explanation of the correlated observations would be that one was observing the very same state or property by two different means. Like behaviourism, the type‐type identity theory had both supporters and critics. Among the issues raised against it, the multiple‐realization objection seems to have played a role in the development of functionalism (Putnam 1967a). The objection turns on the empirical likelihood that the neural bases of mental states will vary in different organisms, across or even within species. Human pain, lizard pain, and octopus pain are quite likely different at the neural level, and thus pain might be said to be multiply realized. If the neural basis of pain can vary so widely across cases, then it would seem the property of being in pain is not strictly identical with any of those particular neural properties. Alien creatures might be even more unlike us physiologically, yet it seems plausible to suppose they too could have beliefs, desires, or pains. Thus, according to the critics, the link between mental states and physical states should not be regarded as one of type‐identity but as a matter of realization, with many physical bases able to realize a mental state of a given type. Being a pain or a belief would be more like being an eye or a stomach than being water or heat. According to the standard history (Block 1980a), behaviourism failed in part because it was ‘too liberal’ in counting things as having minds or particular mental states when in fact they lacked them, while type‐type identity erred in the opposite direction by being ‘too conservative’ in refusing to count creatures as having minds or pains simply because they failed to share our specific human neurophysiology. Functionalism, on that story, developed to avoid both pitfalls. Such functionalists defined types of mental states in terms of the roles they played within an internal network of states mediating an organism's or system's engagement with its environment. A state's role thus included not only links to situational inputs and behavioural outputs but also its interactions with other internal states. The appeal to internal organization thus added conditions beyond the purely behavioural ones that had proved insufficient for the behaviourist. The functionalists could rule out purported behavioural counter‐examples on the ground that Page 3 of 28

Functionalism the behaviour was not produced by the right sort of internal organization. Moreover, since the relevant organization might be realized by many different neural or even non‐ neural structures, the functionalist could avoid the chauvinism charge. Any system, no matter how unhuman in the details of its physiology, might nonetheless count as having a mind, as long its specific structure realized the relevant sort of organization. The standard history is no doubt part of the story, but only part of it. Other factors also played a role in the origin of functionalism; and functionalism in some of its forms has stayed closer to behaviourism or to the identity theory than that history suggests. Philosophic thinking was surely influenced by other developments of the time. The rise of cognitive psychology and of attempts to build data‐driven models of mental processes put the emphasis on the systemic organizational aspect of mind. General advances in computer technology and the widespread acceptance of the software‐hardware metaphor also suggested an analogous realization view of the mind‐body relation. Software is to hardware as function is to structure, and as mind is (p. 131) to brain. Brain processes provide the substrate for the mental processes they realize. The notion of the mind as an information‐processing system, which arose in the 1960s, reflected the influence of both computational and cognitivist trends (Lindsay and Norman 1977). Conversely, not all versions of functionalism broke as cleanly with their behaviourist and identity‐theorist predecessors. Some functionalists, most notably Daniel Dennett (1978, 1987) but others as well (Bennett 1992; Baker 1995), interpret the view in a basically behaviourist way. They accept the importance of holistic interdependence in analysing mental‐state concepts but nonetheless regard the truth makers for mental attributions as solely facts about actual and counterfactual behaviour. They acknowledge that the role played by a given desire, for example, cannot be specified without taking into account other desires, beliefs, and intentions, but they unpack those dependencies solely in terms of complex conditionals about patterns of behaviour. Such functionalists reject any inner‐ route constraint that requires that the relevant behaviour be produced by a specified type of internal process. All that is needed is that there be some internal mechanism able to support the relevant behavioural facts. Other functionalists have appealed to facts about the roles associated with mental kinds to support a version of type‐type identity theory (Armstrong 1968; Lewis 1972). Rather than grounding identity claims on correlational evidence, they argue for a two‐step process in which mental concepts are analysed in terms of their roles and then empirical science discovers the actual structures or properties, probably neural in nature, that in fact play those roles. For example, we might analyse our concept of pain in terms of relations to noxious stimuli, avoidance behaviour, and other mental states such as desires, memories, and emotions. Neuroscientists might then discover the specific brain structures or properties that play those roles in humans; for example, x‐firings in the cingulate cortex. The conclusion drawn by such functionalists would be that pain, at least human pain, is type identical with x‐firing in the cingulate. Functionalism construed in

Page 4 of 28

Functionalism this way is not really an alternative to the type‐type identity theory but rather a way to articulate and support the identity theory. (See occupant functionalism in the next section.)

7.2 Varieties of Functionalism Given that functionalism per se need not conflict with either behaviourism or identity theory, it is all the more important to distinguish clearly among its many versions, including those that do indeed reject both those earlier views. Though they all share the general idea that minds and mental kinds should be understood in terms of their functional roles, specific interpretations of that claim vary along three main parameters: To which mental states or kinds does it apply? What counts as a functional role in the relevant sense? And what does ‘understanding’ the first in terms of the second involve; that is, what relation is supposed to hold between the two? (p. 132)

Some functionalists intend their claim to apply to all mental states, but others restrict it to a particular subset. Some take it to be a claim about our ordinary common‐sense or so called folk mental kinds, such as pain, anger, thought, and desire. Others restrict the range further to just those folk states that figure in our rational‐agent model such as believing, wanting, and intending, or to those that involve propositional attitudes, such as believing that p, hoping that q, or seeing that s. Of particular importance is whether one includes conscious and experiential states within the scope of the claim, since many objections to functionalism appeal to its supposed limits in dealing with the phenomenal or experiential aspect of mind. The scope of the claim also depends on whether one interprets it as solely a claim about actual human mental states, or as extending to animal mental states, or even more broadly to the possible mental states of robots, aliens, or radically non‐human systems. Other functionalists interpret the claim as referring to the mental kinds that are used (or should be used) in some present or future psychological theories, especially empirically based scientific theories. Those kinds might or might not match up very well with our folk kinds, but if the theories are successful in describing and explaining human or non‐ human mental processes, there may be good reason to accept them as real mental kinds. Functionalism about such kinds is thus a sort of description or prescription of how we do or should scientifically theorize about the mind. Claims of this sort are sometimes labelled ‘psycho‐functionalist’ (Block 1980a). The notion of functional role gets interpreted in an equally diverse range of ways. Specific versions of functionalism differ in how they unpack that notion and in the theoretical resources they require to specify such roles. Though each admits of many subtypes, the

Page 5 of 28

Functionalism interpretations of ‘function’ group in three main families: computational, causal, and teleological. Some interpret functional role in terms of the mathematical functions, and thus as covering pretty much any mapping from inputs to outputs. To specify such a function, one needs to specify the items (or types of items) in the input set, as well as in the output set, and the rule or mapping between them. Thinking of roles in this way is especially apt for computational or machine‐state versions of functionalism, which explicate mental states and processes in terms of abstract computational relations such as those that define Turing machines and other sorts of formal automata. Treating functional roles in this way also naturally links up with work in artificial intelligence and computational psychology (Putnam 1967b). Others interpret the relevant roles in terms of causal relations, in particular in terms of fairly simple relations such as ‘causing’, ‘jointly causing’, ‘inhibiting’, and ‘causing unless … ’, which may seem to be the sorts of causal links invoked by folk psychology (Lewis 1972). A desire for coffee together with a belief that there is a café round the corner will jointly cause me to walk there unless I have some contrary attitude such as an intention to get to my office as quickly as possible. Mental states are treated as nodes in a linked network which is explicitly interpreted only in terms of its inputs and its outputs. The inputs might be specified as stimuli or environmental situations, and the outputs as responses or behaviours. The internal states are characterized implicitly and solely in terms of their location within the network of links. (p. 133)

A key issue is the sorts of conceptual resources one may use to specify such causal networks. On an austere model one may appeal only to simple and general causal notions like those listed just above in specifying the links, and only to basic physical descriptions in characterizing inputs and outputs, such as ‘looking at a red cup’ and ‘raising one's right hand’. Specifying causal networks in this restricted way would be apt if one views functionalism as a reductive account of the mental; that is, one that aims to reduce the mental to the non‐mental. However, it is not clear that any such restricted networks could adequately capture the relevant mental roles. In particular, they do not seem in accord with the sorts of causal generalizations one finds in folk psychology, which typically invoke more mentalistic notions in characterizing the relevant links as well as in specifying inputs and outputs. Folk theory, for example, holds that if one is in an embarrassing situation one is likely to apologize or attempt to explain away one's gaffe. How could one specify in purely physical terms what counts as an embarrassing situation or an attempt to explain away one's error? Folk theory includes many similar mentalistic generalizations; for example, if one comes to believe that p, one will typically also come to believe the obvious and plausible consequences of p; one's set of goals and preferences tends toward rational coherence; and if one perceives a dangerous threat one will react in fearful and evasive ways. Such platitudes are among those that figure in the roles associated with our Page 6 of 28

Functionalism ordinary mental kinds, but they characterize the relevant sorts of inputs, outputs, and causal links in ways that involve mental and intentional concepts, and thus could not be used by the reductive functionalist. By contrast, other functionalists of a less reductive bent might well use such concepts in specifying causal roles (Van Gulick 1982). Causal‐role versions also differ in how widely or narrowly they specify the relevant causal networks. Narrow versions restrict the networks to the internal causal structure of the organism or system (Stich 1983), and thus individuate roles or mental states solely in terms of factors internal to the individual. Wide versions allow the relevant networks to extend out into the world beyond the organism, and thus they may appeal to environmental, social, or historical factors in specifying and individuating roles and states (Putnam 1975; Burge 1986). The wide/narrow distinction can also be applied to other sorts of functionalism, but it is especially relevant with regard to causal‐role versions. A third set of functionalists interpret ‘function’ in a teleological way involving a notion of purpose or goal akin to the notions of function applied to biological systems and artefacts (Dennett 1969; Van Gulick 1982; Millikan 1984). When the biologist says the function of the kidneys is to filter and remove waste products from the blood, she asserts not merely that kidneys do so but also that it is their purpose to do so. Similarly with artefacts, it is the purpose of the antivirus software on a computer to detect and remove viruses; that is not merely what it does but what it is supposed to do in a goal‐directed sense. The teleofunctionalist treats the roles associated with mental states in the way same. The function of memories is to encode and retain information for subsequent retrieval and application, just as the function of the heart (p. 134) is to pump the blood. That is both what memories do and what they are supposed to do; it is the purpose they fulfil and why we have them. Teleofunctionalism is especially attractive to those who view mind from a basically biological perspective. Though artificial minds of a non‐biological sort may be a near‐term technological possibility, the only natural minds of which we know are all of biological nature and origin. Minds, like other aspects of complex biological systems, appear to have been produced through the normal process of evolution by natural selection, and thus been shaped by their contribution to the survival and reproductive fitness of the relevant ancestral organisms. The basic purpose of minds and of particular mental structures is to enhance the successful engagement of organisms with their worlds. Some may object that construing ‘function’ in a teleological sense would inject a problematic notion of purpose or ‘final causation’ into functionalism, a worry that may be of special concern to those who view functionalism as a reductive thesis. If mental kinds are to be understood in terms of teleological functions, then the prospects for a reductive account of mind will depend on the degree to which teleology can itself be reductively understood or naturalized (Wright 1973; Nagel 1977; Millikan 1984).

Page 7 of 28

Functionalism Many accounts of teleology have been offered in the recent literature, and most aim to explain it in a naturalistic way. The largest division is between those that treat historical facts about a structure's origin as a necessary condition on its function (Wright 1973; Millikan 1984) and those who do not (Cummins 1975; Nagel 1977). In particular, some hold that a structure S can have the teleological function of doing X only if S has been selected for doing X. Though accounts that include such a historical requirement are in keeping with evolutionary theory, they are open to so‐called swampman objections that appeal to a hypothetical case in which a molecular duplicate of a normal human arises by accident (Davidson 1987). Since such a swampman would have no selectional history, its inner states would lack any functions according to historical accounts of teleology. Yet in so far as it would be physically and behaviourally indistinguishable from ordinary humans, it seems wrong to deny that it would have mental states of the normal sort. Non‐ historical accounts of teleology can avoid such counter‐examples, but they may face other problems of their own. The teleological notion of function thus remains in dispute. Nonetheless, the various teleological accounts—together with the computational and causal readings—provide the three main ways to interpret the functionalist notion of ‘function’. The third parameter along which versions of functionalism vary is the nature of the link they assert between the mental and the functional. What does understanding the mental in terms of the functional involve? Again there are three main families of views, which respectively treat functionalism as an ontological claim about property identity, an analytic claim about mental concepts, or merely as a pragmatic thesis about the utility of viewing minds and mental kinds from a particular theoretical perspective. (p. 135)

Ontological versions of functionalism typically concern the identity and true nature of mental kinds or properties, where properties are considered as objective constituents of reality distinct from whatever concepts or predicates we may use to describe or refer to them. If feeling a pain and believing that lilies smell sweet are real properties instantiated in the world, then what sort of properties are they? What is essential to their instantiation? And how are they related to other properties, whether physical, functional, or of some other sort? Different functionalists answer in different ways. As noted in the history section, some early functionalists were motivated to reject the psychoneural identity thesis on the basis of the multiple‐realization objection. If many different neural (or non‐neural) substrates might realize pain in different organisms, then the property of being in pain could not be identical with any of those particular neural properties. According to such functionalists, the relation between mental and neural properties is better considered as a matter of realization rather of identity. What then is the relation between the functional and the mental? Like mental properties, the relevant functional properties are realized by the underlying neural substrate, but how many distinct acts of realization are involved? If the functional properties are identical with the mental properties, then only one act of realization is required. If they Page 8 of 28

Functionalism are not identical, there are at least two options. Either they are independently realized by the physical, or they get realized in a connected way perhaps by a two‐level process through which the physical realizes the functional, which then in turn realizes the mental. Among those who interpret functionalism as a claim of property identity there is a major division between so‐called role functionalists and occupant functionalists. Role functionalists identify a given mental property M1, for example being an instance of pain, with the property of playing the relevant role R1. The properties of being pain and of playing the pain role are regarded as one and the same property. If one thinks instead in terms of properties had by whole persons, such as that of ‘being in pain’, the role functionalist would identify such mental properties with the property of ‘being in some state which plays the relevant role’; for example, the pain role (Putnam 1967a; Lycan 1987). By contrast, occupant functionalists (Armstong 1968; Lewis 1972) identify the mental property with the structural or neural property that in fact occupies or plays that role in a given reference population, such as normal humans. If neuroscience discovers that patterns of chaotic firing in the cingulate cortex play the pain role in humans, then the occupant functionalist would conclude that the property of human pain is identical with the property of having chaotic cingulate firings. (The cingulate does in fact appear to play part of the pain role, but the neural substrate of human pain seems to be widely distributed across multiple brain regions.) From the perspective of occupant functionalism, the role associated with a given mental kind serves as a means to secure reference to the relevant property, but it does not typically give the identity or essence of that property, which must instead be discovered through empirical investigation. The roles serve more or less as a list of symptoms might do in the discovery of a disease. One might refer to some unknown agent as ‘the cause (p. 136) of river blindness’ and only later discover that the relevant property is that of ‘being infected with the parasitic nematode Onchocerca volvulus’. Thus, both role and occupant functionalists interpret the view as an identity claim about mental properties, but the two groups identify them with very different sets of non‐mental properties: either with role properties or with the specific structural properties that occupy or realize such roles in a given population. The identities proposed by the occupant functionalist may in fact be very much the same as those asserted by the psychoneural identity theorists, at least if the proposed identification is for a population‐ or species‐specific property such as ‘human pain’. The fact that very different structural properties might realize the pain role in different populations need pose no conflict for a suitably restricted version of occupant functionalism. If the structural properties that realize the pain role in octopuses or Martians are structurally very different from those that do so in humans, the occupant functionalist will conclude that human pain, octopus pain, and Martian pain are three distinct properties which merely play parallel roles in their respective contexts (Lewis 1980). The role functionalist might more probably regard the three groups as sharing a common mental property in virtue of instantiating the same

Page 9 of 28

Functionalism role property; namely, the property of having some state or other that plays the pain role for that population. Given the ability to draw the distinction and to individuate mental properties in both ways, one may wonder if there is a genuine dispute between the occupant and role functionalist, or merely a verbal disagreement. Is there really an independent fact of the matter about whether humans and Martians are in identical mental states or only in functionally similar mental states? Are there principled and compelling reasons to individuate mental properties in the one way rather than the other? If there are any such reasons, the burden would seem to be on the disputants to produce them, and it is not clear they have yet done so. Other versions of functionalism interpret it not as an ontological claim about properties, but as an analytical claim about mental concepts or predicates. According to what one might call ‘analytical functionalism’, mental concepts (or at least some particular set of mental concepts) can be analysed in purely functional terms; that is, the meanings of such concepts can be explicated in terms of conditions that can themselves be specified using only functional concepts. In contrast with ontological functionalists, who assert identities or reductions among real‐world items such as properties, analytical functionalists assert an identity or reduction among our ways of describing or thinking about the world; that is, they propose a representational or conceptual reduction rather than an ontological one. Such conceptual claims may vary in strength. A strong version of analytical functionalism may claim the ability to give strict necessary and sufficient conditions for mental concepts in solely functional terms. A more modest version might claim to give conditions that are necessary though not sufficient, or the converse, but ones that nonetheless elucidate critical aspects of our mental concepts. Claims of that latter sort might not qualify as offering a conceptual reduction, but may still explicate a critical functional aspect of our mental concepts. A non‐reductive analytical functionalist, for example, might concede that it is impossible to give strictly sufficient (p. 137) conditions for the mental in solely functional terms, but still hold that functional factors are essential for distinguishing among mental kinds; for example, our concept of a pain may be that of a state that is mental and that plays a given role. Conceptual claims of the more modest sort overlap at the borders with the third family of views about the relation between the mental and the functional, which might be labelled ‘pragmatic functionalism’ in contrast to the ontological and conceptual versions of the view. According to the pragmatic functionalist, attending to the functional roles played by mental states and processes can be of great use in theorizing about the mental, in helping us both to discover the nature of mental reality and to clarify our mental concepts. She regards functional models as a powerful tool for enhancing our understanding of the mental and its relation to the non‐mental. However, the pragmatic functionalist is not

Page 10 of 28

Functionalism committed to any ontological or conceptual reduction, and does not claim that functional roles and relations exhaust the nature of mental properties or mental concepts. There are thus many different versions of functionalism. To interpret the basic claim that mental states/kinds should be understood in terms of functional roles and relations one needs to specify which mental states are covered, which notion of function is involved, and what understanding the former in terms of the latter involves. The diverse answers one might give to those three questions generate a wide variety of functionalist theses as summarized in Table 7.1. Various cross‐combinations from the three columns are possible. The functionalist might ontologically identify the mental properties referred to by some empirical psychological theory with computational properties. Alternatively, she might claim our propositional‐ attitude concepts can be fully analysed in terms of teleological roles. Other (p. 138) functionalists might assert that human mental states can be usefully and practically modelled in terms of the reductively specified causal roles that they play. Indeed, a given functionalist might consistently support several such combinations. For example, some have analysed our folk concepts in terms of causal roles, and then argued that as an ontological matter the properties satisfying those concepts in humans should be identified with the neural properties occupying those roles. Table 7.1 Dimensions of Functionalism Which mental states?

Notions of ‘function’

Types of claims

All mental states

Computational

Ontological

Human mental states

 Realization

Rational states

 Identity

Propositional attitudes

  Role   Occupant

Folk mental states

Causal role

Analytical

 Experiential

 Reductive

 Strong

 Non‐experiential

 Non‐reductive

 Modest

Psychological states in empirical theories

Teleological

Pragmatic

Page 11 of 28

Functionalism  Personal

 Origin‐based

 Scientific

 Subpersonal

 Not origin‐based

 Social

7.3 Arguments for and against Functionalism Given the diversity of functionalist views, what counts as an objection or support will depend on the specific version of functionalism at issue. An argument relevant to analytic claims about propositional‐attitude concepts may or may not have any import for ontological issues about the status of properties referred to by various empirical theories. Indeed, even which factors support and which undermine shifts with perspective, like the blacks and whites of attack and defence on a Go board. Thus, in assessing arguments it is key to keep in mind which claim they aim to address.

Page 12 of 28

Functionalism

Coherence The very coherence of functionalism has been challenged from early in its history. The basic general claim that mental concepts or properties are functional in nature does not amount to much unless one can give a clear idea of what counts as functional and what distinguishes the functional from the non‐functional. Without any such distinction, the basic functionalist claim threatens to collapse from a lack of content. Some early versions of functionalism were explicitly intended as an alternative to type‐type psychoneural identity theory, and thus as offering a fundamentally different solution to the mind–body problem. If mental properties were functional, and neural properties were structural, then their relation should be understood as a matter of realization rather than identity, especially given the possibility of multiple realization. Moreover, the notion of realization provided a means of vindicating the physicalist claim that everything real is physical without needing to embrace outright type‐type identity. The physicalness of reality consists in the fact that everything real is physically realized. Realization can thus support a more robust physicalism than other non‐identity relations, such as the supervenience of the mental on the physical, which turned out to be compatible with non‐physicalist views such as property dualism. However, as critics noted, the structural/functional distinction extends well into the realm of the physical and the neural, and is relative rather than absolute. What counts as functional depends largely on how one chooses to individuate inputs and outputs and on the scheme of abstraction one selects (Kalke 1969). Are neurons, (p. 139) synapses, and dendrites structural kinds and realizers, or are they functional kinds open to multiple realizations? The answer will depend on our particular explanatory project. Should we count a twenty‐amp fuse and a twenty‐amp electromagnetic circuit breaker as different structures that realize the same functional kind? They both allow currents not exceeding twenty amps to flow through the circuit, and block currents above twenty amps. Or are they of different functional kinds because one burns through when overloaded and the other is pulled back by magnetic attraction and can be reset? Such questions have no absolute answer. In so far as the general functionalist claim appeals to an absolute functional/ structural distinction, its coherence is in doubt. In response, functionalists have rejected what William Lycan (1996) calls ‘two levelism’, the view that there is a single functional level and a single structural level. Complex systems such as animals or minds are organized on many levels each of which might be regarded as functional or structural with regard to those above or below it in a hierarchy of nested realizations. An adequate understanding of mind will require a multiplicity of theories and models to capture those many levels and their interactions. The fault of the psychoneural identity theory was not a matter of misidentifying mental properties with structural properties but of believing that all the

Page 13 of 28

Functionalism properties relevant to understanding the mind were to be found at a single relatively anatomical level. Thus, the general functionalist point about realization remains. Indeed, realization is more crucial than ever to understanding the mind‐body relation; it is the basic link that ties together the many levels one needs to explain. As to more specific versions of functionalism, their coherence will depend on the particular ways in which they spell out their respective notion of function and on how successfully they draw the needed distinctions at each relevant level. The multilevel aspect of functionalism also provides the means to reply to a common charge of circularity lodged against functionalism.

Circularity and the Functional Theorist'S Dilemma In so far as the functionalist aims to explain key mental features such as intentionality, rationality, or consciousness in terms of functional relations, she confronts a version of the theoretician's dilemma. If she restricts herself to relations that do not presuppose those very features, her model is likely to prove inadequate, but if they do involve such features then circularity threatens. The functionalist confronts the general problem of trying to explain or construct consciousness or intentionality from components that are themselves devoid of those features, and the task may seem insuperable. How could items devoid of content or phenomenal character satisfy the sorts of relations that seem needed to realize intentional or conscious states. The gap between non‐mental realizers and realized mental features seems too large. Here the multilevel nature of functionalism is again crucial. The gap between non‐mental realizers and sophisticated mental features such as consciousness and propositional intentionality need not be bridged by a single level of realization, but might (p. 140) instead be produced by a series of nested levels of realization, many of which involve cruder, less fully realized versions of the critical mental aspects. The approach relies on the assumption that the relevant features of mind, such as intentionality and content, can occur in many forms, some less sophisticated than others, and that items with those simpler forms might be combined in suitable systems to realize more sophisticated forms. One need not jump from non‐contentful neurons that operate without any understanding to full‐blown intelligent rational agents in a single step. Rather, one might realize simple subsystems with only a crude and limited form of content or understanding and then combine them into successively more complex levels with an increase in the type and degree of intelligence and content at each ascending level (Dennett 1978). The method is sometimes referred to as ‘homuncular functionalism’, in reference to the idea that subsystems and sub‐subsystems might be thought of metaphorically like ‘little men’ or sub‐personal agents performing various tasks within the mind (Lycan 1981, 1987). The aim is to decompose a sophisticated personal‐level mental feature such as propositional‐attitude agency into an interaction between sub‐personal components that are individually less intelligent and possess a less sophisticated form of content than the Page 14 of 28

Functionalism person whom they realize. Each of those sub‐personal modules or ‘agents’ would then in turn be decomposed into systems of interacting sub‐subcomponents that are even less capable, with the basic process being reiterated as many times as needed until all the intelligence and understanding have been discharged at a level that can be fully realized by purely non‐contentful components that require no understanding to perform their roles—what Dennett (1978) has called the ‘army of idiots’. Whether the strategy can in fact succeed for all the relevant mental features remains controversial, with special reservations about those features associated with phenomenal consciousness. Even if intelligence, understanding, and content admit of degrees in the way required by homuncular functionalism, it is less clear that phenomenality does so. Nonetheless, it may do so, and the multilevel approach in general gives the functionalist important theoretical tools for bridging the gap between the mental and the non‐mental. The overall status of functionalism as a theory of mind depends largely on its success in dealing with the major features of mind. In so far as some supposed mental aspect is indeed a real feature of mind, the functionalist should be able to explain it within her general framework. Of course, not everyone agrees about which features of mind are real and need to be accommodated. Some, for example, might deny the reality of free will or the self. However, almost everyone agrees that functionalism needs to address the three big Cs: content, causation, and consciousness. Indeed, many of the standard anti‐ functionalist objections appeal to its supposed inadequacy with regard to one of the three. There is, however, disagreement about what an adequate account would require. More reductionist versions of functionalism may need to provide strict necessary and sufficient functional conditions for the relevant concepts or to specify the essential nature of the relevant properties. However, other more pragmatic versions of the (p. 141) view might be content merely to show that functional considerations can provide important and useful insight into describing and explaining those features of mind. Content. Intentionality is a pervasive feature of the mental. Many, if not all, mental states are about things and have content. It is difficult to imagine how anything could be a perception, a memory, a belief or desire, or even an emotion or a sensation if it lacked all content and was not about anything. An adequate theory of mind needs to provide both a general account of how intentionality comes to exist and also some account of why specific mental items have the particular intentional contents that they do. Moreover, it needs to address not only what given states are about but how they conceptualize or represent their objects. It thus must provide an account of the sense and modes of presentation associated with mental states as well as of their objects and conditions of satisfaction. Giving such accounts would be a project far beyond the scope of this chapter. What matters for present purposes is that virtually all the current major theories of intentionality and content are in one way or another functionalist. There are many disagreements in the intentionality literature—for example between individualist models Page 15 of 28

Functionalism and externalist ones or between causal‐role theories and teleological ones— but most of them are ‘in house’ disputes; that is, disagreements about how to proceed within a general functionalist framework. Among the current models of intentional content are those that appeal to conceptual role, causal history, informational semantics, nomic covariance, teleological function, and role in adaptive behavioural guidance. There is no consensus as to which is best, and indeed there is good reason to want a plurality of different ways of thinking about content for various explanatory purposes. Nonetheless, they are all basically functionalist theories that explain content in terms of the roles that mental items play within complex relational networks. Functionalism provides the basic structure for thinking about intentionality, and most of the major controversies in the literature concern how to set various parameters within that framework. Some limit the relevant networks to relations purely within the mental agent, for example narrow conceptual‐role theories, while others extend the network out into the physical, social, and historical world, as in various externalist or wide‐conceptual‐ role theories. Some accounts specify the roles in a purely causal or computational way, while others appeal to teleological notions. Some models are holistic and appeal to a large array of relations in fixing content; others fix content more locally on a smaller relational base. Some take the primary bearers of content to be representations, and others regard mental states as primary, but in either case the respective models of content appeal to relational facts about the relevant items. Despite their disagreement along these many parameters, all the major theories explicate content in terms of realized roles within relational networks, and they are thus all functionalist in their basic approach. One might of course deny that any of the current theories is likely to provide an adequate account of intentionality. But in so far as one has any optimism about the state of current theorizing on the topic, one should regard that as a factor in favour of functionalism.

(p. 142)

Causation

The causal status of the mental is more controversial. For example, some philosophers deny that ordinary intentional explanations are causal (Dennett 1978; Bennett 1992). They regard folk psychology as a heuristic interpretative structure that is useful in predicting and making sense of complex patterns of behaviour; indeed, one that is essential for our normal social interaction. Nonetheless, they deny that such explanations are causal or that they appeal to mental states as inner causes. However, most philosophers do regard at least many mental states and properties as causally relevant or potent, and they fear that any account of mind that could not account for its causality would collapse into an unacceptable form of epiphenomenalism; that is, the view that the mental is causally inert.

Page 16 of 28

Functionalism Some anti‐functionalist objections fault it for supposedly failing to accommodate the causality of the mental in a sufficiently robust way. In particular, they argue that on the functionalist view all the causal work is done by the underlying realizers, and that the realized functional properties are mere higher‐order constructions that add nothing in terms of real causality. They are carried along as epiphenomena by the realizers which have already done all the causal work there is to do (Kim 1996). The price of functionalism according to such critics is the causal impotence of the mental. To get real mental causality, they argue, one must go back to some form of identity theory. Since the underlying physical properties are doing all the causal work, the only way that mental properties could themselves be causal is if they are indeed the very same properties. Thus, if the physicalist wishes to accommodate our strong intuition that mental properties are causal, she must reject the functionalist's view of the mind–body relation as a matter of realization between distinct properties, and go back to some form of at least localized or species‐specific type‐type identity theory. The problem of mental causation raises far more issues than can be addressed in this chapter, but the functionalist has some reasonable basic responses that can be briefly stated. Most importantly, it is far from obvious that real causality resides only at the realizer level. This might be so for those versions of functionalism that regard functional properties as abstract logical constructions, but many versions do not and instead treat them as concrete systemic features. It is true that their reality depends upon their underlying realizers, but the causal powers of the realized feature derive not only from those of its realizers but also from the systematic way in which they are combined and organized in order to realize that feature. The amplifier in a stereo system really can boost the power of a signal while maintaining its frequency profile, and one's immune system really can produce resistance to many pathogens one encounters. Similarly, one's memory can keep track of where one left one's keys and direct where one looks when one needs them. The abilities and powers of immune systems and memory systems admittedly depend upon the more limited powers of their many realizers. But that does not imply that such systems do not really have those powers. They do indeed have them. And they do so because of the way in which their specific realizers have been recruited and incorporated into the (p. 143) requisite organized general pattern, which is often highly stable and self‐maintaining despite a continuous interchange of realizers (Van Gulick 1993a). Moreover, given that such features are open to a wide range of multiple realizations, it is useful to classify them as of a common kind in virtue of their shared systemic causal powers. Distinguishing among them on the basis of their differences in realization would lead to a loss of descriptive and explanatory power; real causal regularities would be hidden. Given the important patterns that persist at the higher level and that support causal and counterfactual reasoning, there is real value in recognizing causally relevant kinds at the system level (Fodor 1974).

Page 17 of 28

Functionalism Perhaps this would be enough to accommodate our intuitions about the causal status of minds and mental kinds. There might be a stricter more demanding sort of causal status that is found only in ultimate realizers which do not derive their causal powers from any more basic realizers. If so, mental features may lack that status, but that need not be an embarrassment to the functionalist. There is little reason to believe that we have any reliable intuitions about whether mental features are causal in that very demanding sense, and thus the functionalist has no need to accommodate them. Moreover, mental features turn out to be no worse in this regard than physiological, geological, or economic features. None of them is causal in that ultimate sense either, and if mental features are as causally robust as chemical and neural ones, then the functionalist need not be much concerned with the threat of epiphenomenalism.

Consciousness The largest number of anti‐functionalist objections concern its alleged inability to deal with consciousness. Of course, what doing so requires will depend on which properties consciousness really has. The functionalist may deny some of its traditional properties, but at a minimum she must give an account of the basic difference between creatures or mental states that are conscious and those that are not. In so far as conscious perceptions or memories differ importantly from non‐conscious ones, functionalism must address that difference and the general nature of state consciousness. Similarly, it needs an account of creature consciousness and the distinctive mental lives of conscious beings. Both distinctions—state and creature—get drawn in diverse ways, some of which are easier for the functionalist to accommodate. States can be said to be conscious in the access sense if their contents are reportable and broadly available for a rich range of inference and application. They can alternatively be said to be conscious in the phenomenal sense if there is an experiential feel associated with being in such a state, some ‘way it is like from the inside to be in such a state’. The two senses may not always coincide and the former access sense fits more easily into the functionalist framework, since it is primarily a matter of relations and interactions among various contentful items. By contrast, the phenomenal aspect of consciousness may seem more difficult and resistant to the functionalist's approach. (p. 144)

As with intentionality, many of the current theories of consciousness, whether philosophical or scientific, are of a basically functionalist sort. For example, representational theories aim to explicate consciousness solely in terms of intentional notions such as content and perhaps modes of presentation. According to the representationalist, a conscious perceptual experience has no mental properties beyond its representational and intentional ones (Tye 2000). Other theories explain consciousness in terms of self‐awareness and higher‐order intentional content (Lycan 1987; Rosenthal 1997). On such views, a conscious mental state, for example a conscious desire, is simply Page 18 of 28

Functionalism a state one is aware of being in. That self‐awareness consists in having a higher‐order thought (HOT) or higher‐order perception (HOP) directed at the relevant lower‐order state. What makes a desire a conscious desire is the accompanying higher‐order state directed at it. Thus, higher‐order theories also explicate consciousness in terms of intentional relations. In so far as intentionality is itself to be explained functionally, such theories ultimately explain consciousness in functional terms. Yet other theories explain the difference between conscious and non‐conscious states as a matter of degree of influence and interaction within the mind. On such models, a mental state's being conscious is a matter of its cerebral celebrity (so called ‘fame in the brain’) or of its content being ‘broadcast in a global workspace’ which makes it available for use to a wide number of mental modules (Dennett 1991). Some models combine elements of wide‐scale integration with a form of higher‐order awareness. They explain the transition from non‐conscious to conscious state as a matter of its ‘recruitment’ into a globally integrated state which embodies an implicit reflexive aspect in its content. On such higher‐order‐global‐state (HOGS) models, the higher‐order content is carried not by a separate HOT or HOP directed at the conscious state, but is implicit in the content of the conscious state that results from the global integration (Van Gulick 2007). For example, the content of a conscious perceptual state is not merely that the world contains such‐and‐such objects but that those objects are present to and from the perspective of an experiential subject located within that world. The integration serves in part to construct the unity of that world as well as the unity of the ongoing self‐ perspective from which that world is experienced. Once again the sorts of multilevel systemic relations that such models involve are of just the sort that functionalist theorizing is ideally suited to deal with. Thus, despite their differences, these various theories all take a basically functionalist approach to consciousness. Nonetheless, the anti‐functionalist may deny that any of them is really adequate. Even if most currently available theories are functionalist, that would not count for much if none of them really does justice to the reality of consciousness. Indeed, some philosophical arguments aim to show that no functionalist theory could ever be adequate, because there are essential features of consciousness that inevitably fall outside their scope. In particular, they aim to show by a priori means that functional criteria alone are insufficient to capture the nature of consciousness in the phenomenal sense and of the experiential qualia associated with it (Chalmers 1996). (p. 145)

Many such arguments appeal to the supposed possibility of bizarre realizations or of realizations that involve so called ‘inverted qualia’ or ‘absent qualia’. They claim to show that any set of functional conditions can be realized by diverse systems that differ in their qualia or that lack any qualia whatsoever. If so, then it might seem that qualia must fall outside the scope of functional theorizing (Block 1980a).

Page 19 of 28

Functionalism Inverted‐qualia cases involve the possibility of two individuals, call them Norm and Flip, who are totally alike in their functional organization but experience different qualia when they perceive a given sort of object. When they look at lime, they both call it ‘green’, and the inner states produced play the same functional role in each of them, but the quale associated with that state in Flip is the one associated with the states produced in Norm by ripe tomatoes. However, if their respective qualia have always been as they are, the difference between them would be undetectable and would make no functional difference. Thus, the critic concludes that functionalism fails to capture a real mental difference between Norm and Flip and in general fails to capture the nature of specific qualia. Absent‐qualia arguments make the even more radical claim that any set of functional conditions can be realized by systems which possess no qualia at all; that is, by systems for which there is nothing that it is like to be them. Such a realization, call it Zip, would be in effect a functional zombie, that is, a system that was like conscious beings in every functional respect but which nonetheless was not itself conscious in the phenomenal sense. If Zip were indeed possible, functionalism might be faulted for failing to capture not merely the nature of specific qualia but even the general notion of qualia, and thus failing completely as an account of phenomenal consciousness. The supposed possibility of both inverted‐ and absent‐qualia cases is supported largely by appeal to intuitions about what can be imagined or conceived. The anti‐functionalist asserts that given any functional specification, it is always possible to imagine its being realized in ways that invert or lack qualia. These intuitions about what is imaginable are taken to show that they are conceivable in a sense that implies that they are at least logically possible. However, functionalists have challenged both the possibility of such imagined cases as well as the conclusions drawn from them. The coherence of inverted‐qualia cases has been challenged both on a priori conceptual grounds and on empirical evidence about the structure of our sensory colour space. On the conceptual side, doubts have been raised about whether any real sense can be attached to the idea of intersubjective differences between essentially private properties (Wittgenstein 1953). How could be there ever be any evidence or criterion for verifying that there was or was not such a difference, since by stipulation normal and inverted individuals are supposed to be the same in all behavioural and functional respects? And if no verification procedure is even possible, the inverted‐qualia hypothesis may be in danger of becoming a meaningless pseudo‐possibility (Dennett 1991). The conceptual coherence of inverted qualia has been defended by appeal to the possibility of intrasubjective step‐by‐step partial inversions that would together result in an overall inversion (Shoemaker 1982). Each partial step would be detectable. (p. 146) However, the organization and behaviour of the person at the end of the series would be functionally equivalent to that at its start despite the fact that the specific qualia playing

Page 20 of 28

Functionalism the relevant roles were not the same. In so far as each of the partial shifts is coherent, so too, it might seem, must be their sum. Other functionalists have challenged the possibility of inverted qualia on empirical grounds. The actual structure of phenomenal colour space involves several asymmetries, such as the existence of more discriminable hues of green than of yellow, that may make it impossible to shift or invert qualia without producing detectable functional and behavioural differences, especially with regard to the similarities and phenomenal relations among qualia playing various roles (Hardin 1986). In reply, some anti‐ functionalists concede that our actual human colour space may not be invertible but argue that there are other possibilities sufficient to make their point: either that of creatures with more symmetric qualia spaces or of so called ‘alien qualia’; that is, non‐ human creatures whose qualia space is structured just like our human colour space but involves different specific qualia (Shoemaker 1981). Qualia inversions may thus seem possible for those who regard qualia as intrinsic properties of perceptual states. However, those who equate qualia with representational contents will deny the absent‐qualia possibility (Harman 1990; Dretske 1995). On such a view, a state's qualitative character or what‐it‐is‐likeness consists in how it represents the world as being. Most representationalists also hold that a state's content depends upon its functional relations to items in the world; for example, on what objective properties it reliably tracks. Thus, if all those relations were preserved, its content would remain unchanged and so too would its qualitative feel. So given a relational‐representational view of qualia, functionally identical qualia inversions are impossible. Moreover, even if the functionalist concedes that inverted‐qualia cases are possible, the consequences will depend on what her theory must explain to count as a success. If inverted qualia are possible, then functional conditions may suffice to identify only an equivalence class of qualia rather than a specific quale. Nonetheless, if those conditions could be satisfied only by creatures or systems with some qualia or other, that might suffice as a basic account of qualia and phenomenal consciousness. Absent‐qualia cases would pose a greater problem for the functionalist. Again, many functionalists have denied that they are possible, although their reasons for doing so have varied, depending in part on which version of functionalism they endorse. For the computational functionalist, the question is whether robots that shared all our computationally specifiable functional organization might nonetheless be such that there was nothing that it was like to be them. The causal‐role functionalist might ask whether any system could have a state P that played all the causal roles associated with being in pain but that nonetheless lacked any felt quale of hurtfulness. Could there be a pain zombie? Some functionalists have argued that nothing that was not a pain could play the full role of pain. In particular, they have argued that non‐pains could not typically give rise to beliefs about being in pain, at least not if one accepts a plausible (p. 147) functionalist Page 21 of 28

Functionalism view according to which the content of a belief or informational state is determined in large part by whatever features of the world it reliably tracks. Part of what makes my pain beliefs beliefs about pain is the fact that it is pains that typically cause them. Thus, non‐pain states could not play the role of typically causing pain beliefs, and pain zombies could not be functionally equivalent to normal humans in all the relevant respects (Shoemaker 1975a, 1982). Absent‐qualia advocates might reject such a move as circular, since it relies on beliefs that depend on qualitative states for their identity. Whether the functionalist may do so will depend on what resources he is allowed to invoke in specifying causal roles. There will be a trade‐off between sufficiency and explanatory power. The more the functionalist relies on quasi‐qualitative notions in specifying causal roles, the better his chance of ruling out non‐qualia realizations, but also the less his prospects for explaining qualia in non‐qualitative terms (Chalmers 1996). Other functionalists aim to exclude absent‐qualia realizations by defining qualia in terms of qualitative similarities among mental states that tend to produce perceptual judgements about objective similarities (Rosenthal 1991). They treat qualia as properties of perceptual states whose similarity relations produce beliefs about corresponding objective similarities among perceived objects. Again there is a tension between sufficiency and circularity, which in these models turns on how the relevant notion of similarity is defined. If the models require qualitative or phenomenal similarities among internal states, then non‐qualia realizations may be excluded (Shoemaker 1975b). However, if ‘similarity’ is interpreted more loosely, they seem open to absent qualia. As with phenomenal similarity and qualitative belief, the functionalist confronts a general dilemma concerning which concepts she can use in specifying functional roles. Whether those functions are thought of computationally, causally, or teleologically, there is the further issue of the degree to which qualitative or phenomenal concepts can be implicitly assumed in specifying the relevant relations and interactions. To the extent that they are not relied on, absent‐qualia realizations are hard to exclude, but to the degree they are assumed, circularity looms as a danger. The possibility of absent qualia might also be attacked by the causal‐role functionalist on the grounds that such cases implicitly assume that qualia are epiphenomenal; that is, that they lack any causal efficacy. If Zip's states play the same causal roles as Norm's despite the fact that they lack any qualia, then it would seem that Norm's qualia make no causal difference to his states (Shoemaker 1975a; Kim 2005). But that seems implausible. Does the hurt one feels when one bangs a shin not cause one to rub it, and could the yellow quale associated with one's visual experience of a banana really play no part in why one answers ‘yellow’ when asked to describe its colour? If absent‐qualia cases entail such negative causal results, that would be a strong reason against them.

Page 22 of 28

Functionalism Absent‐qualia defenders might deny the entailment by arguing that in absent‐qualia realizations other non‐qualia properties, call them ‘ersatz qualia’, play the causal roles normally played by qualia (Block 1980b). If so, absent‐qualia cases do (p. 148) not imply that qualia are epiphenomenal. They deny only that qualia play any unique causal roles that could not be duplicated by non‐qualia. The dispute again turns on the issue of how to specify roles. Do ersatz red qualia and genuine red qualia play the same role in different ways; that is, are they alternative realizers of one and the same role? Or do the roles they play differ in ways that matter to the functional classification, as the critic of absent qualia will argue? How could a state without any real qualia affect one's beliefs about one's perceptual experience in the same intimate way that one's genuinely qualitative perceptions do (Van Gulick 1993b)? Even if Zip says he is seeing red, the belief he expresses cannot have been produced by the same evidential link to his perceptual states, because those states have no red qualia of the sort his beliefs supposedly refer to. Defenders of absent qualia, on the other hand, will dismiss any such differences as insignificant variations in how the very same role is realized in Zip and Norm. Thus, the possibility of absent‐qualia cases will depend on whether the functionalist can specify the relevant roles in a way that is non‐circular but nonetheless identifies roles that could be filled only by states with genuine qualia. In so far as the absent‐qualia proponent aims his attack not just at present functionalist models but at the future prospects of the basic approach, he needs to show that the functionalist cannot succeed in specifying such roles, and that is very hard to do. To simply insist that any roles specified in the future will always be open to absent‐qualia realizations would seem to beg the question against the functionalist programme. Although most qualia‐based objections to functionalism have appealed to inverted or absent qualia, others have appealed to bizarre realizations or the intrinsic nature of qualia. The bizarre‐realizations objection has been raised most often against computational versions of functionalism. It has been argued that the roles specified in such models are so abstract that they could be instantiated by bizarre systems that could not plausibly involve any qualia or what‐it‐is‐likeness. Searle (1982) imagines satisfying all the required computational relations with a system in which stones are moved algorithmically in and out of beer cans, and Block (1980a) suggests doing so with a system composed of the entire population of China linked by two‐way radio (or cellphones in a more current version). The claim is that such bizarre realizations could not literally have qualia states or be conscious in the what‐it‐is‐like sense. In reply, some computational functionalists have denied that such weird systems could satisfy the relevant computational conditions, especially if real‐time constraints were included (Dennett 1991); they would for example be far too slow. Others have simply replied that such bizarre realizations would be phenomenally conscious, strange though they would be (Churchland 1985). Non‐computational functionalists regard such

Page 23 of 28

Functionalism examples as showing at most the inadequacy of computational functionalism, not of functionalism per se. Functionalism faces another possible challenge, from those who view qualia as intrinsic properties of internal mental states or objects. The functionalist defines mental kinds in terms of the roles they play within a systematic network of interrelated states and processes, and such functional kinds seem to be paradigmatically relational. How could any such relational kinds be identical with qualia, if the latter (p. 149) are intrinsic properties of mental states? In so far as what is intrinsic is by definition non‐relational, any functionalist account of intrinsic qualia would seem straightforwardly inconsistent (Kim 2005). Functionalists might reply in at least two ways. First, they could reject the view of qualia as intrinsic properties of mental states. For example, some representationalists (Tye 1995) identify qualia with the contents of our perceptual states. They argue that such contents are the only mental features to which we have introspective access, and it is those contents that determine what is it like to be in such a state. What it is like to see a yellow banana is just to be in a visual state whose content is that there is a yellow banana in front of me. However, if a state's content is determined largely, if not wholly, by causal and informational links it bears to items in the world, then that content is a relational property of the state rather than an intrinsic one. If so, the relational nature of functionalism poses no difficulty in dealing with qualia. A second, more radical, strategy would be to rethink how the intrinsic/extrinsic distinction applies to complex many‐levelled systems, with special attention to how underlying relational networks or structures might realize items or states with intrinsic properties at a higher level. The functionalist might be able to explain qualia as real intrinsic properties of states at one level of organization that were realized by functionally characterized networks of items at a lower level. Consider the analogy with current computer‐based ‘virtual realities’. Objects in such a reality can have intrinsic properties even though the entire reality depends upon and is realized by relational links and operations in the computer bases that support it. It is unclear at present whether the functionalist could explain qualia in a similar way as intrinsic but relationally realized. Nonetheless, it seems an option worth exploring. Functionalism in one version or another remains the dominant view of mind among philosophers. The general functionalist framework provides important tools for dealing with the mind–body problem, intentionality, mental causation, and even consciousness. It has significant critics, but none of the objections that have been raised against it seems decisive, and functionalists have made plausible responses in every case. Debate will no doubt continue.

References

Page 24 of 28

Functionalism Armstrong, D. (1968), A Materialist Theory of Mind (London: Routledge). Baker, L. (1995), Explaining Attitudes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Bennett, J. (1992), ‘Folk Psychological Explanations’, in J. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 176–95. Block, N. (1980a), ‘Troubles with Functionalism’, in N. Block (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, i (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 268–305. —— (1980b), ‘Are Absent Qualia Impossible?’, Philosophical Review, 89: 257–74. Burge, T. (1986), ‘Individualism and Psychology’, Philosophical Review, 95: 3–45. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Churchland, P. M. (1985), ‘Reduction, Qualia, and Direct Introspection of Brain States’, Journal of Philosophy, 82: 8–28. (p. 150)

Cummins, R. (1975), ‘Functional Analysis’, Journal of Philosophy, 72: 741–64.

Davidson, D. (1987), ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60: 441–58. Dennett, D. (1969), Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge). —— (1978), Brainstorms (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1987), The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston, Mass.: Little, Brown). Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Fodor, J. (1974), ‘Special Sciences’, Synthese, 28: 97–115. Grice, H. P. (1975), ‘Method in Philosophical Psychology’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48: 23–53. Hardin, C. (1986), Colour for Philosophers (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett). Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Hempel, C. G. (1949), ‘The Logical Analysis of Psychology’, in H. Feigl and W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York: Appleton‐Century‐Crofts), 373–84. Kalke, W. (1969), ‘What is Wrong with Putnam and Fodor's Functionalism’, Noûs, 3: 83– 94. Page 25 of 28

Functionalism Kim, J. (1996), Philosophy of Mind (Boulder, Col.: Westview). —— (2005), Physicalism, or Something Near Enough (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Lewis, D. (1972), ‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50: 249–58. —— (1980), ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’, in N. Block (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 122–32. Lindsay, P., and Norman, D. (1977), Human Information Processing (New York: Academic). Lycan, W. (1981), ‘Form, Feel and Function’, Journal of Philosophy, 78: 24–50. —— (1987), Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Nagel, E. (1977), ‘Teleology Revisited’, Journal of Philosophy, 74: 261–301. Place, U. T. (1956), ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’, British Journal of Psychology, 47: 44–50. Putnam, H. (1965), ‘Brains and Behaviour’, in R. J. Butler (ed.), Analytical Philosophy, 2nd ser. (Oxford: Blackwell), 1–19. —— (1967a), ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in W. Capitan and D. Merril (eds.), Art, Mind and Religion (Pittsburgh, Pr.: University of Pittsburgh Press), 37–48. —— (1967b), ‘The Mental Life of Some Machines’, in H. Castaneda (ed.), Intentionality, Mind and Perception (Detroit, Mich.: Wayne State University Press). —— (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press), 131–93. Rosenthal, D. (1991), ‘The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory Quality’, in E. Villanueva (ed.), Consciousness (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview), 15–36. —— (1997), ‘A Theory of Consciousness’, in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Guzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 729–54. Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes & Noble). Searle, J. R. (1982), ‘The Myth of the Computer: An Exchange’, New York Review of Books, 29/11: 56–7. Page 26 of 28

Functionalism Shoemaker, S. (1975a), ‘Functionalism and Qualia’, Philosophical Studies, 27: 291–315. —— (1975b), ‘Phenomenal Similarity’, Critica, 7: 3–37. —— (1981), ‘Absent Qualia Are Impossible’, Philosophical Review, 90: 581–99. —— (1982), ‘The Inverted Spectrum’, Journal of Philosophy, 79: 357–81. (p. 151)

Smart J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68:

141–56. Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2000), Consciousness, Colour, and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Van Gulick, R. (1982), ‘Functionalism as a Theory of Mind’, The Philosophy Research Archives, 8: 185–204. —— (1993a), ‘Who's in Charge Here and Who's Doing All The Work?’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 233–56. —— (1993b), ‘Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?’, in M. Davies and G. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays (Oxford: Blackwell), 134–54. —— (2007), ‘Mirror‐Mirror, Is That All’, in U. Kriegel and K. Williford (eds.), Self‐ Representational Approaches to Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 11–42. Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (New York: Macmillan). Wright, L. (1973), ‘Functions’, Philosophical Review, 82: 139–68.

Robert Van Gulick

Robert Van Gulick is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Syracuse University.

Page 27 of 28

What is Property Physicalism?

Oxford Handbooks Online What is Property Physicalism?   Ansgar Beckermann The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0009

Abstract and Keywords Since the days of Democritus, Plato, and Aristotle the main concern of philosophers of mind has been whether there is an independent realm of the mental beyond the realm of the physical. This question has mainly been understood as that of whether there are independent mental substances — souls or selves. Most of what has been written in the philosophy of mind during the last seventy to eighty years, however, has instead been concerned with the question of whether there are independent or irreducible mental properties. To many it has seemed obviously true that there are no mental substances, but with properties things are different. The history of answers to questions such as ‘Is being in pain or thinking about Paris really something physical?’ (including the answers associated with logical behaviourism, the identity theory, functionalism, and supervenience theories) has been told time and again. Nonetheless, it is worth taking a new look at it. Keywords: mental substances, philosophy of mind, mental properties, logical behaviourism, identity theory, functionalism

Page 1 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? SINCE

the days of Democritus, Plato, and Aristotle the main concern of philosophers of

mind has been whether there is an independent realm of the mental beyond the realm of the physical. This question has mainly been understood as that of whether there are independent mental substances—souls or selves. Most of what has been written in the philosophy of mind during the last seventy to eighty years, however, has instead been concerned with the question of whether there are independent or irreducible mental properties. To many it has seemed obviously true that there are no mental substances, but with properties things are different. Is being in pain or thinking about Paris really something physical? Do we have sufficient reason to believe that all mental properties are physical properties? However, it was not only the truth of property physicalism—the claim that all mental properties are physical properties—that was at issue. Most of the debate has rather been concerned with the question of what property physicalism amounts to. What has to be the case in order to make property physicalism true? The history of answers to this question (including the answers associated with logical behaviourism, the identity theory, functionalism, and supervenience theories) has been told time and again. Nonetheless, it is worth taking a new look at it.

Page 2 of 26

What is Property Physicalism?

8.1 Property Physicalism as Requiring Identity The most obvious answer to the question of what property physicalism amounts to is this: Property physicalism is true if and only if all mental properties are (identical (p. 153) to) physical properties. But what does it mean to say that a property is a physical property? Or, that a property is identical to a physical property? What does it mean to say that properties are identical at all? Obviously, Mark Twain and Samuel Clemens are identical if and only if the two names ‘Mark Twain’ and ‘Samuel Clemens’ refer to the same person.1 It would appear, therefore, that the same holds with regard to properties. Properties F and G are identical if and only if the predicates ‘F’ and ‘G’ stand for the same property (see n. 3 below). The decisive question, thus, is how we can find out whether that is the case. Of course the answer to this question essentially depends on what concept of property one endorses. Rudolf Carnap, whose articles (1932) and (1932/1933) rank among the most important early works on property physicalism, held the view that properties are the senses or intensions of predicates.2 For this reason, according to Carnap, two predicates stand for the same property just in case they have the same sense; that is, just in case they are synonymous (see also Hempel 1949). For Carnap property physicalism amounts to the claim that for each mental predicate there is a synonymous predicate in physical language. Or, in a nutshell: property physicalism requires synonymy. Carnap, however, not only held this view of property physicalism. He also thought that property physicalism in this sense is true. In his view, for example, the predicate ‘x is excited’ is synonymous with the expression ‘x’s body (especially his nervous system) has a physical structure that is characterized by a high pulse and rate of breathing, by vehement and factually unsatisfactory answers to questions, by the occurrence of agitated movements on the application of certain stimuli, etc.’ (1932/1933: 170 ff.). Why did Carnap assume these predicates to be synonymous? Because, according to the verificationist theory of meaning Carnap endorsed in the early thirties, predicates are synonymous if and only if they are applied on the basis of the same observations and because this, in Carnap's view, is true of the two predicates mentioned. Indeed, he thought the second predicate simply comprises an enumeration of these observations. This view, which has become known by the somewhat misleading name ‘logical behaviourism’, however, is untenable. As soon as the verificationist account of meaning was abandoned it became very clear that it is impossible to define the term, say, ‘wants a beer’ without including mental terms in the definiens. If someone wants a beer she will go to the refrigerator—but only if she believes that there is beer in the fridge, that she will not be shot if she goes to the fridge, etc. That someone takes an umbrella may be a sign that she believes that it is raining—but only if she doesn't take the umbrella in order to

Page 3 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? hide from curious gazes. Generally speaking, it turned out to be impossible to define mental predicates in physical language in a non‐circular way. (p. 154)

This finding, however, did not mark the end but rather the beginning of what today is known as ‘identity theory’. At the end of the 1950s Place and Smart argued that statements like ‘The temperature of a gas is identical to the mean kinetic energy of its molecules’, ‘Lightning is an electrical discharges’, and ‘Water is H2O’ are perfectly true identity statements though ‘temperature’ and ‘mean kinetic energy’—or for that matter ‘lightning’ and ‘electrical discharge’ or ‘water’ and ‘H2O’—are by no means synonymous (see Place 1956; Smart 1959). Nonetheless, ‘temperature’ and ‘mean kinetic energy’ stand for the same property—as physics has shown us.3 It is therefore at least possible that empirical science will arrive at the result that even ‘pain’ and ‘C‐fibre firing’ stand for the same property, though they are not synonymous. Place and Smart thus held the view that property physicalism amounts to the claim: Each mental property is identical to a physical property even if the corresponding predicates are not synonymous. Or, in other words: property physicalism does not require synonymy, just identity. But if this is the case, we are again confronted with the question: How do we find out that the mental predicate ‘M’ stands for the same property as the physical predicate ‘P’ if it is not by examining whether ‘M’ and ‘P’ are synonymous? In his seminal paper (1983) Joseph Levine made an important observation that has become the subject of much debate. Levine starts by comparing the following two property‐identity statements: (1) The temperature of a gas is identical with the mean kinetic energy of its molecules. and

(2) Pain is identical with the firing of C‐fibres. According to Levine, statement (1) is fully explanatory while statement (2) is not. The explanatory character of (1) rests on two facts:

(a) Our concept of temperature is exhaustively captured by the causal role of temperature. (b) Physics can render it intelligible that precisely this causal role is played by the mean kinetic energy of the molecules of a given gas. In other words, on Levine's view statement (1) is fully explanatory on the grounds that temperature is reductively explainable in terms of the mean kinetic energy of the molecules involved. Reductive explanation is a two‐step procedure. To show that property F is reductively explainable in terms of property G you will have to, first, give an analysis of F and, second, demonstrate that it follows from the basic laws of nature that all objects possessing property G satisfy this analysis.

Page 4 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? What is crucial is that Levine at least may be understood to claim that the truth of property‐identity statements of the form ‘F = G’ depends on whether it is possible (p. 155) to supply an explanatory reduction of F to G.4 If this were the case there would be a necessary connection between identity and reductive explainability. Property‐identity statements of the form ‘F = G’ could be true only if a reductive explanation of F in terms of G can be given. It is noteworthy that these considerations are in perfect accordance with what early exponents of the identity theory thought about the truth of non‐analytic identity statements. The generally accepted answer to the question why it should be supposed that the temperature of a gas is identical to the mean kinetic energy of its molecules was: ‘Because classical thermodynamics can be reduced to statistical mechanics’. It is easy to see that the basic idea is the same. First, on the basis of a semantics of theoretical terms widely recognized in those days, people assumed that expressions like ‘temperature’ are implicitly defined by the laws in the formulations of which they occur. Thus, the expression ‘temperature’ was supposed to be implicitly defined by the laws of classical thermodynamics; the meaning of ‘temperature’ consists in the causal role described by those laws. Second, from the reducibility of classical thermodynamics to statistical mechanics it follows that for all laws of classical thermodynamics it is possible to derive image laws from statistical mechanics (see Beckermann 2001a: 107–8); that is, laws showing that at the level of statistical mechanics there is a property (i.e. mean kinetic energy of molecules) playing exactly the causal role characteristic of temperature. In other words, since the meaning of the expression ‘temperature’ is implicitly defined by the laws of thermodynamics, it follows from the reducibility of classical thermodynamics to statistical mechanics that it is possible to give an explanatory reduction of the temperature of a gas to the mean kinetic energy of its molecules. From the very beginning the opinion prevailed that there is a very close connection between the identity of properties and their reductive explainability.

8.2 Property Physicalism as Requiring Reductive Explainability The importance of reductive explanation was also stressed in a quite different context. At the start of the twentieth century the question of whether life could be explained in purely mechanical terms was as hotly debated as the mind‐body problem is today. Two factions opposed each other: Biological mechanists claimed that the properties characteristic of living organisms could be explained mechanistically, in the way the behaviour of a clock can be explained by the properties and the arrangement of its cogs, springs, and weights. Substantial vitalists, on the other hand, maintained that the explanation envisaged by the mechanists was impossible and that one had to postulate a special non‐physical substance in order (p. 156) to explain life—an entelechy or élan vital.

Page 5 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? When C. D. Broad developed his theory of emergence in the early 1920s his aim was to create room for a third position mediating between these two extremes—a position he called emergent vitalism. Broad's first step was to point out that the problem of vitalism is only a special case of a much more general problem—the problem of how the properties of complex systems are related to the properties and the arrangement of their physical parts. Regarding this question, there are in principle only two basic types of response. One can hold the view that the properties of a complex system S can or cannot be explained by referring exclusively to its physical parts and their arrangement. But even if such an explanation is possible, there are two further possibilities—the properties may be either mechanistically explainable or emergent. In sum, the difference between emergent and mechanistic theories can be explained as follows: Put in abstract terms the emergent theory asserts that there are certain wholes, composed (say) of constituents A, B, and C in a relation R to each other; that all wholes composed of constituents of the same kind as A, B, and C in relations of the same kind as R have certain characteristic properties; that A, B, and C are capable of occurring in other kinds of complex where the relation is not of the same kind as R; and that the characteristic properties of the whole R(A, B, C) cannot, even in theory, be deduced from the most complete knowledge of the properties of A, B, and C in isolation or in other wholes which are not of the form R(A, B, C). The mechanistic theory rejects the last clause of this assertion. (Broad 1925: 61) Elsewhere (Beckermann 2000) I have tried to analyse this passage in detail and to show that it ultimately amounts to the following two definitions:

(ME) A macro‐property F of a complex system S consisting of parts C 1, …, C n arranged in way R, i.e. of a system with micro‐structure [C 1, …, C n; R], is mechanically explainable if, and only if, it follows from the general laws of nature holding for the component parts C 1, …, C n, and suitable bridge laws,5 that all objects with micro‐structure [C 1, …, C n; R] possess all features characteristic of F. (E) A macro‐property F of a complex system S with microstructure [C 1, …, C n; R] is emergent if, and only if, the following holds: (a) It is a true law of nature that all systems with micro‐structure [C 1, …, C n; R] have F; but (p. 157)

(b) it does not follow from the general laws of nature holding for component parts C 1, …, C n, and suitable bridge laws that all objects with microstructure [C 1, …, C n; R] possess all the features characteristic of property F.

Page 6 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? If this reading is correct, two points become clear straightaway. First, Broad agrees that mechanical explanation is a two‐step affair. Second, the two steps of Broad's account exactly correspond to the steps of Levine's account. The first task is to discover the analysis of the property F in question; that is, to find out the features characteristic of F.6 (For Broad, as a rule these features are characteristic forms of behaviour; for instance, the characteristic forms of behaviour of objects with the property of being magnetic.) And after that has been done, the task consists in showing that it follows from the general laws of nature that objects with a given microstructure possess the features characteristic of F. Thus, according to Broad, an advocate of property physicalism has to claim that mental properties are not emergent but mechanically—or, as we might say today, reductively—explainable.

Page 7 of 26

What is Property Physicalism?

8.3 Identity and Reductive Explainability Broad didn't claim that reductive explainability has anything to do with identity. He was not concerned about the identity of properties at all. But, as we have seen, on the basis of Levine's considerations one could be tempted to hold the view that property‐identity statements like ‘F = G’ are true only if it is possible to give a reductive explanation of F in terms of G. This is, however, certainly not a matter of course. For identity is a symmetrical relation while reductive explainability is an asymmetrical one. It is, therefore, not very surprising that in recent years all attempts at formulating criteria for the identity of properties have been subjected to a fundamental kind of criticism. In effect, this criticism amounts to the claim that identity is a relation which does not admit of any further analysis. Either properties are identical, or they are not. There is no instructive answer to the question ‘Why is it that F and G are identical?’. And that is why there are no criteria that properties would have to satisfy for being identical. The only admissible question is how to find out whether properties are identical; that is, how to find out whether ‘F’ and ‘G’ stand for the same property. This position has been urged with special emphasis by David Papineau (1998).7 In his view, every proponent of property physicalism has to endorse the identity theory. (p. 158) Papineau says that his ‘first task is to show that physicalism is best conceived as a thesis about property identity’ (1998: 374). But Papineau goes on to argue that the identity theory may be true even if it is not possible to reduce mental properties to physical ones. Identities either obtain, or they don't. It makes no sense to ask why it is that objects or properties are identical. And for this reason the question of how P manages to give rise to M does not even make sense for an identity theorist. Identical properties simply are identical, they do not give rise to each other. Nothing gives rise to itself. Objections similar to those mentioned by Papineau are raised by Block and Stalnaker in their criticism of the assumption that physicalists are committed to the claim that mental properties are reductively explainable. In Block and Stalnaker (1999) they argue that this could not possibly be the case. They hold that reductive explainability presupposes that a phenomenon F requiring explanation can be analysed in such a way that the only concepts employed in this analysis are those which also occur in our general laws of nature. According to Block and Stalnaker, however, this is not a general possibility, especially if we are dealing with mental phenomena. Consequently, as a rule, attempts at reductive explanation will come to grief. This, they insist, is no argument against physicalism. After all, a physicalist is merely committed to an assertion of identity; and mental properties may be identical with physical properties even if it is not possible to give a reductive explanation. Generally speaking, talk of criteria of identity is highly misleading. Instead of asking what conditions must be satisfied for property F to be identical with property G, we should ask what reasons justify the claim that F = G.

Page 8 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? In sum, the position put forward by Papineau, as well as by Hill, McLaughlin, and Block and Stalnaker, amounts to the following: (1) Identity has nothing to do with reductive explainability. In fact, if F and G are identical, you can't reduce one to the other; nothing reduces to itself. (2) The only thesis physicalists are committed to is that mental properties are identical with physical properties (see also Hill 1991; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; McLaughlin 2001). With regard to their first claim, I think Hill, McLaughlin, Papineau, and Block and Stalnaker are right. In early debates on the identity theory two quite different ideas were confounded—the idea of identity and the idea of reductive explainability. It should be noted that reductive explainability is compatible with multiple realizability; therefore it is not a sufficient condition for identity. However, it is not even a necessary condition. Water is a good example to elucidate this claim. Levine (1993) argues that though the truth of ‘water = H2O’ cannot be known a priori, it is indeed not conceivable that H2O should fail to manifest the characteristic macro‐ properties of water. For on the basis of the basic laws of nature we can deduce that H2O boils at 212 °F at sea level, that H2O is a liquid, that H2O is transparent, etc. (Levine 1993: 128–9). We have already seen that, in his view, this marks an important epistemic difference between the claim that water = H2O and the claim that pain = C‐fibre firing, since it is not in the same sense inconceivable that a person's C‐fibres are firing while at the same time the person does not feel any pain. But independently of Levine's view it is an important question whether it is a necessary (p. 159) condition for the truth of ‘water = H2O’ that we can deduce that H2O possesses the characteristic macro‐properties of water. Block and Stalnaker have argued that it is not. If we try to find out whether ‘water = H2O’ is true, we, rather, rely on considerations like the following. We know that heating causes water to boil. Furthermore, science tells us why increasing the mean kinetic energy of H2O molecules leads to a certain activity M of these molecules. If we assume that water = H2O, heat = mean molecular kinetic energy, and boiling = molecular activity M we, therefore, ‘have an account of how heating produces boiling … Identities allow a transfer of explanatory and causal force not allowed by mere correlations. Assuming that heat = mke, … etc. allows us to explain facts that we could not otherwise explain. Thus, we are justified by the principle of inference to the best explanation in inferring that these identities are true’ (Block and Stalnaker 1999: 23–4). Assuming that water = H2O, heat = mean molecular kinetic energy, etc. leads to a simpler and more coherent picture of the world. This is what justifies these identity statements. It is not necessary that we are able to deduce that H2O possesses the characteristic macro‐properties of water. In my view, the answer to the question of how we justify the claim that water = H2O is much simpler. We start from the background assumptions that water is a chemical substance and that chemical substances are individuated by their molecular structure. To find out whether water = H2O we, therefore, do nothing but collect some samples of

Page 9 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? water, bring them into a chemical lab, and ask the chemists to analyse the molecular structure of the samples. If the answer is that the molecular structure is the same in all cases, namely H2O, we have a result: water = H2O. However that may be, that reductive explainability is not a necessary condition for identity is shown by the following consideration. Assume that chemists tell us that the molecular structure of all submitted samples of water is H2O. And assume further that it is not possible to deduce from the fundamental laws of nature that H2O boils at 212 °F at sea level, that H2O is a liquid, that H2O is transparent, etc. What should we say in this situation? In my view, the answer is obvious. Water is still H2O, but all surfaces properties of water are emergent in Broad's sense. This may be incredible, but it is not impossible. Thus, we have to keep apart the idea of identity and the idea of reductive explainability (in Broad's sense).8 And we should carefully distinguish the view that physicalism amounts to the claim that all mental properties are identical to physical properties and the view that physicalism is true if all mental properties (p. 160) can be reductively explained in terms of physical properties. But isn't physicalism committed to the claim that everything is physical? Why should we think that the second view actually is a version of physicalism?

Page 10 of 26

What is Property Physicalism?

8.4 Property Physicalism as Requiring Supervenience ‘One notable development in the debates over the mind–body problem during the last dozen or so years … is the revival of type physicalism, the view that mental properties and kinds are identical with physical properties and kinds’ (Kim 2005: 121). This is indeed true, since in the 1960s and 1970s quite a number of arguments were raised against this theory, the most important of which was the argument from multiple realizability. Assume that the mental predicate ‘pain’ stands for a certain physical property; for example, the property C‐fibre firing. This would imply that only beings whose nervous system contains C‐fibres can be in pain. But is it really plausible to assume that animals with a quite different nervous system or robots that have silicon chips instead of neurons can have no pain, just because they do not have C‐fibres? On the contrary, it seems to be much more plausible to assume that having pain can be correlated with quite different physical structures in different beings. In reaction to this argument functionalism was developed: the claim that each mental state or property is characterized by a certain causal role. Functionalism maintains that, say, pain is characterized by the fact that it is caused by tissue damage, that it causes wincing and pain‐relieving behaviour, that it decreases the capacity to concentrate, etc. According to one version of functionalism,9 ‘is in pain’ refers to just this causal role. According to another (Lewis's) version, ‘is in pain’ works rather as a definite description —in each case it stands for just that state that realizes the causal role characteristic of pain in the being in question. Neither variant of functionalism, however, is a version of property physicalism, for neither implies that the states that realize the causal roles in question must be physical states.10 Thus, functionalism as such is neutral with regard to ontology.11 Out of functionalism, however, there grew a real alternative to the identity theory: the theory of supervenience. The basis of this theory is the idea that property physicalism might be true even if mental properties are not identical with physical properties— provided the realm of the mental is in an ontological way dependent on the realm of the physical, provided, that is, all mental facts are ontologically (p. 161) determined by the physical facts. The concept of supervenience was introduced to spell out this basic idea. Essentially, supervenience is a relation between families of properties. A family of properties B supervenes on a family of properties A if, and only if, there can be no differences among B‐properties without at least one difference among A‐properties. If α is a complete description of the distribution of all A‐properties in a given world and β is any statement about the distribution of B‐properties in that world, then B‐properties strongly supervene on A‐properties if the statement ‘If α then β’ is necessarily true for all β.12 The supervenience variant of property physicalism thus amounts to the claim:

Page 11 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? (SV) If π is a complete description of the physical world,13 and ψ is an arbitrary statement about the distribution of mental properties, the statement ‘If π then ψ’ is necessarily true for all ψ. In recent years Jackson has found the neat formula:

(MPD) Any possible world which is a minimal physical duplicate of our world is a duplicate simpliciter of our world. (1998: 13) For purposes of clarification he adds that ‘a minimal physical duplicate of our world is a world that (a) is exactly like our world in every physical respect (instantiated property for instantiated property, law for law, relation for relation), and (b) contains nothing else in the sense of nothing more by way of kinds or particulars than it must to satisfy (a)’ (1998: 13).

Taking these considerations into account, we now have an answer to the question of why the view that property physicalism requires reductive explainability should count as a version of physicalism. Reductive explainability implies supervenience. If all mental properties are reductively explainable in terms of physical properties, a complete description of the physical world analytically implies any statement about the distribution of mental properties and relations. But identity also implies supervenience. If mental properties are (identical with) physical properties there can, of course, be no difference in the distribution of mental properties without a difference in the distribution of physical properties. Thus, we seem to be confronted with two options: supervenience by reductive explanation or supervenience by identity. At least, to my knowledge no other versions of the supervenience theory have ever been seriously advocated. For this reason the supervenience theory does not lead to a new answer to the question of what property physicalism amounts to.

(p. 162)

8.5 A Priori versus A Posteriori Physicalism

Adherents of the view that physicalism requires identity and advocates of the view that physicalism requires reductive explanation may both subscribe to the claim: If physicalism is true, then the physical necessitates the mental in the strongest sense. It is, however, a much‐debated question whether this ‘necessitation is a priori, or whether we should instead put it in the category of the necessary a posteriori’ (Jackson 2005: 252). It is commonly agreed that philosophers who endorse the first option (‘a priori physicalists’) are at least committed to the following claim: If we knew all physical facts, we could infer solely from this knowledge without any further empirical research which things have which mental properties and which things stand in which mental relations to each other. To put it a little more precisely, a priori physicalists are committed to the claim: (AP) If π is a complete description of the physical world and ψ any statement expressing a mental fact, then ψ follows a priori from π.14

Page 12 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? Obviously, the reductive‐explanation theory is a version of a priori physicalism. If all mental properties are reductively explainable, we can deduce any ψ from π if we know the analysis of all mental predicates. The analysis of mental predicates, however, is knowledge each competent speaker is assumed to possess.

On the other hand, the views of Hill, McLaughlin, Papineau, and Block and Stalnaker seem to be versions of a posteriori physicalism, given that identity statements such as ‘Mark Twain = Samuel Clemens’ and ‘water is H2O’ can be known to be true only a posteriori. This, however, seems to imply that we cannot know their truth solely on the basis of knowing the meanings of ‘Mark Twain’, ‘Samuel Clemens’, ‘water’, and ‘H2O’. But things are a bit more complicated. It is certainly a semantic fact that the expressions ‘Mark Twain’ and ‘Samuel Clemens’ are rigid designators; that is, they refer to the same objects in all possible worlds.15 And it is also a semantic fact that ‘Mark Twain’ and ‘Samuel Clemens’ actually refer to the same object—the writer Mark Twain. Thus, everyone who knows that ‘Mark Twain’ and ‘Samuel Clemens’ are rigid designators which refer to the same object in the actual world is able to infer solely from this knowledge that ‘Mark Twain = Samuel Clemens’ is necessarily true. And the same holds for the proposition ‘Water is H2O’. Everyone who knows that the expressions ‘water’ and ‘H2O’ designate the same chemical substance in the actual world and that these expressions also are rigid terms standing for the same substances in all possible worlds is able to infer solely on this basis that ‘water is H2O’ is necessarily true. Thus, that (p. 163) the truth of propositions like ‘Mark Twain = Samuel Clemens’ and ‘water is H2O’ is not knowable a priori is not because these propositions are made true by concealed modal facts that can be known to hold only a posteriori. What makes them true is simply the fact that every object and every chemical substance is identical to itself in each possible world, and to know this we do not have to do any empirical research. Rather, that the truth of the propositions in question is not knowable a priori is because even competent speakers can know some of the crucial semantic properties only on the basis of empirical research.16 The fact that even competent speakers do not know all the semantic properties of the expressions of their language was noticed by Frege, who insisted that true identity statements of the form ‘a = b’ may be valuable extensions of our knowledge. According to Frege, the reason for this is that a competent speaker has to know the sense, but not the reference, of the expressions of her language.17 It may be the case that competent speakers of English will have to know that the expressions ‘evening star’ and ‘morning star’ designate heavenly bodies, but they need not know which heavenly body they designate, and consequently they need not know that they designate the same planet. Similarly, it may be that competent speakers of English have to know that the word ‘water’ stands for a certain chemical substance, but they need not know exactly what substance that is, and hence they need not know that, as a matter of fact, ‘H2O’ stands for the same substance.

Page 13 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? With regard to the view of Hill, McLaughlin, Papineau, and Block and Stalnaker, the upshot of these considerations is this. They claim that physicalism can be true only if all mental properties are identical with physical properties. And they interpret property‐ identity statements on the basis of the model of object‐identity statements. When identity theorists claim, for example, that pain is C‐fibre firing they, of course, do not mean to say that there are two different properties pain and C‐fibre firing which, as a matter of fact, are identical. (Different properties are never identical.) Rather, they mean that the property expressed by ‘pain’ is identical with the property expressed by ‘C‐fibre firing’. And since everything is identical to itself and to (p. 164) nothing else, this is the case if and only if ‘pain’ and ‘C‐fibre firing’ stand for the same property.18 If we knew which properties (or property) ‘pain’ and ‘C‐fibre firing’ stand for, we, therefore, could know a priori whether ‘pain = C−fibre firing’ is true. Yet even competent speakers of English do not know this semantic fact without empirical research. And for this reason the truth of ‘pain = C−fibre firing’ can be known only a posteriori. Or so it seems, since things are in fact even more complicated. The initial question was not what we could know a priori, but what we could derive a priori from the complete knowledge of all physical facts. And, at least at first sight, on the basis of this knowledge we could infer quite a lot of (if not all) semantic facts. Take ‘water’. Competent speakers know that the chemical substance we call ‘water’ is the stuff that we find in rivers and lakes, that falls from the clouds when it is raining, that comes from taps, etc. Obviously, it is a physical fact that this stuff is H2O. From this together with the fact that ‘H2O’ is the canonical name of H2O we can infer that ‘water’ and ‘H2O’ stand for the same substance. Chalmers and Jackson have maintained that this result can be generalized (see especially Chalmers 2002; Jackson 2003). Each name and each predicate, they argue, has a descriptive content—a set of features which, as competent speakers know, the object referred to by the name (or the substance expressed by the predicate) possesses in the actual world. Furthermore, if the features are physical features, it is a physical question which object or which substance actually possesses these features. On the basis of the complete knowledge of all physical facts we must, therefore, be able to tell in this case which object the name refers to or which substance is expressed by the predicate. A posteriori physicalists have to claim that even if we did know all the physical facts we would have to do more empirical research in order to find out whether ‘pain’ and ‘C‐fibre firing’ stand for the same property. But what kind of research could this be? If we really know all the physical facts, it after all seems to be an a priori affair to find out whether ‘F = G’ is true; that is, whether ‘F’ and ‘G’ stand for the same property.

8.6 The Semantics of Mental Predicates and the Practice of Science

Page 14 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? In the last section we saw that among identity theorists there are two factions. Members of the first faction argue that if identity statements like ‘pain = C−fibre firing’ are true their truth must follow a priori from a complete description of the physical world. Members of the second faction deny this claim. In their view, these identity statements may be true even if their truth does not follow a priori from a complete (p. 165) description of the physical world. However that may be, with regard to the question of what property physicalism amounts to we are finally left with the alternative: physicalism requires identity versus physicalism requires reductive explainability in Broad's sense. Let us assume that advocates of a posteriori identity will be able to cope with the argument from multiple realizability.19 Which arguments can be adduced to support one or the other of these two alternatives? Jaegwon Kim (2005) also starts from the observation that with regard to the problem of property physicalism there are two camps of philosophers. On the one hand, there are philosophers like the British emergentists, who hold that property physicalism can be true only if mental properties can be reductively explained in terms of physical properties. On the other hand, there are identity theorists, who deny the indispensability of reductive explanations. British emergentists were seriously worried about questions like ‘Why does pain, not itch or tickle, arise from C‐fibre firing?’, ‘Why and how does conscious experience arise from certain other neural states?’ (see e.g. Kim 2005: 94). Block and Stalnaker, on the other hand, argue that these questions are misguided. Identities cannot be explained. Properties are identical, or they are not. There is no instructive answer to the question, ‘Why is it that F and G are identical?: Identities [as Block and Stalnaker argue] should be seen not as helping to answer explanatory questions like ‘Why is Jones conscious whenever pyramidal cell activity is going on in the brain?’ but rather as neutralizing or dissipating them— that is, as showing that there is nothing here to be explained. Why is there water just where and when H2O is present? Why do the two correlate? The appropriate answer here is this: Water is just H2O, and there is here no correlation to be explained. (Kim 2005: 116–17) Kim argues that the emergentists' why‐questions have such prima facie urgency that Block and Stalnaker have to have very good arguments in order to overcome them. And this, he adds, is not the case. To my mind, however, there is a more direct way to show that the emergentists are right and Block and Stalnaker wrong. The reason why Block and Stalnaker's attempt fails is that, as I am going to argue, mental predicates belong to kinds of predicates that simply do not fit the identity theory.

The decisive issue is the semantics of mental predicates. In former times it was almost common ground among philosophers that the meaning of each predicate consists in a set of necessary and sufficient conditions. A predicate applies to an object if and only if these conditions are satisfied. With the advent of Kripke and Putnam philosophical common sense changed radically. Nowadays many seem to believe that all predicates (including all mental predicates) work rather like names—they, as it were, refer to properties; they Page 15 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? apply to an object just in case the object has the property referred to. Empirical research may reveal the nature of this (p. 166) property. But for the predicate to be true of an object, the object has to possess none of the known surface features of the property. Let us briefly rehearse Kripke's arguments. His aim was to show that certain linguistic expressions, in particular proper names and natural‐kind terms, function in ways different from those often presupposed. Names, he argues, are rigid designators always referring to the same object even in modal contexts. Something very similar is true with regard to natural‐kind terms. Here Kripke starts from situations of the following kind. Scientists invite a group of competent speakers of English to join them in their lab. The members of this group know that the usual gold they have so far been acquainted with is the chemical element with atomic number 79. Now the scientists indicate a substance possessing the same surface properties as our usual gold and say: ‘This is a substance we have discovered in a meteor that recently came down in Siberia; it is a kind of stuff the chemical structure of which is ABC’. How will members of the invited group respond to this? Basically, there are two possibilities. On the one hand, it is possible for them to reply: ‘How very interesting. Thus, there is a different substance with the same surface properties as gold’. But, on the other hand, it is also possible for the members of this group to remark: ‘How very interesting. Evidently there are other kinds of gold besides the chemical element with atomic number 79’.20 On the basis of linguistic intuitions Kripke professes himself certain that competent speakers of English would react in the former manner. And precisely this is his reason for thinking that the word ‘gold’, too, is a rigid designator—an expression which in all possible worlds designates one and the same chemical substance. If competent speakers of English react in the former manner this, however, does not only show that ‘gold’ is a rigid designator, it also shows that none of the known surface properties of gold is decisive for the applicability of the term ‘gold’. This term is used in English to refer to a certain kind of chemical substance. And chemical substances are individuated by their molecular structure. It is, therefore, the job of science to tell us what substance the term ‘gold’ actually stands for. Whether ‘gold’ applies to a given object depends only on its molecular structure, not on its surface properties. But, of course, what I would like to call the Kripke test could have had quite a different outcome. Take, for example, a situation in which scientists tell us: ‘Usually all substances that are water‐soluble have the microstructure UVW. But now we have found a substance with a very different microstructure which nonetheless dissolves when it is immersed in water’. To my mind, there can be no doubt that competent speakers would say that this new substance is water‐soluble. If a scientist proposed identifying water‐solubility with having microstructure UVW we would tend to declare this to be at least a little bit strange. We would say that the scientist just had not understood that objects are water‐ soluble if they dissolve when they are immersed in water. Unlike gold, water‐solubility has no nature that can be discovered by science; unlike ‘gold’, the term ‘water‐soluble’

Page 16 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? has an analysis. There are certain known characteristic surface features an object must have for the term ‘water‐soluble’ to apply to it. (p. 167)

Thus, there are two kinds of predicates. On the one hand, some—especially natural‐kind terms such as ‘water’, ‘gold’, etc.—work rather like names. They apply to kinds of things the nature of which has to be revealed by science. On the other hand, there are predicates like ‘transparent’, ‘water‐soluble’, and ‘poison’ which admit of an analysis. They apply on the basis of associated characteristic features.21 The fact that there are different kinds of predicates for which different kinds of questions are appropriate22 is well reflected in scientific practice. Sometimes, indeed, scientists try to discover the nature of the properties predicates stand for. They tell us what water is, what cats are, what clouds are, what lightning is, etc. They tell us the nature of things that, as it were, have a real essence. If we ask what water is, what clouds are, or what lightning is we get answers like ‘Water is the chemical compound H2O’, ‘Clouds are large amounts of water droplets in the sky forming white, grey, or black masses’, and ‘Lightning is a kind of electrical discharge’. And when we get these answers, there is no point in asking a further ‘Why?’. You just cannot explain why water is H2O, why clouds are large amounts of water droplets in the sky, or why lightning is an electrical discharges. That's how it is, and that's that.23 On the other hand, scientists do not tell us what the nature of water‐solubility is or what the nature of transparency is. We already know that; that is, we know the analyses of the corresponding predicates. An object is water‐soluble if and only if it dissolves when immersed in water. An object is transparent if and only if light passes through it. Water‐ solubility and transparency do not have a real, they just have a nominal essence. Nonetheless, scientists can tell us a lot of things about water‐solubility and transparency. They can tell us why salt is water‐soluble and why glass is transparent; that is, they can give reductive explanations of these facts. With regard to water‐solubility and transparency, scientists do not answer what‐, but why‐questions. It is just the other way round with regard to water and clouds. Let us have a look at a couple of examples. Common salt is a compound with the chemical structure NaCl. The metal sodium reacts with chlorine because chlorine atoms can complete their outer electron shell with the electrons given off by the sodium atoms. In this process sodium and chlorine ions are created, which exert strong electrical forces on each other and which, therefore, form a lattice structure. Because of the forces the ions exert on each other, common salt is solid. But it is nonetheless water‐soluble, since water molecules can—due (p. 168) to their dipolar structure—pull the sodium ions and the chlorine ions from their places within the lattice. The ability of soap to loosen dirt can also be traced back to the structure of its molecules. For materials like oils or fats that are not water‐soluble can be suspended and washed

Page 17 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? away when they are surrounded by molecules having a long lipophilic chain of hydrocarbon on the one end and a hydrophilic group of alcylcarboxylate on the other. And precisely this is true of soap molecules. Finally, the discovery of the double helix was the decisive breakthrough in understanding the chemical processes underlying the biology of reproduction and heredity. There are a number of things to note here. First, all these examples exhibit exactly the two‐step structure that is, as we have already seen, characteristic of reductive explanations. The first step is to give an analysis of the predicate in question, and the second step consists in showing that it follows from the basic laws of nature that objects with a certain microstructure satisfy this analysis. It would not suffice to say that the sodium and chlorine ions form a lattice structure which is responsible for the water‐ solubility of salt if it would not follow from the basic laws of nature that, due to their dipolar structure, water molecules have the ability to pull the ions from their places within the lattice. Second, these examples show that reductive explanations are ubiquitous in all sciences and especially in chemistry and biology. To give such explanations is at least as much an aim of these sciences as to discover general laws. Actually, at the bottom of the search for reductive explanations is what I would like to call the idea of the unity of the world. It is commonly agreed that our world has a layered structure. Atoms consist of elementary particles, molecules of atoms, cells of molecules, living beings of cells, social groups of living beings (see Kim 1998: 15). Time and again, new properties occur at higher levels. Atoms are neither solid nor fluid; only collections of molecules have these properties. Molecules again don't breath or nourish, nor do they reproduce; only living beings have these capacities. The idea of the unity of the world just consists in the claim that all properties of higher‐level entities have a reductive explanation in terms of the properties and the arrangement of their lower‐level parts. That salt is water‐soluble has an explanation in terms of the properties of the ions that salt molecules consist of. That soap has the capacity to loosen dirt can be explained by its molecular structure. That animals have the capacity to digest has a chemico‐physiological explanation, etc. It is, of course, an empirical question whether all higher‐order phenomena can be explained this way. The unity‐of‐the‐world thesis is not a priori true. But it seems to be an aim of science to show that it is an empirical truth. Let us come back to the decisive point. Sometimes scientists are quite content when they get an answer to the question ‘What is X?’. ‘Granite is a magmatic rock, composed primarily of feldspar, quartz, and mica.’ ‘Asthma is a chronic inflammation of the respiratory tract caused by antibodies produced by the humoral immune system in response to inhaled allergens.’ In these cases there is no room left for asking an additional ‘Why?’. On the other hand, there are also cases in which it is not only natural but perfectly legitimate to ask ‘Why?’. Why is salt water‐soluble? To answer (p. 169) this question, it will not do to just point to the fact that water has a certain molecular structure. Nothing short of a reductive explanation will suffice. One has to show that Page 18 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? having this molecular structure explains water‐solubility. If such an explanation can be given, everything is all right. The thesis of the unity of nature once more is proven to be true. If not, there would be, at this point at least, a breach in nature, as it were.24 The water‐solubility of salt would be revealed to be an emergent property—a real new property with effects that cannot be accounted for by the microstructure of salt. In accordance with scientific practice we should say that it is breaches in nature like the one just described that would prove physicalism to be false, at least physicalism with regard to the water‐solubility of salt. If we take scientific practice seriously we must distinguish. With regard to properties for which it suffices to answer what‐questions and for which why‐questions are inappropriate it is reasonable to understand property physicalism as requiring identity. However, with regard to properties which are expressed by predicates that admit of an analysis and for which why‐questions are perfectly legitimate property physicalism must be understood as requiring reductive explanation. Nothing is gained by saying water‐solubility is identical with having microstructure UVW. Here we can be content only if it is possible to show that it follows from the basic laws of nature that substances with this microstructure behave in just the way characteristic of water‐solubility. That is the reason for the intuitive impact of the explanatory‐gap argument.

8.7 What Property Physicalism Amounts To If it is admitted, however, that there are at least two kinds of predicates for which different kinds of questions are appropriate, we finally face the question of which kind of predicates mental predicates belong to. Exponents of analytic functionalism claim that the predicate ‘is in pain’ has an analysis. It is true of a person if the person is in a state which has a certain causal role—it is caused by tissue damage, it causes wincing and pain‐relieving behaviour, it decreases the capacity to concentrate, etc. Qualia friends hasten to add that the most important aspect is that this state has the characteristic qualitative character, that it feels painful to be in that state. Identity theorists oppose.25 On their view, ‘is in

(p. 170)

pain’ stands for a

property which empirical research will reveal to be, for example, a physical property. So let us do the Kripke test. Suppose empirical research has demonstrated C‐fibre firing to be the best candidate for being identical with being in pain. In our world beings feel pain if and only if their C‐ fibres are firing. Now consider the following counterfactual situation. Scientists invite a group of competent speakers of English to join them in their office. The members of this group know that the neural correlate for pain is C‐fibre firing. The scientists declare: ‘Recently we examined a group of original inhabitants living on a so‐far‐unknown island. Members of this group do not exhibit any characteristic pain behaviour even if their C‐ fibres are firing; what is more, none of them is reporting painful feelings. On the other Page 19 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? hand, members of the group exhibit pain behaviour and report painful feelings not if their C‐fibres but if their D‐fibres are firing’. Maybe the members of the invited group will be at a loss for a moment. But how will they describe the new situation? Again, there are two possibilities. On the one hand, it is possible for them to reply: ‘How very interesting. Thus, there are people who are in pain, but do not exhibit any characteristic pain behaviour nor experience any painful feelings. And, what is more, there seems to be another property which is sometimes associated with the characteristic features that usually accompany being in pain’. On the other hand, however, it is also possible for members of the group to remark: ‘How very interesting. Obviously, some people are not in pain though their C‐fibres are firing whereas others are in pain if their D‐fibres are firing’. If the members of the group described the new situation in the first manner, this would prove that in English ‘pain’ is a rigid designator referring to a certain property the nature of which has to be discovered by science. And if they described the situation in the second manner, this would show that in English ‘pain’ is used as a predicate that applies to a person just in case this person behaves in a certain way and has the right feelings. I am quite sure that they would describe the situation in the second way. And if so, this would show that ‘pain’ is akin to ‘transparent’ and not to ‘water’. Incidentally, this result is also supported by the fact Kim has stressed—the fact that it seems perfectly legitimate to ask questions like ‘Why does pain, not itch or tickle, arise from C‐fibre firing?’ and ‘Why and how does conscious experience arise from certain other neural states?’. For we have already seen that such why‐question are appropriate just in case we are dealing with predicates like ‘water‐soluble’ and ‘transparent’. If it is admitted, however, that mental predicates belong to this kind of predicates, they no longer fit the identity theory. Identity statements make sense only if the predicates involved work like names. It is only in this case that we can ask for the nature of the properties these predicates stand for. And it is only in this case that we can reasonably ask whether these properties are (identical with) physical properties. (p. 171) But if mental predicates belong to the same group of predicates as ‘water‐soluble’ and ‘transparent’, it is reductive explanation that is at issue. Just as we can legitimately ask for a reductive explanation of the fact that salt and sugar are water‐soluble, we can also legitimately ask for a reductive explanation of the fact that beings whose C‐fibres are firing feel pain. Physicalism with regard to mental properties, therefore, does not amount to the claim that all mental properties are physical properties. It rather amounts to the claim that all mental properties can be reductively explained in terms of physical properties; that is, that mental properties are not emergent in the sense of C. D. Broad.26

References Beckermann, A. (2000), ‘The Perennial Problem of the Reductive Explainability of Phenomenal Consciousness: C. D. Broad on the Explanatory Gap’, in T. Metzinger (ed.),

Page 20 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 41–55. —— (2001a), Analytische Einführung in die Philosophie des Geistes, 2nd, rev. edn. (Berlin, New York: de Gruyter). Beckermann, A. (2001b), ‘The Real Reason for the Standard View’, in A. Meijers (ed.), Explaining Beliefs: Lynne Rudder Baker and Her Critics (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI), 51–67. Block, N., and Stalnaker, R. (1999), ‘Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap’, Philosophical Review, 108: 1–46. Braddon‐Mitchell, D., and Jackson, F. (1996), The Philosophy of Mind and Cognition (Oxford: Blackwell). Broad, C. D. (1925), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Carnap, R. (1932), ‘Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft’, Erkenntnis, 2: 432–65; trans. as The Unity of Science (London: Kegan Paul, 1934). —— (1932/1933), ‘Psychologie in physikalischer Sprache’, Erkenntnis, 3: 107–42; trans. as ‘Psychology in Physical Language’, in A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism (New York: Free Press, 1959), 165–98. —— (1956), Meaning and Necessity, 2nd edn. (Chicago, Ill.: Chicago University Press). Chalmers, D. (2002), ‘Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?’, in T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 145– 200. Chalmers, D., and Jackson, F. (2001), ‘Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation’, Philosophical Review, 110: 315–60. Frege, G. (1892), ‘über Sinn und Bedeutung’, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, 100: 25–50; trans. as ‘On Sense and Nominatum’, in H. Feigl and W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York: Appleton‐Century‐Crofts, 1949), 85–102. Hempel, C. G. (1949), ‘The Logical Analysis of Psychology’, in H. Feigl and W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York: Appleton‐Century‐Crofts), 373–84. Hill, C. (1984), ‘In Defense of Type Materialism’, Synthese, 59: 295–320. —— (1991), Sensations: A Defense of Type Materialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Page 21 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? Hill, C., and McLaughlin, B. (1999), ‘There are Fewer Things in Reality than are Dreamt of in Chalmers' Ontology’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59: 445– 54. (p. 172)

Jackson, F. (1998), From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2003), ‘From H2O to Water: The Relevance to A Priori Passage’, in H. Lillehammer and G. Rodriguez‐Pereyra (eds.), Real Metaphysics (London: Routledge), 84–97. —— (2005), ‘The Case for A Priori Physicalism’, in C. Nimtz and A. Beckermann (eds.), Philosophie und/als Wissenschaft. Philosophy—Science—Scientific Philosophy (Paderborn: Mentis), 251–65. Kim, J. (1998), Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind–Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2005), Physicalism, or Something Near Enough (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Kripke, S. (1971), ‘Identity and Necessity’, in M. K. Munitz (ed.), Identity and Individuation (New York: New York University Press), 135–64. Levine, J. (1983), ‘Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 354–61. —— (1993), ‘On Leaving Out What It's Like’, in M. Davies and G. W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness (Oxford: Blackwell), 121–36. Lewis, D. (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell). McLaughlin, B. (2001), ‘In Defence of New Wave Materialism: A Response to Horgan and Tienson’, in C. Gillett and B. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 319–30. Marcus, R. B. (1963), ‘Modalities and Intensional Languages: Discussion’, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1: 105–16. Papineau, D. (1998), ‘Mind the Gap’, Philosophical Perspectives, 12: 373–88. Place, U. T. (1956), ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’, British Journal of Psychology, 47: 44–50. Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 429–40. Schütte, M. (2004), Reduktion ohne Erklärung (Paderborn: Mentis). Segal, G. (2000), A Slim Book about Narrow Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Page 22 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? Smart, J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56.

Notes: (1) Gottlob Frege (1892) struggled with the question of whether sameness is a relation between objects or between names of objects. Finally, he decided on the first option. Nonetheless, true identity statements like ‘a = b’ never convey the information that the object referred to by ‘a’ and ‘b’ is identical to itself. That is something we already know in advance. And whatever new information identity statements may convey, it remains the case that ‘a = b’ is true if and only if ‘a’ and ‘b’ refer to the same individual. (2) This view is explicitly expressed in Carnap (1956). (3) Identity theorists, it seems, understand property‐identity statements on the model of object‐identity statements. What has been said in n. 1, therefore, is also true of these statements. Statements of the form ‘F is identical with G’ are true if and only if ‘F’ and ‘G’ stand for the same property. (4) This, of course, is not what Levine really claims. He only maintains that there is an important epistemic difference between the identity statements (1) and (2) even though this difference by itself does not imply that (2) is false. (5) Block and Stalnaker (1999) have argued that even if the property to be explained in a reductive explanation has an analysis, this analysis will be couched in terms that do not belong to the vocabulary of the basic laws the explanation is based on. In order to complete such explanations, we therefore have to add bridge laws which tell us which higher‐level features are identical to which lower‐level phenomena. Reductive explanations, therefore, presuppose true property‐identity statements instead of replacing them. In my view, it is indeed true that reductive explanations presuppose appropriate principles to bridge the gulf between different mereological levels. These principles, however, are not a posteriori identity statements. The bridge principles actually used in science rather seem to be unproblematic a priori conditionals. (‘If all parts of a disc revolve around a certain point, the disc itself rotates around this point’; ‘An object is transparent if light rays pass through it’; ‘An object dissolves in a liquid if its parts [molecules] are untied from each other and distributed among the molecules of the liquid’.) (6) Actually, I think Chalmers and Jackson (2001) are right in arguing that in general reductive explanations do not presuppose a complete analysis of F. It suffices that the truth of the conditional ‘All systems with micro‐structure [C 1, …, C n; R] have F’ can be known a priori on the basis of the general laws of nature holding for component parts C 1, …, C n, suitable bridge laws, and what competent speakers know about the extension of ‘F’. (7) Of course, Papineau was not the first advocate of this view (see e.g. Hill 1984, 1991). Page 23 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? (8) It is very important to distinguish Broad's account of reductive explanation from the account that has recently been developed by Chalmers and Jackson. According to Chalmers and Jackson, a phenomenon is reductively explainable in terms of the physical iff it follows a priori from a complete description of the physical world plus a ‘that's all’ clause plus some indexical truths. As we will see, it may well be that identity statements like ‘water = H2O’ are reductively explainable in Chalmers's and Jackson's sense. That the two senses of ‘reductive explanation’ are different already follows from the fact that a lot of physical macro‐properties that would be emergent in Broad's sense are reductively explainable in the sense of Chalmers and Jackson (see their 2001: sect. 4). The reason for this difference is that Broad's basis is only the fundamental laws of nature while Chalmers and Jackson start from a complete description of the physical world which also comprises all exceptions from these laws. (9) For an overview of the different versions of functionalism see Braddon‐Mitchell and Jackson (1996). (10) This is so even if the causal role itself is entirely expressible in terms of physics. Even then the role filler, the state by which the role is realized in a certain being, may be a non‐physical state. (11) This has already been noticed by Putnam (1975: 436). (12) Actually this formulation only applies to the concept of global supervenience. Here, however, I do not wish to go into the difference between local and global supervenience. (13) As already mentioned (n. 8 above), π also has to include indexical physical truths about ourselves and a ‘that's all’ clause stating that the description really is complete— otherwise π will not entail the mental fact that there are no immaterial ghosts having pain. This is reflected in Jackson's demand that the relevant possible worlds have to be minimal physical duplicates of our world (see Chalmers and Jackson 2001). (14) Again, π also has to include indexical physical truths about ourselves and a ‘that's all’ clause stating that the description really is complete. It should also be noted that a priori physicalism in the sense of (AP) does not maintain that physicalism is a priori true. (15) A rigid designator refers to the same object in all possible worlds if it refers to anything at all.

Page 24 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? (16) To avoid misunderstandings, I would like to make clear what I mean by ‘semantic property’ or ‘semantic fact’. Frege held the view that each expression has a sense and a reference and that the sense and reference of complex expressions result in regular ways from the senses and references of their components. What we may call a ‘Frege dictionary’ thus contains for each non‐complex expression two entries, one in which its sense and one in which its reference is given (for all possible worlds). Moreover, we may assume that all references are given in a canonical, transparent way; that is, if two names refer to the same object, their references are given by the same expression. For example, since ‘Mark Twain’ and ‘Samuel Clemens’ refer to the same writer, their references are given by the same words; say, ‘Mark Twain’. According to Frege, predicates refer to concepts. Exponents of the identity theory, rather, seem to assume that predicates stand for properties. Be that as it may, for each predicate a Frege dictionary contains an entry that gives the reference of this predicate; that is, that tells us what the predicate stands for. This again is done in a canonical, transparent way. If two predicates stand for the same concept or property, their references are given by the same expression. A semantic fact is what follows from all entries in a Frege dictionary. (The idea of a Frege dictionary has already been alluded to by R. B. Marcus: 1963: 115). At least, this is what Kripke takes her to say (1971: 142). (17) ‘The sense of a proper name is grasped by everyone who knows the language […] A complete knowledge of the nominatum would require that we could tell immediately in the case of any given sense whether it belongs to the nominatum. This we shall never be able to do’ (Frege 1892: 86; my emphasis). (18) ‘Identity is utterly simple and unproblematic. Everything is identical to itself; nothing is ever identical to anything else except itself. There is never any problem about what makes something identical to itself; nothing can ever fail to be. And there is never any problem about what makes two things identical; two things never can be identical’ (Lewis 1986: 192–3). (19) Say, by explaining away the alleged possibility or by holding that mental properties are identical to functional properties. Of course, the reductive‐explanation theory has no problem whatsoever with this argument. (20) For more realistic cases see Segal (2000: ch. 5). (21) Of course, the distinction I want to stress could also be put in the following way. All predicates stand for properties. But not all properties are of the same kind. Some do not admit of an analysis, others do. I, however, prefer to speak of predicates instead of properties. Generally, we have to be aware of the fact that the whole debate is threatened by a confusion—the confusion between predicates and concepts on the one hand and properties on the other. Time and again we are told that properties are to be analysed or that we should try to deduce properties of a whole from knowledge of the properties of its parts. Literally speaking, this makes no sense. One can only deduce sentences or

Page 25 of 26

What is Property Physicalism? propositions, but not properties. And one can analyse concepts or the meaning of predicates, whereas it seems at least reasonable to ask whether it is really possible to analyse a property. It is predicates or concepts that get analysed. (22) This idea is also developed in Schütte (2004). (23) Of course, this does not mean that these identity claims have no justifications. See e.g the justification mentioned on p. 159 above. (24) This breach would be no atom smaller even if we assumed that water‐solubility is identical to a certain molecular structure. If the water‐solubility of common salt is emergent, this means that there are circumstances in which salt molecules behave in ways that cannot be accounted for by the general laws holding for sodium and chlorine ions. And this in turn implies that these laws are incomplete; that is, that there are circumstances in which sodium and chlorine ions behave in ways that cannot be accounted for by these laws (see Beckermann 2001b). (25) Some philosophers, however, argue that identity theorists do not have to deny that it is part of the analysis of ‘is in pain’ that pains feel painful, since they are not so much concerned with the property of being in pain (a property of living beings) as with the qualitative character of pains—the quale of feeling painful (a property of certain mental states). This quale, these identity theorists claim, is identical to a physical or functional or representational property. But this version of the identity theory seems to be confronted with quite similar problems; for example, it is possible to construe a similar Kripke test (see the next paragraph). (26) I am very grateful to Brian McLaughlin, Christian Nimtz, Michael Schütte, Sven Walter, and especially Wolfgang Schwarz for extremely helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Ansgar Beckermann

Ansgar Beckermann is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Bielefeld.

Page 26 of 26

What is the Physical?

Oxford Handbooks Online What is the Physical?   Barbara Gail Montero The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0010

Abstract and Keywords Addressing the question of what is the physical is important not only for understanding the general thesis of physicalism, but also for assessing the strength and significance of a number of the central arguments regarding physicalism and the physical nature of the mind. For example, debates over the possibility of zombies pervade the literature on consciousness. Zombies, in the relevant sense, are supposed to be creatures that are just like us in every physical respect yet lack consciousness. Are such creatures possible? Some have argued that while it is not conceivable, or logically possible, that there could be, say, H2O that is not water, it is conceivable that there could be worlds that are physical duplicates of ours yet populated by zombies rather than conscious human beings, and thus consciousness does not logically supervene on the physical. Keywords: physicalism, consciousness, nature of mind, physical duplicates, physicalism, physical nature

PHYSICALISM,

Hilary Putnam once said, is the only metaphysical position with any real clout

(1987). Its clout comes from its alignment with physics; but, as we will see, physics is also a cause of its troubles. Physicalists generally claim that everything, or at least some significant subset of everything, is physical.1 Most significantly, physicalists hold that minds and mental properties—physicalism's primary nemeses—are entirely physical. But what is it to be physical? With a few exceptions, physicalists have had little to say about this. Yet formulating a workable notion of the physical is of utmost importance—for what good is clout, if you don't have substance? Addressing the question of what is the physical is important not only for understanding the general thesis of physicalism, but also for assessing the strength and significance of a number of the central arguments regarding physicalism and the physical nature of the mind. For example, debates over the possibility of zombies pervade the literature on consciousness. Zombies, in the relevant sense, are supposed to be creatures that are just Page 1 of 18

What is the Physical? like us in every physical respect yet lack consciousness. Are such creatures possible? Some have argued that while it is not conceivable, or logically possible, that there could be, say, H2O that is not water, it is conceivable that there could be worlds that are physical duplicates of ours yet populated by zombies rather than conscious human beings, and thus consciousness does not logically (p. 174) supervene on the physical. But how are we to determine whether such zombies are possible? Without some prior notion of the physical, intuitions here are prone to run amok. How one understands the notion of the physical also plays an important role in determining what one thinks about what poor, dear Mary—the imprisoned, brilliant neuroscientist—knows about the experience of seeing red. Would Mary, who knows all the physical facts about colour vision yet has spent her entire life in a black and white environment, be surprised upon seeing her first ripe tomato or would she just say, ‘Ho‐ hum, I knew that's what red would look like all along’? To answer this question we need some understanding of what it is that Mary knows, which minimally involves at least some notion of what counts as a physical fact. Are the physical facts the facts that science tells us about? Are they the facts about the ultimate constituents of nature, whatever they may be? Different answers to the question of what it means to be physical will ground different intuitions about what Mary knows, and even about the coherence of the entire thought‐experiment.2 Another illustration of the importance of understanding what it means to be physical is found in the literature on the causal argument for physicalism. This argument starts from the thought that sometimes we move our bodies in part because of something going on in our minds: say, we reach for a glass of water because we experience the sensation of thirst, see water in front of us, desire to drink it, and so forth. Assuming the world is not set up so that there is systematic causal overdetermination (that is, assuming that bodily effects do not usually have two distinct sufficient causes) and assuming that the physical world is causally closed (that is, assuming that every physical effect has an entirely physical causal history) this argument concludes (with some qualifications) that the mental is physical.3 But what is it that is supposed to be causally closed? What we need is a notion of the physical that allows for the physical world being causally closed and for physicalism being inconsistent with dualism. But in the literature one often finds notions of the physical that fail to satisfy both criteria. To give just one example, one might argue for physical causal closure by pointing out that all inorganic processes have causal histories that remain in the inorganic. Perhaps they do, but the physicalist cannot be claiming merely that the mental is ultimately constituted by inorganic phenomena, at least not when the inorganic is understood as that which is not carbon based, since the dualist can be perfectly content with the immaterial soul being non‐carbon based. Finally, it is often claimed, as Wayne Davis puts it, that ‘the principle argument for physicalism is the success of physics’ (1995: 679). Or, in J. J. C. Smart's words: ‘[S]cience is increasingly giving us a viewpoint whereby organisms are able to be seen as physico‐ chemical mechanisms … yet, that everything should be explicable in terms of physics … except the occurrence of sensations seems to me to be frankly (p. 175) Page 2 of 18

What is the Physical? unbelievable’ (1959: 142).4 The reasoning here assumes that the physical world is the world given to us by physics (or physics and chemistry)—else why would its success be reason to think that the mental will fall under the physicalist umbrella? However, as we will see, there are serious problems with such a view. Although we need at least some conception of the physical to fully engage with these issues, fortunately we need not provide necessary and sufficient conditions for being physical before entering the debate. Understanding concepts and determining what falls under their scope can go hand in hand, and as such the process of determining whether the mind is physical is itself a step in clarifying our understanding of the physical.5 Nonetheless, to enter the debate we need some ground to stand on, since without any conception of the physical at all, debates over whether the mind is physical would be as illuminating as the discussions two five‐year‐olds might have about the nature of infinity (and much less entertaining). Some think that we already have an entry point into the debate; namely, common sense. On their view, our grounds for using the term ‘physical’ in philosophical arguments are no more shaky than, say, our grounds for using the term ‘modest’ in questions about whether an individual is modest: although in neither case can we fully explain the concept, both are intuitive enough. The two cases, however, are not analogous. For one thing, the concept of being modest is a concept from ordinary‐language. To be sure, there are ordinary‐language usages of ‘the physical’ as well, but they tend not to line up with philosophers' needs. For example, one might say, ‘taking care of an infant is physically, but not mentally, challenging’. Here the physical pertains to non‐mental aspects of our bodily actions, but in a debate over whether the mind is physical this cannot be what is meant. In ordinary language ‘physical’ is sometimes contrasted with virtual or digital, as in ‘I'd prefer a physical copy to an email’, but no physicalist should think an email isn't also physical. For another thing, while we can point to examples of modest people and to examples of immodest people, it is often not clear what is supposed to serve as an example of something non‐physical, or at least something that if it were to exist would count as non‐physical. Yet to avoid turning the claim ‘the mind is physical’ into a trivial truth we need to have some idea of a contrasting class, something that, if it were to exist, would count as non‐physical. The mental clearly cannot be taken as an example. But what can? Sometimes—with perhaps just a hint of exasperation—physicalists tell us that when they exclude non‐physical phenomena from their ontology they mean to exclude such things as ghosts and other spooky stuff. Smart, for example, states that physicalists reject the view that experiences ‘are a sort of ghost stuff. (Or perhaps ripples in an underlying ghost stuff.)’ (1959: 154). And, as Jeffrey Poland puts it, the (p. 176) physicalist's bottom line is: ‘there are no ghosts!’ (1994: 15). But what is it about ghosts that, if they were to exist, would make them non‐physical? Is it that ghosts would pass through walls without disturbing them? Millions of neutrinos may be coursing through the wall in front of me right now, yet neutrinos presumably count as physical. Perhaps ghosts would have no mass or wouldn't take up any space. Yet photons have no mass, and point particles, if they Page 3 of 18

What is the Physical? were to exist, would not take up space, yet neither, it seems, should count as counter‐ examples to physicalism. It even seems unreasonable to exclude from the physical realm things that do not exist in space‐time. Physicists have speculatively posited something from which space‐time itself emerges, the playfully called ‘zerobrane.’ Yet since there seems no reason to take zerobranes as nonphysical, we cannot take existing in space‐time as a criterion for being physical.6 Richard Healey sums up the situation well when he says, ‘[the] expanding catalogue of elementary particle states of an increasingly recondite nature seems to have made it increasingly hard for the physicists to run across evidence that would cast doubt on a thesis of contemporary physicalism stated in terms of it’ (1979: 208). Or, as Bertrand Russell said years before, ‘matter has become as ghostly as anything in a spiritualist's séance’ (1927/1992: 78).7 The moral is clear: ghosts, ghost stuff and other pretheoretically bizarre phenomena are not going to provide viable contrasts to the physical. It might be claimed that we can have a useful notion of the physical even without specifying a contrasting class. Certain philosophers have argued that we can merely start with certain prototypical examples of physical objects and properties and extrapolate from there. But after specifying central cases of the physical, determining how to go on from there is no trivial matter. Let us take our prototypical examples of the physical from everyday so‐called physical objects such as rocks and trees. In a sense, the mind, be it physical or not, would fit much more smoothly in with rocks and trees than with the fundamental particles of physics. For example, the notion of the mental fits easily into ordinary language. We also take the mental to fit into the same macro‐level causal network as everyday objects: in explaining why Sam moves his hand (as opposed to the micro‐particles in his hand) toward the glass of water, we naturally refer to his sensation of thirst, desire for water, and so forth. And these things would be true even if the mental were non‐physical. But, presumably, since in formulating our concept of the physical we are supposed to extrapolate from rocks, trees, and hands so as to cover the phenomena of physics but not non‐physical minds, something more needs to be said. A more sophisticated version of this idea is the view that ‘physical’ is a natural kind term. That is, we start with our central examples of physical things and properties and then take our basic physical phenomena to be that which constitutes or realizes such things and properties, whatever it may be. As William Lycan states it, physicalism (p. 177) is the view that ‘creatures with minds are made entirely of the same ultimate components as are ordinary inanimate objects, and their properties are determined by the ways in which those components are arranged and related to external things’ (2003: 15; see also Snowdon 1989). As Lycan sees it, this way of putting the physicalist thesis is ‘good enough to work with and … distinguish[es] that thesis from the views of Descartes and Hume’ (2003: 15). Descartes certainly did reject the view that ‘creatures with minds are made entirely of the same ultimate components as are ordinary inanimate objects’. And Hume seems to at least reject the view that we can know that minds and ordinary objects are made of the same ultimate components since he holds that, in his words, ‘matter … and spirit are at Page 4 of 18

What is the Physical? bottom equally unknown and we cannot determine what qualities inhere in the one or in the other’ (1783/1998: 324). But although physicalists should reject these views this isn't all they should reject. Among other positions, they should reject panpsychism; roughly, the view that the fundamental nature of reality involves mentality. Yet panpsychism can be formulated so that it is consistent with Lycan's proposed criterion. Because Lycan's criterion is too weak to exclude panpsychism, it is unclear whether such a criterion is, in fact, ‘good enough to work with’.8 Lycan's criterion is too weak, since it does not exclude panpsychism, but in another sense it is too strong. Physicalists are monists inasmuch as they think that all matter is fundamentally composed of the same kind of stuff; namely, physical stuff. However, it seems that there can be more than one kind of fundamental physical stuff. Gassendi suggested this when he objected to Descartes's dualism, stating that while he would grant Descartes his conclusion that mind and body are really distinct, he did not accept that this implies that the mind is incorporeal (Haldane and Ross 1968: 237). Moreover, if, as some physicists posit, dark matter is made entirely out of axions, a new kind of fundamental particle, dark matter, it would seem, should still count as physical. To be sure, the thesis that human beings contain within them fundamental stuff that does not occur in such things as rocks and chairs is, as Lycan puts it, rather ‘loony’ (2003: 14). But I think that even Lycan would agree that if such stuff were discovered to exist, it could count as physical. Thus, Gassendi is correct: merely stating that the mental is not made of the same ultimate components as ordinary inanimate objects does not suffice to make it non‐physical. But what then does? In respect to the mind, we want to know what is it that the mental supervenes on, is realized by, or is identical to (fill in your favourite dependence relation) in order for it to count as physical. To be sure, strictly speaking not all physicalists say that the mind, or even the brain for that matter, is physical. This is because not all physicalists apply the term ‘physical’ to higher‐level phenomena. While this can cause some confusion, the issue here is primarily terminological, since physicalists typically (p. 178) do not take the existence of rocks and trees to be counter‐examples to physicalism (since rocks and trees, they will claim, depend on lower‐level physical phenomena) even if they choose to reserve the term ‘physical’ for lower‐level phenomena. A significant issue, however, is how to identify these lower‐level phenomena; that is, how to identify that upon which, according to the physicalist, everything else depends. Identifying such dependence bases is, as Jeffrey Poland puts it, ‘one of the deepest foundational issues facing physicalists’ (1994). Most physicalists want to specify the dependence bases in terms of whatever the physicist says exists. Wave‐particle duality, one‐dimensional strings, and other ghostly phenomena do not count as counter‐examples to physicalism because, it is said, the physical is whatever is given to us by physics itself. In avoiding counter‐examples in this way, however, we run into what is called ‘Hempel's dilemma’ (see Hempel 1980).9 On the one hand, it seems that we cannot define the physical in terms of current physics, since current physics is most likely not correct. Despite some physicists' heady optimism that the end of physics is just around the corner, history cautions prudence. The end of Page 5 of 18

What is the Physical? physics has been predicted before: toward the end of the nineteenth century, just before the relativity revolution, Lord Kelvin remarked that all that is left for physics is the filling in of the next decimal place; then, in the early part of the twentieth century Max Born supposedly claimed that physics would be over in six months. And, in all likelihood, today's claims that we've (just about) got it right are similarly unrealistic: today's physics is probably neither entirely true, in the sense that some of our theories may look as wrong‐headed to future generations as phlogiston theory looks to us now, nor complete, in the sense that there are still unaccounted for phenomena.10 Yet, on the other hand, Hempel claims that if we take physics to be some future unspecified theory, the claim that the mind is physical is extremely vague, since we currently do not know what that theory is. Geoffrey Hellman sums up this dilemma nicely: ‘[E]ither physicalist principles are based on current physics, in which case there is every reason to think they are false; or else they are not, in which case it is, at best, difficult to interpret them, since they are based on a “physics” that does not exist’ (1985: 610). A few philosophers take on the first horn and define the physical over current physics. Apart from making physicalism most likely false, this approach has some other rather odd consequences. For example, it seems to imply that neither Hobbes nor Le Mettrie count as physicalists and, moreover, that if a new particle is discovered next week, it will not be physical. Of course, it does provide us with a theory the truth of which is determinable now. But this can be said as well of the theory that the earth is flat. Hellman's response is basically to reject physicalism as a possibly true theory about the ultimate nature of the world yet allow that physicalism as defined (p. 179) over current physics may be of practical use, as false theories sometimes are. He thinks, for instance, that it may serve as a criterion of adequacy for the completion of physics (Hellman 1985: 610). And perhaps it can, but such a physicalism is far from what most physicalists take themselves to be defending, which is a theory that tells us something substantial about the ultimate nature of the mind. Andrew Melnyk argues for something bolder: physicalism defined over current physics, he argues, is almost certainly false yet nonetheless acceptable as a substantial theory about the ultimate nature of reality (1997). It is acceptable, he argues, because the attitude a physicalist should have towards the thesis of physicalism is the attitude someone with realist and anti‐relativist intuitions has towards her favoured scientific hypotheses. This attitude, he claims, amounts to taking one's favoured theory to be better than current and historical rivals; that is, those formulated theories that are sensibly intended to achieve a significant number of the favoured theory's goals. As such, it does not require that one take one's hypothesis to be true, nor, even, more likely true than false. Rather, just as, say, a string theorist asserts that everything is made out of strings while being aware that string theory is probably far from the last word and in fact more likely to be false than true, a physicalist asserts that everything is physical—in the sense of either being accounted for directly by the phenomena of current physics or realized by such phenomena—while being aware that physicalism is probably far from the last word and in fact more likely to be false than true. According to Melnyk, then, we can take on the first horn of Hempel's dilemma—that is, we can define the physical in terms of Page 6 of 18

What is the Physical? current physics—because (1) one can reasonably accept a scientific hypothesis while at the same time accepting that it is more likely to be false than true as long as the theory is better than its relevant rivals; (2) physicalism, as Melnyk understands it, what we can call ‘M‐physicalism’, while more likely to be false than true is better than its relevant rivals; and (3) M‐physicalism is a scientific hypothesis. Thus, defining the physical over current physics is supposed to give us an acceptable substantial theory. One question to ask here is whether M‐physicalism is better than its relevant rivals. And answering this is no easy task.11 But let us put this issue to the side, since it is not even clear that taking physicalism to be better than its relevant rivals gives the physicalist what she needs. It seems that in philosophy when no options are good yet one is better than the other, it very well may not be reasonable to accept the best of this bad lot, and, in my opinion, philosophical honesty should prevent us from doing so. Consider the case of free will. You might think that one response to the free‐will debate is better than all others because it is, perhaps, clearer, or perhaps it (p. 180) alone is not self‐contradictory, yet since you think that all responses are failures, you do not accept any of them. But Melnyk has a different take, since, as he sees it, ‘surely physicalism should be viewed as a scientific hypothesis’ (1997: 226). Is physicalism, or rather M‐physicalism, a scientific hypothesis? It is empirical in nature, but it is not clear that being empirical suffices to make a theory scientific rather than philosophical.12 However, rather than tackling yet another demarcation problem, let us assume that M‐physicalism is a scientific theory. What follows from this? It seems that whether or not M‐physicalism is a scientific theory, it fails to capture the debate between physicalists and dualists. Perhaps the best current explanation of the ultimate constituents of everything does come from physics.13 Yet this is something dualists can accept. We might not have an alternative theory of how to account for the mental, claims the dualist, but we do know that a physicalist account will not work. Because dualists can accept M‐physicalism, inasmuch as accepting it only amounts to accepting that it is currently the best explanation of the mental, M‐physicalism would not seem to be up to the task of providing a formulation of the physical that is of use in the philosophical debate. It is, of course, an interesting question whether current physics provides the best explanation of the fundamental nature of everything, but this would seem to be a distinct question from that of the truth of physicalism, since physicalism—if we can make sense of it at all—should at least be a theory that dualists reject. Smart proposes a different way to take on the first horn of the dilemma (1978). While Smart defines the physical over current physics, he does not think that this probably makes physicalism false. Rather, he argues that for the purposes of the mind–body problem current physics is good enough, since the principles relevant to understanding the mind are principles of ‘ordinary matter’ (for example, principles relevant to understanding neurons, such as molecular theory) and that these principles will most likely not be overthrown. Or, as Lycan puts it: ‘the changes in the physics underlying biology and chemistry should not matter in any way to the mind, however much they

Page 7 of 18

What is the Physical? matter to matter’ (2003: 15). In other words, physicalism, understood in this way, says that once you've duplicated the phenomena at the neural level, you've duplicated the mental, regardless of what is going on at lower levels. But it seems that the Smart/Lycan approach to taking on the first horn of Hempel's dilemma runs into problems as well, since if the neural itself is not physical, as would be the case if panpsychism were true, then although it may be that once we've duplicated the neural we've duplicated the mental, the mental would still not be physical. Moreover, although it may be very unlikely that our understanding of the mental will not be furthered by new developments in fundamental physics, it would seem to be within the realm of possibility that, say, the particular visual sensation of seeing red requires a certain type of process to be occurring at the level of fundamental physics. And it also seems possible that neural properties do not require this particular fundamental process (brains, as it were, are multiply realizable with respect to it). (p. 181) Such a view, it would seem, could count as physicalistic even though it would not be true that the principles relevant for understanding the mind are the principles relevant for understanding ordinary matter, and even though duplication of the neural does not suffice for duplication of the mental.14 It seems, then, that taking on the first horn of Hempel's dilemma, that is, defining the physical‐dependence base in terms of current physics, does not succeed. But does taking on the second horn fare any better? Many physicalists think it does. For example, David Armstrong explicitly tells us that when he says ‘physical properties’ he is not talking about the properties specified by current physics, but rather ‘whatever set of properties the physicist in the end will appeal to’ (1991: 186).15 In a similar vein, Frank Jackson holds that the physical facts encompass ‘everything in a completed physics, chemistry, and neurophysiology, and all there is to know about the causal and relational facts consequent upon all this’ (1986: 29). And, even if it is not always explicitly stated, it seems that, as Barry Loewer puts it, ‘what many have on their minds when they speak of fundamental physical properties is that they are the properties expressed by simple predicates of the true comprehensive fundamental physical theory’ (1996: 103).16 So for Armstrong, and others as well, it is not today's physics upon which we are to base our notion of the physical, and not any future physics, since, presumably, physics of the future will still be false for a long time to come, but, rather, a true and complete physics, a physics, as it were, sub specie aeternitatis. Can we formulate physicalism in terms of a true and complete physics? For some, one problem with defining the physical in terms of future physics is that since we do not currently know what future physics will be like, we cannot now determine whether physicalism is true. And, indeed, this seems to be Melnyk's main reason to reject attempts to define the physical over future physics. But many physicalists do not think that our current inability to determine the truth of physicalism is problematic. Physicalism, as they see it, can be based on a physics that does not yet exist because it is a hypothesis that

Page 8 of 18

What is the Physical? awaits scientific confirmation (or, for that matter, refutation). Physicalists are betting that it is correct, but do not claim to be able to now determine that it is correct.17 Physicalists, I agree, need not now determine whether physicalism is true. Unfortunately, a more serious problem is that, far from turning physicalism into a thesis whose truth awaits empirical support, using the notion of ‘physics in the end’ or ‘a completed physics’ to explain the physical actually seems to trivially exclude the (p. 182) possibility that the mind is not physical, making physicalism with respect to the mind trivially true. For what is a true and complete physics, save for one that accounts for the fundamental nature of everything? If mentality is a real feature of the world, a completed physics will, by definition, account for the most fundamental nature of the mental as well.18 Yet neither physicalists nor their foes think that at this time in the debate the mind is physical simply as a matter of definition. Physicalists think the claim needs to be argued for and, as many hold, will ultimately depend on what scientific investigation reveals. And their foes clearly do not think that they are denying what amounts to, more or less, an analytic truth. It seems, then, that when physicalists who take on the second horn of Hempel's dilemma talk about a true and complete physics, they cannot simply mean a theory of everything, since this would make their claim that the mind is physical trivially true. Yet there is also reason to think that they do not simply intend to refer to the temporal end of physics. For this physics might still be inaccurate and incomplete; even worse, for all we know physics might regress. So it seems that physicalists need another option. Some argue that there are phenomena that physics, and perhaps scientific investigation entirely, does not aim to cover. Rather, physicists, they argue, in their role as physicists, are only concerned to account for a certain class of phenomena, and because of this we can distinguish a true and complete fundamental physics from the true and complete fundamental theory of the world; that is, the fundamental theory of the world sub specie aeternitatis. The true and complete theory, it is claimed, would account for the fundamental nature of everything, whereas a true and complete physics would account for the fundamental nature of only those things that physics aims to cover. But what sorts of phenomena are to be excluded from the scope of a true and complete physics? According to Brian McLaughlin, physicalists must take a stand on this. For example, the true and complete physics, McLaughlin thinks, ‘would not, for instance, postulate a spiritual realm that is causally isolated from the realm governed by its laws’ (2001: 11424). On McLaughlin's view, if a causally isolated spiritual realm were to exist, the true and complete theory of the world would account for it, yet a true and complete physics would not. And if there are things that exist outside the scope of a true and complete physics, physicalism is not trivially true; rather, in such a situation it would be false, since physicalists, according to McLaughlin, hold that a true and complete physics will be a true and complete theory. Is it reasonable to think that physics has identifiable limits? According to Quine, ‘if the physicist suspected there was any event that did not consist in a redistribution of the elementary states allowed for by his physical theory he would seek a way of Page 9 of 18

What is the Physical? supplementing his theory’ (1981: 98). And, as Bas van Fraassen sees it, ‘there are no science stoppers’ (1996: 80). Quine and van Fraassen suggest what I take to be a good methodological principle: scientific enquiry should not accept a priori barriers, or, in other words, when you discover territory that does not conform to your map, (p. 183) change the map, not the territory. Such changes might involve not only expanding our scientific ontology, but changing our scientific method as well. For example, if standard controlled experiments fail to reveal phenomena that we nonetheless suspect might exist —as some have claimed could be the case with parapsychological phenomena—we should try to find a way to change the control. If we are somehow convinced that there is a spiritual realm that is causally isolated from our world, let us try to understand it. Rather than placing a priori constraints on the scope of scientific enquiry, however, physicalists may make predictions about the limits of scientific enquiry, and can take physicalism to be refuted if such limits are surpassed. This is the point McLaughlin is trying to establish. However, I am not sure that the example he provides of a causally isolated spiritual realm serves this purpose. To be sure, it seems reasonable to claim that physics will never cover that which we will never fathom, that which we will never have any reason to think exists. And it may be that a causally isolated spiritual realm fall into this category. This has nothing to do with spirits, whatever they may be, as it seems that any causally isolated realm would fall into this category as well. So it is a good bet that any causally isolated realm is outside the scope of physics. But do we really want to count, say, a causally isolated collapsed star as non‐physical merely because physics could never touch it? I think that the answer is ‘no’. Moreover, even if we were willing to do this, physicalism, as defined over a true and complete physics, would still be necessarily true of our own causally connected world, which makes the theory trivial enough for most tastes. The prospects for formulating a useful notion of the physical are beginning to look rather grim. But before we lose hope, let us look at some suggestions for demarcating the physical from the non‐physical that come from the other side. While it is not unusual for physicalists to think of the physical so as to favour the truth of physicalism, dualists and other anti‐physicalists, perhaps unsurprisingly, tend to do just the opposite. For example, some anti‐physicalists define the physical over physics yet take physics to tell us only about the purely structural features of the world. If one, then, thinks that the mental has some sort of non‐structural, nature and also that there is a sharp divide between the non‐ structural and the structural, it is easy to be led to the view that the mental is not physical (1996: 153, 163, and passim).19 Other anti‐physicalists think of the physical as the objective, as that which is knowable from a third‐person point of view (see Swinburne 1994, Taliaferro 1994, and, while not a complete anti‐physicalist, Nagel 1986). When experiential phenomena are taken, as they are by dualists, to be knowable only from the first‐person point of view, it is also easy to see how one could be led to reject physicalism. (p. 184)

Page 10 of 18

What is the Physical? Just as we should reject definitions of the physical that make physicalism analytically true, we should reject definitions of the physical, such as the ones that seem to stand behind the dualistic views just considered, that make physicalism analytically false. Where does this leave us? According to some, problems with formulating a working notion of the physical dissolve the problem of physicalism and the mind–body problem entirely. As Chomsky sees it, because we have no way to formulate the physical/non‐ physical distinction, ‘we have no coherent way to formulate issues related to the “mind– body problem” ’ (1995: 5; see also Chomsky 1993, 1998). Chris Daly claims that our lack of understanding of the notion of the physical shows that ‘no debate between physicalism and dualism can even be set up’ (1998: 213), while Tim Crane and Hugh Mellor, after finding flaws with a wide variety of proposals for defining physicalism, conclude that their paper ‘should really be the last paper on the subject of physicalism’ (1990: 83). I think that although the problems we have found with many of the current attempts to demarcate the physical from the non‐physical indicate that there is at least no obvious way to formulate a substantial question, it does not imply that there is no mind–body problem. Rather, there seems to be an interpretation of, or perhaps a replacement for, the physical that, while perhaps not worthy of the clout Putnam claimed was bestowed on physicalism by physics, does give the debate some substance.20 This replacement is hinted at by some of those who attempt to carve a path between the two horns of Hempel's dilemma. These physicalists attempt to give content to the notion of the physical by taking the true and complete physics at issue to be a successor to today's physics.21 On their view, physicalists are betting that future physics will have certain features in common with current physics; most importantly, that it will not incorporate fundamental mental phenomena. Physicalism thus becomes both a thesis about what this true and complete successor physics will account for (the fundamental nature of everything) and also a thesis about what this physics will be like (it will not contain, say, acts of fundamental consciousness). Physicalism as such, it is argued, is not trivial, since it could be false if the true and complete physics does not account for everything or if the true and complete physics is not a successor to current physics. Despite appearances, the notion of the physical we have arrived at is actually not beholden to physics. In the final analysis, the reason it provides the thesis of physicalism with content is because it excludes the mental from the ultimate dependence base. And the question of whether this dependence base includes fundamental mentality is distinct from the question of whether it is exhausted by (p. 185) the phenomena posited by current, future, or final physics. The question being posed by such compromise views, then, is not whether mental properties are determined by the properties posited by physics but, roughly, whether mental properties are determined by non‐mental properties.22 Whereas these compromise views arrive indirectly at a notion of the physical as, roughly, the fundamental non‐mental and whatever is determined by such phenomena, a number of philosophers have suggested this understanding of the physical directly. For example, the idea that our central concern in the mind–body problem is whether mentality is Page 11 of 18

What is the Physical? fundamental is captured by Jerry Fodor's claim that ‘if the semantic and intentional are real properties of things, it must be in virtue of their identity with (or maybe supervenience on?) properties that are themselves neither intentional nor semantic’ (1987: 97). Joseph Levine defends this take on the mind–body problem as well, formulating the thesis of physicalism as: ‘[O]nly non‐mental properties are instantiated in a basic way; all mental properties are instantiated by being realized by the instantiation of other, non‐mental properties’ (2001: 21). David Papineau suggests that we can think of the physical as ‘the “non‐mentally identifiable”—that is, as standing for properties which can be identified independently of this specifically mental conceptual apparatus’ (2002: 41).23 And in trying to formulate a physicalism that allows for the possibility of no fundamental properties, I have argued elsewhere that physicalism is true if all properties are eventually determined by non‐mental properties such that all further determinations of these properties, if any, are non‐mental, and that physicalism is false if there are some properties that are eventually determined by mental properties such that all further determinations of these properties, if any, are mental Montero (2006). I think that taking the fundamental physical as the non‐mental provides a useful starting place for understanding the central debates in philosophy of mind that I mentioned at the start of this paper. Zombies can be understood as creatures that are just like us in every non‐mental respect. Mary, we should say, knows all the relevant facts about the non‐ mental aspects of colour vision. And the causal closure of the physical should be understood as the causal closure of the non‐mental. This understanding of the physical also gives us a starting point in formulating an interesting thesis of physicalism in general. And the reason for this, at least as I see it, is that a central point of contention between physicalists and anti‐physicalists is whether human beings, and perhaps also other animals, have, in some way, a special place in the world. One way we would seem to be special is if mental phenomena were part of the original brew that was set in motion, as one creation story goes, in the big bang. This would seem to give us a place of prominence, since it would hint at a world created with us in mind; that is, it would suggest, as another creation story goes, that when God created the world, she also created minds. Another way we would seem to be special is if mental phenomena were added as something extra somewhere (p. 186) along the way. Thus, it seems that physicalism should rule out fundamental mental phenomena. But we have not arrived at the final word, since taking the non‐mental as our dependence base may not exclude all that physicalists would like to exclude. For example, a world in which numbers form the basic fabric of reality might not be a world in which the mental forms the basic fabric of reality, yet some might see such a world as antithetical to physicalism. And the same could be said of fundamental norms: a world where certain actions are immoral and that's that might make many physicalists uncomfortable. These examples illustrate a problem not just for formulating physicalism in general but even for formulating physicalism with respect to the mental; for excluding the mental from the dependence base is consistent with, say, mental phenomena being ultimately determined only by normative phenomena.24 However, it is not too difficult to see how one can reformulate the theory so as to exclude numbers, norms, or whatever else one is Page 12 of 18

What is the Physical? interested in excluding: rather than the mental/non‐mental contrast, we could employ the numerical/non‐numerical, the normative/non‐normative contrast, or a combinations of these instead. Yet, one might be tempted to ask, what is it about the fundamental mental, the fundamental numerical, the fundamental normative that makes them all antithetical to physicalism? If we could answer this question we would be able to arrive at a unified notion of the physical that could make sense of questions about whether anything at all, including irreducible numbers, norms, and minds, is physical. I think there is no answer to this question save for the rather disappointing one that they tend to make some self‐ called physicalists uncomfortable. But we shouldn't take this disappointment too much to heart, since as long as we specify what is to be excluded from the dependence base, we can make sense of questions about the ontological status of norms, numbers, minds, and so forth (or at least I have not shown that we can't). As such, physicalism as a unified general thesis dissolves, while the mind–body problem awaits a solution. I would like to thank Jonah Goldwater, Joel David Hamkins, and Graham Parsons for their comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References Armstrong, D. (1991), ‘The Causal Theory of Mind’, in D. Rosenthal (ed.), The Nature of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Brandom, R. (1994), Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing and Discursive Commitment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Chomsky, N. (1993), Language and Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press). (p. 187)

—— (1995), ‘Language and Nature’, Mind, 104: 1–61.

—— (1998), ‘Comments on Galen Strawson, Mental Reality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58/2 (June), 437–41. Crane, T., and Mellor, H. (1990), ‘There is No Question of Physicalism’, Mind, 99: 185– 206. Crook, S., and Gillett, C. (2001), ‘Why Physics Alone Cannot Define the “Physical”: Materialism, Metaphysics, and the Formulation of Physicalism’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31: 333–60. Daly, C. (1998), ‘What Are Physical Properties?’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79: 196– 217.

Page 13 of 18

What is the Physical? Davidson, D. (1970), ‘Mental Events’, in L. Foster and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (Amherst, Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press), 79–101. Davis, W. (1995), ‘Physicalism’, in T. Honderich (ed.), The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 679–80. Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston, Mass.: Little, Brown). Dowell, J. (2006), ‘The Physical: Empirical, Not Metaphysical’, Philosophical Studies, 131/1: 25–60. Fodor, J. (1987), Psychosemantics (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Haldane, E., and Ross, G. H. T. (1968) (eds.), Descartes's Collected Works (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Healey, R. (1979), ‘Physicalist Imperialism’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 79: 191–211. Hellman, G. (1985), ‘Determination and Logical Truth’, Journal of Philosophy, 82: 607–16. Hempel, C. (1980), ‘Comments on Goodman's Ways of Worldmaking’, Synthese, 45: 193–9. Horgan, T. (1994), ‘Physicalism’, in S. Gluttenplan (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 471–9. Hume, D. (1783/1998), ‘On the Immortality of the Soul’, in S. Copley and A. Edgar (eds.), David Hume Selected Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 324–32. Jackson, F. (1986), ‘What Mary Didn't Know’, Journal of Philosophy, 83: 291–5. Kant, I. (1781–7/1929), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press). Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Lewis, D. (1983), ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61: 343–77. Loewer, B. (1996), ‘Humean Supervenience’, Philosophical Topics, 24: 101–23. Lycan, W. (2003), ‘Chomsky on the Mind–body Problem’, in L. Anthony and N. Hornstein (eds.), Chomsky and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell), 11–28. McLaughlin, B. (2001), ‘Physicalism and Alternatives’, in N. J. Smelser and P. B. Baltes (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences (Oxford: Pergamon), 11422–7.

Page 14 of 18

What is the Physical? Melnyk, A. (1997), ‘How to Keep the “Physical” in Physicalism’, Journal of Philosophy, 94: 622–37. —— (2003), A Physicalist Manifesto: Thoroughly Modern Materialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Montero, B. (2001), ‘Post‐physicalism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8: 61–80. —— (2003), ‘Varieties of Causal Closure’, in S. Walter and H.‐D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation (Exeter: Imprint Academic), 173–87. —— (2006), ‘Physicalism in an Infinitely Decomposable World’, Erkenntris, 64, 177–191. Nagel, T. (1986), The View From Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Papineau, D. (1993), Philosophical Naturalism (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (2002), Thinking About Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Poland, J. (1994), Physicalism: The Philosophical Foundations (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Putnam, H. (1987), ‘Why There Isn't a Ready‐made World’, in Putnam, Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers, iii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 205–28. (p. 188)

Quine, W. V. (1981), Theories and Things (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Russell, B. (1927/1992), An Outline of Philosophy (London: Routledge). Smart, J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56. —— (1978), ‘The Content of Physicalism’, Philosophical Quarterly, 28: 339–41. Snowdon, P. (1989), ‘On Formulating Materialism and Dualism’, in J. Heil (ed.), Cause, Mind and Reality: Essays in Honour of C. B. Martin (Dordrecht: Kluwer Press), 137–58. Strawson, G. (2003), ‘Real Materialism’, in L. Anthony and N. Hornstein (eds.), Chomsky and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell), 49–88. —— (2006), ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13/10–11. Swinburne, R. (1994) ‘Body and Soul’, in R. Warner and S. Tadeusz (eds.), The Mind–Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate (Oxford: Blackwell), 311–16. Taliaferro, C. (1994), Consciousness and the Mind of God (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Unger, P. (1999), ‘The Mystery of the Physical and the Matter of Qualities: A Paper for Professor Shaffer’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23: 75–99. Page 15 of 18

What is the Physical? Van Fraassen, B. (1996), ‘Science, Materialism, and False Consciousness’, in J. Kvanvig (ed.), Warrant in Contemporary Epistemology: Essays in Honor of Plantinga's Theory of Knowledge (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield), 149–81. Wimsatt, W. (2000), Re‐engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

Notes: (1) Thoughts about the proper scope of physicalism vary; some take it to apply to everything whatsoever, others restrict it to the empirical world, others to the causal world, or the contingent and/or causal, and still others to the concrete realm. (2) Dennett, for example, denies the coherence of the thought‐experiment, since he denies that we can form any coherent thoughts about what follows from knowledge of all the relevant physical facts. See, for example, Dennett (1991: 398–401). (3) See Montero (2003) for further discussion of the causal closure of the physical. (4) Although Smart represents this as a ‘confession of faith’, Melnyk (2003) develops an extended argument for physicalism taking the success of the physical sciences as his starting point. (5) Moreover, when one's purpose is to argue against the view that the mental is physical, one needs at most a necessary condition that one can show does not hold of the mind, and when one's purpose is to argue for the view that the mental is physical one needs at most a sufficient condition that one can show does hold of the mind. (6) Moreover, it would seem that that which was ‘before’ the big bang would not be spatio‐temporal, yet could be physical. (7) For further discussion of this view and its historical precedents see Strawson (2003). See also Unger (1999). (8) Although most take panpsychism to be inconsistent with physicalism, not all do. See, for example, Strawson (2006) and Dowell (2006). (9) Melnyk (1997) dubs the problem Hempel formulates ‘Hempel's dilemma’. (10) Going further, one might say that inasmuch as physics strives for absolute precision, all current physics falls short of accuracy. Or, even worse, one might say that since current physics is probably inconsistent, it is complete for the unsatisfactory reason that from a contradiction one can prove anything. (11) For example, is current physics better than what we can call ‘physics‐plus’; that is, better than current physics plus one additional kind of quark? If, as it seems, it is likely that new kinds of quarks will be discovered, and, as it also seems, that physics‐plus Page 16 of 18

What is the Physical? counts as a relevant rival, then M‐physicalism is not better than its relevant rivals. See Crook and Gillett (2001) for objections along these lines. Melnyk responds that physics‐ plus and variations thereof can count as similar enough to current physics not to be problematic for his view. As such, Melnyk, as I see it, comes closer to proposing a compromise view, which I discuss later, than to accepting the first horn of Hempel's dilemma—though it is a compromise in which physics still plays a role. (12) See Wimsatt's discussion of this issue (2000). (13) Melnyk's ‘everything’ is meant to include everything causal and/or contingent. (14) Externalist views of content pose a further problem to this explanation of physicalism. (15) Of course, not all properties the physicist appeals to are relevant: when a physicist is explaining a proposed budget in a grant application or explaining to her supervisor why she was late for work, she may be appealing to very different properties than when she is applying her mathematical skills in computing a wave function. But perhaps this distinction is intuitive enough. See Poland (1994) for discussion of this point. (16) Terry Horgan also explains physicalism in these terms; as he sees it, physicalism is the view that ‘humans are, or are fully constituted by, entities of the kind posited in (an ideally completed) physics’ (1994: 472). (17) For a clear explanation of this stance see McLaughlin (2001). (18) Of course, if a definition is justified, truth by definition is not necessarily a fault. (19) Note that, confusingly enough, in the literature the structural/relational aspects of the world are sometimes taken to exhaust the physical aspects of the world, as in Chalmers (1996), while at other times the idea that physics tells us only of the structural/ relational aspects of the world is taken to show that we cannot know the essence of the physical world (in the sense that the physical world has an intrinsic, non‐relational aspect). See, for example, Russell (1927/1992) and Unger (1999). Additionally confusing is that the view that everything we know about the world is structural/relational is sometimes taken to support idealism. See, for example, Kant (1781–7/1929). (20) I take it to be merely a terminological matter whether we should call the view a replacement for the notion of the physical or an interpretation of it. (21) For views along these lines see Papineau (1993), Poland (1994), and McLaughlin (2001). Alternatively, one can drop the ‘true and complete’ requirement and turn the question of physicalism into the question of whether a physics very much like ours but somewhat improved provides the fundamental dependence base for the mental, as do Lewis (1983) and Melnyk (2003). But this is uncomfortably close to the first horn of Hempel's dilemma, because it seems that such a physics will not provide the fundamental

Page 17 of 18

What is the Physical? dependence base for the mental, since it will, most likely, have neither a complete nor a correct account of the fundamental properties of nature. (22) I discuss this view further in Montero (2001). (23) One problem, however, with this formulation is that, as Davidson pointed out, even if there were non‐physical events, we might be able to identify, or refer to, them in non‐ mental terms (1970). (24) Brandom (1994) argues that the mental is grounded in the normative (which, as he sees it, is ultimately grounded in the social).

Barbara Gail Montero

Barbara Gail Montero is Associate Professor of Philosophy at City University of New York. She has published papers on wide range of topics related to the mind and is author of a forthcoming Oxford University Press book, The Myth of ‘Just do it’: Thought and Effort in Expert Action. Her research has been supported by fellowships from the National Endowment for the Humanities, the American Council of Learned Societies, and the Mellon Foundation. You can find a more about her and her research at http://barbaramontero.wordpress.com/

Page 18 of 18

Idealism

Oxford Handbooks Online Idealism   Howard Robinson The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0011

Abstract and Keywords Arguments specifically for and against idealism are arguments about the nature of the physical world, not about the nature of mind. This creates a problem for a would-be author of an entry on idealism, in a collection on the philosophy of mind, if he wishes to do justice both to the topic of his chapter and to the theme of the book as a whole. This article tries to resolve this conflict. Arguments for idealism usually take the form of attempted refutations of physical realism. They therefore tend to take the form of trying to prove that, in one way or another, the existence of material objects depends directly on the existence and activity of minds, other than that of the divine creator in his act of creating. Keywords: idealism, physical world, nature of mind, philosophy of mind, physical realism, material objects

10.1 Introduction 10.1.1 Preliminary Caveat AT

first sight the inclusion of a chapter on idealism in a handbook of philosophy of mind

would seem to be not merely natural but obligatory. Will not any textbook tell you that materialism, dualism, and idealism are the three major metaphysical options in philosophy of mind? Nevertheless, matters are not quite so straightforward. The disagreement between materialism and the other two theories concerns the nature of mind; namely, whether or not it can be thought of as purely material. By contrast, the disagreement between idealism and the others concerns the nature of the physical world; namely, whether it is a mind‐independent entity or not. It would seem that, as far as the nature of Page 1 of 20

Idealism mind is concerned, the idealist need have no different theory from the dualist. Arguments specifically for and against idealism are arguments about the nature of the physical world, not about the nature of mind. This creates a problem for a would‐be author of an entry on idealism, in a collection on the philosophy of mind, if he wishes to do justice both to the topic of his chapter and to the theme of the book as a whole. In so far as I can resolve this conflict, how I shall try to do so will emerge at the end of the next section.

10.1.2 What Idealism is Like many terms in philosophy, ‘idealism’ is used in more than one sense, and some of these are looser than others. The minimal idea is that the physical world is dependent on mind in a more‐than‐causal sense. I say in a more‐than‐causal sense, because any orthodox theist would claim that the physical world causally depended on God (p. 190) (who, for these purposes, can be thought of as a mind), but most theists would not regard themselves as idealists. This is because they think that, though the world is caused and sustained in existence by a mind or spirit, the world itself, in its material part, is essentially non‐mental. By contrast, what is required for idealism is that the physical world be, in some sense, itself mental. The two main versions of this are: (i) that the physical world exists only as a complex feature of experience; it exists only ‘in the minds of’ those who do or might experience it: (ii) that the physical world itself is a mind, or consists of minds. The idealisms of Berkeley and Kant are examples of the former, because they have the world as constructed from the sensory contents of individual perceivers. Leibniz and Hegel are in the second group. For Leibniz it is as if every space– time point in the physical world were itself a conscious subject: for Hegel, the whole world is one conscious intelligence developing in its self‐understanding. The principle contrast with idealism is physical realism. Physical realism is the view that, putting aside any role God might have as creator, matter and ordinary material objects— those that are not normally thought to be conscious or to think—could exist, in principle, without there being any minds. The physical world is mind‐independent, such that there could be a time when there was matter and no minds, or a physical world in which minds never evolved. Arguments for idealism usually take the form of attempted refutations of physical realism. They therefore tend to take the form of trying to prove that, in one way or another, the existence of material objects depends directly on the existence and activity of minds, other than that of the divine creator in his act of creating. It is not surprising, therefore, that arguments for idealism tend to focus on one of those aspects of the mind which are held to be difficult for the materialist to accommodate, and then to proceed to show that the nature and existence of the physical world depend on its relation to one of those aspects. This, I think, is the connection between arguments for idealism and the main body of the philosophy of mind.

Page 2 of 20

Idealism It is a commonplace that there are two features of the mind that create problems for the materialist. One of them is consciousness, as paradigmatically represented in sensations and perceptual experiences. This is problematic from a materialist perspective because of the strangely subjective or private nature of its states. The other is thought, because it has the mysterious property of intentionality, in virtue of which it is able to be about something other than itself. ‘Aboutness’ is not a normal physical relation. Arguments for idealism tend to focus on one of these features of the mind and argue that our conception of the physical cannot be disentangled from the mental feature in question, in the way that would be required if physical realism were correct and the physical world were a genuinely mind‐independent reality. My procedure in this chapter, therefore, will be to consider, first, the argument that the physical world cannot be made independent of our sensory consciousness, and, second, that it cannot be set beyond our modes of thinking about it.

10.2 The Physical World and Sensory Consciousness (p. 191)

10.2.1 Sensible Qualities, the Nature of Matter, and the Regress of Powers We naturally think of the physical world as possessing the kinds of properties that our senses perceive it as having. A serious problem arises, however, when we realize that once those qualities that are sense‐dependent (and, hence, consciousness‐dependent) are discounted, the resultant conception of matter is attenuated to the point of emptiness. The argument proceeds as follows. The traditional list of sensible properties centres on what are usually known as primary qualities and secondary qualities. The secondary qualities—such properties as colours, sounds, smells, and tastes—have often been held to be perceiver‐dependent, and not part of the wholly mind‐independent world.1 But even if they are construed in a naive‐realist manner, few philosophers would think them suitable to be taken as constituting the core of matter. The causal powers of matter, when explicated scientifically, are always put down to the primary qualities of objects. This leaves us with the primary qualities, as the materials from which to build up our concept of matter. From the seventeenth‐century atomist tradition, these primary qualities are the spatial properties, such as shape, size, motion through space, and solidity. In effect, this means that Newtonian atoms are volumes of solidity. Solidity is essentially the capacity or power to resist penetration by other bodies. Hume (1739–40: I.iv. 4/1978:229) objected to the idea that material bodies were volumes of impenetrability on the grounds that this left us

Page 3 of 20

Idealism with the concept of a body as something that resists penetration by other bodies, and that this is circular because the concept one is trying to define appears in the definition. Conceptual criticism of the notion of inelastic, solid atoms, and the increasing scientific importance of notions such as energy and charge pointed away from an ontology of solid atoms to one of forces, energy, or fields; that is, to an ontology of powers, or entities defined in terms of what they are disposed to do.2 Properties of these kinds are the primary qualities of modern physics. Rom Harré, drawing on the theories of the eighteenth‐century Croatian priest and diplomat Boscovitch, expresses the general form of the powers ontology as follows: Every fundamental theory must, as expressed in the language of physics, be a field theory. (1970: 313) (p. 192)

The ultimate entities of the world, as we can understand it, must be point sources of mutual influence, that is centres of power distributed in space (1970: 308) Although the ontology of powers can be seen as an alternative to the Newtonian conception of body, for our purposes the difference is irrelevant, because solidity, conceived of as impenetrability, is itself a power—the power to resist penetration. Not surprisingly, therefore, an accusation of vacuity similar to that deployed by Hume can be brought against any pure powers ontology. In outline the case is as follows.

A power is a power to produce some effect, but if everything is a power, it is the power to produce another power (presumably by modification of a power entity already present, not by creation of a power from nothing). Why this leads to a regress can be seen as follows. Let us call the first power A. We only know what A is if we know what kinds of thing the actualization of its potentiality gives rise to. In other words, we only know what A is if we know what it is a power to do, what states would constitute its manifestation. Let us call the power which A is the power to produce B. So what A is, is the power to produce B. But this is not informative unless we know the nature of B. B, being a power, is the power to produce some further power state, call it C. (We could close the circle and say that it is the power to produce a power of kind A, but then we would be in a circle of the kind to which Hume objected in his account of solidity.) It seems that we are moving into a regress. You can understand what a power is only by reference to a further power, of which you have no specific conception unless you know the power state which would be its effect, and so on. And though I have stated this argument in terms of what we could know, the argument is not essentially epistemological. One could equally well say that what the nature of A is depends on what it is a potentiality for; for what a power is, is given by what it is a power to do. What it is a power to do is a function of what would

Page 4 of 20

Idealism constitute its manifestation, and if the nature of this latter can have no determinate expression, neither can the power which is defined in terms of it. If the physical realist is committed to the powers conception of matter, and if that conception is radically defective, then the physical realist is in trouble. Furthermore, his opponent will point out that, if the pure‐powers conception is vicious, then the powers that are supposed to constitute matter must produce something which is not itself a power, but a monadic quality. And such qualities are to be found as sensible qualities in the sense fields of perceivers. So the physical world is a structured capacity to give rise to experience, and this is an idealist conception.3 We must look more closely at the regress argument to see whether it is really vicious. Disputes about whether a particular regress or circle is vicious tend to be between those who say that so long as one can always name the next element along the line, the regress is not vicious, and those who say that unless the process can be completed, (p. 193) nothing contentful has been proposed. There are regresses of both kinds and the problem is to decide into which camp a particular regress falls. The crucial issue seems to be whether the content of the early members of the series depends on the content of the later. Here is an example of a regress where the content of the earlier members does not depend on the later: if it is true that p, then it is true that it is true that p, and so on. No one, so far as I know, thinks that this is a vicious regress. The reason is that neither the content of nor our understanding of the content of the assertion that p is true depends on the later elements in the list. No one would suggest that you cannot understand what it is for p to be true unless you already understood what it is for it to be true that it is true that p. Another kind of non‐vicious regress is where an infinite series approaches asymptotically to a limit, for in that case the earlier elements do not depend on the later. Pi is 3.14159 …, with no end. But, although the next number will make the figure more exact as an expression of pi, the number we have so far (that is, 3.14159 without the dots) is both a complete numerical expression in itself and accurate to a certain degree of precision as a representation of pi. The significance or content of what has gone before—or that it should have any significance or content at all—does not depend on what comes next. The matter is otherwise in the case of powers. What it is to be a particular power does depend on what it is a power to produce, for to say that something is a power, without saying what it is a power to do, does not distinguish it from all other powers—which, if powers are all that there are, fails to distinguish it from anything else. So for any given power there must be a contentful nature to what it is a power to do, otherwise it is not differentiated from anything else. If ‘power to produce x’ is to be differentiated from any other power, there must be a specific content substitutable for x. If that content is ‘power to produce y’, this will have no specific content, differentiating it from any other power, unless there is a significant

Page 5 of 20

Idealism substitution for y. And so on. It is because the notion of ‘power to produce … ’ is an incomplete expression that trying to complete it by putting an expression of the same form into the blank does not improve the situation. It might be productive to compare the regress of powers with one which, unlike pi or the regress of ‘is true’, is genuinely controversial. This is the regress of causes and the kin issue of whether the world could be infinitely old. There are those who think that the regress constituted by causes stretching infinitely back into the past would be vicious and those who think that it would not. Notice that here there is no question of the nature of any event or entity—say a present one—depending conceptually on the nature of the events or entities that went before. So suppose that Aristotle were right and the world were infinitely old and humans had always existed. The essence of what I am—namely, a human being or a rational animal—would not involve essential reference in a regressive way to the previous members of the series. The definition can be given complete and well‐ formed for contemporary humans in their own right. The controversy about a regress of causes relates to the legitimacy of actual infinities, not to anything about the nature of the things that are supposed to participate in the infinite series. This case is, therefore, radically different from the (p. 194) regress of powers, and defenders of the pure‐powers ontology consequently cannot seek any solace by appeal to a comparison with the dispute concerning an unending regress of causes.4

10.2.2 Contemporary Discussion of the Powers Regress Philosophers occasionally acknowledge that the concept of matter is problematic in the way I have tried to make clear in the previous section, but, considering the importance of the issue raised, it is not as widely discussed as one might expect. As it is absolutely fundamental to the issue of whether one can give empirical content to the notion of mind‐ independent matter, I want to consider three recent attempts to respond to it. (1) The most enigmatic is Simon Blackburn's (1990). Blackburn's initial response to the powers ontology is positive. He says of this picture of the world: ‘Is this the way it has to work? I believe so’ (1990: 63). But he then considers a version of the ‘regress’ objection to this theory, accepting that the regress can only be ended because ‘[c]ategoricity in fact comes with the subjective view’. And he continues: ‘The trouble is that such events, conceived of as categorical, play no role in the scientific understanding of the world’ (p. 65). This appears to be a complete surrender to the argument. Blackburn's only response is to lapse into a sceptical detachment. After remarking that ‘I leave the issue in Hume's hands rather than Berkeley's’ (p. 64 n. 7; which, I presume, is a way of refusing to admit that it might have idealist implications), he concludes: It almost seems that carelessness and inattention alone can afford a remedy—the remedy of course of allowing ourselves to have any idea at all of what could fill in space.

Page 6 of 20

Idealism (p. 65) This sceptical hauteur does not seem to me to help the realist come to grips with the challenge that the argument presents.

(2) Stephen Mumford thinks that the argument rests on a view of dispositions which ‘is akin to Ryle's empiricist analysis where the ascription of a disposition is nothing more than affirming the truth of a subjunctive conditional’ (1998: 33). He is attacking the argument specifically as it is stated in Robinson (1982), but if the criticism is to have any general application, it must be an objection to any attempt to define powers or dispositions in terms of the states that constitute their actualizations, meaning by that the states brought about when they are activated. Mumford spells out his objection: We need not look for the actualization of a disposition solely in its manifestation, however, for we understand dispositions to be actual whenever they are ascribed. This is the realist alternative that I will be defending. If we were to treat dispositions as actual properties that (p. 195) play a causal role in their manifestations, then we can understand why dispositions are actual even when not currently manifested. (1998: 33–4) Mumford's objection only works if essentially characterizing a power in terms of its actualization is equivalent to adopting the reductive account of powers and dispositions. Surely, however, the nature or essence of anything which is a pure power must reside in that which it is a power to do, whether one conceives powers realistically or reductively. I think that Mumford is misled by a possible equivocation in the sense of ‘actual’ in this context. The fact that a realist believes that a power is actual, in the sense of actually existing when it is not activated, does not mean that its nature is not expressed by reference to its actualization, in the sense of the manifestation of the power. Even when dormant, it is essentially the power or disposition to give rise to that actualization.

(3) George Molnar (2003: 173 ff.) titles the regress argument ‘always packing, never travelling’. Although not a defender of the pure‐powers ontology, he does not believe that it can be refuted a priori, as the regress argument purports to do. He has two main responses to it. His first objection has some similarity to Mumford's objection considered above, in that it concerns the connection between the real existence of powers and the truth of counterfactual conditionals. When Blackburn states his version of the powers ontology, he does so in a way that seems to imply that powers are either equivalent to or at least imply the truth of conditionals. (He says, for example: ‘An electrical field can abide, certainly, but that just means that there is a period of time over which various counterfactuals are true’; 1990: 63; my emphasis.) Molnar points out that there has been considerable literature in recent years devoted to casting doubt on whether dispositions can be analysed conditionally, or even whether they entail conditionals (2003: 176–7). But the argument as I have stated it above does not make explicit appeal to conditional statements, only to the essentiality to a power of what would constitute its actualization or manifestation. No one would deny that the nature of powers and dispositions

Page 7 of 20

Idealism essentially involves what would constitute their manifestations, and any problem derived from difficulties in formulating the exact connection between powers and conditionals that goes beyond this is not relevant. Molnar has a further objection directed against C. B. Martin's statement of the regress argument against pure dispositionalism: Martin has also suggested that leaving out physical qualia at the level of the fundamental entities results in a Pythagorean ontology in which all is numbers, quantities, ratios and proportions, but there is no whatness, no quiddity, nothing that the numbers are numbers of and quantities of. Except of course further numbers, which returns us to the regress generated by pan‐dispositionalism. I think Martin's worry can be assuaged. If the property of exerting a certain force is a definite something that the numbers can measure, so is being the source of that force. That about the object that makes it a source of a force is a (quantative) power property. It is open to the dispositionalist to say that this is where the quiddity lies, this is what the numbers are numbers of. (2003: 179) (p. 196) The problem with this response is that it is hard to see what content one is supposed to attach to the italicized words in the claims that ‘the property of exerting a certain force is a definite something’ or that there is a ‘[t]hat about the object that makes it a source of a force’, if all the properties are pure powers. Molnar is talking as if that which lies behind the force is something other than the force itself, considered as potential or dormant, which on a pure‐ powers ontology it is not. Assigning a numerical value to this potentiality clearly adds nothing relevant. Of course, it would make a difference if one could consider powers as Janus‐faced, by giving them some other nature additional to the capacity to act. I now want to turn to considering various ways that the physical realist might do this.

10.2.3 Grounding Basic Powers The dispositions, capacities, and powers of complex objects are grounded in and explained in terms of the properties of the more minute structures that make up such complex objects. The problem that concerns us is with the powers of the ultimate elements of physical reality. If a pure‐powers ontology is not coherent, how should a physical realist think of basic powers as being grounded? Harré illustrates what is wanted, taking the example of solidity: Solidity is the alleged quality, the possession of which is responsible for the fact that two material things cannot occupy the same place at the same time and is logically connected with impenetrability, the power to resist penetration, in that

Page 8 of 20

Idealism the possession of the former is supposed to account for the manifestation of the latter. (1970: 305) Martin at one time held a similar theory, with any intrinsic quality treated as ‘a two‐sided dispositional qualitative coin … The dispositional and the qualitative are equally basic and irreducible; there is no direction for one being basic in a property and the other “supervenient” ’ (1997: 216; citing his previous view). He moved, however, from this Janus‐faced theory to one according to which the dispositional and the qualitative are not different aspects of a property, but are identical.

the qualitative and dispositional are identical with one another and with the unitary intrinsic property itself … What is qualitative and what is dispositional for any property is less like a two‐sided coin or a Janus‐faced figure than it is like an ambiguous drawing. A particular drawing, remaining unitary and unchanged, may be considered one way as a goblet‐drawing and differently considered, it is a two‐ faces‐staring‐at‐one‐another‐drawing. (1997: 216–17) The analogy does not look helpful. What is interpreted as a goblet or as two faces is neither of these things, it is a line or lines on a piece of paper. As there is clearly nothing accessible which is seen as a disposition and seen as a quality, what is really present must be some mysterious third unknown.

Such a mysterious unknown plays a part in Harré’s attempt to cope with the regress. Rom Harré played a major role in popularizing the powers ontology in the (p. 197) philosophy of science, and in drawing attention to the importance of Boscovitch in the historical development of this conception of matter (Harré 1970; Harré and Madden 1975). It is interesting to see, therefore, how he copes with the problems that face it. Harré’s way of recognizing the problem is somewhat elusive. He refers to the dilemma that confronts anyone who tries to universalize the dispositionalist account of properties. It seems as if one must choose between the inelegant alternative of grounding science on ungrounded dispositions, and the alarming prospect of an indefinite regress of groundings. (1986: 296; my emphasis) Given that one is dealing with the ultimate nature of reality, it is not surprising if it should turn out to be unfamiliar in a disturbing way; so the force of ‘inelegant’ and ‘alarming’ is unclear. Furthermore, it is hard to see what is inelegant about ungrounded powers, if the notion makes sense. Nevertheless, Harré does acknowledge it as a problem that he wants to solve. The immediate solution that he gives is as follows:

Page 9 of 20

Idealism Ideally the dispositions which theoretical micro‐regresses require physicists to ascribe to unobservable beings, like quarks and gluons, would be grounded, at least in principle, in observable properties of the universe. These properties would be occurrent rather than dispositional, embracing such matters as the quantity and distribution of energy fields. (1986: 296) This solution, which he derives from Mach, looks rather like a form of phenomenalism, because the subatomic world is being grounded, ontologically and not just epistemically, on the observable. (I put aside the oddity of calling energy fields ‘occurrent rather than dispositional’.) But later he develops the theory in a Kantian direction. The basic powers of matter are the product of the interaction between ‘the ur‐stuff of the world’—which he prefers ‘to nickname … “glub”, to avoid any of the metaphysical temptations that arise from the connotations of the word “stuff” ’—and our observation apparatus.

Whatever this theory is, it is not straightforward physical realism. Harré compares his ‘glub’ to Kant's noumenal world, having no characteristics accessible to us. The theory, therefore, seems to have more in common with Kantian idealism than with normal physical realism. A more empiricist option is to adopt the neutral monism that Russell once espoused (1927). This is the line taken by Grover Maxwell (1978), Michael Lockwood (1989, 1993), and Daniel Stoljar (2001). The bearers of the ultimate powers and the intrinsic qualities of matter are those qualities that show themselves in conscious experience. These are in fact the intrinsic nature of the matter of which our brains are made. This theory seems to imply that the intrinsic nature of, for example, an electron, will be something such as a blue quale or a slight itch. One might try arguing that it need not be a phenomenal entity of such a developed kind, but a proto‐phenomenal quality. But what something is that is not phenomenal but which when combined with others of a similar sort becomes phenomenal takes us back to (p. 198) mystery. Furthermore, given the difficulty in formulating a convincing version of the Janus‐faced account of quality and power, the connection between the qualititive core and the causal powers would seem to be entirely contingent and, hence, not explanatory.

10.2.4 Conclusion to Section 10.2 Once it is acknowledged that secondary qualities are not suitable to constitute the fundamental nature of matter, the physical realist has a problem in giving an account of what matter is. The idealist has no such problem, because, on one understanding of ‘matter’, he simply denies its existence. But, nevertheless, he accepts the notion of being material, which is not, for him, the possession of some elusive nature; rather it signifies that the entity in question has a certain status within the common‐sense scheme for understanding experience which we cannot help but apply. The idealist accepts our common‐sense conceptual scheme for interpreting the world, and being material is,

Page 10 of 20

Idealism within that scheme, being a mind‐independent occupant of space with causal powers; that is, from an empirical, as opposed to a metaphysical, perspective, material objects are extra‐mental.5

10.3 The Physical World and the Nature of Thought 10.3.1 Berkeley's Statement of the Problem and Some Initial Development Arguments against physical realism based on the nature of thought are much more murky than those we have just considered and, for historical reasons, are greeted with more suspicion by analytical and empiricist philosophers. One can trace more than one route to idealism via the nature of thought, but for our purposes it is best to start from Berkeley's so‐called master argument in Principles of Human Knowledge: But say you, surely there is nothing easier than to imagine trees, for instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet, and no body by to perceive them. I answer, you may so, there is no difficulty in it: but what is all this, I beseech you, more than framing in your mind certain ideas which you call books and trees, and at the same time omitting to frame the idea of any one that may perceive them? But do not you yourself perceive or think of them all the while? This is therefore nothing to the purpose: it only shows that you have the power of imagining or forming ideas in your mind; but it does not shew that you can conceive it possible, the (p. 199) objects of your thought may exist without the mind: to make this out, it is necessary that you conceive them existing unconceived or unthought of, which is a manifest repugnancy. (Berkeley 1710/1949: sect. 23)

Page 11 of 20

Idealism There are many things that can be said about this passage. In sympathetic vein, Christopher Peacocke (1985) has taken it as making the essentially true point that we cannot imagine an object simpliciter, but only imagine it as it appears from a certain viewpoint. He does not, of course, claim that this is enough on its own to prove idealism. John Campbell (2004) also thinks that Berkeley has identified a deep and serious problem, but one that forces one to direct realism, rather than to idealism. More critical responses, however, often begin by pointing out that Berkeley confuses perceiving something with conceiving or thinking about it: from the fact that you cannot think about an object without thinking about it, it does not follow that one cannot think about an object unperceived. The criticism of the argument from which I wish to start is connected to this one. It is that, in one way, Berkeley misses the intentionality of thought. He confuses the psychological content of the thought episode with the object that the thought is about. Because, platitudinously, one cannot think of an object without thinking of it, Berkeley concludes that what one thinks of must be internal to the act of thinking. No doubt it is because he follows Locke in having an imagist theory of thought that he cannot properly grasp the idea that a mental episode essentially refers beyond itself. I raise this criticism, however, only to show its limitations.

Although the intentionality of language shows how thought refers beyond itself to objects in the world, it does not so easily show how the kinds of facts that we impute to the world are separable from our ways of thought. I think that many of the most suggestive of the thought‐based arguments for idealism can be seen as founded on a single idea. This is that our way of thinking about the world possesses certain logico‐grammatical features which, on the one hand, could have no correlate in a mind‐independent reality, but which, on the other hand, are ineliminable from the world as it is represented in our understanding. A good point to begin to appreciate this line of thought can be found in Strawson's response to Austin on the correspondence theory of truth: What ‘makes the statement’ that the cat has mange ‘true’, is not the cat, but the condition of the cat, i.e., the fact that the cat has mange. The only plausible candidate for the position of what (in the world) makes the statement true is the fact it states; but the fact it states is not something in the world [my emphasis]. It is not an object; not even … a complex object consisting of one or more particular elements … and a universal element … I can (perhaps) hand you or draw a circle round, or time with a stop‐watch the things or incidents that are referred to when a statement is made. Statements are about such objects; but they state facts. (1971: 195)

Page 12 of 20

Idealism At first sight it might seem that Strawson is simply being misled by the double sense of ‘fact’, when it can mean either true proposition or state of affairs, the former being ‘on the side of language’ and the latter ‘on the side of the world’. Surely the condition of the cat—the property instances it possesses—must be just as real as the (p. 200) cat. But even thinking in terms of states of affairs, there are many such states which seem fundamental to our thinking about the world and which do not seem open to a simple realist construal. There are many true and important kinds of facts about the world which seem not only to be a function of how the world coldly and simply in its own right is, but to be a product of how the world is and of a judgement or assessment of how the world is. A simple illustration of this is as follows. The easiest kind of fact to take realistically is one that concerns the location of a particular object in space and time. Thus the thought or proposition ‘There is a pen on the table’, if true, simply reflects a situation in the world. It is made directly true by what there is in concrete reality. But negative propositions do not ‘picture reality’ in the straightforward way that some positive assertions do. The proposition ‘There is no pen on the table’ is not so simple as its positive counterpart. Absences are not part of concrete reality. A fact of an absence is more like an assessment of a situation with a certain thought or perspective in mind—in this case, a concern about a pen or pens. It is grounded in the concrete situation—what the situation positively is on the table's surface—but it is not a representation of that alone. If one wishes to include negative facts in one's ontology, a simple physical realism does not seem to be available.

Even the category of states of affairs is more problematic than it may seem. David Armstrong believes that the world includes states of affairs and that everything in the world is spatio‐temporal; hence, that states of affairs are spatio‐temporal. Indeed, anyone who wishes to include states of affairs within his physical ontology, realistically conceived, would seem to have to deem them spatio‐temporal. But it is not clear that they have spatial location. Perhaps it is easy enough to assign location to the states of affairs of macroscopic objects' possessing the traditional primary and secondary qualities. Thus a ball's being round will be where the circumference of the ball is, and its being red where its surface is. With more arcane properties, the issue is harder. A particular electron has location, but where is its having spin or its having mass? Are they everywhere the electron is? Relations also create further problems. One could draw a rough outline round the state of affairs of a's being six inches away from b: it would include a and b, but what of the intervening space would it include? In Timothy Sprigge's words: The point is that there is no distinguishable portion or piece of reality which is where the relation is exemplified as there is in the case of a property … There is not, so to speak, some sub‐division of the totality of particular reality which actualises the relation to the exclusion of its contraries as in the case of properties. (1983: 164)

10.3.2 A General Statement of the Problem so Far Developed This pattern of argument can be captured in the following general structure: Page 13 of 20

Idealism (1) Our conception of the world, as shown in our language about it, possesses logico‐ grammatical complexity, and certain features of this complexity cannot (p. 201) be treated straightforwardly as representations of aspects of concrete, mind‐ independent reality. Therefore

(2) If there is a realist conception of the world, it must be possible to separate those features of our conception of the world which can be treated in a straightforwardly realist way and those that cannot. It is the former that constitute the realist conception of the world, and the states of affairs they represent must be enough to constitute the realist's world. (3) It is not possible to make the distinction specified in (2). Therefore

(4) A realist conception of the world is not possible. Accepting that there is a prima facie case for (1), there are three ways of responding to the argument. There are two ways in which one might deny (2). One of them is to deny that a realist is restricted to having only concrete elements in his reality. Perhaps a physicalist or a naturalist of a certain kind is committed to this, but a realist per se is not bound to deny that there is a realm of more or less abstract facts, grounded in but going beyond the concrete core of his reality. A second kind of objector to (2) regards the argument as wholly misconceived. This is a response that might come from someone with sympathy for the ‘ordinary language’ school of philosophy. Of course, this respondent will say, when one describes the world, the descriptions possess the logico‐grammatical features of the language used. This is a trivial consequence of using language to describe the world, which is something one cannot avoid. It does not carry strange consequences for one's conception of the world itself.

The third response is to deny (3) and to take up the challenge to distinguish clearly between those features of our conception of the world which are to be taken wholly realistically and those which are not, and to explain how the former sustain the practices which give rise to the latter. This, I take it, is the point of ‘truthmaker theory’, which tries to explain how statements are made true by a world conceived as very much sparcer than the way a literal reading of our statements would make it seem.6 There is not space in this essay to discuss all these responses adequately. I shall make what I hope are suggestive comments about the first two, and then discuss the ‘truthmaker’ option in slightly more detail. I give it the more careful treatment because I share the truthmaker theorist's intuition that his theory represents what the realist is actually committed to. My reservation about the ‘abstract facts’ strategy is easily stated. The suggestion that a physical realist can accept abstract objects fails to distinguish between different kinds of abstract objects. The realist can, at least if he is not a rigorous physicalist, accept universals, numbers, and propositions, but can he accept that the facts that make certain propositions about the physical world true are also abstract? It is one thing to allow the

Page 14 of 20

Idealism proposition that there is no cat on the mat to be abstract, another to treat the fact that makes it true as abstract. (p. 202)

The claim that all the phenomena that have been cited merely reflect the trivial fact that we talk about the world using language and therefore do so in a way that reflects the properties of language ideally requires an extended discussion. I shall make only one observation. It could be argued that the very objection brought against Berkeley's argument works against this strategy. I said that Berkeley fails to give weight to the intentionality of thought and language. But if one does give this weight, then one has the resources to distinguish between thought and language on the one side and what they are about on the other. Once having been allowed this distinction, it is difficult to see what could prevent one from enquiring further into the relation between the logico‐ grammatical features of language and the question of what there is ‘out there’ to be its object. If one denies the possibility of separating these two, it looks as if one is in danger of surrendering to Berkeley's argument as it stands.

10.3.3 Truth‐Maker Theory According to the truth‐maker theorist, for every statement with a truth‐value there is something about fundamental reality that necessitates that that statement have the truth‐ value that it does. For a true statement, this is its truth‐maker. It is important that this is something about the fundamental reality. One cannot generally articulate the truth maker of a sentence simply by repeating it, as one can when stating its truth‐conditions. So the truth‐maker for a statement such as ‘There is a hurricane approaching Florida’ will be some complex state of affairs involving elementary particles moving in a particularly rapid way over other particles that constitute a section of the Atlantic. The statement about the hurricane will have the same truth maker as a statement describing the same event in greater detail: they will both be made true by the same hunk of reality. This still leaves open a choice between two conceptions of how this theory fits with realism. They can be stated as follows. (A) If realism is true, then if, for example, there is no cat on the mat, then it is true that there is no cat on the mat even if there are no minds. Therefore

If realism is true, then there must be both truthmakers and truthbearers for all true statements. The alternative is:

(B) If realism is true, then if, for example, there is no cat on the mat, then there must be that in the world, even if there are no minds in it, which would make it true to say that there is no cat on the mat. Page 15 of 20

Idealism The difference is that the latter does not commit one to the existence of truth bearers in the absence of minds. The point is the following. We are inclined to say that, from the realist perspective, the facts are what they are whether or not there are any minds to appreciate them. From the perspective of the second theory, there is no fact that there is no cat on the mat in a world without minds. In other words, when fact and truth maker are different, the fact will not exist unless minds do. Does this matter? (p. 203)

I want to distinguish between a pure description and a factual assessment. A pure description is a characterization of the world the content of which is the same as the content of its truthmaker. In other words, the truth maker can be identified with the state of affairs that is asserted to obtain in a pure description. A factual assessment is a characterization of the world whose content differs from the content of its truth maker. It seems to me that at least certain kinds of factual assessment are true and essential to our notion of a real world. If this is so, such a world could not exist without minds. A possible example of this is the following. Suppose a certain random event (for example, the decaying of a particle) occurred at t, but that it could have occurred at t′, and that had it occurred at t′ certain very different things stretching into the future would, or could, have happened. If you are a realist about possibilities, you will want to say that it is a fact that these things would, or could, have happened, whether or not there are any minds. The truth makers for such statements will be certain immediate dispositions or powers of actual objects. The extrapolation to more remote future outcomes cannot be thought of as existing in these actual states of affairs. This is shown to be true by the case in which, had the event occurred at t′ not t, the future that ensued could itself have gone either of two ways depending on some further random event. Let us express what actually occurred by p. What might have occurred is q. If q had occurred, then it might have been followed either by r or by s. The ‘might’ here is not epistemological, but is based on genuine indeterminacy. So if p had not been true, but q had, then either q followed by r could have been the case, or q followed by s. The truthmakers for either of those possibilities in the actual world would be the same. This is so because if there is a circumstance C in which there is a set of outcomes that are indeterministically possible, it is the same set of facts that underlies the possibility or probability of any of those outcomes, because they determine the range of probabilities as a whole. Nevertheless, it could be argued that the realist and common‐sense intuition is that it is objectively true that there are the two possible outcomes, whether or not there are any ordinary minds to appreciate this fact. If this is the case then factual assessments and, hence, some form of mentality seem to be presupposed by our common‐sense conception of the world.

10.3.4 Conclusion to Section 10.3

Page 16 of 20

Idealism If the arguments in this section have any force at all—and I think that this is a much more open question here than it is about the arguments presented in section 10.2— then they show that we have no notion of a world as it is in itself that is wholly disembrangled from modes of conception that are definitely mind‐dependent. But what sort of idealism does this give us? The natural upshot might appear to be that the world is dependent on our way of thinking about it, as Kant claimed. Out of this idea, by dint of various obscure moves, came the idealism of the Hegelian tradition.7 (p. 204) But there is an alternative interpretation of the arguments presented in this section. This is that the existence of a world depends on its relation to a mind, but not ours. This interpretation is Platonic or, more precisely, Neoplatonic, rather than Kantian. According to this Platonistic conception, there could not be an objective world if there were not also an objective Intellect understanding it. Our intellect merely participates in this Divine Intellect. How one might set about choosing between the Neoplatonic and Kantian‐Hegelian options is an issue we have no space here to discuss.

10.4 General Conclusion The idealist claims the following. (i) We have no coherent idea of what matter is or could be. (ii) We cannot form any conception of how a mind‐independent world might be in itself, independently of categories which, he holds, are plainly modes of understanding or interpretation, rather than properties of the world in its own right. I hope to have shown that the physical realist has not conclusively disposed of either of these problems.

References Armstrong, D.M. (2004), Truth and Truthmakers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Berkeley, G. (1710/1949), Principles of Human Knowledge, in The Works of George Berkeley, ii, ed. A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (London: Nelson), 25–113. Blackburn, S. W. (1990), ‘Filling In Space’, Analysis, 50: 62–5. Campbell, J. (2004), ‘Berkeley's Puzzle’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 127–43. Craig, W. L., and Smith, Q. (1993), Theism, Atheism and Big Bang Cosmology (Oxford: Clarendon). Ewing, A. C. (1934), Idealism: A Critical Survey (London: Methuen). Foster, J. (1982), The Case for Idealism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul).

Page 17 of 20

Idealism Foster, J. (1993), The Succinct Case for Idealism, in H. Robinson (ed.), Objections to Physicalism (Oxford: Clarendon) 293–313. Harré, R. (1970), Principles of Scientific Thinking (London: Macmillan). Harré, R., and Madden, E. (1975), Causal Powers (Oxford: Blackwell). Harré, R. (1986), Varieties of Realism (Oxford: Blackwell). Hume, D. (1739–40/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon). Lockwood, M. (1989), Mind, Brain and Quantum: The Compound ‘I’ (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1993), ‘The Grain Problem’, in H. Robinson (ed.), Objections to Physicalism (Oxford: Clarendon), 271–92. Martin, C. B. (1997), ‘On the need for Properties: The Road to Pythagoreanism and Back’, Synthese, 112: 193–231. (p. 205)

Maxwell, G. (1978), ‘Rigid Designators and Mind–Brain Identity’, in C. W. Savage (ed.), Perception and Cognition (Minneapolis, Minn. University of Minnesota Press), 365–403. Molnar, G. (2003), Powers: A Study in Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Mumford, S. (1998), Dispositions (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Peacocke, C. (1985), ‘Imagination, Experience and Possibility: A Berkeleian View Defended’, in J. Foster and H. Robinson (eds.), Essays on Berkeley (Oxford: Clarendon), 19–35. Robinson, H. (1982), ‘Matter: Turning the Tables’, in Robinson Matter and Sense (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press); repr. in T. Crane and K. Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 107–19. —— (1985)’, The General Form of the Argument for Berkelian Idealism’, in J. Foster and H. Robinson (eds.), Essays on Berkeley (Oxford: Clarendon), 163–86; repr. in T. O'Connor and D. Robb (eds.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (London: Routledge), 81–102. —— (1994), Perception (London: Routledge). Russell, B. (1927), The Analysis of Matter (London: Kegan Paul). Sprigge, T. (1983), The Vindication of Absolute Idealism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).

Page 18 of 20

Idealism —— (1993), James and Bradley: American Truth and British Reality (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court). Stoljar, D. (2001), ‘Two Conceptions of the Physical’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62: 253–81. Strawson. P. (1971), ‘Truth’, in Logico‐Linguistic Papers (London: Methuen), 190–213.

Notes: (1) For a discussion of arguments against realist views of secondary qualities see Robinson (1994: ch. 3) and, for a more detailed statement of the arguments in the context of a discussion of idealism, Robinson (1982). (2) For a lucid account of this development see Harré and Madden (1975: ch. 9). (3) This is slightly too swift. For a more detailed spelling out of this part of the argument see Robinson (1982). (4) For lucid discussion, from both sides, of whether actual infinities are coherent see Craig and Smith (1993). (5) There is one very important recent, and, I believe, successful, argument for idealism which would fall under the rubric of section 10.2 which I have not the space to discuss. That is John Foster's argument, as found in Foster (1982, 1993) and, in a slightly different form, in Robinson (1985). I have nothing to add to the argument as found in those places. (6) For a thorough working out of truthmaker theory see Armstrong (2004). (7) I have not been able directly to discuss the Kant‐Hegel tradition in the way that might be expected in a chapter with this title, but the arguments of section 10.3 are an analytic philosopher's attempt to cast within his own terms what he can understand from that tradition. Ewing (1934) is a great, but largely forgotten, work by a philosopher with all the analytical skills and real sympathy with Hegelian idealism, which examines the arguments that have been brought for that tradition. Sprigge (1983, 1993) are also works wholly accessible to analytic philosophers, but which make a strong defence of British Hegelianism.

Howard Robinson

Howard Robinson is a member of the Faculty of Philosophy at the Central European University and an honarary visiting professor in Philosophy at the University of York.

Page 19 of 20

Panpsychism

Oxford Handbooks Online Panpsychism   William Seager The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0012

Abstract and Keywords Panpsychism endorses the co-fundamental status of matter and mind in so far as it allows there are features of the world which are non-mental. Panpsychism is also not generally a view in which mentality is taken as ‘substantial’. It is more natural to regard panpsychism as expressing the view that, roughly speaking, everything exemplifies certain mental properties. However, it is an important and distinctive claim of many panpsychists that the ‘object/property’ metaphysics we take for granted is fundamentally mistaken and must be replaced with another metaphysical vision of the basic structure of reality. Keywords: panpsychism, status of matter, status of mind, mental properties, metaphysics, structure of reality

11.1 What is Panpsychism? THE

term ‘panpsychism’ refers to a range of doctrines whose core assertions are that

mentality is ontologically fundamental and ubiquitous. Mentality is fundamental in the sense that it can neither be explained in terms of anything else nor be reduced to anything else. To say that mentality is ubiquitous is to say that every aspect of concrete reality partakes of mentality in some way or in some measure. The commitments of panpsychism can be further clarified by contrasting it with other accounts of mind. Cartesian substance dualism accepts that the mental is fundamental but denies its ubiquity. According to Descartes, minds are self‐standing entities which ‘attach’ to only a tiny fraction of the material bodies in the world. While mind cannot be explained in physical terms and can exist independently of the physical world, the physical enjoys the same status with respect to minds. Minds and bodies are, so to speak, co‐fundamental on the Cartesian view. Standard modern forms of physicalism deny both that the mental is fundamental and its ubiquity. Physicalists split on whether mentality can be explained in Page 1 of 16

Panpsychism physical terms,1 but must agree that the physical is the ontological foundation of the world and that mentality is in some way an expression of the physical. Reflection on this division reveals an obvious third possibility, the ‘inverse’ of physicalism, in which mentality is ontologically fundamental and the physical is in some way an expression of mental reality. Such a view would be a kind of panpsychism but not a form commonly encountered under that (p. 207) label. More frequently, panpsychism endorses the co‐ fundamental status of matter and mind in so far as it allows there are features of the world which are non‐mental. Panpsychism is also not generally a view in which mentality is taken as ‘substantial’. It is more natural to regard panpsychism as expressing the view that, roughly speaking, everything exemplifies certain mental properties. However, it is an important and distinctive claim of many panpsychists that the ‘object / property’ metaphysics we take for granted is fundamentally mistaken and must be replaced with another metaphysical vision of the basic structure of reality. Probably the best way to locate panpsychism within the mind–body problem is to see it as the counter position to emergentist views of mentality (of which modern physicalist theories are all examples).2 Modern common sense bridles at the claim that planets, trees, rocks, atoms, or electrons possess mental attributes. In particular, the modern scientific world‐view has it that all things are ultimately constituted of fundamental, simple, and purely physical entities which possess a relatively small number of basic attributes such as mass, charge, and spin. There is no place for and no need to postulate these physical building blocks having any mental properties whatsoever. And yet it is certain that some of the composite objects—such as ourselves—made from quarks, electrons, and the other fundamental physical entities do exemplify mental properties. Therefore, the modern scientific viewpoint has to endorse some form of emergentism. While any conception of emergence requires that composite things have properties which their components lack, the proper characterization of emergence remains controversial. Theories range from the highly radical (such as those espoused by the so‐called British emergentists; see McLaughlin 1992 for an excellent survey; see also Blitz 1992) to benign accounts that see emergence as nothing more than complexity, perhaps of a high enough degree to forestall all attempts at practical prediction and explanation. (On such accounts, the weather is an emergent feature of the physical processes we call the atmosphere; see Holland 1998.) From the point of view of the panpsychist, the problem with emergence is that radical forms seem highly implausible and no less mysterious and opposed to modern common sense than panpsychism itself, while benign forms seem incapable of explicating the generation of mentalistic features such as consciousness from the mere complex interplay of the available physical features.

11.2 The History of Panpsychism Page 2 of 16

Panpsychism Panpsychism is a truly ancient doctrine that can probably be traced back to the animism that seems to have been universally accepted by our distant ancestors, and which (p. 208) we still see naturally and spontaneously occurring in our children. Philosophical and science‐based articulations of it have persisted throughout our intellectual history, down to the present day (see Skrbina 2005 for a detailed account; see also Seager and Allen‐Hermanson 2005). As a distinctive philosophical doctrine, panpsychism was advanced by several of the Presocratic philosophers of ancient Greece. One of the earliest, Thales (c.624–545BC), deployed an analogical argument to extend mind beyond the obviously conscious people and animals. Thales noted that creatures with minds were ‘self‐movers’, but then observed that other things, notably magnets and amber, were also capable of self‐motion under certain conditions. We have very few of Thales’ writings, but Aristotle tells us that Thales extended the argument to claim that ‘everything is full of gods’ and Diogenes reports that Thales believed that ‘the universe is alive and full of spirits’. The Presocratics understood the panpsychism–emergence dynamic (see Mourelatos 1986). The emergentist line of thought culminated with the atomism of Democritus (c. 460–370 BC), in which more complex elements of reality were formed from a set of ultimately simple atoms which could interlock in a variety of ways. On the other hand, Anaxagoras (c.500–425 BC) flatly denied the intelligibility of emergence and instead maintained a kind of universal mixing theory in which ‘everything is in everything’. Interestingly, mental features alone did not allow of admixture of the other qualities although everything possessed a portion of mind within it (see Barnes 1982). It is tempting to interpret Anaxagoras as thereby endorsing both the fundamentality and ubiquity principles of panpsychism. However, he did not draw the conclusion that everything had a mind—a seemingly paradoxical admission which is in fact a recurring claim amongst panpsychists. The rise of ‘Aristotelian Christianity’ through the Middle Ages was not conducive to panpsychism, until in the Renaissance the doctrine regained its prominence (see Skrbina 2005: ch. 3). But it was the birth of the mechanical world‐view associated with the scientific revolution that really forced the issue between emergence and panpsychism. Galileo famously tried to sweep the problem of mind under the rug with his distinction between primary and secondary qualities, but this could only temporarily put off the need to integrate mind into the burgeoning scientific picture of the world. Of course, Descartes's dualism was the most obvious approach: simply and totally hive off mind from the physical world, permitting only such minor ‘leakage’ between the two realms as necessary for free human action and sensory consciousness. Cartesian dualism is deeply unsatisfactory, with its totally mysterious causal interaction between completely disparate substances, especially as the interaction threatens some of the most fundamental principles governing the physical world, such as conservation of energy. Philosophers were quick to find alternative views of mind, and panpsychism figured in two of the most prominent.

Page 3 of 16

Panpsychism It was Spinoza's view that both mind and matter were but merely two attributes of an underlying, infinite, and infinitely complex substance (which Spinoza notoriously identified with God). Every material thing has its mentalistic aspect, and vice versa. As Spinoza wrote: ‘[A] circle existing in nature and the idea of the existing circle, which is also in God, are one and the same thing … therefore, whether we conceive (p. 209) nature under the attribute of Extension, or under the attribute of Thought … we shall find one and the same order, or one and the same connection of causes’ (1677/1985: prop. 7, scholium). In terms of the core principles of panpsychism, Spinoza clearly holds that mind is fundamental, though not uniquely so, and ubiquitous—there is nothing that is not, when considered from the appropriate viewpoint, mentalistic in its nature. Leibniz's philosophy can be seen as a kind of splintered mirror of Spinoza's. Perhaps to avoid the heretical features of Spinoza's views (e.g. making each of us literally a part of God and identifying God with nature) Leibniz replaces the single supreme substance with an infinity of diverse finite substances and one separate infinite substance. These are monads and each one is what Leibniz called an ‘incorporeal automaton’ (1714/1989: sect. 18) in the sense that each contains within itself the complete cause of its succession of states (which Leibniz called its ‘perceptions’ to emphasize their mental nature). Each monad is completely independent of every other thing, requiring only God for its creation and endurance. There is no element of nature that is not associated with a set of monads, but Leibniz introduced an important distinction between what he called organisms and mere aggregates. A mere aggregate corresponds to a set of monads which is not hierarchically organized; an organism by contrast is an organized set of monads under one dominant monad. For example, your body is made of organs, which have sub‐organs, in a hierarchical organization which subserves its biological functionality. The corresponding system of monads reflects this organization, expressed in the clarity and perspective of the information possessed by each monad in the hierarchy. Thus, while your body has a corresponding dominant monad, that is your conscious mind, a heap of sand has no such ‘top’ monad, but corresponds merely to the set of monads of the smallest organized units constituting it. (Grains of sands are likely to be themselves mere aggregates, but perhaps the molecules are organisms in Leibniz's sense.) Each monad contains within it a complete specification of the entire universe from a particular viewpoint, expressed with more or less clarity. A monad that was incomplete could fit into more than one possible world, putting God into an impossible dilemma about which world to create in so far as He is governed by the principle of sufficient reason. So why is it that we, for example, find ourselves ignorant about so very much? To answer this, Leibniz deployed another novel (for the time) and important distinction: that between conscious and non‐conscious mental states. The mental lives of most monads are almost entirely unconscious, consisting of petite perceptions. Fully conscious states are introspectible and form what Leibniz called apperceptions. Even monads with rich conscious lives, such as ourselves, are aware of only a tiny fraction of our mental states. From the point of view of articulating the forms of panpsychism, the introduction of this distinction naturally bifurcates the theory, but also imposes two great conceptual Page 4 of 16

Panpsychism difficulties. The first is to give a characterization of the mental which captures its essential mental aspect without using the notion of consciousness. The second is to describe the relation between the unconscious and (p. 210) conscious mental states, and this leads to fundamental problems which threaten to undercut the supposed advantage that panpsychism has over emergentist views. It must also be noted that Leibniz did not agree with Spinoza on the co‐fundamentality of matter and mind. For him, the physical world was a ‘well‐founded illusion’ or logical construction from the sum total of all monadic points of view. This is a kind of idealism, but not of the usual sort (such as Berkeley's or the later so‐called absolute idealists). For Leibniz allows that every thing which we regard as a material being (a speck of dust or a single unobservable atom) has its corresponding mental aspect which grounds it. More typical idealists regard objects such as dust motes as mere constructs of the conscious states of fully‐fledged minds. The nineteenth century was the heyday of panpsychism, though generally of the idealist form. Idealism was the ‘received’ metaphysical viewpoint; materialism was but a minor and disreputable pursuit. The founders of scientific psychology: Gustav Fechner, Wilhelm Wundt, Rudolf Lotze, and William James, to name a few, were all panpsychists of one stripe or another. Many embraced a double or multi‐aspect view of the world, in which everything possessed both a mentalistic and physicalistic side, but the mental aspect was frequently regarded as the more fundamental. (For pure idealists this goes without saying.) James, for example, while endorsing a dual‐aspect view he called ‘neutral monism’, added in a notebook entry written in 1909: ‘[T]he constitution of reality which I am making for is of the psychic type’ (see Cooper 1990). The tension between emergentist and panpsychist positions culminated in the early to mid‐twentieth century with several sophisticated theories of emergence that strove to integrate the incredible advances that were being made in the physical sciences into a coherent metaphysical view of the world (see Morgan 1923; Broad 1925; and Alexander 1927; for a survey, McLaughlin 1992). These emergentists clearly made the crucial distinction between epistemological and non‐epistemological forms of emergence. The latter involves ‘merely’ the impossibility of our understanding in detail how complex systems behave, even if we grant that their behaviour is completely determined by the purely physical properties of the fundamental entities that constitute the world. The former, often called radical emergence, entails the production of genuinely novel, causally efficacious features of the world, stemming from the combination of fundamental components. Writing at about the same time as these emergentists, Alfred North Whitehead's ‘process philosophy’ (1929) represented the last and most sophisticated development of panpsychism within the context of a complex, overarching, and revisionary metaphysics. (For an introduction to Whitehead's panpsychism see Griffin 1998.)

Page 5 of 16

Panpsychism But emergentism fell rapidly out of favour as the new quantum mechanics promised to reveal how the heretofore primary example of uncontroversial emergence, chemistry, could be in principle reductively understood in terms of basic physics. This development led in turn to a vigorous renewal of materialist views of the mind, so that, somewhat paradoxically, the death of emergentism was not the victory of panpsychism. Rather, both accounts were supplanted by a vigorous and fruitful materialist research project in philosophy seeking to duplicate, at a (p. 211) very abstract level, the successful treatment of chemistry in the realm of the psychological. Just as chemical properties arise from entities which entirely lack them, so too would mental properties be seen to arise from entirely non‐mentalistic physical constituents. This philosophical project began with ‘logical behaviourism’ (see Carnap 1932/1933), proceeded to the psychoneural identity theory (see Place 1956; Smart 1959) and has led to a host of successor physicalist accounts of mind (see Kim 2006 for a survey). It has proved surprisingly difficult to produce an acceptable version of materialism, however, and the problem of consciousness has loomed recently as especially recalcitrant (see Chalmers 1996). In fact, the so‐called hard problem of consciousness, the problem of explaining exactly how material systems generate, realize, or constitute states which have phenomenal character (states for which there is ‘something it is like’ to be in them) has seemed to some so difficult that a renewed interest in more radical approaches, such as emergentism and panpsychism, has appeared; and it is in this light that we ought to consider the arguments for and against panpsychism.

11.3 Some Arguments for Panpsychism Roughly speaking, the arguments in favour of panpsychism can be divided into three broad categories: genetic arguments, analogical arguments, and arguments from ‘intrinsic nature’. (For a much more comprehensive list of arguments see Skrbina 2005.) Genetic arguments focus on the issue of emergence or the question of how mental features could arise from a non‐mental background. As noted, this argument goes back to ancient times, and it has retained its appeal to the present. The argument can be given either in an a priori form or in more empirical versions. The structure of the a priori argument can be expressed very straightforwardly, if somewhat elliptically: 1. If mind is emergent then it is either epistemologically or non‐epistemologically emergent. 2. Mind is not epistemologically emergent. 3. But no non‐epistemological form of emergence is coherent. 4. Therefore, mind is not emergent, and must therefore be fundamental. Notice that this argument does not quite establish panpsychism, since it does not yield the ubiquity principle. Page 6 of 16

Panpsychism Thomas Nagel presented a clear form of the argument, in which the linchpin principle (2) is stated thus: ‘[T]here are no truly emergent properties of complex systems. All properties of complex systems that are not relations between it and something else derive from the properties of its constituents and their effects on each other when so combined’ (1979: 182). Thus, the only coherent form of emergence is an epistemological doctrine about the limits of our understanding of complex systems coupled with an appreciation for the usefulness of high‐level explanatory systems which we (p. 212) must deploy in the face of intractable complexity. However, it is not altogether clear why Nagel denies that some of the ‘effects’ which arise from the combination of low‐level physical entities are not or could not be radically emergent. The classical emergentists would have agreed with the letter of Nagel's principle, but not the spirit. They allowed that emergence was a lawlike feature of the world, but denied that it was the effect of fundamental physical properties working by themselves. Instead, the world exemplifies underivable ‘laws of emergence’ that govern the combinatory properties of physical entities. As C. D. Broad put it, such a law ‘would be a statement of the irreducible fact that an aggregate composed of aggregates of the next lower order in such and such proportions and arrangements has such and such characteristic and non‐deducible properties’ (1925: 78). It must be noted though that many if not all of the currently fashionable views of emergence in the sciences of complexity seem to be consistent with the purely epistemological reading of emergence (and to resist going beyond it), and to that extent Nagel's argument carries some weight. Recently, Galen Strawson (2006) has argued for the incoherence of radical emergence, roughly on the grounds that the only kind of emergence of Y from X that makes sense is one in which ‘Y is in some sense wholly dependent on X and X alone, so that all features of Y trace intelligibly back to X (where “intelligible” is a metaphysical rather than an epistemic notion)’.3 Perhaps the issue of the coherence of radical emergence comes down to the question of whether it is possible to articulate a sense of dependence in which emergent features are dependent on low‐level features but are not merely the product of these low‐level interactions working ‘by themselves’. Opponents will deny that there is any legitimate kind of dependence that can be explicated without showing how the low‐level features have within themselves the power to produce the emergents, thus demoting radical emergence to the merely epistemological. I am inclined to think, however, that such a conception of dependence is at least barely coherent, which can be shown by a computer‐simulation thought‐experiment. Imagine that we have a working computer simulation of fundamental physics. To some minor extent we have this already; it is, for example, possible to approximately compute the mass of the proton from the fundamental physics of quark interactions using the theory of quantum chromodynamics (plus a host of simplifying assumptions and a few years’ full‐ time effort by a supercomputer). But what I am thinking of is a purely imaginary extension of such computational systems that ignores the practically insuperable difficulties of complexity and encompasses the presently unavailable ‘theory of Page 7 of 16

Panpsychism everything’. The point of the thought‐experiment is that we know that computer programs will provide outputs that depend entirely and only upon the nature of their coded algorithms. If we code into the system only the principles of state evolution and interaction of the fundamental physical features (p. 213) then the output will be just what those features can give rise to according to the theory we are simulating. In a world containing only epistemological emergence, we would expect that such computer simulations would exactly mirror the behaviour we observe in the macroscopic world. But if radical emergence was at work, we would expect an inexplicable divergence of real‐ world behaviour from the behaviour of the simulation. A scenario in which we have good reason to suppose that our fundamental theories are correct and in which simulated behaviour diverges from real behaviour seems perfectly coherent. The fact that computers run the exact code given them obviates the issue that computers themselves might have emergent properties. It seems possible that we would opt for accepting a simpler fundamental theory with radical emergence rather than necessarily declaring that the fundamental theory is mistaken merely because of the divergence of simulated from actual behaviour. In such a case, we would have to add certain ‘laws of emergence’ that would impose new constraints on the simulation when certain complex configurations of the fundamental physical entities arise. We might find that once the laws of emergence are in place within the simulation, no further divergence in behaviour between the simulation and actuality ever occurs. Therefore, I think we can give some real content to the idea that dependence can be preserved within a system that endorses radical emergence. However, while this model may legitimate the concept of radical emergence, it does not go beyond addressing the mere existence and efficacy of emergents. It does not in any way at all tell us how conscious states—that is, states with phenomenal character—could emerge from the entirely non‐conscious. In fact, radical emergentists deny that such an understanding is possible. Emergence must be accepted with, in Samuel Alexander's phrase, ‘natural piety’ as a pure brute fact. While all theories rest upon some brute facts (e.g. the values of certain physical constants) it is passing strange that the generation of something so remarkable as consciousness should be brutely contingent on extremely special configurations of numerous instances of precisely organized physical matter, such as we find in the human brain's exquisitely networked 100 billion neurons. If the creation of states of consciousness is contingent upon the formation of such astonishingly complex and intricate physical states, it is hard not to believe that they occur because of the intricate organization and hence can, in principle, be explained by it. But this would mean that consciousness would turn out to be a merely epistemological emergent. Such a view runs afoul of the obvious reply that ‘nothing comes from nothing’, and that all that the intricate organization of fundamental physical entities can produce is intricate organization and correspondingly intricate patterns of causal relations which are all ultimately resolvable into the causal connections present at the most fundamental level of physical reality. Patterns of organization, however, are manifestly not the same as conscious experience, or, at least, the claim that certain very special and very complex patterns of material organization are conscious states is precisely the kind of bizarre Page 8 of 16

Panpsychism brute fact we are trying to avoid. This line of thought is, in fact, taken to provide a rich support (p. 214) for their theory by panpsychists. But before turning to that, we should examine the more empirical version of the genetic argument. The rapid success of Darwin's theory after its introduction in 1859 transformed debate about life and mind. The genetic argument for panpsychism here rests on the idea that evolution is a gradual process which slowly and incrementally modifies pre‐existing features via natural selection. Yet the advent of consciousness into a world utterly devoid of experience represents a giant discontinuity. The smallest, vaguest twinge of feeling is something radically different from the properties of insensate matter. William Clifford put it thus: ‘[W]e cannot suppose that so enormous a jump from one creature to another should have occurred at any point in the process of evolution as the introduction of a fact entirely different and absolutely separate from the physical fact. It is impossible for anybody to point out the particular place in the line of descent where that event can be supposed to have taken place’ (1874/1886: 266). Such considerations also moved William James, who wrote that ‘we ought … to try every possible mode of conceiving of consciousness so that it may not appear equivalent to the irruption into the universe of a new nature non‐existent to then’ (1890/1950: 148). The empirical content of this argument is that Darwinian evolution is the mechanism of emergence (at least within the biological realm). But then it is clear that all emergence will be of the epistemological variety, and will not suffice to account for the generation of consciousness. Turning briefly to the argument from analogy, the basic idea is to find some feature of matter which suggests—ideally strongly suggests—some fundamental similarity with mentality. It is unfortunately difficult to come up with anything along these lines which is at all convincing (see the remarks on Thales above). Some, including Whitehead, have seen in the indeterminacy of modern quantum physics an echo of freedom of will, but the pure randomness of quantum indeterminacy seriously weakens this analogy. Perhaps a more promising avenue is the role of information in quantum physics. The entangled states which express what Einstein derisively labelled ‘spooky action at a distance’ suggest that it is information rather than causal connection which grounds at least some of the fundamental constraints at work in the physical world. One might then hope that there is some kind of proper analogy between quantum information and the intentionality of mental states. For example, mental intentionality is underived; that is, it does not depend upon interpretation, convention, or other derivative methods of assigning meaning. Presumably, the kind of informational connections lurking in the quantum world are similarly underived. (This does not preclude quantum states having standard derived intentionality via our interpretation of them, as in the pioneering use of quantum systems to perform standard computations.) However, it is difficult to provide much real content to the analogy, at least as things stand now. It is also conceivable that work on the measurement problem in quantum mechanics will implicate consciousness at the fundamental level (see Wigner 1962; Lockwood 1989).

Page 9 of 16

Panpsychism Another argument in favour of panpsychism depends upon the idea of ‘intrinsic nature’. This argument has close links to the genetic argument, but goes further in attempting to spell out what makes the emergence of consciousness seem (p. 215) so preposterous. Although the argument is far from novel, it has been recently revived and advocated in Rosenberg (2004) and Strawson (2006).4 The argument assumes a distinction between relational and intrinsic properties, which although intuitively acceptable is notoriously difficult to spell out precisely, and in particular on the concept of dispositional properties (which are a species of the relational). For example, we say that an electron has a negative charge of about 1.6×10−19 Coulombs, but what this means is that the electron is disposed to move in such‐and‐such a way in an electric field of such‐and‐such a strength. The intrinsic nature of electric charge remains utterly mysterious. And yet it seems reasonable to think that every dispositional property stems from underlying intrinsic properties. Of these, with respect to the fundamental physical constituents of the world, we know absolutely nothing, since physics deals only with the dispositional properties of matter. This is a long‐standing position. Both Eddington and Russell, among others, agree that ‘science has nothing to say as to the intrinsic nature of the atom’. (Russell called the dispositional properties of matter ‘mathematical properties’.) This led Eddington to assert further that we know nothing of atoms which ‘renders it at all incongruous that they should constitute a thinking object’ (1927: 259) and to adopt a panpsychist understanding of matter. We might put the argument in another way, as follows. Matter must have an intrinsic nature to ground its dispositional properties. We know nothing of this nature, and in fact the only intrinsic nature with which we are familiar is consciousness itself5. It is arguable that we cannot conceive of any other intrinsic nature because our knowledge of the physical is entirely based upon its dispositions to produce certain conscious experiences under certain conditions. Of course, we can assert that matter has a non‐experiential intrinsic nature which is utterly mysterious to us, but this would seem to make the problem of emergence yet more difficult. An emergentism which made the generation of consciousness intelligible would be one that showed how experience emerged from what we know about matter; that is, from its dispositional properties. But it seems impossible to see how the dispositions to move in certain directions under certain conditions could give rise to or constitute consciousness, save by the kind of brute and miraculous radical emergence discussed above. If granting some kind of experiential intrinsic aspect to the fundamental physical entities of the world eliminates this problem, it might be worth the cost in initial uncomfortable implausibility. Before turning to argument opposed to panpsychism, it is worth noting that the arguments advanced so far do not establish the ubiquity principle of panpsychism, even if it was granted that they made the case for fundamentality. Strawson (2006) argues that the most economical viewpoint endorses ubiquity in the absence of any reason to withhold mental properties from just some of the fundamental physical (p. 216) entities. (Why, after all, if we go so far as to grant electrons some kind of mentalistic aspect would

Page 10 of 16

Panpsychism we baulk at granting something similar to neutrinos.) And in the absence of any alternative intrinsic nature to assign to putatively non‐mentalistic fundamental physical entities, it would seem reasonable to assign them all a mental nature.

11.4 Arguments Opposed to Panpsychism The simplest, and for most quite compelling, argument against panpsychism is that it is intuitively absurd to suggest that electrons, atoms, rocks, planets, etc. have minds or any kind of consciousness. Our experience with everyday physical objects gives no hint that they might possess hidden psychological depths. But panpsychism is by no means obliged to grant mind or experience to all such things. As we have seen, even if the fundamental entities that constitute the world (which are physical) have a mentalistic aspect, it does not follow that every composite made from them is similarly endowed. Leibniz's distinction between mere aggregates and ‘organic unities’ can stand the panpsychist in good stead here to deflect the first onslaught of incredulity. But what of the fundamental features themselves? They do not show any very noticeable signs of a mental life. In reply to this, the panpsychist can note that the primitive and extremely simple sort of consciousness which the fundamental entities presumably enjoy is something of which we have little understanding, so it is not clear what would count as revealing their mental aspects. More important, why should we expect that the fundamental entities should show any sign at all of a mental attribute? Gravitation is taken to be a fundamental feature of all physical things, and yet we do not expect that an individual electron will provide the slightest evidence that it generates a gravitational field. A more serious objection turns the aggregate/unity distinction against the panpsychist. A natural interpretation of the deployment of this distinction assumes that there is some combinatory principle by which the simplest psychological features come together to form the kind of complex minds we are familiar with. Of course, this is the problem of emergence reappearing. William James, though eventually endorsing a panpsychist philosophy, presented this objection to good effect: Take a sentence of a dozen words, and take twelve men and tell to each one word. Then stand the men in a row or jam them in a bunch, and let each think of his word as intently as he will; nowhere will there be a consciousness of the whole sentence. Where the elemental units are supposed to be feelings, the case is in no wise altered. Take a hundred of them, shuffle them and pack them as close together as you can (whatever that might mean); still each remains the same feeling it always was, shut in its own skin, windowless, ignorant of what the other feelings are and mean. There would be a hundred‐and‐first feeling there, if, when a group or series of such feelings were set up, a consciousness belonging to the group as such should emerge. And this 101st feeling would be a totally new fact;

Page 11 of 16

Panpsychism the 100 original feelings might, by (p. 217) a curious physical law, be a signal for its creation, when they came together; but they would have no substantial identity with it, nor it with them, and one could never deduce the one from the others, or (in any intelligible sense) say that they evolved it (1890/1950: 160). This is a powerful objection, but it's worth noting that Leibniz would not have been troubled by it. For him, each mind is a separate, self‐standing entity which is not composed of sub‐minds, even though the material object to which it corresponds can be thought of as, in a certain sense, thus composed. Nonetheless, most panpsychists accept that there is mental emergence. Whitehead embraced this, as explained by Charles Hartshorne, one of his most prominent followers and an important panpsychist of the later twentieth century: ‘[I]t is the destiny of the many to enter into a novel unity, an additional reality’ which means that Whitehead makes the ‘admission not merely of emergence, but of emergent or creative synthesis as the very principle of process and reality’ (Hartshorne 1972: 162).

The panpsychist, however, can deny that this emergence is of the incoherent radical sort discussed above. For it is not so hard to see mind as becoming more complex via organization of already mentalistic features. After all, could we not parody James's remark thus: Take 1023 molecules of H2O and then jam them in a bunch and let them each vibrate and move as intently as they will; nowhere will there by any liquidity. Yet we know, more or less, how liquidity does emerge from the ceaseless jostling of the individual molecules. This is merely epistemological emergence, and arguably it cannot explicate the relation between an insensate sort of matter and mind. But the emergence of complex minds from the joint activity of already experiential components is perhaps easier to understand, especially in light of the fact that the simple part–whole reductionism which James seems to be presupposing has been undercut with the introduction of the superposition principle in quantum mechanics. Some emergentists have seen this as a way to revive the idea of radical emergence (see Silbertstein and McGeever 1999), but superpositions seem to be no more than rather special combinations of the pre‐existing properties of motion, mass, spin, etc. Nonetheless, the idea might point to a way to understand the combinatory powers of intrinsically mentalistic fundamental features of the world (see Seager 1995). Another complaint against panpsychism arises from what is called the causal closure of the physical (see Kim 1998 for extensive discussion of this concept and its implications). The physical world seems to be causally complete in the sense that every event has a purely physical determining cause (or, if indeterminism is allowed, a cause which fully determines the statistics of possible effects). The addition of mentalistic features to the fundamental entities of the physical world would thus be causally otiose and consign mentality to the status of epiphenomena (see n. 3 above). But, in the first place, this argument threatens to make all emergent features epiphenomenal, since their ‘effects’ can be completely explained in terms of the underlying fundamental physics. One might reply here that the emergent properties retain efficacy because these properties simply are compositions of certain fundamental, and efficacious, features. If so, the panpsychist

Page 12 of 16

Panpsychism can adapt this reply. The (p. 218) fundamental dispositional properties of matter are just a reflection of its mentalistic intrinsic nature; calling them physical with the implication that they are entirely non‐mental comes close to begging the question. Finally, there is a methodological problem with panpsychism. It is a purely metaphysical doctrine with no distinctive empirical consequences. As Nagel put it, panpsychism has ‘the faintly sickening odor of something put together in the metaphysical laboratory’ (1979: 49). The methodology of the physical sciences is of course to put together empirical hypotheses that can be tested in experiment and which explain and predict empirical findings. Within philosophy, there has grown up a kind of shadow of this empirical methodology which is often labeled ‘naturalism’, which is the game of providing answers to philosophical problems using conceptual material drawn from and acceptable to the natural sciences. To advance a panpsychist understanding of the mind‐matter relationship is thus against the rules of naturalism. Now, I think naturalism is a great game, and that it is important to see how far we can get in our understanding of the world within its confines. To embrace panpsychism would be to give up on the game, and this would be, given our current exploding but still very rudimentary understanding of the neurological conditions underlying mental activity, dangerously premature. But there is no real fear of that, as the empirical sciences of the mind have never been healthier and, in itself, panpsychism does not in any way undercut these sciences or want to impose on them any methodological strictures. Philosophy of mind also remains in a very healthy, extremely unsettled state, which will not suffer from the occasional expedition into the metaphysical wilderness. Panpsychism reminds us of certain very difficult problems that beset naturalism, and it stands as a perennially interesting metaphysical position which may yet turn out to be the best way of understanding the fundamental nature of mind and matter.

References Alexander, S. (1927), Space, Time and Deity (London: Macmillan). Barnes, J. (1982), The Presocratic Philosophers (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Blitz, D. (1992), Emergent Evolution: Qualitative Novelty and the Levels of Reality (Dordrecht: Kluwer). Broad, C.D. (1925), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Carnap, R. (1932/1933), ‘Psychology in Physical Language’, Erkenntnis, 3: 107–42. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Churchland, P. (1981), ‘Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes’, Journal of Philosophy, 78: 67–90.

Page 13 of 16

Panpsychism Clark, D. (2004), Panpsychism: Past and Recent Selected Readings (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press). Clifford, W. (1874/1886), ‘Body and Mind’, Fortnightly Review, 16: 199–245; repr. in L. Stephen and F. Pollock (eds.), Lectures and Essays (London: Macmillan), 244–73. Cooper, W. E. (1990), ‘William James's Theory of Mind’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 28/4: 571–93. Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown). Eddington, A. (1927), The Nature of the Physical World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). (p. 219)

Griffin, D. (1998), Unsnarling the World Knot: Consciousness, Freedom and the Mind– Body Problem (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press). Hartshorne, C. (1972), Whitehead's Philosophy: Selected Essays 1935–1970 (Lincoln, Nebr.: University of Nebraska Press). Holland, J. (1998), Emergence: From Chaos to Order (Reading, Mass.: Addison‐Wesley). James, W. (1890/1950), The Principles of Psychology, i (New York: Dover). Kim, J. (1998), Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind–Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2006), Philosophy of Mind, 2nd edn (Boulder, Col.: Westview). Leibniz, G. (1714/1989), Monadology, in Leibniz: Philosophical Essays, ed. and trans. R. Ariew and D. Garber (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett). Lockwood, M. (1989), Mind, Brain, and the Quantum (Oxford: Oxford University Press). McLaughlin, B. (1992), ‘The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism’, in A. Beckermann, J. Kim and H. Flohr (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter), 49–93. Morgan, C. (1923), Emergent Evolution (London: Williams & Norgate). Mourelatos, A. (1986), ‘Quality, Structure, and Emergence in Later Presocratic Philosophy’, Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 2: 127–94. Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1979), ‘Panpsychism’, in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) (ch. 13). Pepper, C. (1926), ‘Emergence’, Journal of Philosophy, 23: 241–5.

Page 14 of 16

Panpsychism Place, U. (1956), ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process’, British Journal of Psychology, 47: 44– 50. Rosenberg, G. (2004), A Place for Consciousness: Probing the Deep Structure of the Natural World (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Russell, B. (1927), The Analysis of Matter (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner). Seager, W. (1995), ‘Consciousness, Information, and Panpsychism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2: 272–88. Seager, W., and Allen‐Hermanson, S. (2005), ‘Panpsychism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2005 edn. , accessed 2008. Sellars, W., and Meehl. P. E. (1956), ‘The Concept of Emergence’, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1: 239–52. Silberstein, M., and McGeever, J. (1999), ‘The Search for Ontological Emergence’, Philosophical Quarterly, 49: 182–200. Skrbina, D. (2005), Panpsychism in the West (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Smart, J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56. Spinoza, B. (1677/1985), Ethics, in The Collected Works of Spinoza, i, ed. and trans. E. Curley (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), 408–19. Strawson, G. (2006), ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13: 3–31. Whitehead, A. (1929), Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (New York: Macmillan). Wigner, E. (1962), ‘Remarks on the Mind–body Problem’, in I. Good (ed.), The Scientist Speculates (London: Heineman), 284–302. (p. 220)

Notes: (1) Non‐reductive physicalists deny that there is any explanation of mentality in purely physical terms, but do not deny that the mental is entirely determined by and constituted out of underlying physical structures. There are important issues about the stability of such a view, which teeters on the edge of explanatory reductionism on the one side and dualism on the other (see Kim 1998). (2) Save perhaps for eliminative materialism (see Churchland 1981 for a classic exposition). In fact, however, while eliminative materialism is willing to declare beliefs,

Page 15 of 16

Panpsychism desires, and other intentional mental states mere fictions of primitive proto‐theorizing, consciousness itself has never been seriously attacked (but see Dennett 1991: esp. ch. 12). (3) A similar argument was given by S. Pepper (1926), although Pepper seemed to allow for radical emergence if the emergent features were physically epiphenomenal. For a reply see Sellars and Meehl (1956). (4) Rosenberg argues further that we must accept a more radical revision of our metaphysical views than stems just from the intrinsic‐nature argument and revamp our conception of causality itself. (5) Russell put the point with characteristic bluntness: ‘[E]verything we know of [the world's] intrinsic character is derived from the mental side’ (1927: 402).

William Seager

William Seager: Professor of Philosophy, Department of Humanities (University of Toronto Scarborough) and Department of Philosophy (University of Toronto), 170 St. George Street, Toronto Ontario, M5R 2M8. Email: [email protected]

Page 16 of 16

Subjectivity

Oxford Handbooks Online Subjectivity   John Perry The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0013

Abstract and Keywords Subjectivity is to many philosophers what the frog is to many biologists: the object of fascination that first drew them to their discipline. The first part of this article discusses what we find there in our individual consciousness or subjectivity: experiences of various sorts, including thoughts and thoughts about thoughts and thoughts about other experiences. It also briefly considers what these things are doing there. The second part discusses whether Frank Jackson's ‘knowledge argument’ provides a good reason to doubt that all these things we find in our minds are events in and states of our brain. Keywords: subjectivity, individual consciousness, thoughts, experiences, Frank Jackson, mental state

Subjectivity (Philosophy) … Of or pertaining to the thinking subject: proceeding from or placed within the individual consciousness or perception, originating in the mind, belonging to the conscious life. (Shorter Oxford English Dictionary) is to many philosophers what the frog is to many biologists: the object of fascination that first drew them to their discipline. That we have experiences; that we can't say for sure that they reflect an external world; that we might be alone in the world; that our mind might be the plaything of an evil demon; that perhaps to be is to be perceived; that will and idea might exhaust reality; that even the self might be an illusion—to certain teenagers, who may prefer books to ponds and introspection to vivisection, these are thrilling thoughts. As the adult biologist, awash in dissertations about DNA, NSF proposals, and university committee meetings, needs to return to the pond for a few weeks each summer to rekindle love for the subject, so the philosopher needs to return periodically to his or her own subjectivity, accept it for what it is, or at least seems to be, enjoy it, explore it, swim in it, and think about it. If your Chair or your Dean asks what you are doing, say ‘phenomenology’. SUBJECTIVITY

Page 1 of 17

Subjectivity In the first part of this chapter I discuss what we find there in our individual consciousness or subjectivity: experiences of various sorts, including thoughts and thoughts about thoughts and thoughts about other experiences. I also briefly consider what these things are doing there. In the second part I discuss whether Frank Jackson's ‘knowledge argument’ provides a good reason to doubt that all these things we find in our minds are events in and states of our brain.

(p. 224)

12.1 What We Find in Our Minds

12.1.1 Experiences Locke calls everything we find in our minds ‘ideas’. Hume calls them all ‘perceptions’. Neither of these seems felicitous as a general term. I'll just stick with ‘experiences’, and use ‘perception’ with its ordinary meaning, as the recognition and interpretation of sensory stimuli, even when talking about Hume. Hume divides experiences into impressions on the one hand and thoughts and ideas on the other. Impressions include sensations and passions—what we now usually call ‘emotions’. Impressions come unbidden; we are passive; we have them but do not do them; they are not the products of thought and will. Ideas and thoughts are less lively and vivacious than impressions, and we often bring them to mind at will. It's easier to think about a roast‐beef sandwich than to see or taste one; to do the latter you have to order one or make it yourself. Once Hume gets to work, however, he finds things less simple than his dichotomy suggests. Impressions come intimately associated with ideas, based on previous experience; what we would ordinarily call a perception involves not just a passive component, but also the result of various activities on our part: we compare, we remember, we classify, we anticipate, we predict, all of this rolled up with the having of sensations. What we would ordinarily call seeing a chair involves not only the sensations caused by the colour and shape of the chair, but anticipations of visual sensations to be had by moving this way or that, of experiences we expect to have (being supported) and not have (falling) if we do try sit on it, and the like. Perceptions are sensations associated with ideas and thoughts. In Book II of his Treatise Hume also develops a theory of passions as combinations of impressions and thoughts. This all suggests that what we need is not so much two disjoint categories of experiences, but rather two dimensions, along which experiences differ, each dimension being more or less important in different cases. I'll call these the feel and the content of experiences. A third dimension is physical painfulness and pleasure. Intensely painful and intensely pleasant sensations are perhaps as close as we get to the limiting case: all feel, almost no content. But even these sensations have a bit of content: the sensations are taken as Page 2 of 17

Subjectivity ‘located’ in various parts of our body, and may give us information about what to do or not do with those parts to eliminate the pain or sustain the pleasure. By the same token, thoughts are not all content and no feel. There is something it is like to think a thought, although we don't think of this feel as definitive of the thought. Thoughts involve words, often unspoken, images, anticipations of other kinds of experiences, and inclinations to act in various ways, and are often intimately associated with emotions. (p. 225)

The most striking feature of a sensation, segregated, as best we can, from the anticipations and memories and attendant thoughts that flesh it out into a perception,1 is what it is like to have it, its feel, the aspect philosophers have called the quale, subjective character, phenomenal aspect, and raw feel (see Chalmers 1996; Nagel 1974; Block 2007; Feigl 1967). Having a sensation of a red fire hydrant is quite different from having a sensation of a green patch of grass, even if we bracket off the information we seem to be getting about hydrants and lawns. Having a sensation of green is quite different from having the sensation one has when one hears a high trumpet note; the pain of a toothache is different than the pain of a backache; such unpleasant sensations are quite different than pleasant ones, like tasting chocolate, or smelling a rose. Although we may be convinced that there is this aspect of raw feel in experiences, we are hardly able to categorize without employing the idea of of‐ness, where the far side of the of relation is not something subjective, but something that is outside the mind—a colour, a sound, a back, a tooth, a piece of candy, a rose, a fire hydrant, a lawn—or would be outside if it were real—a unicorn or my (imaginary) red Porsche. Right now I have a visual field full of shapes and colours, which I take to be a computer in front of me, a book to my side, a cup full of hot coffee, a table underneath these things, my own hands perched on the keyboard of my computer, often waiting for inspiration, occasionally typing, a window, trees, and rooftops outside the house, and a lot more. I am listening to Johnny Cash sing about poor drunken Ira Hayes, so the sounds that comprise his words, and the sounds from his guitar, take up a lot of my auditory space. There are also, now and then, the sounds the keys on the computer make as I tap them, the sounds made by the cats pursuing various sort of mischief, occasionally the ring of a telephone, occasionally a request from my wife Frenchie. I feel the computer keys at the end of my fingers, and the surface on which my hands rest. I occasionally take a sip of coffee, so, and have that peculiar taste. While having all of these experiences, I think. I think about what to write, about whether to respond to Frenchie immediately or take a few seconds to finish what I am doing, whether to go investigate the cat noises or ignore them, whether coffee is unhealthy like the doctors said five or six years ago or actually not bad at all like they seem to say these days, and a zillion other things. Thinking is often an active, purposeful activity. We intend to think about a certain subject matter: the weather, Calvin Coolidge, prime numbers, the commitments of the day, and then we manage to do it. But thoughts often come unbidden. While trying to remember

Page 3 of 17

Subjectivity the year of Calvin Coolidge's election, I find myself thinking about George Bush and Iraq. While trying to identify the first fifteen prime numbers in my (p. 226) mind, or follow the arguments of a student in my office, I find myself thinking about a roast‐beef sandwich. The most striking features of thoughts are their contents rather than their feels. We get at their contents by saying what things must be like to fit the thought, where the evaluative property and direction of fit are determined by what kind of thought it is.2 The content of the thought ‘It's sunny today’ is quite different from the content of the thought ‘Calvin Coolidge was a man of few words’. The direction of fit in the case of such doxastic or belief‐manifesting thoughts is mind to world, the evaluative properties are truth and falsity. With wishes, like ‘Would that I receive a big raise’, the dimension of success is being granted or not; the direction of fit is world to mind; if my wish is not granted, the world, or at least the Dean's office, is defective, not the thought. Thoughts are about things and their properties: days, weather conditions, presidents, loquaciousness, money, and such. The contents are conditions, involving these things—truth‐conditions in the case of doxastic thoughts, conditions of being granted in the case of wishes. But still it is like something to think, and it is like something to have thoughts simply occur to you: thoughts are experiences. A lot of thinking involves something like inner speech; something similar in feel to rehearsing what one is going to say, or anticipating saying it, or remembering saying it, or exhorting oneself. Indeed, people often lapse into talking to themselves when they are really into a piece of thinking. Thinking in English is different than thinking in German; it's a thrill for the language student when the first thought formulated in the new language spontaneously makes its appearance. And thinking is not limited to words; all sorts of ideas, including images corresponding to various types of sensations are also involved. The feel and content of experiences differ in their ontological status. The feel of an experience is an intrinsic quality of it. The sensation may be caused by an external object, and may be part of a contentful perception of that external thing. But the feel of the sensation is a fact about what is going on in my mind. A phrase like ‘the sensation of seeing red’ gets at the feel of the sensation in a roundabout way: it is (roughly) the type of visual sensation typically caused by seeing red things in favourable light. The content of experiences, of perceptions and thoughts, is at least not entirely intrinsic to them. If I see Condoleezza Rice and think ‘That woman is the Secretary of State’, then my thought is about Rice, and is true because she is the Secretary of State. If it is not Rice that I see, but Angela Davis, then my thought is about Angela Davis, and is false because she is not Secretary of State, at least as I write this paragraph. The truth‐value and truth‐conditions of my thought depend on whom my perception is of, and so are not intrinsic properties of it. The feel of the thought, however, seems intrinsic. I could have just those words running through my mind even if I didn't perceive anyone. I'll return to this issue below.

Page 4 of 17

Subjectivity

(p. 227)

12.1.2 Cognitive States

Subjectivity does not exhaust what we ordinarily think of as ‘the mind’ or ‘the mental’. Beliefs and desires are mental, but they are not experiences in the way that sensations and thoughts are.3 My beliefs and desires guide my thinking, and my thoughts and experiences in turn affect my beliefs and desires. Thoughts, like actions directed at the external world, manifest my beliefs and desires. If I believe that Sacramento is the capital of California, then when the question arises in my mind I will think ‘Sacramento is the capital of California’; if the question arises in conversation, that's what I'll say. The word ‘concept’, as I shall use it, stands for cognitive structures involved in my beliefs and desires and other cognitive states. Using ‘concept’ in this way, concepts are not the same as ideas, considered as the bits of thinking that make up our thoughts.4 Concepts, beliefs, and desires are not, like thoughts, transitory by nature; they are acquired at various times; they may last for years, or they may change after a few seconds. New experiences and new inferences lead to revisions in our beliefs; desires get changed by deliberation; sometimes they are satisfied and disappear; and we just forget things we once knew or at least believed or thought it was important to do or have. We then must distinguish between that in our minds that we experience, the parts of the stream of consciousness, and the beliefs and desires that are more like rocks and fallen trees below the surface of the stream that direct its flow. These we are not directly aware of but can, in at least a wide range of cases, easily determine, and often alter. Let me return now to the question of whether any of the intentional or semantic properties of beliefs and the thoughts to which they give rise are intrinsic. This question is somewhat vexed, as it is connected with Big Issues like anti‐individualism and narrow content, and I won't discuss it at great length here. But I will say a bit. There are two mistakes that are made in discussions on this topic I do want to mention. The first, common in discussions of anti‐individualism, is failing to distinguish between cognitive properties and cognitive states. In general, we distinguish between the properties systems have in virtue of the states of the system—the intrinsic properties of their parts and the relations the parts have to one another that are relevant to the way the system works—and the further properties that the system has in virtue of the way it is embedded into the wider world.5 An engine may run at 4800 rpm while in a car, connected to the transmission, driveshaft, and wheels, or unconnected, while being tested in the factory. In the former circumstance it will also have the property of moving the wheels at some number of rpm, depending on the state of the transmission. The formula we use to think about such things, which has proven too (p. 228) useful to be discarded by philosophers just when we get to truly interesting things like subjectivity, is that the states of a system plus its external relations yield its properties.

Page 5 of 17

Subjectivity There is no doubt that having the property of perceiving that Condoleezza Rice is reviewing the troops is not something I have simply on account of what is going on in my head, the states of my brain, and so too with believing that Condoleezza Rice did review the troops last week. Those properties require that what goes on in my head be related in certain ways to Condoleezza Rice, and these relationships require things of the external world, not just things inside my head. It does not follow from this that the state I am in, in virtue of which, together with the external situation I find myself in, I have those properties is not simply a matter of what goes on in my head. It seems, for example, that there might be a state such that when a person is in it, in a fairly wide range of circumstances, that person perceives that the person they see is reviewing the troops. Well, maybe this is too optimistic, for how about the fact that what Rice was reviewing were troops? We can retreat further, to the state one is in such that, in a wide variety of circumstances, one who is in that state perceives that the person they are seeing is examining in an authoritative manner the group of uniformed persons that person is looking at. Well, one could have further qualms. That is, one might have to work hard to squeeze the commitments about the external world out of the property, so that the intentional description that is left, stripped of these commitments, only constrains the internal properties of the state. But the avenue for getting fewer and fewer commitments is fairly clear. We start with some intentional characterization of a minded being, such as: Bush believes that Condoleezza Rice is reviewing the troops. and then we reformulate things in a way that makes the intentional contributions of internal and external factors clear, relative to some account of the structure of internal states, which for purposes of illustration can be rather clunky and naive:

Bush is in a belief state with the structure C(n, g), where C is a concept of the activity of reviewing, n is a notion of Condoleezza Rice and g is a notion of some troops, that is true only if the person n is of is performing the activity C is of upon the group g is of. and then we abstract over the specific external factors we can identify:

Bush has a belief b with the structure C(n, g), such that if there is an individual X, and activity A and a group G, and C is of A, n is of X, and g is of G, belief b is true if and only if X performs A upon g. The second mistake infected the once common and often quite worthwhile discussions of narrow content. This was the supposition that the content that we end up with, when we have completed this stripping enterprise, will be a proposition P such that the agent has the property believing P. The model was the transition from de re belief to a supposed underlying de dicto belief. This supposition is quite groundless. The whole idea of ‘intentionality’ is to describe what goes on inside of us in terms of what is outside of us; it is things outside of us that we by and large have beliefs about. But the conditions our stripping operation will leave us with will be existentially quantified conditions on things inside of us, our perceptions, concepts, notions, (p. 229) and what have you. Bush may believe that Condoleezza Rice is reviewing the troops because he is in some state C (n, g) that meets the conditions above. That does not mean Bush believes the proposition that there is a person X a relation R and a group G and my ideas C, n and g are of respectively Page 6 of 17

Subjectivity R, X, and G and X is R‐ing G. What he believes will be that Condoleezza Rice is reviewing the NATO troops. I doubt very much that Bush has many beliefs about his own concepts and notions. The narrow content we assign to what goes on inside our heads, as a part of an account of what we believe, perceive, know, conjecture, and the like, can play its role without itself being what we believe, perceive, conjecture, and the like (see Perry and Israel 1981).

12.1.3 The Epistemology of Subjectivity While writing some of the paragraphs above I was not only having experiences and thinking, I was aware of my experiences; I attended to them, thought about them, and indeed wrote about them. It seems to me that having experiences, and becoming attuned to the information they carry, is something I share with all sorts of animals. All of these animals we might ordinarily call ‘conscious’, during those periods when they haven't been knocked unconscious. But for this use of ‘conscious’ I'll use ‘sensate’. The way ‘conscious’ is used in the OED definition of ‘subjectivity’ quoted at the beginning of this paper is different. We are conscious of things. We use the term in this way quite broadly. I am conscious of the dangers posed by Bush's overspending, I am conscious of the racket made by the leaf‐blower across the street, and I am conscious of the sensations I have as I type. Not everything we are conscious of is subjective, but it is consciousness of the subjective that we now turn to. It seems clear that we not only have experiences and think thoughts, we can become aware of, focus our attention on, compare, classify, ponder, admire, detest, describe, and in all sorts of ways think about our experiences and thoughts. There is also the matter of remembering, imagining, and anticipating experiences, particularly sensations, perceptions, and emotions, which is a bit like thinking about them, but not quite. As I sit here typing, I begin to think about lunch, and the sandwich I can make from the fresh supply of roast beef from the deli. I anticipate eating and tasting it. Or maybe I just imagine doing so, for I know that when the time comes I'll opt for some healthier alternative. Remembering, imagining, and anticipating experiences is a very special way of thinking about them, which I suppose we share with animals that cannot think about their experiences in the more robust way that we can. So in order to be aware of my experiences I have to have them, but having them is not sufficient. Right now I am having an experience of seeing a computer. It is like something to have this experience. The experience plays a role in my life; it is involved in my perception of the computer, and my perception of it is involved in the interactions I am having with it: supporting it on my lap, typing on the keys, watching letters appear on the screen, and the like. None of this requires me to be aware of (p. 230) the experience; having the experience is part of my being aware of the computer. I am attuned to the fact that when I have this sort of experience, in relatively normal conditions, there is a computer on my lap, and I can make letters appear on the screen by typing the keys. I am Page 7 of 17

Subjectivity able, however, not only to have the experience but to attend to it, to form a concept of it, to apply concepts to it, and the like. It is a visual experience; it is neither pleasant nor unpleasant; I didn't directly pay money to have the experience, although I paid good money for the computer. I can also form a concept of the type of experience I am having, and of course I can classify the experience in various ways. It is an experience of a computer; of this particular computer; a visual experience; an experience of a square white region embedded in an off‐white region, with letters that form words on the white region and letters on keys in the off‐white region. When we attend to the experiences involved in perception, the path of least resistance is to classify them in terms of what they are of. There are two ways the phrase ‘of’ can be taken here, and often it is not necessary to mark the difference. I see my computer; my experience is of a computer; that is, a computer causes it. But it is also of a computer in that I see what I am seeing as a computer, and not, say, a mere computer façade or a television. I could mistake my television for a computer; then my experience would be of a television, in the first sense, but of a computer, in the second. To see the object I am looking at as a computer involves much more than mere sensation. I take various discontinuities in my visual field as corresponding to the edges of the screen, for example; I see it as three‐dimensional, which involves expectations of what would happen if I were to move my head a bit, or stand up and approach the computer, or reach out and touch it. I expect the pattern in my visual field to remain relatively unchanged as long as I keep my eyes open and stay still; because I see what I see as a computer, I don't expect it to suddenly walk away. I actually can see two computers, the laptop on which I am typing, and, in the distance, a desktop computer. The two experiences seem similar, but the similarity in the experiences mostly amounts to their being of the same sorts of things: computers with visible screens, keyboards, and the like. When we turn from perceptions whose importance is the information they carry about the external world to those whose dimension of painfulness and pleasure dominates our interest in them, we still have difficulty squeezing all of the intentionality out of our way of thinking of them. I have a slight pain in my right wrist. Locating the pain in this way is to describe it in terms of the information it gives me about the part of my body that is the source of the pain. I know the pain is in an important sense not located in my wrist but in my head. I could have a phantom pain like this, without even having a wrist, were the nerves between wrist and head properly stimulated. The pain is in my wrist in that it gives me information about my wrist, and it is my wrist I will move in order to deal with the pain.

12.1.4 What's it All About? Why do we have experiences? In particular, why are we sentient? Why are some of our brain states like something to be in? There are two questions here. Perhaps the (p. 231) first is what David Chalmers calls the ‘hard question’ of consciousness (1996). It is pretty Page 8 of 17

Subjectivity much the same as Heidegger's question, ‘Why is there something rather than nothing?’, at least on one interpretation of it. That is, the question is not why there is any universe at all, rather than nothing, but why there is experience at all, rather than a ‘dark’ universe. The only way I can imagine of answering this question is by identifying the physical characteristics that differentiate states it is like something to be in from those that it is not like something to be in, an enterprise that will doubtless lead to a more complex set of distinctions than we have adumbrated here, as scientists mine the interplay between the three ways we have of knowing of such things: examining brains, studying behaviour, and attending to the states in which we find ourselves. As this knowledge develops, the question why a given brain‐science‐identified state is like this i (using ‘thisi’ as an inner demonstrative for experiences and the types they exemplify) may have a clear answer, against a background of what it is like to be in other brain‐science‐identified states. At that point, when we can answer each such question against the background of answers to many others, there will not be, as far as I can see, any ‘explanatory gaps’ left; at least, none of the sort that ever get closed. Perhaps at some point there will be a moment of conceptual clarification, where the mysteries of the more general question no longer grip us. I hope so, for then philosophers may play a role in the Great Day when the answer to this secret is laid bare. The second question is this. Given that there are brain states it is like something to be in, experiences, what purpose does it serve to be in such brain states? What are they for? What is mother nature trying to do with them? In his Dialogues on Natural Religion Hume complains that an omnipotent, omniscient, and indulgent deity could have come up with something better than pain to motivate us to get out of dangerous situations. One can imagine a sort of permanent semi‐erotic pleasure that normally suffuses all parts of our body. An injury to the foot or a sprained elbow or a decayed tooth wouldn't cause the sorts of pain it actually does, but instead merely a diminution of pleasure in foot or elbow or tooth. But we're not here to complain. Working within the metaphor of a purposeful mother nature, this mother is clearly either not omnipotent or not omniscient or not indulgent. She makes do with what she has, to work her bizarre purpose, which is basically to get plants and animals to reproduce so that there will be plenty of nutritious stuff, decomposing, crawling and walking around for other plants and animals to absorb one way or another so they can last long enough to reproduce and get absorbed in turn. Given these purposes, and the fact that she has brain states it is like something to be in her repertoire, what can she do with them? What are experiences for? Behind Hume's complaint is the idea that our sensations give us information and motivate us to act in ways that makes sense given that information. Experiences that are dramatically painful or pleasant provide both motivation and information. When we step

Page 9 of 17

Subjectivity on a tack we are motivated to do something to bring the experience of pain to an end, and we know, innately or based on relatively little experience, what to do about it. (p. 232)

Less dramatic experiences, with no pain or pleasure intrinsic to them, provide more delicate kinds of information, that can be exploited through mechanisms built up through evolution, experience, accretions of culture, and the memories and thoughts of a particular person. So our experiences are there to give us information about our bodies and the broader environment, in order to enable us to act in ways that increase the probability of successful reproduction, and to give us motivation for so acting. The basic way we use the information that is made available to us is through habit or, more generally, attunement. As Hume points out, these matters are much too important for nature to leave mainly to understanding and reason. Attunement means basically that (i) being in some state S carries the information that we are in some situation E; (ii) being in S causes us to act in some way that makes sense, given that we are in E. If I step on something sharp, I move my foot. I may not have the concept of danger, or injury, or survival, or of pain, or of a foot, or of me. Still, moving the foot makes sense given that not moving it will cause injury. I am attuned to the regularity or constraint that stepping on sharp things causes injury. Most of our visual and auditory sensations aren't unpleasant or pleasant enough or informative enough on their own to motivate us to do much of anything. But we can learn. Pavlov's dog learned that the bell meant food; he became attuned to this constraint in his environment, and started to salivate when he heard the bell. My goats learn that when they hear the sound I make by pounding the side of an old five‐gallon paint bucket there will be some alfalfa and sweet cob for them to eat if they walk in the direction of the sound. Dogs and goats need to discriminate and have the capacity to learn new habits—to become attuned to new constraints. An information game is a pair of episodes in which a being gathers the information that P at some time, and some being, perhaps the same being, perhaps not, uses that information at some time, perhaps the same time, perhaps not, to do something that makes sense given the fact that P. If the beings and the times are the same, we have the ‘straight‐through’ information game. Given the pain in my foot, I move it. Given the bell, the dog salivates. Given the sound of stick on bucket, the goats start to move in the direction of the sound. We, and a number of other animals, have the ability to store information for later use. We detach some of the information from the perception that carries it, and reapply it later, when we recognize the same object. I call this ‘the detach and recognize’ information game. This is where beliefs and concepts come in. Perhaps a goat isn't hungry at the time it hears me pound on the bucket. It wanders off to do some other business for a while. Then it moves towards the place where the sound came from. The goat picked up the Page 10 of 17

Subjectivity information that there was food in such‐and‐such a direction at one time, and then later— but not so much later that the food wouldn't still be there—it does something that makes sense given that information. To do this, the goat has to reorient itself, to reidentify the direction from which it heard the sounds of food, probably by recognizing local landmarks. It (p. 233) won't suffice to be attuned to general patterns in its sensory field; it will have to have the conceptual apparatus to separate out trees and people and other salient objects, and reidentify them. The process of identification and reidentification requires a sort of concept I call a ‘buffer’. A buffer is a temporary structure in which we store information about a perceived object, prior to forming a full‐blooded detached notion, or identifying the object as something we already have a notion of. Such buffers, and the whole phenomenon of recognition, lead to problems for certain received doctrines about the structure of knowledge and belief. Suppose, for example, that I see Condoleezza Rice at a Stanford party. Because of the stress of her years in the Bush administration, and her diplomatic wardrobe, she doesn't look quite the same as she did while a professor at Stanford, and at first I don't recognize her. For a while I have two notions of Rice, my long‐standing notion, associated with such concepts as being brilliant, strong‐willed, and having left Stanford to join the Bush administration, and a temporary buffer, associated only with the concepts my perceptions deliver. What do I learn when I recognize her? It isn't hard to say how my doxastic states change. The two notions have to be of the same person, if my belief, ‘Oh, that person is Condoleezza Rice’, is to be true. But the change from before to after the recognition can't be captured by a proposition involving only Rice, without bringing in my buffer. It can't, that is, be captured by a proposition whose constituents are confined to the subject matter of my thoughts, the external objects my notions are of. To suppose that all knowledge can be so captured is what I call ‘the subject‐matter fallacy’. Such recognitional knowledge is fleeting, for our buffers are usually simply absorbed into the more permanent notions.6 It is this strategy, developed in many different ways, that has come to dominate human cognition. We each possess a rich set of concepts, or notions of individual things. We have two uses for the information associated with each of these notions. We use it to help us to recognize the objects of which we have notions, and we use it to help us do something that makes sense with those objects (or, more generally, something that makes sense given what those objects are like and their relation to us), once we have found them. So, for example, I have a notion of Michael Bratman that provides me with the ability to recognize him in favourable circumstances: when I can see him, when I hear his voice on the phone. But my notion also provides me with facts about him that are useful in interacting with him. For one thing, I know that his name is ‘Michael Bratman’, so I can address him with that name. I know he thinks a lot about the philosophy of action, so I can ask him questions about his work, as a way of being friendly, and as a way of learning about the topic.

Page 11 of 17

Subjectivity Communication is an extension of the detach and recognize information game. A large part of what we are interested in communicating—and this includes putting it (p. 234) in books to be read by others as well as conveying it in face‐to‐face conversation—is incremental information about objects; that is, information that is only useful, in guiding action, once we have recognized the object in question and gotten ourselves in a position where we can act on it, or at least do things whose results depend on its properties. It is this sort of information that our language is designed to convey. We deal with detached information, in print, and in our minds, when we think and reason about things we are not perceiving. Suppose, for example, that my goats have language and cellphones and somewhat more altruistic relations with one another than they actually do. One goat might call a friend, out of earshot of the signs of food, and tell him that there is food near tree X. This would be much simpler than providing the goat friend with all the information the latter needs to get to the food. The responsibility for reattaching the detached information is left to the goat friend; he can wander around until he sees tree X, then he can apply the incremental information, that X has food near it. It seems impossible to envisage the development of communication without a pretty rich structure of concepts and belief‐like states already in place. But, in turn, it seems impossible to understand thinking, of the sort that humans do, apart from abilities to conceptualize and symbolize information in the way required for communication. Our thinking, both theoretical and practical, is typically detached from the exact relationships to the objects thought about that will be necessary to act fruitfully on them. We deliberate, imagine, rehearse, and conjecture, all with detached notions of things and aided by the symbols of communication. And of course many concepts and thoughts are totally enmeshed with words, agreements, practices, and complex institutions made possible by language. As Norman Malcolm once remarked, the thought ‘I need to put the bottles out because the milkman comes tomorrow’ isn't one that arose in anyone's consciousness before there were milk bottles and milkmen (1970). Come to think of it, many younger readers may have no idea what milk bottles and milkmen are, or were. Being able to attend to our experiences, classify them, note whether we like them or not, think about their causes and how to avoid having them or increase the chances that we will have them, adds power to our deliberations. We can plan not only to bring about certain results in the external world, but also to bring about or avoid certain results in our own subjectivity. Whether this itself serves any of mother nature's purposes I rather doubt. It is certainly useful in subverting her plans. We invent ways to have the internal pleasures of the procreative act without procreating, for example, or ways to link the tastes we like to substances of no nutritional value. Most likely it is something she didn't plan on. Human thought, language, and culture have taken the detach and recognize information game and run amok. That, at any rate, is my picture of human science and culture, but I'll spare the reader details.7

Page 12 of 17

Subjectivity

(p. 235)

12.2 Could Experiences be Brain Events?

12.2.1 Mary In Frank Jackson's classic statement (1986) the ‘knowledge argument’ has one character and three steps. Mary is a brilliant woman who, for one reason or another, is raised in a room where she never sees colours, only black and white and, I suppose, shades of grey in between. Mary has new knowledge when she finally steps out of the black and white room and sees a red fire hydrant. But while in the black and white room she could well have known all the physical facts relevant to colour vision. Conclusion: her new knowledge is of a non‐physical fact. We need to look closely at Mary. Mary emerges from the black and white room, sees a fire hydrant, and has her first colour experience, call it E, of the type qualeRED. She thinks: ‘Thisi experience is the type I have when I see, in these conditions, the colour of that fire hydrant’. She has a certain relation to the experience: she has it. A less inquisitive person might have left it at that, but she also attends to the experience. E is the referent of her thought ‘thati experience’ because of the relations it has to her: it is the one she is having and attending to. She is having an experience of the colour of the grass beside the fire hydrant too, but ‘thisi experience’ doesn't refer to that experience, because it is not the one to which she attends. Mary forms a concept of the type of colour experience E exemplifies. She notes that E is similar to the colour experience she has of the fire engine parked nearby, and not similar to the colour experience she is having of the grass next to the fire hydrant. She can introduce a term, ‘quale?’ and ask: Is quale? = qualeRED? Mary's concept quale? seems like a good candidate for a phenomenal concept, for it is tied to her current experiences of the fire engine and the fire hydrant; it is the type of colour experience of which those two colour experiences are instances. Many philosophers put great weight on such phenomenal concepts, and they are useful in considering the fine structure of Mary's cognitive states at the moment of liberation. But such concepts are by their nature temporary, like the perceptual buffers involved in recognizing external objects.

Since quale? is qualeRED, Mary is thinking about the same type of experience in two different ways when she uses the two terms in thought or language. The referential relations are quite different; she is related to the quale in two quite different ways. On the one hand, it is the quale that two of her current experiences exemplify. On the other, it is the quale that her textbooks referred to, and identified as the type of experience normal people have in favourable light when they see red objects. Her conceptions of the two are different. She believes that qualeRED is the one people (p. 236) with normal vision have when they see red things in favourable light, and she also believes—since my Page 13 of 17

Subjectivity version of Mary is a physicalist—that qualeRED is a type of brain state: B52 to be precise; that to experience qualeRED is to be in brain state B52. She believes quale? is the type of two of her present colour experiences, and is the quale caused in her in her present conditions by the colours of the surfaces of the fire hydrant and the fire engine. She also believes that if her vision is normal, and the present lighting is favourable, and this fire hydrant is, as most of them are, painted red, then quale? is qualeRED and having qualeRED is being in B52. Once she is confident that her vision is normal and conditions are favourable and no one has repainted the local fire hydrants and fire engines to fool her, she will believe that quale? = qualeRED. Once she draws this inference, she knows something new about qualeRED, that she didn't know in the black and white room; namely, that it is the type of colour experience exemplified by her current experiences of the colours of the fire hydrant and the fire engine. This is a relational fact about particular experiences that hadn't occurred when she was in the black and white room; it is not knowledge of some new fundamental property of qualeRED that was of necessity missed by her physicalist texts. Perhaps Mary is so brilliant that she was able to predict that upon leaving the black and white room she would see a fire hydrant, grass, and a fire engine, all with their normal colours, in favourable light. She can introduce terms for the predicted experiences, say EH and EE. So she had a way of referring to and thinking about the experiences she is now having and their common quale, qualeRED, before having them. But the referential relations, in virtue of which she was able to refer to these things and talk about them, are quite different than the referential relations that enable her to think and talk about them as ‘thisi colour experience’ (attending to the hydrant), ‘thisi colour experience’ (attending to the engine), and ‘quale?’. She can predict, while in the black and white room, that she will have a phenomenal concept, but she cannot yet think of it as one she is having. She can ask herself whether thisi colour experience is EH, thisi colour experience is EE, and whether quale? is the one she predicted, qualeRED. She can figure out that they are. So she still has new knowledge that she didn't have before. Does anything in all of this give Mary a reason to abandon her physicalist view, that qualeRED is B52? I cannot see that it does. If her physicalist views are correct, and she is wearing a new‐fangled autocerebroscope, that produces visual images of the goings‐on in her brain as she had her experiences, she would have to grant that she was seeing the very experiences she was having. She might think, ‘Goodness, seeing an experience of qualeRED through an autocerebroscope (which I've never done before) is certainly nothing like having an experience of type qualeRED (which I've never had before). But then, why should it be?’.

12.2.2 Locating Mary's Knowledge

Page 14 of 17

Subjectivity Variations on the Mary story have been proposed, in order to produce the insights that will lead those of us unconvinced by the original story to dualism. But, actually, most of the more interesting and dramatic aspects of the various Mary stories (p. 237) seem irrelevant. The basic point is well made by Feigl's original autocerebroscope fantasy. Here is a slight variation on it that may prove helpful. Suppose Mary is never imprisoned and has experienced a normal range of colours by the time she makes it to graduate school to work on colour vision and brain states. She has good colour vision, good colour memory, and a good command of the standard names of dozens of colours and shades. Then she learns as much as you please about the various brain states involved in colour vision. Suppose she has clearly before her mind what it's like to experience six colours: red, yellow, blue, orange, brown, and mauve. And she has, on her computer, complete physical descriptions of the six brain states that correspond to the state one is in when one perceives those colours. This is a sophisticated hyper‐linked set‐up, so she can zoom in on pictures, x‐rays, sonograms, or whatever else you want. She can do in a virtual way what Leibniz imagined doing; she can enlarge the relevant parts of the brain and walk in and look around them. So far so good. However, the final interface between this sophisticated program and natural language, the identification of the scientifically described brain states in terms of ordinary colour words, is not in Mary's native Australian but in Cantonese, which she doesn't know. Now, can she match up the colours, or, more precisely, the quale that she associates with seeing the colours, with the physical states that she is in when she perceives those colours? I can't see how she could. When her Cantonese room‐mate returns home, and deciphers the names, Mary will learn something. Here is the situation as I see it. Let's take mauve as our example. Mary has a memory of seeing mauve, she knows what it is like to see mauve; and, if you like, she can generate an actual experience of seeing mauve by pulling her mauve scarf from the drawer. So she has a concept, as phenomenal a concept as could be wished for, of the state one is in when one sees mauve. And she has a concept of the brain state people are in when they see mauve things in ordinary conditions, whose scientific name is BSμ. Between her and her computer program the whole of brain science is at her fingertips; she can look at actual pictures of BSμ; she can look at helpful diagrams of it; push a button and the chemical composition of the various stuff involved in such states will pop up annoyingly; and so forth. These two concepts are both concepts of the same physical state, according to the physicalist; and, in addition, if she got her scarf from the drawer it is the state she is in. Does this mean that the physicalist should expect her to figure out, before her room‐ mate comes home to decipher the Cantonese, that the two concepts are concepts of the same state? There is no reason the physicalist should suppose this. What magic would drive a mental identity sign between two such different concepts as these, even for someone as brilliant as we suppose Mary to be? Neither concept is defined in terms of the other; neither is introduced in terms of the other; neither makes reference to the other; they have no common parts. At this point the knowledge argument says: but then, what does she learn when her room‐mate comes home? But the answer is clear. It's just the difference Page 15 of 17

Subjectivity between having two concepts that are, in fact, of the same thing, and two concepts that are required by that internal identity sign to be of the same thing. She learns that the type of experience she is having, and so the type of experience her phenomenal concept is of, is the type of experience that her other, (p. 238) brain‐science‐based concept is of; namely, the mauve quale. The contents of her doxastic states change, in that the truth of her total doxastic state, abstracted from the referential relations of her concepts, requires that the two concepts are concepts of the same type of experience; that is, BSμ,; that is, the experience one has when one sees mauve. That is how her beliefs change, and how her knowledge changes.

References Bach, K. (1981), ‘An Analysis of Self‐deception’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 41: 351–70. Block, N. (2007), ‘Max Black's Objection to Mind‐Body Identity, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 249–306. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Feigl, H. (1967), The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’: The Essay and a Postscript (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press). Hall, L. (1993), ‘Individualism, Mental Content and Cognitive Science’, Ph.D. diss. (Stanford University). Jackson, F. (1986), ‘What Mary Didn't Know’, Journal of Philosophy, 85: 291–5. Malcolm, N. (1970), ‘Scientific Materialism and the Identity Theory’, in C. V. Borst (ed.), The Mind/Brain Identity Theory (New York: Macmillan), 171–80. Nagel, T. (1974), ‘What is it Like to Be a Bat?’, Philosophical Review, 83: 435–50. Perry, J. (2001), Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2002), Identity, Personal Identity, and the Self (Indianapolis, lnd.: Hackett). —— (2003), ‘The Subject Matter Fallacy’, Journal of Applied Logic, 1: 93–105. Perry, J., and Israel, D. (1981), ‘Fodor and Psychological Explanations’, in B. Loewer and G. Rey (eds.), Meaning in Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 165–80; repr. in Perry, The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays, expanded edn. (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI, 2000), 301–22.

Page 16 of 17

Subjectivity Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Notes: (1) I'll often ignore the ‘success’ or ‘veridicality’ or ‘factive’ implications of words like ‘perception’, and ‘information’. This seems fair in an essay about subjectivity; by ‘perception’ I mean ‘perception or would‐be perception’. (2) For direction of fit see John Searle (1983). (3) This is a point I did not adequately grasp when I wrote Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness (see Bach 1981). (4) This is a departure from how I have used these terms in the past. (5) For a helpful discussion see Hall (1993). (6) For more on the subject‐matter fallacy see Perry (2001) and Perry (2003). (7) For more on the topics of this section see the last part of Perry (2002).

John Perry

John Perry is a professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside and Henry Waldgrave Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305–2155. USA. Email: [email protected]; [email protected]

Page 17 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness

Oxford Handbooks Online Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness   David M. Rosenthal The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0014

Abstract and Keywords There are several phenomena that constitute what we call consciousness, each of which gives rise to special problems and puzzles. One is the condition people and other creatures are in when they are conscious, as against when they are, for example, asleep, knocked out, or anaesthetized. And there is the related question about what distinguishes people and other creatures that can be conscious in that way from things that can not, such as stones and trees. We may call these questions the problem of creature consciousness. There is also a question about what it is for a person or other creature to be conscious of something. We may call this phenomenon transitive consciousness. Keywords: theories of consciousness, creature consciousness, creatures, transitive consciousness, inner sense, higher-order thoughts

THERE

are several phenomena we call consciousness, each of which gives rise to special

problems and puzzles. One is the condition people and other creatures are in when they are conscious, as against when they are, for example, asleep, knocked out, or anaesthetized. And there is the related question about what distinguishes people and other creatures that can be conscious in that way from things that can not, such as stones and trees. We may call these questions the problem of creature consciousness. There is also a question about what it is for a person or other creature to be conscious of something. We may call this phenomenon transitive consciousness. One is conscious of something when one sees or hears that thing, or senses or perceives it in some other way. Having a thought about something also sometimes suffices for one to be conscious of that thing, but not always. Sometimes our thoughts are not about a thing as being present to us, as with thoughts of Julius Caesar, the number 17, or the planet Saturn, and we are not in these cases conscious of those things. But one is conscious of something when one has a thought about it as being present to one, even when one does not also sense or perceive

Page 1 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness that thing. It is likely that an analogy with sensing leads us to regard this as being conscious of something, since sensing is arguably the more basic way of being conscious of things and one always senses things as being present to one. A third type of consciousness is a property of mental states themselves, independently of the kind of state and how it represents things. The thoughts, perceptions, and feelings we have in everyday life are often conscious, but not always. We sometimes (p. 240) sense things subliminally, and sometimes our thoughts and desires occur outside our stream of consciousness. Arguably the most pressing and challenging problem about consciousness is to explain what the difference is between mental states that are conscious and those that are not. We may call this the problem of state consciousness. It is this question that higher‐order theories of consciousness address.

13.1 Higher‐order Theory and the Transitivity Principle Descartes, Locke, and their contemporaries never use ‘conscious’ as a one‐place predicate applied to mental states. Locke does speak of the totality of an individual's conscious states as a consciousness, and he maintains that personal identity consists in the identity of such a consciousness (Locke 1700/1975: II. xxvii. 19). But he does not describe the thoughts, feelings, or perceptions themselves as conscious. What these authors do urge is that whenever these states occur in somebody, that individual is conscious of them. Descartes famously adds that this consciousness is unmediated; one is immediately conscious of all one's thoughts whenever they occur (Descartes 1964–1975: vii. 246). It is not until the latter part of the nineteenth century that theorists come to recognize that some mental states do occur of which we are wholly unaware. And, because of the resulting need to mark the difference between those mental states and those we are conscious of, the one‐place predicate ‘conscious’ comes then to be increasingly applied to mental states themselves. When we now describe states as conscious, we are presumably saying just what Descartes and Locke had in mind in saying that one is immediately conscious of a state; indeed, we often paraphrase those writers using the phrase ‘conscious state’. This suggests a first step in explaining state consciousness; a state is conscious if one is conscious of that state in some suitable way. I shall call this the transitivity principle (TP), since it explains state consciousness in terms of transitive consciousness.TP receives support from noting that no state is conscious if one is in no way whatever conscious of being in that state. We can understand the various higher‐order theories as all holding TP, but as differing in how we are conscious of our conscious states.

Page 2 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness It is sometimes urged that TP is circular, since it appeals to consciousness in explaining consciousness. One is conscious of something by sensing or perceiving that thing or by having a thought about that thing as being present. But since those states need not themselves be conscious, there is no circularity in explaining state consciousness by appeal to those states. Only if sensations, perceptions, and thoughts were all conscious would TP be circular. One might insist that when one is conscious of something, the state in virtue of which one is conscious of it must itself be a conscious state. But that is not so. Subliminally perceiving something makes one conscious of that thing, though not in the way we are conscious of it when we sense it consciously. We sometimes mark this (p. 241) distinction by saying that in subliminally perceiving something one is conscious, or aware,1 of that thing, but not consciously aware of it. Only if subliminally perceiving something makes us conscious of it can we explain the effect subliminal perception has on our behaviour and on the rest of our mental lives. Fred Dretske has argued against TP, urging that a state's being conscious consists not in one's being conscious of it, but in one's being in a state in virtue of which one is conscious of something else (Dretske 1993; sect. 4). But this view makes problematic the distinction between mental states that are conscious and those that are not.

13.2 Inner Sense As already noted, sensing is arguably the most basic way we are conscious of things. So it is natural to understand TP in terms of sensing. On this construal, a mental state is conscious if one is conscious of the state by sensing it. This type of higher‐order theory is doubtless the most widespread view about what it is for mental states to be conscious; it is usually traced to Locke, who very likely adapted it from Aristotle.2 D. M. Armstrong and William G. Lycan are the best known contemporary proponents of the inner‐sense view (Armstrong 1981; Lycan 1996, 2004). Both hold TP, and explain how we are conscious of conscious states by positing an inner monitoring mechanism that tracks many of the mental states we are in. This appeal to monitoring allows us, they urge, to explain the function state consciousness has in our overall psychological economy; monitoring enhances our ability to think rationally, to make plans, and to coordinate our actions. As Lycan puts it, such monitoring has ‘the job of relaying and/or coordinating information about ongoing psychological events and processes’ (2004: 100). There are, however, difficulties in understanding TP this way. For one thing, sensing and perceiving always involve some mental quality. States of seeing or hearing things, for example, always exhibit some visual or auditory qualitative property; otherwise, the resulting awareness of those things would be indistinguishable from simply having a thought that those things are present to one. But the only mental qualities that occur Page 3 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness when we are conscious of our conscious mental states are qualities that belong to the states we are conscious of; the higher‐order consciousness of those states exhibits no mental qualities of its own. So that higher‐order consciousness cannot be a matter of sensing or perceiving the first‐order states. When no mental qualities occur in being conscious of something, consciousness is a matter of one's having a thought about that thing. And since no mental qualities (p. 242) do occur in the higher‐order awareness of our mental states, it must be that we are conscious of those states not by any inner sense, but by having thoughts about them. Lycan rejects this conclusion, arguing that though such higher‐order consciousness has no mental qualities, it nonetheless resembles perceiving more closely than it does thinking (2004: sect. 6). But there is reason to doubt this. Lycan urges that the monitoring that results in some of our mental states’ being conscious ‘is the functioning of internal attention mechanisms directed upon lower‐order psychological states and events’ (2004: 99). And he holds that these attentional mechanisms operate in a quasi‐ perceptual way. Just as we have voluntary control over what we perceive, for example, so we have considerable voluntary control over which of our mental states are conscious. But it is unclear that we do have much voluntary control over which of our mental states are conscious. And even if we do, our higher‐order awareness will not on that account resemble perceiving more than thinking, since we also have considerable voluntary control over our thoughts. Lycan urges several other points in support of higher‐order perceiving. He argues that higher‐order perceiving better explains the monitoring function of consciousness than higher‐order thoughts can. But thoughts could monitor first‐order psychological states equally well, and the absence of any known inner sense organ suggests that such monitoring very likely occurs that way. Lycan urges that a perceptual model fits better with the way we focus attentively on some conscious states; but we focus attentively on things in thought no less than in perception. Lycan holds that the reliability of our higher‐ order awareness of mental states suggests a perceptual model. But the general accuracy of that higher‐order awareness itself needs explaining, and whatever factors are responsible for it might figure just as well in a higher‐order‐thought model.3 Many of Lycan's reasons for holding that our higher‐order awareness is more like perceiving than thinking depend on his seeing that higher‐order consciousness as a kind of monitoring. But there is reason to question that monitoring model. Not all our mental states are conscious, nor even all those which matter in some significant way to our psychological functioning. If our higher‐order awareness is due to some perception‐like monitoring mechanism, why does it miss so many significant states? Our higher‐order awareness of our mental states is often affected by our interests, desires, and fears in ways that resist a model based on perceptual monitoring. Dental patients are sometimes conscious of themselves as being in pain even though the relevant

Page 4 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness nerve is anaesthetized or even dead. The usual explanation of this phenomenon is that fear and the sensation of the drill's vibration lead patients to be conscious of themselves as being in pain; they are inaccurately conscious of the fear and the sensation of vibration as pain. This explanation of the phenomenon, known clinically as dental fear, is confirmed when giving patients the explanation leads to their no longer being conscious of (p. 243) themselves as being in pain when drilling resumes. Still, they strikingly remember the earlier experience as pain, suggesting that what matters to what the experience is like for one is simply how one is conscious of it. Less dramatically, robust experimental results in social psychology show that people confabulate conscious beliefs and desires that fit in with the way they want to see situations (see Nisbett and Wilson 1977; White 1988). These findings fit at least as well with an appeal to thoughts in understanding our higher‐ order awareness as with an appeal to perceiving. The perceptual model has actually led to theoretically problematic results. Thus, Hume's well‐known problem about the self rests on his assumption that any awareness of the self would be perceptual, since we never perceive the self, as against the states it is in (Hume 1739–1740/1978: app. p. 634). And the perceptual model has led some to reject TP altogether, on the ground that we do not perceive our mental states (e.g. Searle 1992: 96– 7). As noted earlier, proponents of inner sense urge that a quasi‐perceptual monitoring model explains what function consciousness has in one's psychological life. And the appeal to such a monitoring mechanism might help explain why some states come to be conscious, and why we are typically conscious of those states in reasonably accurate ways. Also, we are often conscious of our perceptual states in respect of exquisitely fine‐ grained qualitative differences among them; for example, in respect of very slightly variations in shades of colour or qualities of sound. Since we have no concepts that correspond to all these fine‐grained qualitative variations, perhaps only perceiving could explain how we are conscious of all those subtle qualitative variations. If TP is not implemented by some quasi‐perceptual monitoring, we must handle these issues some other way.

13.3 Higher‐order Thoughts Since we are conscious of things by perceiving them or by having a thought about them as being present, if our higher‐order awareness about our conscious states is not perceptual, it must be due to our having such thoughts about those states. Those thoughts will each be to the effect that one is in some particular state.

Page 5 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness We are seldom conscious of ourselves as having such higher‐order thoughts (HOTs), but that is to be expected. HOTs are themselves mental states, and no HOT is conscious unless one has a third‐order thought about it. And we can safely assume that this seldom happens. There is good independent reason to posit such HOTs.4 One reason rests on the main way of determining whether a mental state is conscious in the case of humans, which appeals to whether one can report being in the state. People are in many (p. 244) mental states that manifest themselves only in non‐verbal behaviour, but non‐verbal behaviour seldom if ever reveals whether a state is conscious. If an individual is able to report being in some state, however, that state is conscious. This reportability test both underlies our common‐sense determinations of whether mental states are conscious and is also widely used in experimental psychology (see e.g. Marcel 1983a, 1983b). The reason is straightforward. Verbal reports of mental states express an individual's consciousness of those states; so, by TP, they reliably show that they are conscious states. But every sincere speech act expresses an intentional state with the same content as the speech act. So a report that one is in some mental state always expresses a corresponding thought that one is in that state. Verbally expressing one's consciousness of a mental state is just expressing one's thought about that state.5 This argument relies on a connection between consciousness and speech; because reporting one's own mental states expresses one's consciousness of those states, reportability is a reliable indicator that a state is conscious. This does not mean that mental states are never conscious in human infants and non‐human animals, which lack language and so cannot report being in mental states. We can appeal to the coincidence of consciousness with reportability to fix cases of conscious states in creatures that can report their mental states, and then determine what is essential to the cases thus fixed. On the foregoing argument, what is essential to these cases is that the mental state in question is accompanied by a HOT that one is in that state. Since there is ample empirical evidence that human infants and many if not all mammals have the ability to think, it is open to find out whether they have at least some HOTs of the requisite kind.6 Other features of the connection between consciousness and speech also point toward HOTs.7 But there are other reasons to posit HOTs as well. When we consciously see something, we can be conscious of our visual experience in more or less fine‐grained ways. One may be conscious of one's experience of red, for example, as a relatively generic experience of red or as an experience of a highly specific shade. Sometimes this variability is a function of perceptual conditions, but not always; attention to one's experience may make one conscious of that experience in more detailed and fine‐ grained ways. HOTs offer a credible explanation of this variability in how we are conscious of our qualitative experiences. The way we are conscious of a (p. 245) Page 6 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness qualitative state, on the HOT hypothesis, is a matter of how the accompanying HOT conceptualizes that state's mental properties. The way we are conscious of our qualitative experiences varies with the fineness of grain with which our HOTs represent those experiences. A vivid example is the way learning new words for qualitative properties sometimes results in one's experiences coming to be conscious in respect of those very qualities. When one is inexperienced in tasting wines, for example, the tastes that result from different wines may be indistinguishable; similarly with the auditory experiences of distinct musical instruments to one unfamiliar with those sounds. Simple repetition of the relevant experiences often is not enough to learn to distinguish them. But often learning words for the different qualitative experiences helps. How can that be? Coming to have command of new words for experiences means coming to have command of concepts for those experiences. But that can help only if those concepts figure in the way we are conscious of our qualitative experiences, which can happen only by way of intentional states about those experiences. The effect that learning new words for qualitative states sometimes has on the way we are conscious of those states is evidence that we are conscious of those states in virtue of intentional states in which those concepts figure, that is, by way of HOTs.

13.4 Difficulties for HOT Theories On the HOT hypothesis, qualitative states, such as perceptions, emotions, and bodily sensations, are conscious in virtue of being accompanied by suitable HOTs. Qualitative states that are not so accompanied simply are not conscious. Indeed, given TP, a qualitative state's being conscious consists in one's being conscious of being in that state; so qualitative states of which one is not conscious will themselves not be conscious. Some theorists, however, deny that a state can be qualitative, strictly speaking, and yet not be conscious. On their view, there would be nothing to a state's having qualitative character at all if that state is not conscious. But being conscious and having qualitative character are distinct properties. Conscious qualitative states differ in qualitative character; one may have the mental quality red and another the mental quality blue. So it may be that states can resemble and differ from one another in just the ways that conscious visual sensations of red and blue resemble and differ, but without being conscious. Robust experimental results, moreover, show that states that are not conscious can nonetheless vary in their effects in ways characteristic of conscious states with different mental qualities. Such priming effects make it reasonable to conclude that non‐ conscious states resemble and differ in just the ways that conscious qualitative states do, but without being conscious (see e.g. Marcel 1983a). (p. 246)

Page 7 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness It is sometimes thought that we can describe mental qualities only in respect of the way we are conscious of them.8 If that were so, there would be nothing to a state's having mental qualities apart from that state's being conscious. But we can describe mental qualities independently of their being conscious. We can understand a state's having the mental quality red, for example, in terms of that state's resembling and differing from other mental qualities of colour in just the ways that perceptible red resembles and differs from other perceptible physical colours (see e.g. Sellars 1963: chs. 2, 5; Shoemaker 1975; Rosenthal 2005: chs. 5–7). And we can fix these similarity relations among perceptible physical colours by reference to which physical colours we can perceptually discriminate among, whether or not the relevant perceptions are conscious (see e.g. Rosenthal 2005: ch. 7). The monitoring model that underlies inner‐sense theories promised help in understanding the function of consciousness, on the assumption that monitoring one's thought processes enhances rationality and the coordinating of desires. But it is unclear that this assumption, however inviting, is correct. Occasionally we do consciously note that our plans conflict or that our thinking is unsound. And we may then consciously seek to correct such plans and thinking. But such rationality results mainly from the causal connections that thoughts and desires have with one another, in virtue of their intentional contents. And since thoughts and desires have intentional content independently of their being conscious, their rationality is itself largely independent of their being conscious. Indeed, there is experimental evidence that we come to be conscious of our decisions only after those decisions have been formed (see Libet 1985; Haggard 1999); so consciousness cannot play a role in determining what we decide even when our decisions are conscious. Plainly we do not have words for all the subtle variations in qualitative character that occur consciously in us. So it is unlikely that we have concepts for them. This presents a challenge for the HOT hypothesis, and an apparent advantage of inner sense. If our concepts cannot capture all the conscious differences among our qualitative states, neither can our thoughts. Higher‐order sensations, however, would face no such difficulty, since their qualitative differences could be as fine‐grained as those of our first‐order qualitative states. But we need not have individual concepts for each mental quality to capture all their qualitative differences conceptually. We routinely use comparative terms to describe colours that differ only slightly from one another: we say that one is brighter than the other or has more blue in it or is darker. So it may well be that we are conscious of subtle differences among the corresponding mental qualities partly in those terms. It does not seem, of course, as though we are conscious of mental qualities even partly in comparative terms. But, since the relevant HOTs would seldom be conscious, we have little reason to trust our pretheoretic intuitions about how HOTs would represent the subtle differences among conscious mental qualities.

Page 8 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness

13.5 Variant HOT Theories (I): Dispositional Higher‐order Thoughts (p. 247)

Any theory of consciousness must do justice to what it's like for one to be in conscious states. And what it's like for one to have a conscious thought, perception, or feeling is that one is in one mental state, not two. This raises a challenge for the HOT model, on which being in a conscious state involves two states, not one; one has the thought, perception, or feeling, and in addition a HOT in virtue of which one is conscious of being in the state that's conscious. It may also seem that distinct HOTs in effect repeat the states they are about, and so are psychologically superfluous, and even that having HOTs in addition to their targets may tax or exceed our cortical capacity. These considerations have led Peter Carruthers to adopt a variant HOT theory, on which a state is conscious if a HOT is disposed to occur, even if the HOT does not actually occur (see Carruthers 1996, 2000, 2004). A dispositional theory may seem appealing also because a state's being conscious coincides with its being reportable and its being introspectible, and these are dispositional properties. We do not introspect or make reports about all our conscious states, but it seems that we always have some disposition to do so. Introspection occurs when we are conscious of a state in a deliberately focused, attentive way that goes beyond the way we are ordinarily conscious of our mental states. This suggests another consideration in support of a dispositional theory. When one introspects a red sensation, for example, one has a HOT about that sensation. When that sensation is not conscious, by contrast, there is presumably no HOT about it. But ordinary, non‐ introspective consciousness plainly involves something intermediate between a state's not being conscious at all and one's introspecting it. And it may seem that being disposed to have a HOT is the only thing intermediate between having it and not having it. But this overlooks a possibility. When one introspects a state, one has a conscious HOT about that state; so it is open to argue that what happens in the intermediate case of ordinary, non‐introspective consciousness is that one has a HOT about the state, but that HOT is not itself a conscious state. Introspection is the special case in which one's HOTs are conscious thoughts. Nor do the reportability and introspectibility of conscious states support a dispositional theory. It often happens that something's having an occurrent, non‐dispositional trait results in its also having various dispositional traits, as when occurrent chemical structure results in something's being soluble. Without knowing how mental states are cortically subserved, moreover, it is idle to urge that we lack cortical capacity for HOTs; indeed, it is likely that we have cortical capacity to spare. Nor do HOTs repeat the mental properties of their targets; rather, they Page 9 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness represent those states as having those mental properties. So occurrent HOTs are not psychologically superfluous. Most important, a dispositional theory cannot do (p. 248) justice to TP, since being disposed to have a thought about something does not make one conscious of that thing. When a state is conscious, we are seldom conscious of ourselves as being in two states. But that is because the higher‐order state, in virtue of which we are conscious of the target, is typically not itself a conscious state. A theory of consciousness must do justice to what it's like for one to be in conscious states, but the occurrent HOTs that the HOT model posits are rarely themselves conscious states.

13.6 Variant HOT Theories (II): Intrinsic Higher‐order Content A dispositional theory will not preserve TP, since merely being disposed to have a HOT does not make one conscious of the state that HOT would be about. Carruthers has sought to meet this difficulty by adopting a theory of intentional content on which a state's content is in part a matter of what that state is disposed to cause. And he argues that, on such a theory, states that dispose one to have a HOT themselves have higher‐ order content in virtue of which we are conscious of them. On this theory of content, simply by being disposed to cause a HOT, a state has higher‐order content that implements TP (Carruthers 2000: ch. 9). Whatever the merits of this controversial theory of content, it arguably is not desirable to hold a theory of consciousness hostage to any such theory. But, that aside, the resulting theory is no longer dispositional, since it ascribes occurrent higher‐order content to each conscious state. The only dispositional aspect of the theory is that it explains this occurrent higher‐order content by positing a disposition the relevant state has to cause a HOT. Still, the revised theory resembles a purely dispositional theory in positing no occurrent state distinct from the state we are conscious of. So it conforms in that way with the phenomenological appearances, on which a state's being conscious involves only one state, and not two. The higher‐order content that implements TP is intrinsic to the conscious state itself. Carruthers arrives at this intrinsic higher‐order‐content theory by modifying his dispositional HOT theory. But, apart from such reasoning, some theorists have held that the higher‐order content that implements TP should be seen as intrinsic to the conscious state, and not as belonging to a distinct higher‐order state (Brentano 1874/1973: II. ii; Gennaro 1996, 2005; Kriegel 2003).

Page 10 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness One reason to see such higher‐order content as intrinsic to the state in question is to avoid the problem of what to say about HOTs that occur in the absence of any suitable target. Just as mental states can occur without HOTs, so distinct HOTs can in principle occur without suitable targets, and it may seem unclear what it would be like for one in such a case. If higher‐order content is intrinsic to the target, this difficulty cannot arise. (p. 249)

But a problem also seems to arise when there is a target, but the higher‐order content misrepresents its mental properties. Would what it's like for one in such a case match the higher‐order content or the target it misdescribes?9 Some theorists have urged that even such misrepresentation cannot occur if the higher‐order content is intrinsic (Natsoulas 1999; Gennaro 2004). But it is unclear why a state's higher‐order content cannot misrepresent that state's other mental properties. In any case, TP itself resolves the problem without positing that the higher‐order content is intrinsic. On TP, a state is conscious if one is conscious of that state; so the mental properties in respect of which a state is conscious will be those one is conscious of it as having. If one has a sensation of red and a distinct HOT that one has a sensation of green, the sensation of red may nonetheless be detectable by various priming effects. But what it will be like for one is that one has a sensation of green. Similarly if one has that HOT with no relevant sensation at all. Mental qualities can be individuated either by reference to the way we are conscious of them or, as urged in Section 13.4, by way of some tie they have with perceptible physical properties. Those, like Joseph Levine (2001), who take the first route, find problematic the possibility of divergence between qualitative states and the way we are conscious of them. But they generally regard it as at least conceivable that undetectable quality inversion, which severs the tie between mental qualities and perceptible properties, can occur. Individuating mental qualities the second way, by contrast, allows mental qualities to diverge from the way we are conscious of them, but suggests that undetectable quality inversion is not even conceivable.10 Empirical results also suggest that the higher‐order content that implements TP belongs to distinct states. As noted earlier, there is strong evidence that decisions occur in advance of our being conscious of them. We can best explain that on the hypothesis that our consciousness of our decisions is due to distinct higher‐order states. Positing intrinsic higher‐order content also makes it harder to explain why particular states may be conscious at one moment but not another; why, if the higher‐order content is intrinsic to the state, does that intrinsic property come and go? The explanatory job is easier if the higher‐order content belongs to a distinct state. This problem becomes especially pressing in explaining the shift between a state's being non‐introspectively conscious and our introspectively scrutinizing it. On the HOT hypothesis, introspection occurs when a HOT becomes conscious. But if the higher‐order Page 11 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness content is intrinsic, this shift is a matter of a state's sometimes being conscious in respect of its higher‐order content and sometimes not. One might seek to explain that shift as a shift of attention to the higher‐order content.11 But since shifts of attention need not make the difference between a state's being conscious or (p. 250) not, they cannot by themselves explain a shift in whether the higher‐order content is conscious. Whatever the case with qualitative states, higher‐order content cannot be intrinsic to intentional states. Intentional states differ not only in content, but also in respect of mental attitude; two states can share intentional content even though one is a belief, another a doubt, and a third a case of wondering. And though a single state may, by conjoining contents, have more than one, no state has more than one mental attitude. No state is at once a case, for example, of both doubting and believing. When we are conscious of something by being in an intentional state about that thing, the state's mental attitude is always assertoric; doubting does not make one conscious of anything. So the higher‐order content that implements TP must occur in connection with an assertoric mental attitude. Consider, then, a conscious doubt. It is conscious in virtue of higher‐order content that one has that doubt, but one cannot doubt that higher‐order content; one must hold an assertoric attitude towards it. Since distinct mental attitudes require distinct intentional states, the higher‐order content must belong to a state distinct from that of the doubt itself (see Rosenthal 2005: ch. 2).

13.7 Higher‐order Theories and Qualitative Consciousness The consciousness of qualitative states presents special problems. On TP, a state's being conscious is a matter of one's being conscious of that state in some suitable way. But how can simply being conscious of a state with mental qualities make the difference between there being something it's like for one to be in that state and there being nothing it's like? The inner‐sense model may seem to have an advantage here; perhaps the qualitative character of the higher‐order sensing explains why sensing a qualitative state results in there being something it's like for one to be in that state. But that advantage is illusory, since the higher‐order sensing would itself seldom be conscious. HOTs may seem even less promising here than inner sense. But there is reason to think HOTs can make the difference between there being something it's like to be in a qualitative state and there being nothing it's like. Recall that learning new concepts for more fine‐grained mental qualities sometimes results in one's coming to be conscious of one's qualitative states in respect of those more fine‐grained qualities. That suggests that higher‐order conceptual states can also make the difference between there being something it's like for one to be in qualitative states and there being nothing it's like.

Page 12 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness Some have urged that an explanation of what makes that difference is acceptable only if it is rationally transparent. But this demand is excessive. Explanations come to seem rational not on their own, but only against the background of accepted theory. (p. 251) Whenever a qualitative state becomes conscious, we seem automatically to recognize its mental qualities. This suggests that a sensation's being conscious involves purely recognitional concepts, which apply to the sensation solely in virtue of some ability to recognize that type of sensation, rather than by way of ties that concept has with other concepts. And some higher‐order theorists have recently urged that such recognitional concepts figure in the relevant higher‐order states. But it is unlikely that any concepts are purely recognitional in this way; conceiving and recognizing involve distinct mental abilities. And without having an informative explanation of such purely recognitional concepts, appealing to them would simply dissolve the problem by fiat. If qualitative states resemble and differ in ways that parallel the similarities and differences among the corresponding perceptible properties, it is natural to construe our higher‐order concepts as appealing to such similarities and differences. That helps explain why HOTs about qualitative states arise at all. The concepts that figure in HOTs about qualitative states will have connections with concepts for perceptible properties, which figure in perceiving. So once a creature has such concepts for qualitative properties, perceiving will itself facilitate the occurrence of the relevant HOTs. Higher‐order theories of consciousness capture the compelling folk‐psychological idea that conscious states are those we are conscious of in some suitable way, and they fit well with results in experimental psychology. It is likely that some version of a higher‐order theory will prove to be correct.

References Armstrong, D. (1981), ‘What Is Consciousness?’ in Armstrong, The Nature of Mind and Other Essays (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 56–67. Brentano, F. (1874/1973), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. L. McAlister, trans. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Campbell, J. (1996), ‘Molyneux's Question’, Philosophical Issues, 7: 301–18. Carruthers, P. (1996), Language, Thought, and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2000), Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2004), HOP over FOR, HOT Theory, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins), 115–35.

Page 13 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness Descartes, R. (1964–75), ‘Fourth Replies’, in Oeuvres de Descartes, vii, ed. C. Adam and P. Tannery (Paris: Vrin). Dretske, F. (1993), ‘Conscious Experience’, Mind, 102: 263–83; repr. in Dretske, Perception, Knowledge, and Belief: Selected Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 113–37. Gennaro, R. J. (1996) (ed.), Consciousness and Self‐Consciousness (Amsterdam/ Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins). —— (2004), Higher‐order Thoughts, Animal Consciousness, and Misrepresentation: A Reply to Carruthers and Levine’, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins) 45–66. Gennaro, R. J. (2005), ‘The HOT Theory of Consciousness: Between a Rock and a Hard Place?’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12: 3–21. (p. 252)

Haggard, P. (1999), ‘Perceived Timing of Self‐initiated Actions’, in G. Aschersleben, T. Bachmann, and J. Müsseler (eds.), Cognitive Contributions to the Perception of Spatial and Temporal Events (Amsterdam: Elsevier), 215–31. Hill, C. S. (1991), Sensations: A Defence of Type Materialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Hume, D. (1739–40/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby‐Bigge, rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). Kriegel, U. (2003), ‘Consciousness as Intransitive Self‐consciousness: Two Views and An Argument’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33: 103–32. Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Libet, B. (1985), ‘Unconscious Cerebral Initiative and the Role of Conscious Will in Voluntary Action’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8: 529–39. Locke, J. (1700/1975), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed., from the fourth (1700) edn., P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975). Lycan, W. (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2004), ‘The Superiority of HOP to HOT’, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins), 93–113. Marcel, A. J. (1983a), ‘Conscious and Unconscious Perception: An Approach to the Relations between Phenomenal Experience and Perceptual Processes’, Cognitive Psychology, 15: 238–300.

Page 14 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness —— (1983b), ‘Conscious and Unconscious Perception: Experiments on Visual Masking and Word Recognition’, Cognitive Psychology, 15: 197–237. Natsoulas, T. (1999), ‘The Case for Intrinsic Theory, IV An Argument from How Conscious Mental‐occurrence Instances Seem, Journal of Mind and Behaviour, 20: 257–76. Neander, K. (1998), ‘The Division of Phenomenal Labor: A Problem for Representational Theories of Consciousness’, Philosophical Perspectives, 12: 411–34. Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. (1977), ‘Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes’, Psychological Review, 84: 231–59. Rosenthal, D. (1986), ‘Two Concepts of Consciousness’, Philosophical Studies, 49: 329–59. —— (2004), ‘Varieties of Higher‐Order Theory’, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins), 17–44. —— (2005), Consciousness and Mind (Oxford: Clarendon). Searle, J. R. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Sellars, W. (1963), Science, Perception, and Reality (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Shoemaker, S. (1975), ‘Functionalism and Qualia’, Philosophical Studies, 27: 292–315. repr. in Shoemaker, Identity, Cause, and Mind: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 184–205. Van Gulick, R. (2000), ‘Inward and Upward: Reflection, Introspection, and Self‐ awareness’, Philosophical Topics, 28: 275–305. —— (2004), ‘Higher‐order Global States (HOGS): An Alternative Higher‐order Model of Consciousness’, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: John Benjamins), 67–92. White, P. A. (1988), ‘Knowing More Than We Can Tell: “Introspective Access” and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later’, British Journal of Psychology, 79: 13–45.

Notes: (1) I'll speak interchangeably of being conscious of something and being aware of it. (2) Locke speaks of ‘internal Sense’ (1700/1975: II. i. 4); the term ‘inner sense’ derives from Kant (Critique of Pure Reason, A22/B37). Aristotle holds that we perceive that we perceive, though in the case of thinking he holds that we think that we think (see e.g. de Anima, Γ2, 425b12–20 and Nichomachean Ethics, IX. 9. 1170a29–34).

Page 15 of 17

Higher‐Order Theories of Consciousness (3) For more discussion of Lycan's argument that our higher‐order consciousness more closely resembles perceiving than thinking see Rosenthal (2004: sect. 3). (4) For more on this see e.g. Rosenthal (1986), reprinted, along with other essays on the HOT hypothesis, in Rosenthal (2005). (5) For more on this see Rosenthal (2005: ch. 2). For a qualification on the way the content of speech acts corresponds to that of the intentional states expressed see Rosenthal (2005: ch. 12). (6) Some theorists assume that whenever a creature is conscious, whatever mental states it is in are themselves conscious states. This assumption seems natural, since whenever people are awake, and hence conscious, many of their mental states are conscious. But, however alert we are, not all the mental states we are in are conscious; indeed, many non‐conscious mental states play a significant role in waking behaviour. So there may well be creatures none of whose mental states are conscious, even when they are fully awake. The inference from creature consciousness to state consciousness is unreliable. (7) E.g. only the HOT hypothesis affords an informative explanation of why, in the human case, verbally expressed intentional states are always conscious (see Rosenthal 2005: ch. 10). (8) John Campbell calls this view internalism (1996: 302). (9) Karen Neander and Joseph Levine both press this difficulty (Neander 1998; Levine 2001: sects. 4.4, 6.4), and both reject higher‐order theories altogether. (10) On such undetectable inversion see Rosenthal (2005: ch. 7, sect. 7). (11) See Christopher S. Hill's notion of volume adjustment (1991: ch. 5, sect. 3) and Robert Van Gulick's related appeal to volume control (2000: sect. III; 2004: sect. III).

David M. Rosenthal

David M. Rosenthal is Professor of Philosophy and Coordinator of Cognitive Science, City University of New York, Graduate Center.

Page 16 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness

Oxford Handbooks Online Representationalist Theories of Consciousness   Michael Tye The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0015

Abstract and Keywords This article surveys representationalist theories of phenomenal consciousness as well as the major arguments for them. It also takes up two major objections. The article is divided into five sections. The first section offers some introductory remarks on phenomenal consciousness. The second section presents the classic view of phenomenal consciousness to which representationalists are opposed. The third section canvasses various versions of representationalism about consciousness. The fourth section lays out the main arguments for the representationalist stance. The final section addresses the two objections. Keywords: representationalist theories, theories of phenomenal consciousness, phenomenal consciousness, representationalism, mental state, character of experiences

IT

is obvious that some mental states have representational content. Take the case of

beliefs, for example. Beliefs are either true or false. They are true if the world is as their subjects believe it to be and false otherwise. Each belief, thus, has accuracy conditions—it is accurate in certain circumstances and inaccurate in others—and any state with accuracy conditions has representational content. It is also obvious that some mental states are conscious. Recent representationalist theories of consciousness hold that there is a deep and important connection between the sort of consciousness that has most puzzled philosophers—phenomenal consciousness, as it is often called—and representational content. This chapter surveys representationalist theories of phenomenal consciousness as well as the major arguments for them. It also takes up two major objections. The essay is divided into five sections. Section 14.1 offers some introductory remarks on phenomenal consciousness. Section 14.2 presents the classic view of phenomenal consciousness to

Page 1 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness which representationalists are opposed. Section 14.3 canvasses various versions of representationalism about consciousness. Section 14.4 lays out the main arguments for the representationalist stance. The final section addresses the two objections.

14.1 Phenomenal Consciousness Of our conscious mental states, some are inherently conscious. That is to say, some of our mental states cannot fail to be conscious. For each such mental state there is a (p. 254) subjective perspective that goes along with it. This perspective is conferred upon the subject simply by his or her undergoing the mental state. It is captured in everyday language by talk of ‘what it is like’. There is something it is like subjectively to feel pain, to smell vomit, to taste chocolate, to feel elated. Furthermore, what it is like to undergo one inherently conscious mental state can be compared with what it is like to undergo another. For example, what it is like to experience bright red is subjectively more similar to what it is like to experience bright orange than to what it is like to experience dark green. Mental states that are inherently conscious are said to be ‘phenomenally conscious’ by philosophers. But just which mental states are these? One not very informative answer is that they are experiences. More helpfully, we can classify the relevant states into at least the following categories: (1) Perceptual experiences; for example, experiences of the sort involved in seeing green, hearing loud trumpets, tasting liquorice, smelling the sea air, running one's fingers over sandpaper. (2) Bodily sensations; for example, feeling a twinge of pain, feeling an itch, feeling hungry, having a stomach ache, feeling hot, feeling dizzy. Think here also of experiences such as those present during orgasm or while running flat out. (3) Felt reactions or passions or emotions; for example, feeling delight, lust, fear, love, feeling grief, jealousy, regret. (4) Felt moods; for example, feeling happy, depressed, calm, bored, tense, miserable. Some philosophers claim that there are also such experiences as, for example, the experience of suddenly remembering something or the experience of understanding a story. Others insist that in so far as there are experiences in these cases they are simply various perceptual and/or bodily experiences that accompany memory and understanding. Phenomenal consciousness attaches to mental states. Each phenomenally conscious mental state—each experience—is such that there is something it is like subjectively to undergo it. What it is like subjectively to undergo a given experience is known as the phenomenal character of the experience. Experiences vary in what it is like subjectively to undergo them and in so doing they vary in phenomenal character. Possession of a phenomenal character by a mental state endows it with the property of being phenomenally conscious.

Page 2 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness As we will see in Section 14.3, representationalist theories of consciousness are theories about the phenomenal character of experiences.

14.2 The Classic View The classic view of experiences to which representationalist theories are opposed has it that although all experiences have phenomenal character, not all of them have representational content. Consider, for example, an endogenous feeling of elation or an experience of throbbing pain. These experiences, according to the classic view, are phenomenologically rich but they do not represent anything. Furthermore, even where experiences do have representational content, adherents to the classic view (p. 255) insist (a) that they can vary in their phenomenal character while having the same representational content and (b) that they can vary in their representational content while having the same phenomenal character. In defence of (a) the most famous case offered is that of the inverted spectrum. Here is one version of that case. Suppose that Tom has a very peculiar visual system. His colour experiences are systematically inverted with respect to those of his fellows. When Tom looks at red objects, for example, what it is like for him subjectively is the same as what it is like for other people when they look at green objects, and vice versa. This peculiarity is one of which neither he nor others are aware. Tom has learned the meanings of colour words in the usual way and he applies these words correctly. Moreover, his non‐linguistic behaviour is standard. Now, when Tom views a ripe tomato, say, in good light his experience is phenomenally, subjectively different from the experiences you and I undergo. But his experience has the same representational content as ours. For his experience is the sort that is usually produced in him by viewing red objects and that usually leads him to believe that a red object is present. So he, like you and I, in viewing the tomato has an experience that represents the tomato as red. But the phenomenal character his experience has is the one tokened in our experiences when we view green objects, not red ones. So phenomenal character is not the same as, nor does it supervene upon, representational content. In defence of (b) above, one well‐known example that is often adduced is that of inverted earth. Inverted earth is an imaginary planet, on which things have complementary colours to the colours of their counterparts on earth. The sky is yellow, grass is red, ripe tomatoes are green, and so on. The inhabitants of inverted earth undergo psychological attitudes and experiences with inverted representational contents relative to those of people on earth. They think that the sky is yellow, see that grass is red, etc. However, they call the sky ‘blue’, grass ‘green’, ripe tomatoes ‘red’, etc. just as we do. Indeed, in all respects consistent with the alterations just described, inverted earth is as much like earth as possible.

Page 3 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness The example of inverted earth is due to Ned Block (1990). In Block's original version of the tale, one night while you are asleep a team of alien scientists insert colour‐inverting lenses in your eyes and take you to inverted earth, where you are substituted for your inverted‐earth twin or Doppelgänger. Upon awakening, you are aware of no difference, since the inverting lenses neutralize the inverted colors.1 You think that you are still where you were before. What it is like for you when you see the sky or anything else is just what it was like on earth. But after enough time has passed, after you have become sufficiently embedded in the language and physical environment of inverted earth, your representational contents will come to match those of the other inhabitants. You will come to believe that the sky is yellow, for example, just as they do. Similarly, according to Block, you will come to have a visual experience that represents the sky as yellow. For the experiential state you now undergo, as you view the sky, is the one that, in you, now normally tracks yellow things. So the later (p. 256) you will come to be subject to inner states that are representationally inverted relative to the inner states of the earlier you, while the phenomenal aspects of your experiences will remain unchanged. It follows that phenomenal character is not the same as representational content. Those who accept the classic picture of experience typically think of the phenomenal character of an experience as an intrinsic property of the experience, a property that in some cases is accompanied by a representational content. Philosophers who accept the classic view and who are materialists about phenomenal consciousness hold that once all the internal, physical facts are fixed for any given individual, the phenomenal character of each experience of that individual is fixed too. On this view, physically identical individuals located in different environments may well differ with respect to the representational contents of their experiences but the phenomenal characters of their experiences must be the same. Philosophers who accept the classic view but who are immaterialists about phenomenal character are more liberal. They allow that it is metaphysically possible for phenomenal character to vary even if all the internal physical facts are the same.

14.3 Versions of Representationalism As noted above, on the classic view phenomenal character is an intrinsic property of some mental states. Arguably, representationalist theories are best understood as rejecting even the basic assumption that the phenomenal character of a state is a property of that state, intrinsic or otherwise. To be sure, we talk of states having phenomenal character, but nothing in ordinary usage or thought commits us to the view that phenomenal characters are properties. After all, we talk of beliefs as having content and of words as having meaning, but we don't take belief contents or word meanings to be properties of beliefs and words respectively. Why do that from the outset for phenomenal character? Buy into the supposition that experiences are inner ideas or pictures viewed by an inner

Page 4 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness eye and it may be natural to take the ‘feel’ of an experience to be a property of the idea or picture. But that isn't common sense. It is philosophical dogma—precisely the dogma which representational theories of phenomenal consciousness oppose. Let us distinguish initially two representationalist positions:2 Strong representationalism: phenomenal character is one and the same as representational content that meets certain further conditions. Weak representationalism: phenomenal character supervenes on representational content that meets certain further conditions (so that necessarily any two states (p. 257) that are alike with respect to the relevant representational content are alike phenomenally). It should be clear why the qualifiers ‘meets certain further conditions’ and ‘relevant’ are added. Not all states with representational content have any ‘feel’ or phenomenal character at all. Consider, for example, unconscious beliefs or subpersonal representational states involved in early vision representing light intensity or zero‐crossings.

Reductive strong representationalism is the view both that the representational content with which phenomenal character is identical can be spelled out in physical or functional terms and that the further conditions on that content can be spelled out similarly. Non‐reductive strong representationalism is the view that either aspects of the content itself or aspects of the further conditions on the content are neither physical nor functional. On this view, phenomenal character is identified with representational content, but the content itself, or conditions on it, are irreducibly subjective. Corresponding reductive and non‐reductive positions are possible with respect to weak representationalism. Representationalism admits further of wide or narrow contents. Externalist representationalism is the thesis that microphysical duplicates can differ with respect to the relevant representational contents of some of their internal states. On this view, differently situated duplicates or duplicates with different histories can differ phenomenally. Internalist representationalism denies this. According to the internalist, microphysical duplicates must be alike with respect to the appropriate representational contents of their internal states. There is also room for disagreement about whether the contents are Fregean or not. For the Fregean representationalist the pertinent representational contents are individuated at least in part by conceptual modes of presentation. For the non‐Fregean the contents are non‐conceptual. Non‐Fregean contents may be Millian (after John Stuart Mill), individuated exclusively by worldly entities such as concrete objects and properties, or hybrid, individuated in part by non‐conceptual, sensory modes of presentation as well as worldy entities (paradigmatically properties).

Page 5 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness The hybrid position here faces some difficult questions that the Millian position does not. If there are indeed non‐conceptual sensory modes of presentation, is there one generic mode of presentation of this sort? Is there one for each sense? Or are there modes that vary within a sense? If so, how finely are they to be individuated? And what is it about these modes that makes them non‐conceptual? It is worth emphasizing that the Fregean representationalist can allow that the concepts whose modes of presentation are at least partly individuative of the relevant contents need not be concepts the subject of the experiences has, however. Thus, in another sense of non‐conceptual content (under which the content of state S of person P is non‐ conceptual if and only if P need not possess any of the concepts used by theorists to state the accuracy conditions for S), Fregean representationalism is compatible with the thesis that the sort of content relevant to phenomenal character is non‐conceptual content. (p. 258)

Philosophers who are representationalists may or may not be reductionists about phenomenal concepts. Those who are see the representationalist story as analysing the contents of those concepts, as spelling out in a priori terms what it is to be in a state with such‐and‐such a phenomenal feel and more generally what it is for a state to have a phenomenal feel. Those who are not reductionists here think of the representationalist theory as offering the best explanation of various pieces of data about phenomenal consciousness without itself being a conceptual truth. Regarding the entities that enter into the relevant representational contents, on the representationalist view, it should be clear that none of them can be concrete individuals. These individuals can play no role as far as phenomenology goes; for hallucinatory experiences have a subjective ‘feel’ to them and in cases of hallucination there are no appropriate concrete individuals. This much is agreed upon by all representationalists. I want now to say something more about the reductive and non‐reductive forms of the view. The standard reductive version of representationalism holds that the conditions on representational content are functional. More specifically, the usual view is that the relevant contents must be poised to make the right sort of difference with respect to cognitive responses. For the purposes of illustration, let me focus again upon the example of visual experience. Intuitively, visual experiences are not themselves beliefs but they are apt for the production of beliefs. Admittedly, some states that might reasonably be classified as visual experiences, for example seeing that the table is covered with books, already involve beliefs or belief‐like states. But such states seem best taken to be hybrid, having a visual experience proper and a belief or thought as components. Visual experiences proper are not apt for the production of any old beliefs, however. Intuitively, each visual experience is the direct basis for the formation of a belief about

Page 6 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness the perceptible qualities represented by the experience. Each experience is also, in creatures equipped with the capacity to introspect, the direct basis for the formation of beliefs about the experience and its content. The content of the visual experience proper supplies the input to the relevant belief‐ forming processes, where the role of the belief‐forming processes is to generate beliefs of the sorts just described. But the appropriate beliefs are not always formed, of course; for introspection can malfunction and, at least in the case of external belief formation, other background beliefs can interfere. There is also the possibility that attention is not appropriately directed. A visual experience has a poised content, then, so long as it is apt for the production in the right ways of the right beliefs. Likewise for the other senses. In the case of bodily experiences, desire is also relevant. The experience of pain, for example, is the direct basis for the desire to protect oneself, to avoid damage. (p. 259)

Poisedness, then, is a functional‐role condition. It is standardly taken by reductive representationalists as one important condition that a representational content must meet in order to be a phenomenal character. Another condition standardly imposed by reductive and non‐reductive representationalists alike is that the relevant content be non‐conceptual. This can be understood as indicated earlier, so that it is simply the condition that the subject of a state with phenomenal character need not have the concepts used to state the correctness conditions for the state. According to some philosophers, however, experiences have representational contents that are non‐conceptual in the stronger Millian way, and in this respect experiences have contents that are different in kind from belief contents (on the assumption that belief contents are Fregean). Putting these points together, one well known reductive representationalist proposal is that the phenomenal character of an experience is one and the same as its poised abstract non‐conceptual intentional (or representational) content or its PANIC, for short (see Tye 1995: 2000).3 Turning now to the non‐reductive form of representationalism, as noted earlier there are two ways in which such a view might be developed: either some of the entities out of which the relevant contents are built are themselves non‐physical or the further conditions these contents must meet are neither physical nor functional. Of these two possibilities, only the first has been worked out in any detail.4 Here the most straightforward proposal is that the content itself is Millian but that it involves non‐ physical qualities—qualities that experiences represent as belonging to things in the world or part of the body, but qualities that the represented items do not really possess. These qualities are projected on to the world by experiences; in reality either nothing at all has them or the experiences themselves do. It is worth noting that the last of these Page 7 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness proposals has features in common with the classic view of experience. For it is now conceded that experiences have special properties that are relevant to phenomenal character. What is denied is that these properties are phenomenal characters. Experiences have phenomenal character, on this view, via their (mistakenly) representing such qualities as belonging to things other than experiences.5

(p. 260)

14.4 Arguments for Representationalism

There are five main arguments for representationalism to be presented here. I call the first argument ‘the appeal to transparency’. Suppose that you are standing before a tapestry in an art gallery. As you take in the rich and varied colours of the cloth, you are told to pay close attention to your visual experience and its phenomenology. What do you do? The representationalist says that you attend closely to the tapestry and details in it. You are aware of something outside you— the tapestry—and of various qualities that you experience as being qualities of parts of the tapestry, and by being aware of these things, you are aware of what it is like for you subjectively or phenomenally. But your awareness of what it is like, of the phenomenology of your experience, is not de re awareness of the experience or its qualities.6 It is de dicto awareness that you have an experience with a certain phenomenal character or ‘feel’. Here is another example to illustrate these preliminary points. Suppose that you have just entered a friend's country house for the first time and you are standing in the living room, looking out at a courtyard filled with flowers. It seems to you that the room is open, that you can walk straight out into the courtyard. You try to do so and, alas, you bang hard into a sheet of glass, which extends from ceiling to floor and separates the courtyard from the room. You bang into the glass because you do not see it. You are not aware of it; nor are you aware of any of its qualities. No matter how hard you peer, you cannot discern the glass. It is transparent to you. You see right through it to the flowers beyond. You are aware of the flowers, not by being aware of the glass, but by being aware of the facing surfaces of the flowers. And in being aware of these surfaces, you are also aware of a myriad of qualities that seem to you to belong to these surfaces. You may not be able to name or describe these qualities but they look to you to qualify the surfaces. You experience them as being qualities of the surfaces. None of the qualities of which you are directly aware in seeing the various surfaces looks to you to be a quality of your experience. You do not experience any of these qualities as qualities of your experience. For example, if redness is one of the qualities and roundness another, you do not experience your experience as red or round. (p. 261)

Page 8 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness If your friend tells you that there are several ceiling‐to‐floor sheets of glass in the house and that they all produce a subtle change in the light passing through them so that things seen on the other side appear more vividly coloured than is usually the case, as you walk gingerly into the next room you may become aware that there is another partitioning sheet of glass before you by being aware of the qualities that appear to belong to non‐ glass surfaces before your eyes. You are not aware of the second sheet of glass any more than you were aware of the first; but you are now aware that there is a sheet of glass in the room by being aware of qualities apparently possessed by non‐glass surfaces before you. Visual experiences, according to the representationalist, are like such sheets of glass. Peer as hard as you like via introspection, focus your attention in any way you please, and you will only come across surfaces, volumes, films, and their apparent qualities. Visual experiences thus are transparent to their subjects. We are not introspectively aware of our visual experiences any more than we are perceptually aware of transparent sheets of glass. If we try to focus on our experiences, we ‘see’ right through them to the world outside. By being aware of the qualities apparently possessed by surfaces, volumes, etc., we become aware that we are undergoing visual experiences. But we are not aware of the experiences themselves.7 This is true even if we are hallucinating. It is just that in this case the qualities apparently possessed by surfaces, volumes, etc. before our eyes are not so possessed. The surfaces, volumes, etc. do not exist. Introspection, on the view just presented, is importantly like displaced perception or secondary seeing‐that, as Fred Dretske (1995) has observed. When I see that the petrol tank is nearly empty by seeing the petrol gauge, or when I see that the door has been forced by seeing the marks on the door, I do not see the petrol tank or the forcing of the door. My seeing‐that is secondary or displaced. I am not aware—I am not conscious—of either the petrol tank or the forcing of the door. I am aware of something else—the petrol gauge or the marks on the door—and by being aware of this other thing I am aware that such‐and‐such is the case. Similarly, in the case of introspection of a visual experience I am not aware or conscious of the experience itself. I am aware that I am having a certain sort of experience by being aware of something other than the experience—the surfaces apparently outside and their apparent qualities.8 Returning now to the first example, the representationalist claims that when you are told to attend closely to your visual experience, as you view the tapestry, what you actually do is to attend closely to the tapestry and the various ways it, or parts of it, look to you. Ways things look to people are typically expressed by predicates (p. 262) (as in ‘looks red’, ‘looks square’, ‘looks close’), and predicates express qualities—in this case, qualities represented by the relevant experiences of those people, qualities such that if the things

Page 9 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness seen have them, the experiences are veridical or accurate. Change the qualities ‘out there’, more specifically the qualities which are the ways the tapestry looks, and necessarily the ‘feel’ of your experience changes. What is true for vision is true for the other senses. Attending to the phenomenology of a perceptual experience, to its felt character, is a matter of attending to the ways things look, smell, taste, sound, or feel by touch. In the case of bodily sensations, the object of your attention is the way a certain part of your body feels.9 With emotions and moods, the attentional focus is often on things outside—things perceived as dangerous or foul or pleasing—but there is also attention to ways one's body is changing (pounding heart, shaky legs, higher blood pressure). More generally, attention to phenomenal character is a matter of attention to the ways things other than the experience seem; that is, to qualities that are not qualities of experiences. Change any of the qualities that are the various ways things look, smell, sound, etc. and necessarily the phenomenal character of the experience changes. Why should this be? The answer the strong representationalist proposes is that phenomenal character is identical with a certain sort of representational content into which the relevant qualities enter. Some representationalists take a weaker stand. They say merely that once the qualities that are directly experienced are fixed, the phenomenal character is fixed. Either way, the appeal to transparency is taken by intentionalists to be a key supporting argument for their position. The second argument for the representationalist position I call ‘the many‐property problem revisited’.10 In the 1970s Frank Jackson presented a problem for the adverbial approach to visual experience involving multiple after‐images. He called this problem ‘the many‐property problem’. The problem in essence was this: If what it is to have a sensory experience of something red is to sense redly, as adverbialists hold, then sensing something red and round should be a matter of sensing redly and roundly. So having a red, square after‐image at the same time as a green, round one is to be analysed as sensing redly and squarely and greenly and roundly. Since the conjuncts here can be commuted, this is the same as sensing redly and roundly and squarely and greenly. Thus, the distinction between having a red, square after‐image and a green, round one and having a red, round after‐image and a green, square one is lost. Now evidently the phenomenal character of a visual experience of a red, round object and a green, square one is different from the phenomenal character of a green, round object and a red, square one. How is this difference to be accounted for? If the phenomenal character of an experience is an intrinsic property of that experience, then it seems that the phenomenal character of the first experience must (p. 263) be a conjunctive property of the experience that is constituted by conjoining the phenomenal characters of experiences of red things, round things, green things, and square things. This, however, leaves no room for a phenomenal distinction between the first experience and the second one (the experience, that is, of a green, round object and a red, square one). To reply that the first phenomenal character is more complex in that it has a further conjunctive Page 10 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness constituent corresponding to the relative spatial position of the green, round object and the red, square one is not to solve the problem. For this simply adds a further conjunct and the problem arises again. One solution to this problem is to say that each experience has real objects, sense‐data, that are present whether or not the experience is veridical. The phenomenal character of the first experience is really a matter of its being an experience that relates its subject to two sense‐data, one of which is red and square and the other of which is green and round (in whatever senses of these terms are deemed applicable to sense‐data). Since the phenomenal character of the second experience involves sense‐data with different qualities, the phenomenal difference between the two experiences is preserved. The price paid for this solution is the admission of sense‐data. Since the introduction of sense‐data via the argument from illusion is not well motivated and there is a whole host of problems generated by them, this solution seems unacceptable. So, what is the answer? The representationalist will say that the answer is simple. The first experience has different accuracy conditions and thus a different representational content from the second. Since phenomenal character is the same as representational content (or is metaphysically determined by it), the difference in phenomenal character is straightforwardly preserved. The third argument for representationalism points to the intuitive connection between the phenomenal character of an experience and the way things seem to the person undergoing the experience. If things subjectively seem the same to you and me, then intuitively what it is like for me subjectively is the same as what it is like subjectively for you; and if what it is like subjectively for the two of us is the same then things seem subjectively the same to us. Since the way things seem subjectively is naturally taken to be the representational content of the experience just as the way things are believed to be is standardly taken to be the content of a belief, and sameness of phenomenal character is no more or less than sameness in ‘what it is like’, phenomenal character necessarily co‐varies with representational content. Why should this be? The answer, according to the strong representationalist, is that phenomenal character just is representational content of a certain sort. Anti‐representationalists will respond to this argument by denying that sameness in how things seem automatically goes with sameness in phenomenal character. They will say that, as the case of the inverted spectrum shows, sameness in how things (p. 264) seem is compatible with a difference in phenomenal character.11 The representationalist can respond that this is just not so—that where there supposedly is sameness in subjective seeming, there is sameness in phenomenal character—and that for each putative counter‐ example an account is possible that preserves the above linkage between seeming and phenomenal character. This point brings me to the fourth argument.

Page 11 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness The fourth argument for the representationalist view is in general form extremely simple. Many very smart philosophers have tried their best to come up with clear, actual cases of experiences which are identical in their representational contents but which differ phenomenally.12 They have appealed to blurry vision, double vision, vision with eyes closed, phosphenes, experiences with one eye open versus two, experiences of tilted versus untilted coins, gestalt effects of various sorts, the experience of pain, the experience of elation, experiences of trees at varying distances away, peripheral vision, seeing versus touching a round object, and many other actual phenomena. Representationalists have replied to these cases one by one and in detail; and they have made a plausible case for the view that, in each of these cases, where there is a phenomenal difference, there is a representational difference too. That leaves the opponents of representationalism with possible cases. And here the inverted spectrum and inverted earth loom large. These cases can be handled by the representationalist too (see Section 14.5). So it seems that no one as yet has managed to describe a clear‐cut example of representational identity and phenomenal difference among experiences. Why should this be? The simplest and most straightforward explanation is that phenomenal character is a certain kind of representational content. On this view, once all the representational facts are fixed, the phenomenal facts are automatically fixed too. Let us call this argument ‘the absence of counter‐example argument’. Obviously, this argument does not prove that the representationalist view is correct, even granting the assumption (which some philosophers would certainly contest) that as yet no clear actual or possible counter‐example has been adduced. But few arguments in philosophy are even close to proofs. The fifth argument I want to mention I call ‘the appeal to phenomenal indeterminacy’. This may be illustrated by the case of blurriness in visual experience. As noted above, this phenomenon is sometimes adduced by opponents of representationalism as creating a difficulty for the view. But representationalists maintain that this could not be further from the truth. Consider the example of the visual image of a speckled hen. How many speckles are there? This question posed an insuperable problem for the sense‐datum theory. For to the subject of the experience it is indeterminate how many speckles are present; yet there seems no room for such indeterminacy on the sense‐datum proposal. Not only does representationalism give a straightforward and (p. 265) satisfying account of such phenomenal indeterminacy but it also enables us to understand how there could be a phenomenal difference between seeing blurrily and seeing clearly something blurry. In the former case there is phenomenal indeterminacy with respect to the number of speckles, since there is no number of speckles, N, such that the visual experience represents a hen with N speckles. The visual experience here does not ‘comment upon’ the precise number of speckles. It leaves open how many speckles are present just as does the linguistic report that there is a speckled hen in the garden. In the latter case one sees blurrily just in case one undergoes a visual experience that represents fewer surface details than are represented when one sees clearly. By contrast, one sees clearly something blurry (e.g. a water‐colour picture with blurry edges) just in case one's visual experience represents that the boundaries of the blurry thing lie between precisely Page 12 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness located spatial regions A and B without representing exactly where they lie. There is a phenomenal difference between the two cases, the representationalist will say, precisely because there is a representational difference. No other theory of phenomenal character can give a satisfying and plausible account of this difference.13

14.5 The Inverted Spectrum and Inverted Earth In the standard inverted‐spectrum case it is usually supposed that the person with phenomenally inverted colour experiences does not differ from normal perceivers with respect to the representational contents of those experiences. This supposition is one that the representationalist challenges. For one thing, the background assumption that the invert would make the same judgements with respect to the colours as normal perceivers is clearly false. There are more discriminable hues between blue and red than between yellow and green. So the invert would make fewer hue discriminations than normal perceivers when shown things for which he and they use colour terms in the blue‐red range. The invert would also misclassify something saturated yellow in colour as darker than something that is saturated blue. Furthermore, the invert would count brown as merely darker in colour than yellow; for his experience would be the same as the experience the rest of us undergo as we view dark‐blue things, and dark blue does not differ except in brightness from lighter blues. So the invert would behave in ways that would mark him out from normal perceivers and lead us to think of him as making mistaken judgements about the colours of things. These judgements are based upon his colour experiences. So those experiences are also in error. The upshot is that his colour experiences do not have the same representational contents as normal perceivers'; for normal colour experiences typically do not err. (p. 266)

The second point to make is that even if it is metaphysically possible for some creatures to undergo colour experiences that are phenomenally inverted relative to those of others without there being any difference in narrow functioning or behaviour, this does not refute the representationalist. For the representationalist can insist that in such a case there is still a difference in representational content. To appreciate how this can be so, consider the following case. Imagine that in a country in Latin America after a revolution car tyres are replaced as they wear out in a haphazard way and that at some given time in this country there are forty‐seven cars travelling on the road, all with replaced tyres, and all going at exactly 30 mph. The speedometers in these cars read different things: some read 30, some read 31, some read 37, some read 28, and so on. Is there any way of telling which of the forty‐ seven speedometers is representing accurately actual car speed just by looking at the speedometer? Of course not. The speedometers were designed for use with tyres of a

Page 13 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness certain size. They give an accurate read‐out of the speed just in case they are operating as they were designed to operate with tyres of the appropriate size. Similarly in the case of colour. The colour‐experience system in the brain was designed by evolution for use with an optic nerve and retina meeting certain further conditions. There is no way of telling who, among present‐day actual colour perceivers, has the retinal apparatus and optic nerve meeting the historical design specifications (Dretske 1995). But whoever does gets the colours of things right in experience. What is true in this case, the representationalist can say, is true in the metaphysically possible case in which there is a phenomenal difference unaccompanied by any difference in narrow functioning or behaviour. Here the perceivers who get the colours of things right are those whose visual systems are operating in the right historical way. But there is no way of knowing from current behaviour just which these perceivers are. The response to the inverted‐earth case is similar. The person who switches to inverted earth and who is wearing colour‐inverting lenses has the representational contents of his visual experiences fixed by the historical setting in which his visual system was designed to be used. Since the experiential state he is in on inverted earth when he views red things is the state that in his species was designed to track green things on earth under optimal conditions, it represents green and not red. This remains the case however long he remains on inverted earth. Furthermore, this difference between Mr Invert and those who have always lived on inverted earth is one that will show up in subtle behavioural differences which do not change through time. For example, if Mr Invert is shown two colour patches, one yellow and one blue, each at maximum saturation, he will classify the blue patch as brighter, whereas the locals will classify the other patch as the brighter one. The upshot is that the representationalist about phenomenal consciousness has plausible replies to the standard cases of the inverted spectrum and inverted earth.

References Block, N. (1990), ‘Inverted Earth’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 53–79. —— (1996), ‘Mental Paint and Mental Latex’, Philosophical Issues, 7: 19–49. Boghossian, P., and Velleman, D. (1989), ‘Colour as a Secondary Quality’, Mind, 98: 81– 103. Byrne, A. (2001), ‘Intentionalism Defended’, Philosophical Review, 110: 199–240. —— (2006), ‘Inverted Qualia’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , accessed 2008. Chalmers, D. (2006), ‘Perception and the Fall from Eden’, in J. Hawthorne and T. Gendler (eds.), Perceptual Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 49–125. Page 14 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness Dretske, F. (1993), ‘Conscious Experience’, Mind, 102: 263–83. —— (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press). Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Jackson, F. (1977), Perception (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2003), ‘Mind and Illusion’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Minds and Persons (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 251–71. Kirk, R. (1994), Raw Feeling (Oxford: Clarendon). Lycan, W. (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press). McDowell, J. (1994), ‘The Content of Perceptual Experience’, Philosophical Quarterly, 44: 190–205. McGinn, C. (1982), The Character of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1991), The Problem of Consciousness (Oxford: Blackwell). Moore, G. (1903), ‘The Refutation of Idealism’, in Moore, Philosophical Studies (London: Routledge & Keagan Paul), 1922, 1–30. Peacocke, C. (1983), Sense and Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Shoemaker, S. (1990), ‘Qualities and Qualia: What's in the Mind’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50: 109–31. —— (1994), ‘Phenomenal Character’, Noûs, 28: 21–38. Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press). —— (2000), Consciousness, Color and Content (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press). —— (2003), ‘Book Symposium: Ten Problems of Consciousness, Precis, Comments, and Replies’, Philosophical Studies, 113: 233–90.

Notes: (1) Your body pigments are also changed.

Page 15 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness (2) Versions of representationalism are to be found in Harman (1990), Shoemaker (1990, 1994), Kirk (1994), McDowell (1994), Dretske (1995), Tye (1995, 2000), Lycan (1996), Byrne (2001), Jackson (2003), Chalmers (2006). (3) For detailed discussion and criticisms of this theory, along with replies, see the web symposium at http://host.uniroma3.it/progetti/kant/field/tyesymp.htm, accessed 2008. See also the shorter symposium on Tye (2000) in Philosophical Studies (Tye 2003). (4) A (qualified) version of the first view is presented in Chalmers (2006). (5) Another view not dissimilar to this one is held by Sydney Shoemaker (1990, 1994). There are two main differences. For Shoemaker, experiences have intrinsic qualities that they correctly represent things in the world as producing or as being disposed to produce. Moreover, these qualities have a physical nature. Neither the physical nature of these intrinsic qualities nor the relational nature of the properties external things are represented as having (properties such as the property of being disposed to produce an experience with such‐and‐such an intrinsic quality in normal perceivers) is revealed to the subjects of the experiences. Even so, according to Shoemaker, the phenomenal ‘feel’ of the experiences is given by the relevant representational contents. (6) This claim, it is worth noting, fits well with the linguistic constructions that are naturally employed in connection with such awareness. To talk of our being aware of the phenomenology of an experience or of how an experience ‘feels’ is to use a generic perceptual verb (‘aware of’) followed by an abstract noun (‘the phenomenology’) or an interrogative nominal (‘how the experience feels’). In cases of this sort, where there is a perceptual verb, the abstract noun or interrogative nominal typically stands in for a factive clause so that what is being described is (a species of) awareness of some fact. For example, if I am described as hearing the answer to your question or as seeing who is at the door, I do not satisfy the description merely by hearing the sentence that is the answer or seeing the person who is at the door. I must be aware that the given sentence is the answer to your question, that the given person is the one at the door. In short, I must be aware of some appropriate fact. Likewise in the case of awareness of the phenomenal character of a current experience. For more here see Dretske (1993). (7) This claim is one that the sense‐datum theorists would have endorsed, although they would have insisted that the things apparently outside are really immaterial surfaces or sense‐data rather than physical surfaces. After all, sense‐datum theorists were at pains to distinguish the act of sensing from the thing sensed. G. E. Moore (1903) is the modern father of transparency. (8) There are dissimilarities. In typical cases of seeing‐that, background beliefs play a role in generating the propositional state of awareness. This is not so in the case of introspection. For more here see Tye (2000: ch. 3). (9) I ignore here the case of phantom‐limb sensations, for which there is no relevant limb to feel any way. Page 16 of 17

Representationalist Theories of Consciousness (10) See here Byrne (2006). (11) I am assuming here that the opponent of representationalism will say that the person with phenomenally inverted colour experiences nonetheless is such that ripe tomatoes and other red things look or seem red to him (or her). (12) See here McGinn (1982), Peacocke (1983), Searle (1983), Boghossian and Velleman (1989), Block (1996), among others. (13) Further arguments for representationalism about phenomenal consciousness are to be found in Byrne (2001) and Jackson (2003).

Michael Tye

Michael Tye is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, The University of Texas at Austin.

Page 17 of 17

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities

Oxford Handbooks Online Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities   Alex Byrne The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0016

Abstract and Keywords In theorizing about perception philosophers have often multiplied qualities. To perceptible qualities of external objects, like colours and shapes (‘sensible’ qualities), have been added qualities of experiences (‘sensory’ qualities) or of sense-data (‘sensational’ qualities). This article starts with sensory qualities. The phrase ‘sensory quality’ is not much in use these days, having lost out to ‘phenomenal character’, ‘phenomenal property’, ‘qualitative character’, or ‘quale’. But whatever sensory qualities are called, pinning them down is no easy matter. Keywords: sensory qualities, sensible qualities, sensational qualities, perception philosophy, external objects, qualitative character

IN

theorizing about perception philosophers have often multiplied qualities. To perceptible

qualities of external objects, like colours and shapes (‘sensible’ qualities), have been added qualities of experiences (‘sensory’ qualities) or of sense‐data (‘sensational’ qualities). Start with sensory qualities. The phrase ‘sensory quality’ is not much in use these days, having lost out to ‘phenomenal character’, ‘phenomenal property’, ‘qualitative character’, or ‘quale’. But whatever sensory qualities are called, pinning them down is no easy matter.

15.1 Sensory Qualities Austen Clark's Sensory Qualities can serve as an initial illustration, especially because this important book is an exemplary specimen of clarity and rigour. If the elusiveness (p. 269) of sensory qualities is apparent here, then a large part of the blame can be

Page 1 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities apportioned to the subject matter itself. Clark opens the explanation of his topic as follows: A whiff of lilacs presents a particular sweet odour. The warmth of the rising sun yields certain tactile sensations. Bees' honey has a specific taste. The qualities that characterize the smell of the lilacs, sensation of the sun, or taste of the honey are all what I will call sensory qualities. Broadly speaking, such qualities characterize what it is like to sense or perceive things. One perceives the blooms, sun and honey in a particular way; sensory qualities characterize the way such things appear. (1993: 1). It is not immediately clear from these two paragraphs what sensory qualities are qualities of. Consider the ‘sweet odour’ of lilacs. We may take the odour of lilacs to be the same as ‘the smell of the lilacs’, in which case one quality that presumably ‘characterize[s] the smell of the lilacs’ is sweetness. And what is the smell of the lilacs? One candidate—reading ‘the smell of the lilacs’ like ‘the colour/size of the lilacs’—is a certain odiferous property of the lilacs. On this reading, sweetness ‘characterizes’ the smell of the lilacs in the sense that it is identical to the smell; it is identical to an odiferious property of the lilacs. Another candidate for the smell of the lilacs— leaning heavily on the fact that smells ‘drift’, ‘linger’, and are ‘given off’ by objects like lilacs—is a certain volume of gas, an ‘effluvium’ (Gibson 1966: 144), or ‘vaporous emanation’ (Lycan 1996: 146). On this rival account, sweetness ‘characterizes’ the smell of the lilacs in the sense that it is a property of the smell—the effluvium emitted by the lilacs. In any case, there do not seem to be any mental candidates for the smell of the lilacs: if the smell is anywhere, it is in the lilac bed, not the mind.

So if we focus on Clark's first example, sensory qualities are not properties of anything mental. But his second example—the ‘sensation of the sun’—and the tell‐tale ‘what it is like’ locution suggest exactly the opposite, that sensory qualities attach to mental items (experiences, probably). However, Clark goes on to say that sensory qualities ‘characterize the way such things [the blooms, sun, and honey] appear’. Since the blooms appear red, the sun appears hot, and the honey appears sweet (suppose), sensory qualities ‘characterize’ redness, hotness, and sweetness, for example. Either this means that sensory qualities are (higher‐order) properties of redness, hotness, etc., or else it means (a more likely interpretation) that the redness, hotness, etc. are examples of sensory qualities. Either way, sensory qualities are not—or are not obviously—properties of experiences. This is somewhat unfair to Clark: it is perfectly clear from other passages that sensory qualities are stipulated to be properties of experiences or, as he prefers, ‘sensations’: Although ‘sensation’ proper is a term confined to bodily sensation, often one extends its use to describe appearances in all perceptual modalities. Whenever any creature perceives something, there is some internal state of the creature in virtue of which it perceives that thing. One can label that state the creature's ‘sensation of’ or ‘sense impression of’ or ‘experience of’ the perceived thing. So, Page 2 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities for example, the internal state in virtue of which I now see the red rug (p. 270) and without which I would not see the red rug is (by stipulation) my visual sensation ‘of’ the rug. Sensory qualities are qualities of sensation, construed in this broad way. (1993: 3–4) A number of questions can be raised about this explanation. First, there is a contrast between states and events: states are properties or conditions, not occurrences or events, although frequently philosophers of mind use ‘state’ in a semi‐technical umbrella sense to include events. Clark might be assuming that sensations are events, and using ‘state’ in the broad sense. If so, then sensory qualities are properties of particulars; alternatively, if Clark is using ‘state’ in the narrow sense, they are properties of properties. If it is unclear which option to choose, that casts some doubt on the idea that ‘sensory quality’ is a label for something we all pretheoretically recognize.

Second, is it even true that ‘[w]henever any creature perceives something, there is some internal state of the creature in virtue of which it perceives that thing’? Setting aside the state/event distinction, much hangs on the interpretation of ‘in virtue of’, which Clark leaves unexplained. One suggestion would be that seeing the red rug can be decomposed into an internal state (the ‘sensation’), the red rug, and an appropriate causal relation connecting the rug to the internal state. But that would require an argument: the decomposition thesis is considerably stronger than the relatively uncontroversial claim that a causal connection is necessary for seeing. Third, are we aware of sensations and their sensory qualities? That might sound like a silly question—one is frequently aware of one's bodily sensations (‘sensations proper’) and some of their properties. I am aware of a twinge, its location (my left elbow), and its achiness. That sort of awareness seems (quasi‐)perceptual—rather like the awareness I have of a flash of light, its location (the far side of the room), and its brightness. However, on this conception of (bodily) sensations, they are not experiences; rather, they are objects of experiences. The twinge is—or at any rate appears to be—some sort of disturbance in my elbow, not in my mind or head, unlike the presumed ‘experience’ of the twinge. Clark, however, has a very different conception of bodily sensations, on which the experience of the twinge, not the twinge, counts as a bodily sensation; hence his extension of the use of ‘sensation’ to cover paradigmatic perceptual experiences. Without distinguishing between the two conceptions of sensations it might appear evident that we are aware of sensations (as Clark conceives of them) and their sensory qualities; in fact, it is far from evident. For these reasons, it should not be taken for granted that Clark has succeeded in circumscribing his purported object of study. For another attempt, consider how Levine introduces sensory qualities in Purple Haze—a synthesis of his influential work on the ‘explanatory gap’:

Page 3 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities Let's take my current visual experience as I gaze upon my red diskette case, lying by my side on the computer table. I am having an experience with a complex qualitative character, one component of which is the colour I perceive. Let's dub this aspect of my experience its ‘reddish’ character … Qualitative character concerns the ‘what’ it's like for me: reddish or greenish, painful or pleasurable, and the like. From within the subjective point of view I am presented with these qualitative features of experience, or ‘qualia,’ [aka sensory qualities] as they are called in the literature. Reddishness, for instance, is a feature of my experience when (p. 271) I look at my red diskette case. It is notoriously difficult to explain this feature by reference to either the physical or formal features of my brain states. (2001: 6–7) Plainly Levine intends sensory qualities (‘qualitative character’, ‘qualitative features’, ‘qualia’) to be properties of experiences, although he says little about what experiences are supposed to be. Suppose one is looking at Levine's red diskette case, balanced precariously on the computer table. One might be aware of a state of the diskette case (its redness), and an event involving the diskette case (its falling off the table). Is it so obvious that one can also be aware of, or be ‘presented with’, a ‘qualitative feature’ of a mental event or state—one's experience of the diskette case? Uncontroversially, one is in a position to know that one sees the diskette case, and that it looks red to one. What is not immediately clear is whether this piece of self‐knowledge requires any kind of awareness of a mental event or state. Indeed, the very existence of an appropriate event is a matter of some doubt. ‘One's seeing the diskette case’, for example, is not a good candidate for such an event—the nominal ‘one's seeing the diskette case’ behaves more like the name of a fact than of an event (see Bennett 1988: ch. 1). (On the difficulty of squeezing some philosophical juice out of the word ‘experience’ see Hinton 1973: pt. I.)

Of course, one can easily play along with Levine's terminology, at least to some extent, by saying ‘My experience is reddish’ iff it looks to one that something is red. But Levine does not intend ‘reddish experiences’ to be a stylistic variant of ‘looks red’ and similar expressions (and this chapter will follow Levine's terminological intentions). Levine evidently assumes that we have some independent handle on reddish experiences, and that the relation between reddish experiences and how things look with respect to colour is an open question. The role played by the red appearance of the diskette case is merely to fix the reference of ‘reddish’; the relation between reddish experiences and the visual representation of the colour red might well be entirely contingent. And, in fact, that is exactly what Levine thinks (2001: ch. 4).1

15.2 Sensory Qualities and Sensible Qualities Sensory qualities—if there are any—are properties of experiences. They are not properties of external objects like diskette cases and the like. Going by the quotation from Levine, sensory qualities are not even ostensible properties of diskette cases: properties

Page 4 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities of experiences that appear mistakenly to be properties of diskette cases. Introspection, attention to one's experience, acquaintance, or something similar seems to reveal them as properties of experiences, and that is indeed what they are. (p. 272)

Levine's sensory quality of reddishness, then, is not redness, the colour. Even if tomatoes are not in fact red, at least they appear red. And one's experiences do not appear red at all. Levine himself is quite explicit that redness and reddishness are distinct (2001: 179 n. 5). Redness can be called a sensible quality—a quality that one perceives, like roundness, motion, and sweetness. (To say that one ‘perceives redness’ when looking at a tomato is not to presuppose that the tomato is red.) Clark's A Theory of Sentience distinguishes between sensible and sensory qualities, using the terminology of ‘phenomenal’ and ‘qualitative’ properties (2000: 2). Although sensible and sensory qualities should not be identified, presumably they are closely related. But before canvassing one popular account of their relation (in Section 15.5) it needs to be pointed out that separating the two is, for the most part, a comparatively recent innovation. Hume, for example, reports that the ‘fundamental principle’ of the ‘modern philosophy’ ‘is the opinion concerning colours, sounds, tastes, smells, heat and cold; which it asserts to be nothing but impressions in the mind’ (1739–40/1978: I. iv). By saying that colours are ‘impressions in the mind’, and so ‘internal existences’, Hume is (arguably) saying that items ‘in the mind’ are coloured. And if we suppose that the items are experiences (for an alternative, see the following section), then Hume is apparently identifying sensible and sensory qualities. F. A. Hayek's The Sensory Order provides a mid‐twentieth‐century example of this identification (as well as a notable example of the use of ‘sensory quality’). Hayek begins by explaining that [f]or the purposes of this discussion we shall employ the term sensory ‘qualities’ to refer to all the different attributes or dimensions with regard to which we differentiate in our responses to different stimuli. We shall thus use this term in a wide sense in which it includes not only quality in the sense in which it is contrasted with intensity, extensity, clearness, etc., but in a sense in which it includes all these other attributes of a sensation. We shall speak of sensory qualities and the sensory order to distinguish these from the affective qualities and the other mental ‘values’ which make up the more comprehensive order of ‘mental qualities’. (1952: 2) Sensory qualities, then, are mental qualities, specifically ‘attributes of a sensation’. And sensations, or ‘sense experiences’ are ‘events taking place in some organism’ (Hayek 1952: 3, 16).

Immediately after giving this explanation Hayek says: Page 5 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities A precise statement of the problem raised by the existence of sensory qualities must start from the fact that the progress of the physical sciences has all but eliminated these qualities from our scientific picture of the external world. (1952: 2) In a footnote he quotes from Planck's A Survey of Physics:

The sense perceptions have been definitely eliminated from physical acoustics, optics, and heat. The physical definitions of sound, colour, and temperature are today in no way associated with the immediate perception of the respective senses, but sound and colour are defined respectively by the frequency and wavelength of oscillations, and temperature is measured (p. 273) theoretically on the absolute temperature scale corresponding to the second law of thermodynamics. (Planck 1925: 5) So the sensory qualities—as Hayek goes on to say—include ‘colours, sounds, odours, feeling of touch, etc.’ (1952: 3). Science has only turned up correlates of these qualities in our external environment—‘the frequency and wavelength of oscillations’—not the qualities themselves.

Suppose that Hume and Hayek are right, and that nothing in the external world is coloured or noisy or tasty. What remains quite unclear is why they think items in the ‘internal’ world—sensations, for instance—have these qualities. Why not say instead that absolutely nothing has these qualities? Whatever the answer to this question might be, the introspective psychologists tended to take it as simply obvious that ‘sensations’ had colours, sounds, and so forth: Sensations have always been distinguished by their qualities. Every sensation can be said to have an attribute of quality, which designates it as red or yellow or bitter or cold or C#. (Boring 1933: 19) Returning to Clark's Sensory Qualities, soon it becomes apparent that he is working squarely within this framework. Examples of ‘a particular sensory quality’ include ‘a red colour or a camphoraceous odour’ (1993: 128). So the familiar colour solid, with the colours arranged along dimensions of hue, brightness, and saturation, is taken to be a space of sensory qualities; and the main task of Clark's book is to supply a broadly physicalistic theory of such spaces.

One way of justifying this surely rather odd talk is to take ‘red’, ‘camphoraceous’, and so forth to be ambiguous. In one sense ‘red’ refers to a property of tomatoes and strawberries; in another sense ‘red’ refers to a property of mental items: experiences, sensations, or whatever. Locke is often supposed to hold such a view. (For discussion see Stuart 2003.) However, taken as a descriptive semantic claim about English, the ambiguity thesis is not very appealing. Phrases like ‘red experience’ and ‘red sensation’ cannot be adduced in its support, since these are examples of philosophical jargon, not

Page 6 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities ordinary English. ‘An experience of red’ is fairly natural, but here there is no reason to suspect that ‘red’ has a second semantic value. (The phrase ‘the Taj Mahal’ in ‘an experience of the Taj Mahal’ refers to the mausoleum, not to anything mental.)2

15.3 Sensational Qualities In his famous 1903 paper ‘The Refutation of Idealism’ G. E. Moore argued that esse is not percipi. In particular, Moore claimed that ‘[w]e can and must conceive the (p. 274) existence of blue as something quite different from the existence of the sensation [of blue]’ (1903: 445). That sounds like the claim that, for example, ‘a blue tie should exist at a time when nothing is looking blue to anyone’, as Moore put it nearly forty years later in The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (1942: 655). However, in that volume Moore goes on to tell us that this is not the question at issue … In order to see what the issue is, it seems to me to be absolutely essential to see that such words as ‘blue’ and ‘bitter’ may be used in two very different senses. When we say of such things as a tie or a flag or an india rubber ball that they are blue, what we are saying about them may be something very different from what we are saying of an after‐image, which we see with closed eyes, when we say that it is blue; and when we say of quinine or wormwood that they are bitter, what we are saying of them is certainly something very different from what we are saying of a taste which we are tasting or a taste ‘which is in our mouth,’ when we say that it is bitter. (1942: 655) Forget for the moment about the wormwood, and concentrate on the alleged ambiguity in ‘blue’. In one sense it stands for a property of external objects like ties, rubber balls, and so on. In another sense, it stands for a property of an after‐image ‘or any other sense‐datum’ (Moore 1942: 658). In this second sense ‘blue’ stands for what Moore calls ‘the sensible quality “blue” ’ (1942: 658); to avoid confusion, let us adapt some terminology from Peacocke (1983) and call this quality instead ‘the sensational quality blue’.3

We now have a third quality to contend with, at least nominally: the sensational quality blue, in addition to the sensible quality blue and the sensory quality blue (i.e. bluishness, as Levine would call it). Again borrowing some terminology from Peacocke, call the sensational quality blue, blue′ (‘blue‐prime’). Blue′ is a property of sense‐data: objects of experiences, not experiences themselves. According to Moore, when a tie looks blue to one, one is (or can be) aware of something else, an immaterial (or at least not clearly material) thing that appears blue′. Even though the tie may not in fact be blue, the sense‐ datum is as it appears, and so is blue′.

Page 7 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities Is there such a property as blue′? If ‘blue’ has ‘two different senses’ when we speak of a ‘blue after‐image’ and a ‘blue tie’, then there is at least an initial reason for thinking so. But there appears to be no ambiguity: ‘My after‐image and this tie are both exactly the same shade of blue’ would strike us as false if ‘blue’ were ambiguous between ‘the colour blue’ (not a property of after‐images) and ‘blue′’ (not a property of ties). On the contrary, this sentence seems unproblematically true. Of course, it might not in fact be true. Offhand, the sentence is true only if there are such things as after‐images, and arguably there are no after‐images, there only seem to be (see Smart 1959). But this would trace the falsity of the sentence to the metaphysics of after‐images, rather than to an ambiguity in ‘blue’. After‐images appear to be located on the focused surface (Emmert's law), and can be mistaken for coloured patches. This would be mysterious if after‐images did not (p. 275) appear coloured. Further, as explained in any textbook on colour vision, there are theories of after‐images. These theories explain why, for instance, staring at a yellow surface will produce a blue after‐image. If after‐images are not blue (or do not appear blue), the widely accepted characterization of the data to be explained is wrong. Moore's case for blue′ is uncompelling. Let us briefly turn to his second example, of ‘bitter’. Here the claim of ambiguity (or, better, polysemy) is considerably more plausible. Wormwood is bitter because it has a bitter taste, just as a skunk is malodorous because it produces a malodorous smell, and (to borrow Aristotle's example), an apple is healthy (in the secondary sense) because it is conducive to a healthy body (in the primary or focal sense). It is at least strained to say that wormwood and the taste it produces are both bitter. Have we not found a sensational quality, bitter′, which attaches to gustatory sense‐data? Not obviously: on the face of it, a bitter taste is some kind of bitter ‘emanation’ produced by wormwood, just as the sweet smell of lilacs is (on one understanding) a sweet effluvium produced by lilacs. Notice that Moore can't quite keep his scare quotes off the phrase, but there is no apparent reason why the taste should not be (spatially) in the mouth. A proponent of sensational qualities should look elsewhere for support, perhaps to Peacocke's much‐discussed arguments. But these are beyond the scope of this chapter.4

15.4 Sensory Qualities and Natural Signs According to a long tradition, external objects act on our perceptual apparatus to produce experiences with distinctive sensory qualities—or, alternatively, experiences of sense‐data with distinctive sensational qualities. The epistemological problem of perception is then

Page 8 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities conceived as one of working out what the distal stimulus must be like, given that it produces these effects in us. Thus Russell: if we take any common object of the sort that is supposed to be known by the senses, what the senses immediately tell us is not the truth about the object as it is apart from us, but only the truth about certain sense‐data which, so far as we can see, depend upon the relations between us and the object. Thus what we directly see and feel is merely ‘appearance’, which we believe to be a sign of some ‘reality’ behind. But if the reality is not what appears, have we any means (p. 276) of knowing whether there is any reality at all? And if so, have we any means of finding out what it is like? (1912/80: 6) This sort of view was set out with particular clarity by Thomas Reid. When a tomato is seen, Reid thinks, an ‘appearance’ or ‘sensation’ or what ‘Mr Locke calls … an idea’ (1764/1970: 100) of colour is produced in the mind, and ‘[t]his sensation is followed by the perception of the object’ (1764/1970: 214). The sensation, whose nature we can know perfectly, ‘suggests the conception and belief of some unknown quality in the body, which occasions the idea; and it is to this quality, and not to the idea, that we give the name of colour’. Here Reid takes himself to have an essentially linguistic dispute with Locke and his followers, whom Reid takes to hold that ‘colour is not a quality of bodies, but only an idea in the mind’. Reid thinks it is absurd to hold that the vulgar ‘give the name of colour to the sensation’. Instead, colour words denote the power in bodies to produce our colour sensations, the ‘unknown cause’ of a ‘known effect’ (1764/1970: 100, 102, 101).

Borrowing Reid's terminology, let us call this picture of perception the natural‐sign theory. According to it, the only information solely about the colour of a tomato that can be extracted from the experience of seeing it is that the tomato has some property or other that causes experiences with the sensory quality of reddishness (the ‘natural sign’ of the sensible quality red).

15.5 Natural Signs and Dispositionalist Accounts of Sensible Qualities As the last paragraph hinted, there is an intimate relation between the natural‐sign theory and accounts of sensible qualities as dispositions to affect perceivers in certain ways. This connection is brought out in some striking passages from Evans's classic paper ‘Things Without the Mind’. After quoting Reid with approval (1980: 271), Evans claims that ‘[a]ll it can amount to for something to be red is that it be such that, if looked at in the normal conditions, it will appear red’ (1980: 272). Some misguided philosophers deny this: Page 9 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities They have tried to make sense of the idea of a property of redness which is both an abiding property of the object, both perceived and unperceived, and yet ‘exactly as we experience redness to be’. By concentrating upon one's experience of colour, one is supposed thereby to know what it is for an object to have this property: ‘This’, one is to say, referring neither to the experience nor to any primary property of the thing, ‘this, just as it is, can exist in the absence of any observer’. But the leap gets us nowhere, for it inevitably involves an attempt to make sense of an exemplification of a property of experience in the absence of experience. Wittgenstein once imagined a world in which there were places which affected everyone painfully, so that pains (p. 277) were located at places in the way we locate smells. Suppose this fantasy came true. Would it then make sense to give a non‐dispositional account of what it is for there to be a pain at such and such a spot: to suppose a ‘pain as we feel it’ existing in the absence of any observer? What can the latter form of words mean save that something awful is going on there, and how can that be, when there is no one who is hurt? To modify a dictum of Wittgenstein, conceiving of a pain which no one feels on the model of a pain which one does feel is none too easy a thing to do. (1980: 272–3) This passage is not easy to understand, but one interpretation (there may be others) leans heavily on Evans's remark about ‘an exemplification of a property of experience’ and the analogy with Wittgenstein's example. So interpreted, the argument takes the natural‐sign theory as a premise, and runs as follows.

Start with pain, and assume that pains are ‘painful’ experiences. This view, unlike one that takes pains to be the intentional objects of certain experiences, and not the experiences themselves, makes pains ‘existing in the absence of any observer’ decidedly suspect, just as Evans says.5 Further, assume the common view that painful experiences are ‘mere’ sensations: experiences with no representational content (and so no intentional objects). Now make the counterfactual supposition that Wittgenstein's fantasy is true: ‘The surfaces of the things around us (stones, plants, etc.) have patches and regions which produce pain in our skin when we touch them … In this case we should speak of pain‐patches on the leaf of a particular plant just as at present we speak of red patches’ (Wittgenstein 1953: sect. 312). That is, suppose that certain surfaces are disposed to produce pain sensations (painful experiences) in us, and we use the word ‘pain’ to refer to a property of those surfaces that they possess even when no one is touching them. ‘Pain’, as used in these counterfactual circumstances, can hardly refer to a property that our experiences represent certain surfaces as having, because ex hypothesi painful experiences have no representational content. Instead, the obvious candidate, given that ‘pain’ is used to refer to an abiding property of surfaces, is that it refers to the disposition to cause painful experiences in us.

Page 10 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities The next step of the argument compares pain to colour. When we look at a tomato we have reddish sensations, experiences with a distinctive sensory quality, but with no representational content (no colour content, anyway). Trying to make sense of ‘colour‐as‐ we‐see it’ (Evans 1980: 273) when we don't see it amounts to making sense of reddishness, a ‘property of experience’, exemplified ‘in the absence of experience’. However, we use the word ‘red’ to refer not to a property of experiences but to an abiding property of objects. As with the pain‐patches example, this word plausibly refers to a disposition to cause reddish sensations in us (a disposition to ‘appear red’, as Evans unfortunately puts it). Thus, the familiar ‘secondary‐quality’ theory of colours as dispositions or powers is established. Once the natural‐sign theory is in place, the secondary‐quality theory is not far behind. However, the natural‐sign theory is mistaken. (p. 278)

One difficulty is the assumption of special epistemic access to the ‘effect’, without which the natural‐sign theory would not get off the ground. And that, although it might be true, is unobvious and needs arguing for. (Here of course the spatial metaphor is pernicious, encouraging us to think that sensations are particularly accessible because they are ‘in’ the mind.) But the decisive defect is this. The natural‐sign theory cannot accommodate the plain fact that objects look coloured. Imagine that someone is looking at a tomato and sees that it is red. If we apply the basic outline of the natural‐sign theory to the perception of the tomato's colour, what is going on? First, a property of the tomato causes a certain effect in the perceiver: a reddish sensation. Second, she becomes aware that this sensation is reddish. Third, she forms the belief that the tomato has the power to cause reddish sensations (i.e. she believes that the tomato is red). End of story. Of course, the tomato will look red to the perceiver. The natural‐sign theorist can say that this simply amounts to the fact that the perceiver believes that the tomato is red and has a reddish sensation. But now imagine that our perceiver does not in fact believe that the tomato is red; she suspects, say, that the lighting conditions are abnormal. The tomato will still look red to her. And this cannot be accommodated by the natural‐sign theory. According to it, the perceiver in this situation is having a reddish sensation, is aware that her sensation is reddish, and does not believe that the tomato is red. It is not very plausible that the tomato's looking or appearing red can be reconstructed from such meagre materials. Adding that the perceiver has some sort of tendency or disposition to believe that the tomato is red does not help much. If appearances are analysed partly in terms of dispositions to believe then there are no causal explanations of the latter in terms of the former. But, intuitively, there are such explanations: a perceiver might be disposed to believe that the tomato is red because it looks red.6

Page 11 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities The inadequacy of the dispositional suggestion can be shown more convincingly by returning to Wittgenstein's pain patches. Notice that we sometimes do use ‘painful’ rather like the way ‘pain’ is used in Wittgenstein's imagined situation, as when we speak of painful nettles (or painful parts/areas of nettles). Suppose that someone is in pain, is touching a nettle, and does not believe that the nettle is painful. (She takes her pain to be caused by a bee sting, and is generally ignorant about nettles.) Further suppose, as may well be the case, that she has some suppressed inclination to believe that the nettle is painful: she would have believed this had she not believed that she had been stung by a bee. Despite having such a disposition to believe, the nettle will not appear painful to her, as a tomato appears red: pain is felt in the skin, but never on a nettle. There are other routes to the secondary‐quality theory, but they are considerably less direct. Contemporary proponents of one or another sophisticated variant of the secondary‐quality theory reject the natural‐sign theory, at least in its full Reidian (p. 279) dress, but the assumption that there are sensory (or sensational) qualities is often crucial to their arguments (see, for instance, Peacocke 1983: ch. 2, 1984; McLaughlin 2003).

15.6 Summary Historically there has been a persistent tendency to identify sensible qualities with sensational qualities or sensory qualities: to take the striking quality of a tomato to be a quality of one's experience, or a quality of a sense‐datum. Once the three kinds of quality are separated, it is not so clear that there are any sensory or sensational qualities. And if there aren't, then a lot of the motivation for secondary‐quality theories of sensible qualities drains away. More threatens to be thrown out with the bathwater, since the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness arguably presupposes that there are sensory qualities.7 The issue is one of the major fault lines in contemporary philosophy of mind. Introspection is an unlikely way of making progress. A more promising method is to proceed on the assumption that sensory and sensational qualities are a myth, and see how quickly—or whether—one runs into sand.

References Bennett, J. (1988), Events and Their Names (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett). Block, N. (1990), ‘Inverted Earth’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 53–79. Boring, E. G. (1933), The Physical Dimensions of Consciousness (New York: Century). Brown, D. H. (2006), ‘On the Dual Referent Approach to Colour Theory’, Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 96–113.

Page 12 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities Byrne, A. (2006), ‘Color and the Mind–Body Problem’, Dialectica, 60: 223–44. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Clark, A. (1993), Sensory Qualities (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2000), A Theory of Sentience (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Evans, G. (1980), ‘Things Without the Mind—A Commentary upon Chapter Two of Strawson's Individuals, in Z. van Straaten (ed.), Philosophical Subjects (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 76–117; repr. in Evans, Collected Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), 249–90, (pp. refs. in the text are to the reprint). —— (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Gibson, J. J. (1966), The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems (Boston, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin). Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Hayek, F. A. (1952), The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). (p. 280)

Hinton, J. M. (1973), Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Hume, D. (1739–40/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby‐Bigge, rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). Jackson, F. (1977), Perception (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Lycan, W. (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). McLaughlin, B. (2003), ‘The Place of Colour in Nature’, in R. Mausfeld and D. Heyer (eds.), Colour Perception: Mind and the Physical World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475–502). Moore, G. E. (1903), ‘The Refutation of Idealism’, Mind, 12: 433–53. —— (1942), ‘A Reply to My Critics’, in P. Schillp (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (Chicago, Ill.: Northwestern University Press), 535–677. —— (1953), Some Main Problems of Philosophy (London: Allen & Unwin).

Page 13 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities Peacocke, C. (1983), Sense and Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1984), ‘Colour Concepts and Colour Experience’, Synthese, 58: 365–82. Planck, M. (1925), A Survey of Physics (New York: Dutton). Reid, T. (1764/1970), An Inquiry into the Human Mind (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). Rosenthal, D. (1999), ‘The Colors and Shapes of Visual Experiences’, in D. Fisette (ed.), Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 95–118. Russell, B. (1912/80), The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Smart, J. J. C. (1959), ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, Philosophical Review, 68: 141–56. Stuart, M. (2003), ‘Locke's Colours’, Philosophical Review, 112: 57–96. Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Color and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell).

Notes: (1) One notable argument for contingency is presented in Block (1990). It should be emphasized that Clark's views on sensory qualities are generally quite different from Levine's (see Clark 2000: 22, 35–8). (2) For arguments in support of the ambiguity thesis see Rosenthal (1999) and Brown (2006). Reid, who was an ambiguity theorist for ‘smell’ (1764/1970: 39), drew the line at colour terms (1764/1970: 101–2); see also Section 15.4 below and Clark (2000: 1–2). (3) Of course, traditionally sense‐data were taken to be either coloured items or else the colours themselves (see Moore 1953: 28–40; Jackson 1977). (4) For criticism see Tye (2000: ch. 4). It should be noted that Peacocke's ‘primed’ notation is not quite as simple as our simplified variant of it. ‘Blue′,’ as explained above, expresses a property of a sense‐datum. However, Peacocke introduces primed expressions as expressing relations between experiences and regions of an ‘imagined interposed plane’ perpendicular to the line of sight (1983: 20). Later, though, Peacocke speaks freely of ‘red regions of the visual field’ (1983: ch. 2; see also Peacocke 1984), where a ‘region of the visual field’ appears to be very much like a sense‐datum. (5) The truth may be a confused amalgam of both views: sometimes we think of pains as intentional objects (‘the pain is in my wrist’) and sometimes as experiences (‘pain is a feeling’) (see Harman 1990: 40).

Page 14 of 15

Sensory Qualities, Sensible Qualities, Sensational Qualities (6) Since Evans basically makes this point elsewhere (1982: 123–4), the interpretation of his argument in the text should be treated with some caution. (7) For the hard problem see Chalmers (1996). For an argument that the hard problem vanishes if there are no sensory qualities see Byrne (2006).

Alex Byrne

Alex Byrne is Professor of Philosophy, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

Page 15 of 15

The Explanatory Gap

Oxford Handbooks Online The Explanatory Gap   Joseph Levine The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0017

Abstract and Keywords This article outlines the strategy for reconciling materialism and the explanatory gap. As one might imagine, there are a number of complex issues that must be sorted out concerning the alleged special nature of phenomenal concepts, and their alleged incommensurability with non-phenomenal concepts, before one can determine whether or not the strategy works in the end. In particular, it is unclear whether materialists can deliver an explanation of the special cognitive access afforded by phenomenal concepts which is itself consistent with its precepts. Keywords: materialism, explanatory gap, phenomenal concepts, non-phenomenal concepts, cognitive access

16.1 THE

term ‘explanatory gap’ was first introduced in Levine (1983), in the context of a

discussion of Kripke's argument (1980) against the mind–body identity thesis. Since then the discussion surrounding it has developed beyond the context of Kripke's argument. Along with notions like ‘the hard problem’ (Chalmers 1996) and Nagel's worries about what it's like to be a bat (1974), the idea that there exists an explanatory gap expresses the deep puzzle concerning the place of conscious experience in a material world. Materialism, or physicalism (I will use the two terms interchangeably), is the thesis that the physical facts metaphysically determine, or constitute, all the facts. Whatever happens in the world is ultimately a matter of how certain physical objects and properties are distributed in space–time. It is of course a notoriously difficult matter to specify precisely what this means, but, despite the growing literature on this controversy, most

Page 1 of 13

The Explanatory Gap philosophers have a clear enough idea of what physicalism means that they take a stand pro or con regarding it. For our purposes we'll leave the specification of physicalism fairly rough, since nothing of substance regarding the nature of consciousness will turn on making it precise. With respect to conscious experience, then, physicalist doctrine comes down to this. If you take a physical object like a brain, composed of cells standing in various physical relations to each other and instantiating various electrochemical properties, then you have all it takes for there to be conscious experience. Conscious experience just is nothing over and above these cells interacting in their various physical (p. 282) ways. Sure, our descriptions of conscious experience employ a different, conceptually independent vocabulary, but what they describe are the very same phenomena as the descriptions employed by neuroscientists. Before we get to what's puzzling about this it's worth asking why we should believe it in the first place. Why has physicalism become the dominant (though by no means universal) position in the philosophy of mind? Despite its large‐scale acceptance, probably the reasons offered by many philosophers who adhere to the doctrine would differ. Still, one consideration seems to turn up consistently: the problem of causal interaction. We know that purely physical, non‐mental events can cause conscious experiences and that conscious experiences can cause purely physical, non‐mental events. Light bouncing off objects in my vicinity and hitting my retina causes me to have certain visual experiences, and my having those visual experiences causally contributes to my arm's extending and grasping an object in my vicinity. We know that the relevant brain processes intervening between stimulus and response in this case are causally responsible for the reaction, so if conscious experience is also playing a role, it had better be somehow constituted by at least some of these brain processes. Of course, the argument needs refining, but that's the main idea. So what's puzzling about this? Well, simply put, it's difficult to see how we can actually explain the features of our conscious experience by appealing to the physical properties of the brain processes that allegedly constitute it. This of course requires some elaboration. So consider a typical conscious sensory experience, such as seeing a red rose in daylight. There is something it is like to have such a visual experience, one component of which is the particular way the rose's colour appears. This is a feature of experience with which one is immediately acquainted. By ‘immediately acquainted’ here I don't intend anything more than that it is not something we have to conduct any sort of investigation or inference to determine. We just are aware of it in seeing the rose. Every sighted person knows what I'm talking about here. So now let's consider for the moment just this one feature of the experience, the precise colour the rose appears to have. Of course, we seem to be aware of a feature of the rose, and one can ask what is responsible for this feature, what explains its colour. But right now we want to focus not on features of the rose, but on features of the experience. Seeing the rose as having that precise shade of red, with that precise brightness and Page 2 of 13

The Explanatory Gap saturation, constitutes a property of the experience itself. If this experience is indeed constituted by certain neural processes taking place in certain locations of the brain, then it ought to be possible to explain why the experience is as it is—that the rose looks to us just the way it does—by appealing to the underlying neurological phenomena. We ought to be able to say something like this: You see, since these neurons are firing in this way, that's why the rose looks reddish in this particular way, as opposed to greenish, say, or even no way at all. But once we put it that way, we see immediately that it doesn't really work. After all, what could there be about the firing rates and connectivity of a bunch of neurons that explains why we're having this particular reddish type of experience? This chasm between what is (p. 283) going on at the neural level and what we are acquainted with in our experience is the explanatory gap.

Page 3 of 13

The Explanatory Gap

16.2 While the foregoing gives the basic idea, there are various ways to elaborate the notion of the explanatory gap, and connect it with other aspects of the mind–body problem. One particularly important connection is that between the explanatory gap and the traditional conceivability argument against physicalism. The conceivability argument—best known from Descartes's discussion, but revived recently by Kripke (1980) and Chalmers (1996)— goes like this. It certainly seems possible—or, as we say, it's conceivable—that there be a brain functioning like ours, and yet there be no conscious experience associated with it. Put another way, there might be nothing it's like to be that brain. Of course, one has to understand what's meant by ‘possible’ and ‘conceivable’ here in a particular way, otherwise this claim will not seem so plausible. Admittedly, given what we know of the role played by the brain in our mental life, it's not like we think in any practical sense there really is any possibility that there could be a brain that is in a state just like mine right now but which has no conscious experience going on in it. However, the sense of ‘conceivability’ at issue here doesn't demand that level of likelihood. Rather, by saying that it's conceivable that there be a brain in a state just like mine but there's nothing it's like to be that brain (or to have one's brain in that state) all we intend is that there is no logical contradiction or conceptual incoherence involved in the supposition. That this standard is met can be seen from the fact that it took an empirical discovery to determine that we think and experience with our brains, and not our hearts, say, or even our immaterial souls. Suppose, at least for the moment, we grant this conceivability premise. The next step in the argument is the claim that identity entails a kind of logical necessity. The idea is this. If we say one thing is identical to another, what we've asserted is not really (despite the term ‘another’) that two things stand in an identity relation—after all, what would that even mean?—but rather that there is just one thing there. Now take any object and ask: Could it possibly have been something other than it is? Not, mind you, ‘Could it have had different properties than it has?’ but, ‘Could it have been a different object than the one it in fact is?’. Well, no, it is what it is, and the idea that it, that very thing, could have been something else, doesn't really make sense. For then it wouldn't have been it, after all, would it? Now, let's take the basic claim of physicalism, that the mind is the brain, or that certain mental processes are identical to certain physical processes in the brain. This certainly sounds like an identity claim. If it is, then it expresses a logical necessity, in that it doesn't make sense—as per our discussion in the paragraph above—to (p. 284) claim that it's possible that the mind isn't the brain, or that this conscious experience isn't a brain process; that, again, would be like the possibility that something isn't itself, which is incoherent. (To be sure, we may have discovered the identity through empirical means, but that doesn't change the logical import of the identity claim once accepted.) But if we accept the initial conceivability premise, it seems that we are committed to just this Page 4 of 13

The Explanatory Gap possibility. The only way to maintain the conceivability premise and the logical necessity of identity, it seems, is to deny physicalism; deny that in fact the mind and brain, or conscious experience and certain brain processes, really are identical. Now physicalists have a standard reply to this argument (Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Levine 2001; Melnyk 2001). They point out that the conceivability premise doesn't establish that it is really possible for there to be brains without conscious experience, just that it's conceivable. It seems possible because we can't determine a priori that conscious experiences and brain processes are identical, and so we can imagine a world in which they aren't. But, in fact, if they are identical, then a world in which there's a brain like mine that isn't conscious is impossible. While this reply to the conceivability argument has not gone unchallenged (Kripke 1980; Jackson 1993; Chalmers 1996), it has gained wide acceptance. The problem for physicalists is that even if we accept this reply, one can still use the conceivability premise to push the explanatory gap. The problem is this. Why, after all, is it conceivable that there could be a brain in a state just like mine but unconscious, or, more precisely, such that there is nothing it's like to be this brain? Contrast this situation with the following. Suppose I know a brain is in a state just like mine and the laws of physics and chemistry are working as usual. Is it conceivable that this brain shouldn't cause the normal behavioural effects that my brain in fact causes? Well, if these very neurons are firing, and the laws of physics and chemistry are obeyed, then these other neurons will fire, which will cause these other neurons downstream to fire, which will eventually cause the relevant muscles in my limbs to contract, and my body will move as expected. Without an interruption in natural law, I can't even conceive how this effect could be stopped. However, I still can conceive of all this going on without there being anything it's like for the creature whose brain it is. What's the difference? One might suggest the following. When it comes to the connection between the brain's state and its behavioural, or motoric, effects, we understand how the effect is brought about. Once we can explain something, it is no longer conceivable that it shouldn't be that way. After all, explaining why something happens, or is the way it is, by appeal to certain facts is a matter of showing why it had to be that way and not some other (relevant) way, given those facts. So now consider again the case of the brain without consciousness. According to the argument, the reason that this situation is conceivable is that we don't understand how the conscious experience is a result of, or constituted by, the relevant brain process. If we knew why these very neurons firing the way they do amounted to conscious experience, then we wouldn't still find it conceivable that a brain could occupy this state and yet lack the conscious experience. The fact that this situation is still conceivable is a symptom of our lack of the requisite explanation; it's a symptom of the explanatory gap.

Page 5 of 13

The Explanatory Gap

(p. 285)

16.3

I've been talking so far as if physicalism involved a straightforward identity claim between conscious experiences and brain processes. However, most materialists are functionalists (see Putnam 1991), which means that they identify mental states not with brain states per se, but rather with more abstract, ‘higher‐order’ states of the brain. That is, it is assumed that there are certain formal, or more abstract, properties that brains implement, or ‘realize’, and any physical device, whatever it's made out of, if it implemented these same abstract, functional states would also be conscious. There is still a necessary relation posited between brain states and conscious states, but only in one direction, as it were. That is, physicalists who are functionalists will claim that one can be conscious and still not have a brain like ours—since any physical device that realizes the relevant functional states will be conscious—however, any creature with a brain like ours will necessarily be conscious. But now we face another problem, one that also can be seen as a symptom of the explanatory gap. Suppose we arrange a sequence of creatures starting with ourselves and ordering them in terms of the degree of difference from human neurophysiology and functional organization. Functionalists are already committed to the idea that creatures physically different from us can be mentally, even consciously, like us nevertheless. But not only are physical differences allowed, it's clear that we can't demand complete and exact functional identity either. After all, there are many levels of functional organization underlying human psychological capacities, each implementing the level above it, and bottoming out with the neural mechanisms that implement the entire hierarchy. There is also an enormous range of psychological capacities that interact with each other, some of which can differ from creature to creature while others stay the same. So assuming we have some sequence of creatures with increasing difference from normal humans, at which point, even roughly, do we say that the conscious experiences are no longer similar to our own? What can give us even a clue how to answer this question? To make the problem a little more concrete, suppose we create an intelligent robot, like Data on Star Trek, and also meet an intelligent alien. We now ask: When they look at a red rose, are they seeing it the same way we are? Is their visual experience qualitatively like ours, or each other's? Suppose we know all there is to know about how they process colour information, and know that there are some differences from the way we do it and some similarities. What determines an answer to our question about what it's like for them? If we had an explanation of what it's like for us in terms of our functional or physical organization, then it seems we'd have a principle for determining what it's like for them. We'd look for those very features in them that explain the qualitative character in us. But it seems pretty clear that we don't have a clue how to answer this question. Why? The answer seems to be that since we don't really know why our particular functional and physical organization should be associated with just this type of

Page 6 of 13

The Explanatory Gap experience, we don't know which features to look (p. 286) for to determine what it's like for the aliens and robots. Our inability to project our experience on to other types of creatures is again a symptom of the explanatory gap.

16.4 The brain–mind connection, then, seems mysterious and inexplicable. By appeal to the physical properties and processes of the brain we seem able to explain how we process information, how our bodies react to the environment, and even—on analogy with computers—how we reason. But why any of these processes should give rise to consciousness, that there should be something it's like for creatures who have these processes going on inside them, this seems mysterious to us. There are two standard ways for a materialist to respond to this challenge. On the one hand, some materialists claim to have theories that actually bridge the gap. On the other hand, other materialists admit that the gap is unbridgeable, but argue that there is a good reason the gap is so persistent, and once we understand why we will see that it poses no threat to materialism. As mentioned above, most materialist theories embrace some form of functionalism, which is the idea that what constitutes a mental state is not the kind of physical process involved but a more abstract feature of its causal role: the kinds of state that cause it and the kinds it causes in turn. One version of this view, what we might call straight functionalism, just identifies mental states with causal roles. That is, we see the mind as a system of interacting states, and any physical system that meets the relevant description counts as conscious. Straight functionalism itself breaks down into two types, analytic functionalism and psycho‐functionalism, which differ in how they determine the relevant description of the system. Analytic functionalism (Lewis 1980) says that associated with each mental concept—such as ‘pain’ and ‘visual experience of red’—is a set of platitudes concerning the kinds of stimuli that cause it, the kind of behaviour it causes, and the other mental states with which it interacts. So, on this view, to be in pain is just to be in whatever physical state it is that normally results from damage to the body, causes avoidance behaviour, and causes difficulty in concentrating and a strong desire to stop it. While this is oversimplified, it gives the general idea. Psycho‐functionalism is the view that the proper description of pain's (or any other mental state's) functional role will result from scientific investigation into its nature. Just as we discovered empirically that water is H2O, so too we will discover that pain is such‐and‐such a functional role. Neither of these positions really bridges the explanatory gap. Analytic functionalism must explain why, if our concept of a conscious experience is captured by the relevant description of a functional role, it is still conceivable that some physical systems satisfy that role and yet fail to be conscious. The problem for psycho‐functionalism is that it's Page 7 of 13

The Explanatory Gap hard to see how scientific investigation alone, without some conceptual breakthrough, could support the claim that conscious experiences were (p. 287) identical to specific functional states. The analogy—or rather, disanalogy—with the case of water is telling. Why, after all, do we take water to be identical to H2O? What have we discovered that supports this identification? Well, we have taken samples of water, broken them down chemically, and discovered H2O molecules. What's more, the chemical properties of H2O explain the superficial properties of water by which we normally identify it, such as its liquidity at room temperature, its transparency, and the like. If it were not for this explanatory structure, it would be unclear why we would accept the claim that water is H2O. Now contrast the situation with pain, say, and whatever detailed causal/functional role we find it plays. The psycho‐functionalist wants to claim that pain should be identified with this causal role, but on what basis? After all, we normally identify pain in our own experience by how it feels. Can we explain this feeling by appeal to the causal role? If we could, then it would no longer be conceivable that a creature could occupy a state with this causal role and yet not really feel pain, but this does seem to be conceivable. In fact, the order of explanation seems quite the reverse. Pain seems to be the kind of state we want to avoid because of the way it feels! It's very unclear, then, what could be discovered from a third‐person perspective that would justify the claim that that causal role is what pain really is, not just a role pain in fact plays. In other words, we can't bridge the explanatory gap by appeal to a functionalist identity thesis. On the contrary, we won't be in a position to accept any functionalist identity thesis until we bridge the gap. There are other functionalist views that provide a more specific account of what constitutes a conscious state than ‘straight functionalism’. Two in particular are the higher‐order‐mental‐state view (Lycan 1996; Rosenthal 1997) and representationalism (Dretske 1995; Tye 1995; Byrne 2001). On the higher‐order‐mental‐state view, a state is conscious when one is conscious of it, the point being that consciousness is really a relation between a subject and one of her mental states, not an intrinsic property of a single state. The way a subject becomes conscious of one of her states is that she occupies yet another mental state that has the first state as its content—that ‘says’, as it were, that she is in the first‐order state. According to representationalism, the precise character of a conscious experience is determined by which properties of the environment presented to the senses the state is representing. To experience redly, as it were, is just to represent the property of being red in one's visual system. As one can see from the descriptions just presented, the two views are not really competitors, since each attempts to address a different aspect of conscious experience. The higher‐order view provides an analysis of what it is for a mental state to be conscious, as opposed to unconscious. The conscious mental states, on this view, are those that are monitored, or detected by other mental states. But this theory doesn't say why a particular conscious experience is like this—say, the way my current visual Page 8 of 13

The Explanatory Gap sensation of a ripe tomato is for me—as opposed to some other way. The particular experiential content is not explained by this theory; it just attempts to say what it is for there to be any experiential content at all. Representationalism, on the other hand, while not addressing the general question of what makes a state conscious at (p. 288) all, does try to say why a conscious state is like what it's like. It's like this rather than that because this is what it represents, not that. So together one might see the higher‐order view and representationalism as constituting a comprehensive theory of conscious experience (see Lycan 1996 for just such a combination). Does this combination serve to bridge the explanatory gap? It's hard to say until one knows what the account of representation is. Notice that both views rely crucially on the idea that a mental state is representing something: the higher‐order view has one mental state representing another, and representationalism has the first‐order state representing sensible properties of external objects. It's possible to build consciousness into the representation relation in such a way that to really represent is to be conscious of what one is representing, but then the account is circular. We still need to know how a purely physical system can represent in this way. On the other hand, if one's theory of representation follows recent causal/informational accounts (Fodor 1990; Dretske 1995), then, while there isn't any mystery how a purely physical device could satisfy such an account, it isn't clear how this bridges the explanatory gap. The very same considerations described above with respect to straight functionalism attend this more refined theory as well. This persistence of the intuition of an arbitrary or brute connection between the states posited by the various theories of consciousness and one's inner, first‐person conception of conscious experience lends considerable support to the second strategy. That is, rather than attempt to bridge the gap, materialists who follow the second strategy try to show that there is something special about our first‐person access to our experience that makes the existence of an explanatory gap inevitable. Whether or not this feature of first‐person access is itself explicable in materialist terms is the challenge.

16.5 A number of philosophers have attempted to reconcile the existence of the explanatory gap with materialism (Loar 1997; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Tye 2000; for critiques see Levine 2001, 2007; Chalmers 2007). Though the details of their various proposals differ in important ways, we'll sketch the response in a broad manner here. The basic idea is to locate the problem in the special nature of one's first‐person access to one's own conscious experiences. That is, there is a way of thinking of one's conscious experience that is only available to the subject of the experience, and which is sufficiently different in crucial respects from third‐person, theoretical ways of thinking of it that one can't

Page 9 of 13

The Explanatory Gap integrate the two in the way necessary for an understanding of how what the latter describes could be the same phenomenon as what the former describes. Let's revisit the contrast between the theoretical identification of water with H2O and pain with some neurological state. (The same considerations apply to functional identity theses.) As we noted above, the identification of water with H2O is justified largely by the explanatory work it does. There are these properties of water, such as its (p. 289) freezing and boiling temperatures, which can be explained by appeal to its chemical structure (and general laws of physics and chemistry). Similarly, if our only concept of pain had to do with its causes, behavioural manifestations, and interaction with other internal states we would have no problem identifying it with the relevant neurological state. We could say why certain stimuli led to this state, which in turn led to the typical behavioural responses to pain. Notice that if we ourselves had never experienced pain, and our only cognitive access to it was through our observations of others, the explanatory account just outlined would appear quite adequate; there would be no gap. Our problem is that we know what it's like to have pain, we know what it feels like, from the ‘inside’. What's more, it seems to be that what we find from this internal perspective is precisely the aspect of pain that appears to elude the explanatory reach of neuroscience. If we have powerful reasons to think that materialism about pain (and all other conscious experiences) must be true, and it is what we find in the first‐person perspective that seems to be creating the obstacle to materialism's acceptance, then it's reasonable to see if the blame can be placed not on materialism itself, but on the peculiar nature of the first‐person perspective. A common approach along these lines is to introduce the notion of a ‘phenomenal concept’ (Loar 1997), a concept of phenomenal properties (the qualitative features of conscious experience) that is formed from the first‐person perspective. For instance, take a visual experience of red. There is something specific that it is like to see red. I form a concept of what it's like merely by experiencing it. This way of thinking of what it's like to see red is not available, say, to a blind person, though of course they can conceptualize there being a kind of experience that humans normally have when seeing a ripe tomato. But the phenomenal concept of what it's like to see red is available only to those who have had the experience. The reconciliation of materialism with the explanatory gap then proceeds as follows. Except for the concepts of conscious experiences possessed by the subject herself, all of a cognitive subject's concepts are of the non‐phenomenal sort. So when she forms functional and physical concepts to explain human behaviour and information processing, these are non‐phenomenal concepts. The explanatory gap exists precisely because there is a kind of ‘architectural’ gap within the human psyche between phenomenal and non‐ phenomenal concepts. To explain conscious experiences in the way that would bridge the explanatory gap would require taking as explanatory premises—the explanans— propositions framed with non‐phenomenal concepts and joining them with an explanatory conclusion—the explanandum—framed with phenomenal concepts. However, our minds Page 10 of 13

The Explanatory Gap are just not capable of integrating these two radically different kinds of concept in a way that would result in a satisfying explanation. Hence, it always seems intelligible to us that what is described by the phenomenal concepts should turn out to be distinct from what is described by the non‐phenomenal concepts. This fact doesn't show that they aren't identical, and that, as far as the metaphysics goes, neurological features don't explain conscious features. Rather, it's just a sad fact about us that we aren't (p. 290) capable of appreciating this connection between neurological states and conscious experiences. We are, as it were, just wired the wrong way to bridge the gap. The strategy for reconciling materialism and the explanatory gap just outlined represents a powerful weapon in the arsenal of materialism. As one might imagine, there are a number of complex issues that must be sorted out concerning the alleged special nature of phenomenal concepts, and their alleged incommensurability with non‐phenomenal concepts, before one can determine whether or not the strategy works in the end. In particular, it is unclear whether materialists can deliver an explanation of the special cognitive access afforded by phenomenal concepts which is itself consistent with its precepts. Some have argued that a special mental relation like ‘acquaintance’ (Russell 1912) that is itself inexplicable in materialist terms would have to be posited, and thus the materialist may have just substituted one gap for another (Chalmers 2007; Levine 2007). Whether or not this is so is the topic of much current research (Kriegel 2006; Alter and Walter 2007).

References Alter, T., and Walter, S. (2007) (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Byrne, A. (2001), ‘Intentionalism Defended’, Philosophical Review, 110; 199–240. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2007), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 167–94. Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Fodor, J. A. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Hill, C. S., and McLaughlin, B. (1999), ‘There are Fewer Things in Reality than are Dreamt of in Chalmers' Philosophy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59: 445– 54. Jackson, F. (1993), Armchair Metaphysics, in J. O'Leary‐Hawthorne and M. Michael (eds.), Philosophy in Mind (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 23–42. Page 11 of 13

The Explanatory Gap Kriegel, U. (2006) (ed.), Consciousness and Self‐Reference (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Levine, J. (1983), ‘Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 354–61. —— (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2007), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Materialist Constraint’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 145–66. Lewis, D. (1980), ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’, in N. Block (ed.), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, i (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 216–22. Loar, B. (1997), ‘Phenomenal States’, in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 597– 616. Lycan, W. (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Melnyk, A. (2001), ‘Physicalism Unfalsified: Chalmers' Inconclusive Conceivability Argument’, in C. Gillett and B. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 331–49. (p. 291)

Nagel, T. (1974), What is it Like to Be a Bat? Philosophical Review, 83; 435–50.

Putnam, H. (1991), ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in D. M. Rosenthal (ed.), The Nature of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 197–203. Rosenthal, D. (1997), ‘A Theory of Consciousness’, in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 729–53. Russell, B. (1912), The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2000), Consciousness, Color and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Joseph Levine

Joseph Levine is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

Page 12 of 13

Phenomenal Concepts

Oxford Handbooks Online Phenomenal Concepts   Katalin Balog The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0018

Abstract and Keywords This article is about the special, subjective concepts we apply to experience. These are called ‘phenomenal concepts’ (PCs) and they are of special interest in a number of ways. First, they refer to phenomenal experiences, and the qualitative character of those experiences whose metaphysical status is hotly debated. Conscious experiences strike many philosophers as philosophically problematic and difficult to accommodate within a physicalistic metaphysics. Second, PCs are widely thought to be special and unique among concepts. The sense that there is something special about PCs is very closely tied up with features of the epistemic access they afford to qualia. Keywords: phenomenal concepts, phenomenal experiences, qualitative character, metaphysical status, qualia, epistemic access

Page 1 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts

17.1 Introduction THIS

chapter is about the special, subjective concepts we apply to experience. These are

called ‘phenomenal concepts’ (PCs) and they are of special interest in a number of ways. First, they refer to phenomenal experiences, and the qualitative character1 of those experiences whose metaphysical status is hotly debated. Conscious experiences strike many philosophers as philosophically problematic and difficult to accommodate within a physicalistic metaphysics. Second, PCs are widely thought to be special and unique among concepts.2 The sense that there is something special about PCs is very closely tied up with features of the epistemic access they afford to qualia. When we deploy phenomenal concepts introspectively for some phenomenally conscious experience as it occurs, we are said to be acquainted 3 with our own conscious experiences. While philosophers have understood ‘acquaintance’ in various ways, it is generally taken to be a (p. 293) unique epistemological relation that relates a person to her own mental states directly, incorrigibly, and, according to some, in a way that reveals the essence of these mental states. Such a relation has struck many philosophers as deeply puzzling. Accounts of PCs either have to explain the acquaintance relation, or acquaintance with our phenomenal experiences has to be denied. The way different accounts of PCs handle these issues will be the main topic of this chapter. PCs have received much attention in recent philosophy of mind mainly because they figure in arguments for dualism and in physicalist responses to these arguments.4 In Section 17.4 I will briefly explain how features of our epistemic relation to phenomenal consciousness provide the ground for dualist arguments. In Sections 17.5 and 17.6 I will discuss some recent accounts of PCs and their role in arguments over physicalism/ dualism. But first, in Section 17.2 I will clarify some background assumptions that it is important to put on the table, and in Section 17.3 I will elaborate on the epistemic and semantic constraints on a satisfactory account of PCs.

17.2 Some Background 17.2.1 Qualia Realism Throughout the chapter I will assume realism about qualia. I use ‘qualia’ in a minimalist sense; that is, the sense of there being something it is like to undergo an experience, something one can normally introspect; for example, the feeling of my fingers flexing that (partly) characterizes my present bodily sensation. All accounts of phenomenal experience agree that there are qualia in this sense, though they might disagree on what Page 2 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts exactly it means to introspect qualia.5 Philosophers who think for (p. 294) whatever reason that there are no qualia might still hold that there are concepts that work much like PCs except that they fail to refer at all.6

17.2.2 Basic and Non‐Basic Applications of PCs Some accounts of PCs explain the unique epistemic role of PCs by the way they relate to their referent in a uniquely intimate way. The idea is that in their basic uses we apply PCs to our experiences directly as they occur, merely on the basis of having the experience. One can object to this by observing that the very same PCs can also be applied in the absence of the phenomenal experiences they refer to, for example when we apply them to other people or our own past experiences, and in these cases it is not plausible to say that the application of the concept is direct or that there is a special, unique relationship between the concept and its referent. Accordingly, some philosophers locate the uniqueness of PCs instead in the uniqueness of the properties they refer to, in the luminosity and transparence7 of qualia themselves. Those who maintain that there is something unique about the relationship between PCs and their referents emphasize the difference between basic applications of PCs (closely tied to first‐person experience itself) and other applications (not so tied), and they count those latter applications as derivative of, and in some important respect different from, the basic ones.8 Here is a way to explicate the difference between basic and derivative applications of PCs. We employ PCs in their basic applications when attending to and thinking about conscious experiences and their phenomenal qualities from the first‐person perspective (i.e. subjectively). ‘First‐person perspective’ here means that in the basic applications of PCs their reference is (or is exemplified) in the mind of the thinker, and this fact is crucial from the point of view of the application of the concept. In a basic application of a PC a person is aware, for example, that her finger tingles in a particular way and thinks to herself Here it goes again.9 This thought (though not its public‐language expression) involves a PC and the PC itself is intimately connected to the very itchy kind of experience that it is referring to.10 In the case of (p. 295) basic applications of PCs the token concept and its reference are both occurrences in the person's mind. This is different from other kinds of concepts (and also from the non‐basic applications of PCs). For example, one can think the descriptive concept ‘the present king of France’ without— absurdly—there being any king in one's mind or, for that matter, anywhere at all. But in a basic application of a PC the reference is in the thinker's mind. In non‐basic applications of PCs we are thinking from the first‐person perspective (i.e. subjectively) only in a derivative sense, without there necessarily occurring exemplars of that qualia. These applications are subjective only via their connections to basic applications of PCs. Non‐basic applications of PCs can refer both to a person's own experiences and to those of other people and creatures.11 For example, when Mary thinks

Page 3 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts that she will later experience the taste of lemon or that Sam is currently experiencing this taste, she doesn't literally experience a lemony taste herself. What is the relation between basic and non‐basic applications of PCs? One suggestion is that a non‐basic application of a PC, as for example in Mary's thought I will soon experience the taste of lemon, requires some previous basic application of the concept to an instance of the type of phenomenal experience it refers to (i.e. the lemony taste); or at least it requires a previous instantiation of the experience itself. There are two ways to understand this requirement. One is as a claim about how we acquire PCs. The other is as a claim about necessary conditions for possessing PCs. The former seems correct as a (contingent) matter of fact, but the latter may be false. Here is an argument that it is false due to Dennett (2007). Suppose that Mary possesses the concept lemony taste, having previously tasted a lemon, but she is not now experiencing a lemony taste. Dennett imagines ‘Swamp Mary’, who comes into existence and who duplicates Mary's intrinsic physical (and, if there are such, non‐physical) properties. Swamp Mary doesn't share all of Mary's concepts but it seems very plausible that she shares Mary's phenomenal concept lemony taste. She can ‘recall’ a lemony taste, anticipate it, compare it with other tastes, and so on. Dennett says that she has the concept. But if so, the occurrences of previous instances of lemony taste 12 are not constitutive of possession of the concept lemony taste, and non‐basic applications of lemony taste are possible for a person even before she ever had a basic application of the concept. What makes ‘basic’ applications basic then, as opposed to the ‘non‐basic’ ones? It is clear that to possess a PC lemony taste it is necessary to be capable of recognizing an instance of lemony taste as falling under the concept; that is, to be able to produce a basic application of lemony taste. But this is too weak; the capacity in question is a trivial capacity of any normal human. There could be a person, let's call him ‘Joe’, who has never experienced a lemony taste, and so can't recall, compare, anticipate, etc. the taste —in short, doesn't have the concept lemony taste at all; nevertheless, he would also have this capacity. But there is a capacity Swamp Mary has that (p. 296) Joe doesn't, which arguably is constitutively necessary for possession of the concept lemony taste; namely, the capacity of recognizing lemony taste when she encounters it as the same taste she attributed to others on occasions when she didn't have the experience.13 This is why basic applications are basic; a concept can be a non‐basic application of a PC only if certain non‐trivial counterfactuals involving basic applications hold. This condition also explains the subjectivity of PCs.

17.2.3 Qualia and Representation Most (perhaps all) phenomenal experiences are representational. For example, a token of a visual quale blue represents a blue expanse or the sky or perhaps both. If qualia represent then it is plausible that they represent non‐conceptually. That is, they do not Page 4 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts have language‐like structure but rather are akin to pictures and represent in something along the lines of the way pictures, images, graphs, and other so‐called analogue representations represent. Exactly how analogue representations work is controversial.14 According to one view of qualia, qualia are not intrinsically representational. A way of thinking about this is to say that they are aspects of sensation and can occur in the absence of representational content.15 Some qualia‐realists, for example Loar (2003), hold that phenomenal states and their qualia are themselves representational, in the sense that there couldn't be non‐ representational qualia. According to his view, however, there is more to qualia than representational content; in other words, representational content doesn't exhaust all there is to it. Representationalists about phenomenal consciousness (e.g. Harman 1990; Tye 2002) go further and claim that the phenomenal quality of an experience can be accounted for entirely in terms of its representational features. Such accounts deny the qualophile's claim that phenomenal character goes beyond representation, but they are generally understood as being realists about phenomenal character.

Page 5 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts

17.2.4 Concepts: The Language‐of‐Thought Model Most of the recent discussion of phenomenal concepts presupposes the representational theory of mind (RTM). According to the RTM, beliefs, thoughts, intentions, and so on involve representations that refer, have truth‐conditions, and so on. For example, Mary's thought that Sam experiences a (p. 297) lemony taste refers to Sam and is true iff he experiences a lemony taste. The RTM says that concepts are constituents of thoughts. So Mary's thought is composed from the concepts Sam and experiences a lemony taste. Most of the contributors to the recent discussion also assume, as I will, the ‘language of thought’ (LOT) account of the representations involved in thinking, belief, intention, and so on.16 According to the LOT there is an internal mental language, Mentalese, and thinking, deciding, and so on are processes involving tokenings of expressions of this language.17 On the LOT account concepts are ‘words’ of Mentalese. Some concepts correspond to singular terms, some to predicates, and so on. Just as in the case of words, there are concepts (types) and tokens of these types. My concept of, for example, Jerry Fodor is a type—a mental word Fodor that is tokened on various occasions. Exactly how concepts should be individuated is controversial. Among the proposed determinants of a concept are its vehicle, reference, mode of presentation, and conceptual role. By ‘vehicle’ I mean features of the way the concept is realized in the brain. A concept's mode of presentation is the way it presents or purports to present its reference.18 For example, the perceptual concept that I am now tokening of my computer screen presents it in a particular way (as black on white with blue borders, as in front of me, etc.). A concept's conceptual role involves the class of causal and/or inferential relations among thoughts (and other Mentalese expressions) that contain the concept. For concepts in general, there is controversy concerning whether all, a special subclass, or none of a concept's conceptual role is individuative of the concept.19 But, as we will see, it is plausible that a PC does have a unique conceptual role. A concept's mode of presentation and its conceptual role are distinct but related. In the case of some concepts, for example the first‐person concept I, it is plausible that the unique way in which the concept presents the thinker to herself is completely determined by its conceptual role. Whether the modes of presentation of PCs are determined by their conceptual roles will be discussed below. In this framework PCs, being concepts, are particular kinds of words in Mentalese. This framework will allow us to raise the question of what (if anything) is special about PCs by discussing what is special about their vehicle, reference, mode of presentation, and conceptual role.

17.2.5 Phenomenal and Psychological Concepts

Page 6 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts It is important to distinguish PCs from what have been called ‘psychological concepts’.20 Psychological concepts characterize mental states functionally in terms (p. 298) of causal relations with stimuli, other states, and behaviour and are distinct from PCs.21 For example, the psychological concept itch* may be (simplistically) characterized as the state that is caused by tissue irritation and causes scratching.22 In contrast, the PC itch picks out a certain sensation (itch) directly, without the mediation of a functional or behavioural mode of presentation. A psychological concept is a third‐person concept in the sense that the mental state that it refers to does not play any direct role in the mental machinery associated with the concept nor does the concept contain any reference to the subject. Fifty years ago or so most philosophers of mind would have declared that there cannot be PCs. I have in mind the verificationist and behaviourist views that dominated philosophy of mind in the mid‐twentieth century and still linger in some places. Wittgenstein (1953), in his famous private language argument,23 argues that for a term (concept) to have meaning (or reference) it must be possible to intersubjectively check whether an application of that term is correct.24 The third‐person psychological concept of itch just mentioned is like this, since in principle anybody can check whether or not a person is in a state that satisfies the characteristic causal role. But PCs, if they exist, are not like that. This led him to the view that first‐person attributions of sensations don't possess truth‐ conditions but rather are used to express pain in something of the way an exclamation ‘ouch’ does. However, few philosophers now would accept this radical conclusion. Some hold (e.g. Chalmers 1996 and Ch. 18 below) that psychological and phenomenal concepts are so different (and different in such a way) that they cannot refer to the same property. Other philosophers, of a physicalist persuasion, think they might, even though they present their referent in very different ways.25

17.3 Desiderata for a Theory of Phenomenal Concepts (p. 299)

Here is a list of semantic/epistemic features that PCs have been held to have in relation to phenomenal consciousness. An obvious constraint on the adequacy of an account of PCs is that it either has to explain them or it has to explain them away; that is, show why claims about these features seem plausible even though nothing real corresponds to them. (a) Acquaintance. We know our conscious states not by inference but by immediate acquaintance which gives us direct, unmediated, substantial insight into their nature. (b) Asymmetric epistemology. We are directly aware of our own conscious states in ways no one else can be. As we have observed above, one can be aware of one's

Page 7 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts conscious states simply by attending to them; to be aware of others' conscious states one has to observe their behaviour. (c) Infallibility/incorrigibility intuition. We seem to be infallible about certain judgements involving certain phenomenal concepts—e.g. my judging ‘phenomenal red is occurring right now’. The reason we tend to believe this is that it doesn't seem as though any belief concerning objective matters of fact can coherently override or correct our own judgement about what we feel when it occurs simultaneously with the experience. (d) Transparency. When one turns one's attention to one's own conscious perceptual experience, one is aware of the features of the objects perceived. There is a stronger version of the transparency thesis advocated by representationalists.26 (e) Experience Thesis. Only subjects who have undergone or at least are currently undergoing the relevant phenomenal states can acquire the corresponding phenomenal concepts. (f) Fineness of grain. There is a fineness of grain in experience that cannot be captured by the phenomenal concepts possessed by the subject of experience; certainly not by concepts that can be applied and reapplied in thought. We can discriminate between millions of different shades of colour experiences, but we can only form at most a few dozen standing colour‐experience concepts. (g) Semantic stability. PCs refer to the same properties independently of the actual context; i.e. their extension can be determined independently of any empirical discoveries. In contrast, the reference of semantically unstable concepts (like e.g. water, which refers to the liquid, transparent, etc. stuff that the thinker is in contact with) is actual‐context dependent. (p. 300)

(h) The conceivability of zombies. A scenario in which zombies exist cannot be ruled out on a priori grounds. Zombies are creatures that are physically exactly like human beings—they move like us, apparently speak and behave intelligently—but they completely lack phenomenal experience. There is ‘nothing it's like’ to be them. Zombies are conceivable, since no amount of information couched in physical and causal terms is a priori logically sufficient for the application of a basic PC. Whatever a person may learn about the causal role or neurophysiological nature of what is going on in her (or anyone else's) brain (or any physically characterized facts) is obviously not a priori sufficient for her to judge that she is experiencing a particular qualia. In contrast, some philosophers claim, all other truths, for example the truth that there is water in the Danube, are a priori derivable from the full physical truth (Chalmers 1996).

Page 8 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts (i) The explanatory gap. A closely related issue is what Joe Levine ( 2001 : 76–80) calls the ‘explanatory gap’ between physical and phenomenal descriptions, i.e. between a physical description of a person who is having certain experiences, however detailed and informative, and a phenomenal description of those same experiences. No current accounts bridge the gap, and the gap appears to be in principle unbridgeable. The problem doesn't seem to be that we don't know enough of the functioning of neurons and their interconnections. We certainly will learn a lot more about all that in the future. One way to explicate the difference between the usual perspicuous reductive explanations we encounter in science and the putative cognitive or neurophysiological reductive explanations of phenomenal consciousness is that whereas the hypothesis that phenomenal consciousness is non‐physical will always seem comprehensible, the hypothesis that, for example, water is not H2O but some non‐physical property just doesn't seem intelligible. Many find (a)–(i) deeply mysterious. Some of these features present a challenge to any theorist of phenomenal concepts. However, they, and especially semantic stability, the conceivability of zombies, and the explanatory gap, are particularly worrisome if one is a physicalist, and so wants to show that both phenomenal experiences and our concepts of them are physical in nature.

17.4 Anti‐physicalist Arguments Though a number of different dualist arguments have been proposed in the last thirty years (Nagel 1974; Kripke 1980; Jackson 1982; Robinson 1993; Bealer 1994; Chalmers 1996 and Ch. 18 below; Nida‐Rümelin 2007; White 2007), all of them have to do with one of the epistemic/semantic features listed above. I summarize some of the main lines of argument below.27 (p. 301)

The conceivability of zombies. The conceivability of zombies, or some equivalent thesis, has been the key premise in so‐called conceivability arguments. A statement S is conceivable28 iff it can't be ruled out a priori. Accordingly, zombies are conceivable, since no phenomenal statement is a priori derivable from information couched in physical and causal terms. Some dualists (e.g. Chalmers in Ch. 18 below) claim that this sets phenomenal truths apart from all other truths; truths about water, or mountains, stars, or tables, are, on this view, a priori derivable from the basic physical truths. The other key premise of the argument is that if zombies are conceivable, they are possible. If, as follows, zombies are possible, then there are some truths that are not metaphysically necessitated by the complete physical truth about the world, and therefore physicalism is false.

Page 9 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts The explanatory gap. The gap argument starts from the premise that there is no perspicuous explanatory relation between a physical description of a person undergoing some experiences and a phenomenal description of those same experiences. The problem is related to the conceivability of zombies, but it can be stated without appealing to the notion of conceivability, or any thesis linking conceivability and possibility, and so has the advantage that it doesn't rely on any substantial assumptions about concepts and conceptual truths. It only relies on a contrast between the comprehensibility of the hypothesis that phenomenal consciousness is non‐physical and the incomprehensibility of corresponding hypotheses involving properties figuring in the special sciences; for example, heat, life, digestion, etc. The key premise of the gap argument is that if physicalism is true there can be no explanatory gap between true descriptions of a phenomenon and some physical description of the same phenomenon. But, the argument goes, since there is an explanatory gap between phenomenal descriptions and any neurophysiological description, physicalism is false. There is a physicalist reply to these arguments that is based on the idea that a zombie can meaningfully mimic these arguments and arrive at a false conclusion (Balog 1999). But this reply leaves the puzzling epistemic features the dualist arguments rely on unexplained. A stronger reply to the dualist arguments would be to show that these features can be explained physicalistically. Since (a)–(i) are all epistemic/semantic in nature, and our epistemic relation to phenomenal consciousness is mediated by PCs, it is plausible that (a)–(i) will be explicable by appeal to the nature of PCs. The insight that is at the core of what came to be called the ‘Phenomenal Concept Strategy’29 is that to account for the key epistemic/semantic features of PCs we do not need to invoke the (p. 302) nature of phenomenal consciousness itself; it is enough to invoke the special nature of PCs. To what extent this is possible is the key issue both from the point of view of theories of PCs and from the point of view of the ontology of mind. This is what we are going to discuss in the next two sections. But before that I would like to mention another type of physicalist response to the dualist arguments: analytic functionalism or analytic representationalism (see e.g. Lewis 1966; Jackson 2003). Analytic functionalism or representationalism is a doctrine about the meaning of phenomenal terms; it is the doctrine that such meanings can be analysed in functional or representational terms. Pain, for example, according to analytic functionalism, has a conceptual role that connects it (in the meaning‐constituting way) with complex concepts like typically caused by injury, typically causes avoidance behaviour, typically causes saying ‘ouch’, etc. Analytic functionalism or representationalism rebuts the conceivability arguments by denying the premise that zombies are conceivable.30 Anything that has an internal state that plays the appropriate causal roles/has such‐and‐such a representational profile (and zombies do have such states) is, by definition, in pain. Analytic functionalism/representationalism, of course, has to explain why zombies seem conceivable even though they are not.

Page 10 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts However, this view, just like the analytic behaviourism that is sometimes attributed to Wittgenstein, runs into problems with the first‐person applications of PCs. In our first‐ person—and usually considered basic—applications of phenomenal concepts functional role/representational profile is not even in play. We can apply phenomenal terms directly to the phenomenal states that we are currently aware of, without the mediation of any functional, representational, behavioural, or physical definition or physical criteria. Therefore, it doesn't seem that such criteria can constitute the meaning of phenomenal terms.31 Also, analytic functionalism or representationalism cannot account for many of the features on our list (a)–(i). Because of these problems, a majority of philosophers have taken a different approach.

17.5 The ‘Phenomenal Concept Strategy’ Most recent theories of phenomenal concepts are driven by a desire to provide an account of phenomenal concepts that explains features (a)–(i). Dualists appeal to (p. 303) non‐physical qualia whose very nature is to be present to the mind, to be objects of immediate awareness by acquaintance. They tend to think acquaintance is a primitive relation; or they attribute its special nature to the non‐physical nature of qualia themselves.32 They attempt to explain (a)–(i) by this special, non‐physical nature of qualia and acquaintance, and they maintain that the conceivability of zombies is explained by their possibility, and the explanatory gap is explained by an ontological gap. This approach has been criticized by physicalists as merely labelling a mystery, instead of making a serious attempt to deal with it. More to the point, there are also serious problems with dualist metaphysics, one of which is the problem of how a non‐physical property can causally engage the rest of the cognitive system. Physicalists, on the other hand, try to explain (a)–(i) in a manner compatible with physicalism. A satisfactory explanation would be one on which (a)–(i), far from posing a problem for the physicalist view, turned out to be features the physicalist would expect to arise in our relation to phenomenal consciousness. On this view, metaphysical dualism is false; however, there is a dualism of concepts: PCs are unlike other concepts in ways that have very significant ramifications for how we ordinarily think about the mind; specifically, they are responsible for our inclination to believe in dualism—even though dualism is false. The locus classicus for the Phenomenal Concept Strategy is Brian Loar's paper ‘Phenomenal States’ (1990/97).33 Loar suggested the idea that PCs are direct recognitional concepts.34 Abstracting from some of the details, what he seems to have in mind is that when a person is having a particular experience she can deploy a concept that refers directly to that experience. Loar also suggests that the mode of presentation of a PC involves the experience itself.

Page 11 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts We can understand the subsequent discussion of PCs as developing two different strands in Loar's original proposal. One kind of account elaborates on the idea that PCs refer directly,35 so it emphasizes the special conceptual role of PCs; the other tries also to make good Loar's suggestion that the mode of presentation of PCs in some way involves the experience itself. I am going to sketch the basic ideas underlying these theories in the rest of Section 17.5. (p. 304)

17.5.1 Direct‐Reference Accounts Those who focus on the directness of the reference of phenomenal concepts have proposed causal‐recognitional, demonstrative, and information‐theoretic accounts. (i) Causal‐recognitional account. Tye (2003), for example, claims that PCs are special recognitional concepts that refer directly. They have no associated reference‐fixing descriptions; their mode of presentation is empty, so to speak. According to Tye, PCs refer via the causal connection they have with their referents. On this account, a phenomenal concept C refers to a phenomenal quality Q via C's being the concept that is exercised in an introspective act of awareness by person P if, and only if, under normal conditions of introspection, Q is tokened in P's current experience and because Q is tokened. (Tye 2003: 7) But since someone could be wired to recognize another person's brain states (that happen to be phenomenal states), it is clear that to be a PC it is not enough to be a recognitional concept of a phenomenal state. Tye thinks that for the concept to be a PC it also has to have the right sort of functional role. This functioning, however, cannot be specified a priori in a way that eschews any phenomenal language.

(ii) Demonstrative account. A number of philosophers have suggested that PCs are a sort of demonstrative. On Perry's account (2001) PCs are demonstratives, equivalent to something like ‘this qualitative character’, where the demonstrative is guided by a perceptual state to its referent. Levin, on the other hand, suggests that PCs are type demonstratives without any mode of presentation at all. She thinks physicalists ‘should reject the claim that phenomenal concepts require some sort of “presence” of, or “acquaintance” with … the quality denoted, since this claim is backed only by the intuitions that they have already explained away’ (2007: 105).36 (iii) Information‐theoretic account. Aydede and Güzeldere (2005) have proposed an information‐theoretic analysis of the special relation between phenomenal concepts and sensory concepts. On this account, we are wired to acquire sensory concepts from our experiences. (For example, concepts of particular colours, sounds, shapes, etc. are

Page 12 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts triggered by the corresponding experiences.) These sensory concepts double as phenomenal concepts when we use the same cognitive structures in introspection. All of the above accounts are aimed at explaining the conceivability of zombies and the explanatory gap in a manner compatible with physicalism. The main point is that there is nothing in the idea of direct reference appealed to in the recognitional and demonstrative accounts that is at odds with physicalism—but once you have concepts that refer directly in the way suggested by these accounts, the conceivability of zombies and the existence of the explanatory gap will follow. Consequently, the (p. 305) conceivability of zombies and the existence of the explanatory gap are compatible with physicalism. These accounts, however, are less successful at explaining some other features on our list (a)–(i).37 An examination of (a)–(i) suggests that a successful account of PCs will posit an intimate connection between conscious states and the concepts we form of them. We can see this by considering that the above accounts conceive of PCs and their referents as distinct existences related by causation. It seems that this leaves too much of a distance between, for example, a basic application of the PC pain to a particular pain as it occurs and the particular pain itself, as on this view their occurrence is independent. In particular, it is conceivable on this account that a basic application of pain be tokened by someone in the complete absence of pain. But it seems that this is really inconceivable. Anybody who tokens a basic application of pain is really in pain. Loar tried to capture the special intimacy between phenomenal concepts and phenomenal states by proposing that the mode of presentation of a PC involves the experience itself that the concept refers to. If thinking about one's own current pain already somehow involves pain itself then the situations we have been talking about are ruled out. But how should this idea be best understood? As Papineau (2002: ch. 4) points out, by ‘mode of presentation’ we cannot mean an associated description that we can already think and use to refer to an entity which has those properties the description attributes. That would be presupposing PCs in the explanation of those very concepts. We have to think about the mode of presentation of PCs in some other way.

17.5.2 The Special Modes of Presentation of PCs Carruthers (2004) is another proponent of the recognitional account: he proposes that PCs are pure recognitional concepts; that is, recognitional concepts that don't have any descriptive modes of presentation. However, he does seem to think that there is something like a mode of presentation that guides PCs to their referents. Carruthers observes that via our introspective judgements we are acquainted with our experiences, and he proposes that to account for the acquaintance relationship we need to posit higher‐order experiences of experiences that guide our PCs to their referents. This is because he thinks that an account of PCs should ‘accommodate our sense that we are directly aware of what grounds the application of a phenomenal concept, in a way that need involve no a priori connections with non‐phenomenal concepts’ (2004: 17). These Page 13 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts higher‐order experiences, he believes, are riding piggyback on our first‐order experiences in that first‐order experiences, when they are available to a ‘ “mind‐reading” faculty, themselves acquire higher order analog, experience‐representing contents. Each state that is an analog representation with the content reda is at the same time an analog representation with the content (p. 306) experience of reda’ (2004: 22). Just as sensory representations of red guide applications of our concept red, these higher‐order experiences of experiences guide, in a special, direct, yet substantial way, applications of our PC reddish.38 The Constitutional Account. On Carruthers's view, the special mode of presentation PCs have is to be accounted for partly by the special nature of phenomenal experiences themselves (that they represent themselves) and partly by the special nature of PCs (they are direct recognitional concepts guided by these self‐representing states). There is another way of thinking about PCs which is silent about the nature of phenomenal states but still incorporates Loar's suggestion that phenomenal states themselves are involved in their own presentation by PCs. This view involves variations on the idea that phenomenal concepts are constituted by the phenomenal experiences they refer to. More precisely, on this view, every concept token applied to current experience is constituted by a current token phenomenal experience, and—on most versions of the constitutional account—this fact is crucial in determining the reference of the concept. On this account, there is an intimate relation between a phenomenal concept and its referent, more intimate than any causal or tracking relation. It is also a way of fleshing out the idea that the experience serves as its own mode of presentation. Metaphorically speaking, a token of the reference provides the ink in which the token concept is written.39 In terms of the RTM/LOT model, what is special about PCs then is that in so far as they have a mode of presentation it has to do with the special vehicle involved in the basic applications of the concept/mental representation.40 Not only is it the case that a token state that realizes a token concept is also a token of the referent, but it is because the concept is so constituted that it so refers. Unlike most concepts—for example the concept dog, where it doesn't matter exactly what neural configurations constitute a particular token of dog as long as the requisite causal/informational relations between it and dogs hold—in the case of phenomenal concepts, for example the concept pain, constitution matters for reference, both in terms of how the reference is determined, and in terms of how the concept cognitively ‘presents’ its reference. Versions of this view have been proposed, on the physicalist side, by Hill and McLaughlin (1999), Papineau (2002, 2007), Balog (2006), and Block (2007), and David Chalmers (2003) put forward a variation of this account on the dualist side. (p. 307)

Page 14 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts The constitutional account can explain many features of our epistemic relation to phenomenal consciousness on our list (a)–(i). Take the infallibility of certain kinds of phenomenal judgements. On the constitutional account, tokens of a phenomenal concept that refers to a particular type of visual experience, say reddish, are constituted in part by tokens of that type of experience. Then, for example, in a basic application of the judgement I am experiencing reddish one's judgement cannot fail to be true. Semantic stability is also easily explainable on the constitutional account. PCs refer to the same properties independently of the actual context because—according to the constitutional account—their reference is determined by their constitution (and conceptual role), and that is independent of any external factors. Explanations of the other features on the list (a)–(i) can be constructed on the constitutional account as well. I will only mention the response to the Conceivability Argument that this account of PCs makes possible. Hill and McLaughlin's paper (1999) is primarily a reply to Chalmers's Conceivability Argument for dualism. Elaborating on a suggestion by Nagel (1974), Hill and McLaughlin argue that phenomenal concepts and physical concepts are governed by very different epistemic constraints, and they presuppose the use of radically different faculties. Since conceiving of zombies requires the joint exercise of phenomenal and physical concepts, they argue, there is no reason to conclude that the conceivability of zombies must be explained by their possibility. As they put it: Given … [the] differences between sensory41 concepts and physical concepts, a sensory state and its nomologically correlated brain state would seem contingently related, even if they were necessarily one. (1999: 449) On their account, phenomenal concepts are special recognitional concepts that are constituted by their referents:

When one uses a sensory concept to classify one's own current experiences, the experiences that guide and justify one in applying the concept are always identical with the experiences to which the concept is applied. Sensory states are self‐ presenting states: we experience them, but we do not have sensory experiences of them. We experience them simply by virtue of being in them. Sensory concepts are recognitional concepts: deploying such concepts, we can introspectively recognize when we are in sensory states simply by focusing our attention directly on them. (1999: 448) Block (2007) has a similar view of phenomenal concepts. He discusses the nature of phenomenal concepts in the context of the many versions of the Property Dualism Argument (see e.g. White 2007), a close relative of the Conceivability Argument:

Page 15 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts if a token phenomenal feel does double duty … (as a token of an aspect of both the pain and our way of thinking of the pain), no extra specter of dualism arises. If the phenomenal (p. 308) feel is a physical property, then it is a physical property even when it (or a token of it) does double duty. (Block 2007: 263) There are many questions the constitutional account raises, but one is particularly urgent: How do phenomenal concepts come to refer to experiences that they themselves exemplify? How does the constitution relation determine or partly determine the reference of a phenomenal concept? The idea that it does seems strange, since it is not the case for most concepts. The concept dog is not constituted by dogs, and the fact that the concept atom is constituted by atoms has nothing to do with why it refers to atoms. The problem of how phenomenal concepts refer is a pressing one for philosophers across the board, but whereas dualists can appeal to a primitive relation of acquaintance, physicalists are under a strict obligation to provide a naturalistic account; that is, an account that appeals only to physicalistically respectable entities and properties.

The idea of an item partly constituting a representation that refers to that item is reminiscent of how linguistic quotation works. The referent of ‘—’ is exemplified by whatever fills in the blank. In a quotation expression, a token of the referent is literally a constituent of the expression that refers to a type which it exemplifies, and that expression has its reference (at least partly) in virtue of the properties of its constituent. Some physicalists have tried to follow up on this idea to explain the reference of phenomenal concepts. Papineau (2002) has put forward one of the most elaborate versions of the constitutional account. He suggests that phenomenal concepts are formed by prefixing perceptual experiences with the operator ‘the experience …’. He calls this the quotational account of phenomenal concepts. He hopes to give an answer to questions about the reference of phenomenal concepts by invoking teleosemantics: We should also note that phenomenal concepts are compound referring terms (composed of an ‘experience operator’ and a ‘perceptual filling’). … [A] causal or teleosemantic account of phenomenal concepts will view the contribution of the parts to the semantic value of the whole as depending on the systematic contribution which those parts make to the causes or biological functions of the wholes they enter into. (2002: 117) Papineau (2007), however, apparently in keeping with the teleosemantic account, claims that the fact that phenomenal concepts are constituted by exemplars of their referent plays no direct role in explaining why they so refer. This amounts to a repudiation of the idea that phenomenal concepts work in similar ways to quotation expressions.

Balog (2006), on the other hand, holds that phenomenal concepts are very closely analogous to quotation expressions and that one must look to the conceptual role of phenomenal concepts for an explanation of this. Page 16 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts These versions of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy are all meant to support physicalism by invoking the special nature of PCs to explain the epistemic puzzles (p. 309) involving phenomenal consciousness. However, since these accounts are neutral about the nature of phenomenal properties, they can be adopted by a non‐physicalist. Chalmers (2003) himself proposes a version of the constitutional account. On such an account, the explanations of most aspects of our epistemic relation to phenomenal consciousness will look much the same, with the exception that phenomenal concepts are constituted by non‐physical states. However, according to the Phenomenal Concept Strategy, there will now be two parallel explanations of features (a)–(i). Take the conceivability of zombies. The dualist says that zombies are conceivable because phenomenal properties are not physical or functional properties. But this explanation is redundant, since, as we have seen, there is an explanation of why zombies are conceivable in terms of the special nature of PCs. Accordingly, the Phenomenal Concept Strategy, if successful, provides support for physicalism and undermines the rationale for dualism.

17.6 Critics of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy Levine (2007) observes that our epistemic relation to our own experience (i.e. our acquaintance with it) seems substantive in a way that differs from our epistemic relation to anything else. He thinks that accounts of phenomenal concepts that appeal to directness of reference or constitution falter on the fact that they cannot really explain the substantivity of acquaintance. Directness of reference doesn't in itself explain the substantive nature of acquaintance. Constitutional accounts try to explain the substantivity of acquaintance by appeal to the cognitive presence of phenomenal properties in our phenomenal concepts, which, in turn, is explained by physical presence. This last move, however, according to Levine, is bound to fail. In a related vein, Chalmers (2007) poses an intriguing dilemma for the Phenomenal Concept Strategy. Let C be the physicalist's account of phenomenal concepts, or the physicalist's account of key features of these concepts responsible for our epistemic relation to phenomenal consciousness. He argues that if a scenario physically exactly like ours is conceivable where C is missing, then C is not physically explicable. On the other hand, if such a scenario is not conceivable then C cannot explain our epistemic situation. These criticisms provide challenges for the Phenomenal Concept Strategy. There are other worries for the strategy relating to how, on a physicalist account, determinate reference to an objective property can be achieved by subjective phenomenal concepts (see e.g. Papineau 2002: ch. 7). Many of these problems require purely philosophical treatment; however, one might wonder if in the future psychology and neuroscience will

Page 17 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts play a larger role in our quest to understand phenomenal consciousness and acquaintance.

References Aydede, M., and Güzeldere, G. (2005), ‘Cognitive Architecture, Concepts, and Introspection: An Information‐theoretic Solution to the Problem of Phenomenal Consciousness’, Noûs, 39: 197–255. Balog, K. (1999), ‘Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind–Body Problem’, Philosophical Review, 108: 497–528. —— (2006), ‘Aquaintance and the Mind–body Problem’, , (unpublished), accessed 2008. Bealer, G. (1994), ‘Mental Properties’, Journal of Philosophy, 91: 185–208. Block, N. (1994), ‘An Argument for Holism’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94: 151–69. —— (2003), ‘Mental Paint’, in M. Hahn and B. Ramberg (eds.), Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 165–200. —— (2007), ‘Max Black's Objection to Mind–Body Identity’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 249–306. Carruthers, P. (2004), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and Higher‐Order Experiences, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68: 316–36. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2002), ‘Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 145–200. —— (2003), ‘The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief’, in Q. Smith and A. Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 220–72. —— (2006), ‘Two‐dimensional Semantics’, in E. Lepore and B. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 574–606. —— (2007), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 167–94.

Page 18 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston, Mass.: Little, Brown). —— (2007), ‘What RoboMary Knows’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 15–31. Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought (New York: Crowell). —— (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (forthcoming), ‘Revenge of the Given’, in B. McLaughlin and J. Cohne (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell). Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Hill, C., and McLaughlin, B. (1999), ‘There are Fewer Things in Reality than are Dreamt of in Chalmers's Philosophy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59: 445–54. Jackson, F. (1982), ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 127–36. —— (2003), ‘Mind and Illusion’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Minds and Persons (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 251–71. —— (2004), ‘Representation and Experience’, in H. Clapin, P. Slezack, and P. Staines (eds.), Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation (Amsterdam: Elsevier), 107–24. (p. 311)

Kirk, R. (2005), Zombies and Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Kriegel, U. (2004), ‘Consciousness and Self‐consciousness’, Monist, 87: 185–209. Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Levin, J. (2007), ‘What is a Phenomenal Concept?’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 87–110. Levine, J. (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2007), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Materialist Constraint’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 145–66. Lewis, D. (1966), ‘An Argument for the Identity Theory’, Journal of Philosophy, 63: 17–25.

Page 19 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts Loar, B. (1990/97), ‘Phenomenal states’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 81–108; repr. with revisions in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 597–616. —— (2003), ‘Transparent Experience and the Availability of Qualia’, in A. Jokic and Q. Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 77–96. Nagel, T. (1974), ‘What is it Like to Be a bat?’, Philosophical Review, 83: 435–50. Nida‐Rümelin, M. (2007), ‘Grasping Phenomenal Properties’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 307–38. Papineau, D. (2002), Thinking about Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2007), ‘Phenomenal and Perceptual Concepts’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 111–44. Peacocke, C. (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Perry, J. (2001), Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Rey, G. (2007), ‘Phenomenal Content and the Richness and Determinacy of Colour Experience’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14/9–10. Robinson, H. (1993), ‘The Anti‐materialist Strategy and the Knowledge Argument’, in H. Robinson (ed.), Objections to Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 159–84. Rosenthal, D. (2002), ‘Explaining Consciousness’, in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 406–21. Russell, B. (1910), ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11: 108–28; repr. in Russell, Mysticism and Logic (London: Allen & Unwin, 1963), 152–67. —— (1918/19), ‘The Philosophy of Logical Atomism’, Monist, 28: 495–527; 29: 32–63, 190– 222, 345–80; repr. in Russell, Logic and Knowledge (London: Allen & Unwin, 1956), 177–281. Stoljar, D. (2005), ‘Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts’, Mind and Language, 20: 469– 94. Sturgeon, S. (1994), ‘The Epistemic View of Subjectivity’, Journal of Philosophy, 91: 221– 36.

Page 20 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Colour and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Tye, M. (2002), ‘Representationalism and the Transparency of Experience’, Noûs, 36: 137–51; repr. in B. Gertler (ed.), Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self‐ knowledge (Aldershot: Ashgate), 31–44. (p. 312)

—— (2003), ‘A Theory of Phenomenal Concepts’, Philosophy, 53: 91–106. White, S. (2007), ‘The Argument for the Semantic Premise’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 210–48. Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell).

Notes: (1) I will talk of the ‘ “what it's like” character’, or ‘qualitative character’ of those experiences, ‘qualia’, and ‘qualia properties’ interchangeably. There are some issues involving representationalism about qualia concerning a possible distinction between ‘qualitative character’ and ‘qualia’. Later I will mention these issues briefly, but for the most part this possible distinction will not play a part in the discussion. (2) There are also philosophers who downplay the uniqueness of PCs—I will come back to this issue when I discuss particular accounts of PCs. (3) The term ‘acquaintance’ was introduced in this context by Bertrand Russell. Russell (1910) developed his famous distinction between ‘knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description’. He then went on, in his (1918/19) lectures on logical atomism, to argue, in a Cartesian manner, that we are only ever acquainted with ‘sensibilia’; roughly, our phenomenal experiences. (4) According to a widespread understanding of physicalism, the world's fundamental ontology is physical and the best account of that ontology is provided by fundamental physics. Physics also claims that there are only a few fundamental dynamical and perhaps non‐dynamical laws that govern the structure of space–time and evolution of its occupants. Physicalism thus understood is defined as follows: all truths, including truths about phenomenal consciousness, are metaphysically necessitated by the complete physical truth about the world. Dualism, on the other hand, claims that the complete physical description of our world is not the complete description. Contemporary philosophical proponents of dualism generally do not think that there are non‐physical entities—as Descartes did—but they do maintain that there are basic non‐physical properties. Further, they hold that these properties are mental or proto‐mental properties. They also usually think that there are fundamental laws that link mental properties to each other and to certain properties of physical systems. By their lights a

Page 21 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts complete description of our universe must include truths about where, when, and which consciousness properties are exemplified. (5) Main accounts of the nature of phenomenal character are representationalism (e.g. Tye 2000), higher‐order monitoring theories (e.g. Rosenthal 2002), the self‐ representational theory (e.g. Kriegel 2004), and different varieties of dualism (e.g. Chalmers 1996), according to which qualia are either fundamental non‐physical or non‐ physically realized properties or they comprise the categorical bases of physical dispositional properties. Some physicalists hold that though qualia are physical, it is not possible to give an explanatorily perspicuous account of them in non‐phenomenal terms. The accounts of phenomenal concepts we will discuss are non‐committal concerning these debates about the nature of phenomenal character, though as far as the mind–body problem is concerned some of them have been used to attempt to defeat anti‐physicalist arguments. (6) Rey (2007), for example, denies that phenomenal concepts refer to any properties at all and so he denies the existence of qualia altogether. He still thinks that phenomenal concepts play an interesting and unique role in our mental life. Eliminativists, however, may not want to deny altogether that there is something it is like to see a red rose, or, at least, that it seems that there is something it is like to see a red rose. I won't pursue this matter here. (7) I use ‘transparence’ here not in the usual sense it is invoked in arguments for representationalism, but rather to indicate the sense that qualia properties reveal their essence (and the fact that what is revealed is their whole essence) directly to their subjects. (8) These are not exclusive options for those who think that there is something unique about PCs. Papineau (2007), for example, thinks that there is something unique about phenomenal concepts but it doesn't lie either in a unique reference relation or in some special feature of the referent; it rather lies in a special feature of the physical vehicle of the concept. More on this later. (9) I will refer to thoughts and concepts by italicized expressions. (10) PCs can be singular concepts referring to a particular qualitative experience or predicate concepts referring to a type of qualia. I will primarily discuss the latter. Though there are different construals as to the difference between them, a plausible view (Papineau 2007) is that the singular concepts are more complex than, and derivative of, the predicate concepts, involving descriptions like the particular pain I am having right now. (11) Under certain circumstances even basic applications of PCs can refer to the phenomenal experiences of others; for example, when one thinks that another person is

Page 22 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts having the same type of experience one is currently undergoing. Kati Farkas made this point in conversation. (12) I'll refer to phenomenal properties by expressions in bold type. (13) There are various other accounts of the exact relations non‐basic, derivative applications of PCs bear to basic ones (see e.g. Papineau 2007). (14) It is sometimes claimed, e.g. in Fodor (forthcoming), that a non‐conceptual representation, unlike linguistic representations, does not possess a canonical decomposition. (15) Block (2003) seems to hold that there can be qualia in the absence of representation. (16) The originator and foremost exponent of this view is Jerry Fodor; see e.g. Fodor (1975). (17) Mentalese is a hypothesized language over whose expressions mental processes are defined. It is a language in the way that computer languages are languages and of course is not a language for communication. Some philosophers resist the LOT hypothesis but it is widely employed in cognitive‐psychological models of mental processes. (18) For some concepts, e.g. descriptions, the concept's reference is determined by its mode of presentation. But for other concepts, e.g. names, reference may be determined by more than, or factors other than, the mode of presentation. (19) Holists (e.g. Block 1994) say all of the role is individuative, molecularists (e.g. Peacocke 1992) say just some, and atomists (e.g. Fodor 1987) say none. (20) The term ‘psychological concepts’ was introduced by Chalmers (1996). (21) There are two ways of understanding functional characterizations of properties: one as picking out the first‐order‐state type, if there is one, that satisfies the functional characterization and the other as picking out the second‐order functional property specified by the functional characterization. (22) Concepts of experience that characterize their referents representationally are, in a physicalist framework, special cases of psychological concepts. (23) His remarks in §§ 243–315 are often referred to as the ‘private‐language argument’. (24) Wittgenstein puts the point this way:

Page 23 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts Let us imagine the following case. I want to keep a diary about the recurrence of a certain sensation. To this end I associate it with the sign ‘S’ and write this sign in a calendar for every day on which I have the sensation.—I will remark first of all that a definition of the sign cannot be formulated.—But still I can give myself a kind of ostensive definition.—How? Can I point to the sensation? Not in the ordinary sense. But I speak, or write the sign down, and at the same time I concentrate my attention on the sensation—and so, as it were, point to it inwardly. —But what is this ceremony for? For that is all it seems to be! A definition surely serves to establish the meaning of a sign.—Well, that is done precisely by the concentrating of my attention; for in this way I impress upon myself the connection between the sign and the sensation.—But ‘I impress it on myself’ can only mean: this process brings it about that I remember the connection right in the future. But in the present case I have no criterion of correctness. One would like to say: whatever is going to seem right to me is right. And that only means that here we can't talk about ‘right’. (1953: § 258)

(25) Papineau (2002: 97–8) makes the point that natural‐language psychological words like ‘pain’ are ambiguous between phenomenal and psychological concepts of pain or perhaps express a concept that is an amalgam of the two. (26) See e.g. Harman (1990), Tye (2000), and Jackson (2004) for transparency arguments. Representationalists argue that when one attends to one's conscious experience one is aware only of the representational content of the experience, or, alternatively, only of features of the objects perceived, and conclude from this that, contrary to common sense, there are no intrinsic, qualitative, introspectable features of conscious experience. This is a controversial thesis that runs counter to the acquaintance thesis. I am merely noting the disagreement; we cannot go into the merits of the argument here. (27) I will confine myself here to the conceivability and gap arguments. Arguments from semantic stability are based on variations of the premise that if all the concepts in some identity claim are semantically stable then its truth or falsity can be determined a priori, coupled with the claim that psychophysical identities contain semantically stable terms and yet they are a posteriori. From these premises dualism follows. The exact definition of semantic stability and the formulation of the corresponding arguments are too complicated to go into in this discussion. Related arguments are Nida‐Rümelin (2007) and White (2007); Chalmers's two‐dimensional framework (2006 and Ch. 18 below) also yields a version of the argument. (28) Chalmers (2002) distinguishes between two notions of conceivability: positive and negative conceivability. I am going to rely on the notion of negative conceivability here, given its greater clarity and simplicity. (29) Stoljar (2005) introduced this phrase. Page 24 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts (30) See also Kirk (2005) for an interesting argument against the conceivability of zombies on grounds that go beyond analytic functionalism. (31) Functionalism or representationalism about phenomenal experience is not disputed here. For all we said about analytic functionalism/representationalism, functionalists/ representationalists (e.g. Harman 1990; Tye 2000) might be right that qualia are functional/representational states, or, at any rate, it might be that every phenomenally conscious experience always is representational (though this is a contentious claim for e.g. bodily sensations). What is at issue is whether PCs can be analysed in functional/ representational terms. (32) Some dualists, e.g. Chalmers (2003), have more to say about acquaintance and phenomenal concepts. I'll discuss those proposals below. (33) The idea that the mind–body problem is a product of the special ways in which we conceive (in the first‐person) of our phenomenal states is first formulated in this paper. A similar proposal by Scott Sturgeon (1994) appeals to the special epistemology of phenomenal states. (34) Loar, like other proponents of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy, focuses his attention on the basic applications of PCs, and thinks about the non‐basic applications as somehow derivative of the more central, basic cases. See the earlier discussion of basic and non‐basic applications of PCs. (35) Stoljar (2005) argues that there are analyticities involving phenomenal concepts and that this refutes the idea—integral to the Phenomenal Concept Strategy—that PCs are direct and unanalysable. However, his examples merely show that there are analytically necessary conditions on something being a conscious state but not that there are analytically sufficient conditions, and this is all a proponent of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy needs to be committed to. (36) Chalmers (2003) criticizes demonstrative accounts on the grounds that demonstratives pointing to current experience have different cognitive significance from direct phenomenal concepts, evidenced by the fact that I can conceive of the experience I am demonstrating to myself right now as having a different character from what it actually has. (37) Some philosophers—e.g. Dennett (1991), Levin (2007)—deny these other features of our epistemic access to consciousness. (38) By ‘reddish’ I mean the type of phenomenal experience typically caused by seeing red objects in ordinary light, etc.

Page 25 of 26

Phenomenal Concepts (39) Notice that this view of PCs is distinct from the self‐representational account of phenomenal states. The latter is a view of the nature of phenomenal states and is compatible with constitutional and non‐constitutional accounts of PCs (see e.g. Carruthers's recognitional account), while the former is a view of PCs and is compatible with different accounts of the nature of phenomenal states. Of course, one can combine the self‐representational account of the nature of phenomenal states with the constitutional account of PCs and claim that the kind of self‐representation that is essential for a sensory state to be phenomenally conscious is just to be represented by a PC partly constituted by the sensory state itself. Ouroboros indeed. (40) That means, among other things, that PCs in their basic applications simply don't have descriptive modes of presentation. (41) ‘Sensory concepts’ in Hill and McLaughlin's usage apply to what we have called phenomenal concepts.

Katalin Balog

Katalin Balog is Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Yale University.

Page 26 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism

Oxford Handbooks Online The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism   David J. Chalmers The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0019

Abstract and Keywords A number of popular arguments for dualism start from a premise about an epistemic gap between physical truths and truths about consciousness, and infer an ontological gap between physical processes and consciousness. Arguments of this sort include the conceivability argument, the knowledge argument, the explanatory gap argument, and the property dualism argument. Such arguments are often resisted on the grounds that epistemic premises do not entail ontological conclusions. This article views that one can legitimately infer ontological conclusions from epistemic premises, if one is careful about how one reasons. To do so, the best way is to reason first from epistemic premises to modal conclusions (about necessity and possibility), and from there to ontological conclusions. Here the crucial issue is the link between the epistemic and modal domains. Keywords: dualism, epistemic gap, physical truths, truths about consciousness, ontological gap, physical processes, consciousness

A number of popular arguments for dualism start from a premise about an epistemic gap between physical truths and truths about consciousness, and infer an ontological gap between physical processes and consciousness. Arguments of this sort include the conceivability argument, the knowledge argument, the explanatory gap argument, and the property dualism argument. Such arguments are often resisted on the grounds that epistemic premises do not entail ontological conclusions. My view is that one can legitimately infer ontological conclusions from epistemic premises, if one is careful about how one reasons. To do so, the best way is to reason first from epistemic premises to modal conclusions (about necessity and possibility), and from there to ontological conclusions. Here the crucial issue is the link between the epistemic and modal domains. How can one reason from theses about what is knowable or conceivable to theses about what is necessary or possible?

Page 1 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism To bridge the epistemic and modal domains, the framework of two‐dimensional semantics can play a central role. I have used this framework in earlier work (Chalmers 1996) to mount an argument against materialism. Here I want to revisit the argument, (p. 314) laying it out in a more explicit and careful form, and responding to a number of objections.

18.1 The Conceivability Argument The most straightforward form of the conceivability argument against materialism runs as follows. (1) P&∼Q is conceivable. (2) If P&∼Q is conceivable, P&∼Q is metaphysically possible. (3) If P&∼Q is metaphysically possible, materialism is false. ———————— (4) Materialism is false. Here P is the conjunction of all microphysical truths about the universe, specifying the fundamental features of every fundamental microphysical entity in the language of microphysics. Q is an arbitrary phenomenal truth: perhaps the truth that someone is phenomenally conscious, or perhaps the truth that a certain individual (that is, an individual satisfying a certain description) instantiates a certain phenomenal property. P&∼Q conjoins the former with the denial of the latter.

If Q is the truth that someone is phenomenally conscious, then P&∼Q is the statement that everything is microphysically as in our world, but no one is phenomenally conscious. In this version P&∼Q says that the world is a zombie world. If Q is the truth that a certain individual instantiates a certain phenomenal property, then P&∼Q is the statement that everything is microphysically as in our world, but that it is not the case that the individual in question instantiates the relevant phenomenal property. In this case it will suffice for the truth of P&∼Q that the world is a zombie world, or simply that the individual in question is a zombie in a physically identical world. It will also suffice that the individual in question is an invert, who has an experience that differs slightly from the corresponding experience of the corresponding individual in our (physically identical) world. The first premise of this argument asserts an epistemic thesis, about what can be conceived. The second premise steps from the epistemic thesis to a modal thesis, about what is possible. The third premise steps from the modal thesis to a metaphysical thesis, about the nature of our world. The third premise is relatively uncontroversial. It is widely accepted that materialism has modal commitments. Some philosophers question whether materialism is equivalent to a modal thesis, but almost all accept that materialism at least entails a modal thesis. Here

Page 2 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism one can invoke Kripke's metaphor: if it is possible that there is a world physically identical to our world but phenomenally different, then after God fixed the physical facts about our world, he had to do more work to fix the phenomenal facts. A familiar complication arises from the observation that physicalism about our world is compatible with the possibility of dualism in other worlds, and in particular (p. 315) is compatible with the possibility of a physically identical world that contains extra, non‐ physical phenomenology. This means that if Q is a negative truth about our world—say, the truth that no one instantiates a certain phenomenal property—then materialism about our world is compatible with the possibility of P&∼Q. To finesse this point we can stipulate that in the argument above, Q is a positive truth (one that holds in all worlds that contain a duplicate of our world: see Chalmers 1996: 40): if Q is a positive truth, then materialism is incompatible with the possibility of P&∼Q. Alternatively, we can conjoin P with a ‘that's‐all’ statement T, stating that the world is a minimal world that satisfies P (see Jackson 1998: 26). Then even when Q is a negative truth, materialism is not compatible with the possibility of PT&∼Q (where PT is the conjunction of P and T). The real work in the argument is done by the first and second premises. The second premise is particularly controversial, as there are a number of examples that have led many philosophers to deny that there is an entailment from conceivability to metaphysical possibility. To assess these premises we need to understand the notion of conceivability.

18.2 Varieties of Conceivability Conceivability is to be understood as an epistemic notion, defined in epistemological (and perhaps psychological) terms. To a first approximation, we can say that S is conceivable when S expresses a coherent hypothesis: one that cannot be ruled out a priori. To refine this understanding it is useful to make some distinctions. (These distinctions are discussed at much greater length in Chalmers 2002.) We can say that S is prima facie conceivable for a subject when that subject is unable to rule out the hypothesis expressed by S by a priori reasoning, on initial consideration. We can say that S is ideally conceivable when the hypothesis expressed by S cannot be ruled out a priori, even on ideal rational reflection. The main difference here is that prima facie conceivability is tied to a subject's contingent cognitive limitations, while ideal conceivability abstracts away from those limitations. Some examples: (1) ‘2 + 2 = 5’ is neither prima facie conceivable nor ideally conceivable. (2) Where S is a highly complex but provable mathematical truth, ∼S will be prima facie conceivable for most subjects, but it is not ideally conceivable. (3) Where S is ‘There is a flying pig’, S is prima facie conceivable, and is almost certainly ideally conceivable.

Page 3 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism The notions of conceivability discussed above are versions of negative conceivability, which is defined in terms of what a subject can rule out through a priori reasoning. We can say that S is negatively conceivable when S cannot be ruled out through a priori reasoning. The two notions above can then be seen as prima facie negative conceivability and ideal negative conceivability respectively. It is also possible to define notions of positive conceivability, which is defined in terms of what subjects can form a positive conception of. We can say that S is (p. 316) positively conceivable when one can coherently imagine a situation in which S is the case. Where negative conceivability requires merely entertaining a hypothesis and being unable to rule it out, positive conceivability involves being able to form some sort of clear and distinct conception of a situation in which the hypothesis is true. One can then say that S is prima facie positively conceivable when a subject can imagine a situation that they take to be coherent and that they take to be one in which S is the case. And one can say that S is ideally positively conceivable when its prima facie positive conceivability cannot be defeated on ideal rational reflection (in particular, when arbitrary details can be filled in in the imagined situation without any contradiction revealing itself, and when ideal reflection reveals the imagined situation as one in which S is the case). Traditional notions of conceivability (Descartes's clear and distinct conceivability, for example) are arguably varieties of positive conceivability rather than negative conceivability. At the same time, the notion of positive conceivability is more complex than that of negative conceivability, and a rigorous characterization of the notion requires saying much more about just what it is to imagine a situation, and so on. I characterize positive conceivability in more depth in Chalmers (2002). In this chapter the roles of positive and negative conceivability will often be interchangeable (I will make clear when the difference is relevant), so the informal account above will suffice for present purposes. For much of the discussion one can focus on negative conceivability without much loss, but positive conceivability is available as an alternative if there turn out to be any problems with theses tied to negative conceivability. In so far as there is a gap between prima facie conceivability and ideal conceivability, it is ideal conceivability that is a better guide to possibility. This is especially clear in the case of prima facie negative conceivability: we have seen that the negation of a complex mathematical truth may be prima facie negatively conceivable, but it is not ideally conceivable and it is not possible. It is less easy to find cases of prima facie positive conceivability without ideal positive conceivability (see Chalmers 2002 for some potential cases), but in so far as there are such cases, there will be little reason to think that they are possible. Correspondingly, some familiar purported counter‐examples to the claim that conceivability entails possibility are really counter‐examples to the claim that prima facie conceivability entails possibility. For example, it is sometimes said that both Goldbach's conjecture and its negation are conceivable, while only one of them is possible. Here the relevant notion of conceivability is something like prima facie negative conceivability. Page 4 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism There is no reason to believe that both Goldbach's conjecture and its negation are ideally conceivable, so there is no reason to think that this is a counter‐example to the claim that ideal conceivability entails possibility. So from here onward talk of ‘conceivability’ simpliciter should always be understood to be talk of ideal conceivability (either positive or negative). The other familiar class of purported counter‐examples arises from Kripke's analysis of the necessary a posteriori. It is often said that sentences such as ‘Water is not H2O’ provide counter‐examples to the claim that conceivability entails possibility: it is conceivable that water is not H2O, but it is not metaphysically possible. (p. 317)

Here one has to be careful. There is a sense of ‘conceivable’ in which ‘Water is not H2O’ is not conceivable (given that water is H2O in the actual world): in this sense, any conceivable situation in which it seems that water is not H2O (a Twin Earth world, say) whould better be described as a conceivable situation in which water is still H2O, but in which there is watery stuff that is not H2O. Using the term ‘conceivable’ this way, one might say that ‘Water is not H2O’ seems conceivable (or that it is prima facie conceivable, to one without relevant empirical knowledge), but that it is not really conceivable. We might call this sense of conceivability secondary conceivability (for reasons familiar from a two‐dimensional analysis and discussed in Chalmers 2002). Then the Kripkean cases are compatible with the claim that secondary conceivability entails metaphysical possibility. But at the same time this claim is not very useful for present purposes, as whether a sentence is secondarily conceivable will typically depend on a variety of empirical factors, and an opponent might deny that zombies are secondarily conceivable, on the grounds that there is an a posteriori identity between phenomenal and physical properties. So a link between secondary conceivability and possibility does not offer an a priori route to conclusions about metaphysical possibility. Instead, what is relevant here is primary conceivability: the sense in which ‘Water is not H2O’ can correctly be said to be conceivable. The notion of negative conceivability defined above is a sort of primary conceivability, as it is defined in terms of what can be ruled out a priori, and ‘Water is H2O’ cannot be established a priori. (One might define a distinct notion of negative secondary conceivability, but I will set that aside here.) One can likewise define a notion of positive primary conceivability, so that S is positively primarily conceivable when a subject can imagine a coherent situation that verifies S, where a situation verifies S when, under the hypothesis that the situation actually obtains, the subject should conclude that S. If the subject imagines a Twin Earth situation with XYZ in the oceans and lakes, and assumes that the situation obtains in their own environment, then the subject should conclude that water is XYZ rather than H2O. So ‘Water is not H2O’ is positively primarily conceivable, as well as negatively primarily conceivable.

Page 5 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism Unlike secondary conceivability, matters of primary conceivability are plausibly in the a priori domain: whether S is primarily conceivable turns on matters of a priori reasoning. But primary conceivability does not entail metaphysical possibility: ‘Water is not H2O’ is primarily conceivable, but it is not metaphysically possible. Still, there remains a link between primary conceivability and metaphysical possibility in these cases. When we conceive that water is not H2O we imagine (for example) a Twin Earth situation in which the watery liquid in the oceans and lakes is XYZ. This situation is metaphysically possible, so there is a sense in which our conceiving involves access to a possible world. Under the usual way of describing possible worlds, this world is not a world in which water is not H2O. But the world still stands in a strong relation to the sentence ‘Water is not H2O.’ In particular, if we came to accept that our own world had the character of this world (with XYZ in the oceans and lakes), we should then endorse the claim ‘Water is not H2O.’ (p. 318)

This can be put in two‐dimensional terms by saying that while the Twin Earth does not satisfy ‘Water is not H2O’ (‘Water is not H2O’ is not true of that world considered as counterfactual), the Twin Earth world verifies ‘Water is not H2O’ (‘Water is not H2O’ is true of that world considered as actual). Equivalently, we can say that while the secondary intension of ‘Water is not H2O’ is false at W, the sentence's primary intension is true there. To a first approximation, a world W verifies S (or S is true at W considered as actual, or the primary intension of S is true at W) when if we came to accept that our own world is qualitatively like W we should then endorse S. Strictly speaking, the worlds W that are relevant to primary intensions are centred worlds: worlds that come with a marked ‘centre’ consisting of an individual and time. When we consider a centred world W as actual, we consider the hypothesis that we are currently in the situation of the individual at the centre. (For much more on these notions see Chalmers 2004.) We can say that when the primary intension of S is true at some centred world (i.e. when some centred world verifies S) S is primarily possible, or 1‐possible. When the secondary intension of S is true at some world (i.e. when some world satisfies S), S is secondarily possible, or 2‐possible. Then ‘Water is not H2O’ is not 2‐possible, but it is 1‐possible. The observation that sentences such as ‘Water is not H2O’ are conceivable but not possible, in these terms, comes to the claim that these sentences are primarily conceivable (1‐conceivable) but are not secondarily possible (2‐possible). So there is good reason to believe that 1‐conceivability does not entail 2‐possibility. However, these cases are entirely compatible with a link between 2‐conceivability and 2‐possibility, and, more importantly for present purposes, they are entirely compatible with a link between 1‐ conceivability and 1‐possibility. In fact, it is not hard to argue that all of the standard Kripkean a posteriori necessities (‘Heat is the motion of molecules’, ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’, and so on) have this structure. For each of these necessities one might say that its negation is conceivable but Page 6 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism not possible, meaning that it is 1‐conceivable but not 2‐possible. But in each of these cases the sentence in question is 1‐possible. For example, ‘Heat is not the motion of molecules’ is verified by a world in which something other than molecules causes sensations as of heat. ‘Hesperus is not Phosphorus’ is verified by a world in which the objects visible in the morning and evening skies are entirely distinct. Furthermore, it is plausible that worlds such as these are just what one is conceiving of when one conceives that heat is not the motion of molecules, or that Hesperus is not Phosphorus. So in these cases there remains a strong link between conceivability and metaphysical possibility. To summarize: we have seen that the standard counter‐examples to a conceivability– possibility link are accommodated by noting that (i) prima facie conceivability is an imperfect guide to possibility, and (ii) primary conceivability is an imperfect guide to secondary possibility. But (i) is entirely consistent with a link between ideal conceivability and possibility, and (ii) is entirely consistent with a link between primary conceivability and primary possibility. Putting the pieces (p. 319) together: all of these counter‐examples are compatible with the thesis that ideal primary conceivability entails primary possibility. There are two versions of this thesis, depending on whether one interprets the relevant sort of conceivability as positive or negative. (CP+) Ideal primary positive conceivability entails primary possibility. (CP−) Ideal primary negative conceivability entails primary possibility. CP− entails CP+, as ideal primary positive conceivability entails ideal primary negative conceivability. If S can be ruled out a priori, then no coherent imagined situation will verify S. It is not obvious whether or not CP+ entails CP−, as it is not obvious whether ideal primary negative conceivability entails ideal primary positive conceivability. That is, it is not obvious whether or not there is an S that cannot be ruled out a priori, but such that no coherent imagined situation verifies S. (In Chalmers 2002 I argue that there is no such S, so that ideal primary negative conceivability entails ideal primary positive conceivability.) So CP− is at least as strong as CP+ and is possibly somewhat stronger.

Most importantly for present purposes, however, both CP+ and CP− are compatible with all the familiar purported counter‐examples to the conceivability–possibility link. Furthermore, it seems that there are no clear counter‐examples to either thesis (though later in the chapter I will discuss some potential counter‐examples that have been put forward). In particular, both theses are entirely compatible with the existence of Kripkean a posteriori necessities, so while existence of these necessities is often used to case doubt on conceivability–possibility theses, they cannot be used to cast doubt on CP+ or CP−. So for now I will take these theses as reasonable conceivability–possibility theses that might be used in mounting a refined conceivability argument against materialism. Later in the chapter I will return to the question of their truth.

Page 7 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism

18.3 A Refined Conceivability Argument Henceforth, unqualified uses of ‘conceivability’ and ‘conceivable’ should be understood as invoking ideal primary conceivability. I will often be inexplicit about whether positive or negative conceivability is involved. In effect, the argument forms below can be understood as generating two different arguments, depending on whether one understands conceivability as ideal primary positive conceivability or as ideal primary negative conceivability. For many purposes the distinction will not matter. When it does matter, I will be explicit. Given the discussion above, one might try generating an anti‐ materialist argument by simply substituting primary possibility for metaphysical possibility in the original argument. (1) P&∼Q is conceivable. (2) If P&∼Q is conceivable, P&∼Q is 1‐possible. (p. 320)

(3) If P&∼Q is 1‐possible, materialism is false. —————— (4) Materialism is false. On this reading (1) and (2) are both plausible theses, but (3) is not obviously plausible. The reason is that materialism requires not the 1‐impossibility of P&∼Q but the 2‐impossibility of P&∼Q. That is, materialism requires that it could not have been the case that P were true without Q being true. This is a subjunctive claim about ordinary metaphysical possibility, and so invokes 2‐impossibility rather than 1‐impossibility.

A materialist might reasonably question (3) by holding that even if there is a world W verifying P&∼Q, W might be a world with quite different ingredients from our own. For example, it might be that W does not instantiate true microphysical properties (those instantiated in our world), such as mass and charge, but instead instantiates quite different properties; say, pseudo‐mass and pseudo‐charge, which stand to mass and charge roughly as XYZ stands to H2O. Likewise, it might be that W does not lack true phenomenal properties, but instead lacks quite different properties: say, pseudo‐ phenomenal properties. If so, then the possibility of W has no bearing on whether true microphysical properties necessitate true phenomenal properties. And it is the latter that is relevant for materialism. Still, it may be that the gap between 1‐possibility and 2‐possibility could be closed. In particular, when a statement S has the same primary intension and secondary intension, then a world will verify S iff it satisfies S, so S will be 1‐possible iff it is 2‐possible. If P and Q both have primary intensions that coincide with their secondary intensions, then so will P&∼Q, and we could run the following argument: (1) P&∼Q is conceivable. (2) If P&∼Q is conceivable, P&∼Q is 1‐possible.

Page 8 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism (3) If P&∼Q is 1‐possible, P&∼Q is 2‐possible. (4) If P&∼Q is 2‐possible, materialism is false. —————— (5) Materialism is false. Here the truth of (3) requires that both P and Q have primary and secondary intensions that coincide. In the case of Q, this claim is quite plausible. As Kripke noted, there does not seem to be the same strong dissociation between appearance and reality in the case of consciousness as in the cases of water and heat: while it is not the case that anything that looks like water is water, or that anything that feels like heat is heat, it is plausibly the case that anything that feels like consciousness is consciousness. So it is not clear that the notion of ‘pseudo‐consciousness’, something that satisfies the primary intension of ‘consciousness’ without being consciousness, is coherent. Likewise for other more specific phenomenal properties. So there is a strong case that the primary and secondary intensions of phenomenal terms coincide. (For more on this case see Chalmers 2003.)

However, in the case of P this claim is less plausible. A materialist might reasonably hold that microphysical terms (such as ‘mass’ and ‘charge’) have primary intensions that differ from their secondary intensions. In particular, it is plausible that the primary intensions of these terms are tied to a certain theoretical role. We might (p. 321) say that the primary intension of ‘mass’ picks out whatever property plays the mass role (e.g. resisting acceleration in certain ways, being subject to mutual attraction in a certain way, and so on), and that the primary intension of ‘charge’ picks out whatever property plays the charge role (e.g. obeying certain electromagnetic principles, being subject to attraction and repulsion in certain ways, and so on). By contrast, one might reasonably hold that the secondary intension of microphysical terms is tied to the property that actually plays the role. For example, if property M plays the mass role in the actual world, then one might hold that in any world in which mass is instantiated, mass is M. It follows that if there are worlds in which some other property M′ plays the mass role, then M′ is not mass in that world (at best, it is pseudo‐mass). If so, then the primary and secondary intensions of ‘mass’ will not coincide: the primary intension of ‘mass’ will pick out whatever plays the mass role in such a world, but the secondary intension will not. There are other views of the semantics and metaphysics of microphysical terms that may reject this argument for the distinctness of the primary and secondary intensions of ‘mass’. In particular, the argument will not go through on views according to which it is necessary that mass is the property that plays the mass role. (These include views on which ‘mass’ is a non‐rigid designator whose secondary intension picks out different properties that play the role in some worlds, and views on which it is necessary that M is the property that plays the mass role, where M is the property rigidly designated by ‘mass’.) Still, the view sketched above is a quite reasonable view—more plausible than the alternatives, in my opinion—and it is the view that best grounds resistance to an inference from the 1‐possibility of P&∼Q to its 2‐possibility. So we can suppose that the view is correct in order to see what follows.

Page 9 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism On this view, a world may verify P without satisfying P. The secondary intension of P requires that certain specific properties such as mass, spin, and charge are distributed in a certain specific way across space–time, with appropriate causal and nomic relations among them. The primary intension of P requires only that whatever properties play the mass role, the spin role, and charge role are distributed in this way. If W is a world where these roles are played by properties other than mass, spin, and charge (we might say that they are played by ‘schmass’, ‘schmin’, and ‘schmarge’), which are otherwise distributed in the right way over space–time and have appropriate causal and nomic relations among them, then W will verify P, but it will not satisfy P. Here we might say that the physics of W has the same structural profile as physics in the actual world, but that it has a different intrinsic profile, in that it differs in the intrinsic properties that fill this structure. To verify P, a world must have the right structural profile, while to satisfy P, a world must have the right structural and intrinsic profile. It follows that premise 3 is not guaranteed to be true. Because a world can verify P without satisfying P, it may be that P&∼Q is 1‐possible but not 2‐possible. However, this requires that P and Q be related in a certain specific way. In particular, it requires that some worlds that verify P also verify ∼Q, while no worlds that satisfy P also satisfy ∼Q. This requires in turn that some worlds that have the same structural profile as the actual world verify ∼Q, while no worlds that have the same structural (p. 322) and intrinsic profiles as the actual world satisfy ∼Q. We can assume for the moment that the primary and secondary intensions of Q coincide. Then we can put all this by saying that the falsity of (3) requires that the structural profile of physics in the actual world does not necessitate Q, but that the combined structural and intrinsic profiles of physics in the actual world do necessitate Q. This idea—that the structural properties of physics in the actual world do not necessitate the existence and/or nature of consciousness, but that the intrinsic properties of physics combined with the structural properties do—corresponds to a familiar view in the metaphysics of consciousness. This is the view that I have elsewhere called Russellian monism (or type‐F monism, or panprotopsychism). On this view, consciousness is closely tied to the intrinsic properties that serve as the categorical bases of microphysical dispositions. Russell and others held that the nature of these properties is not revealed to us by perception (which reveals only their effects) or by science (which reveals only their relations). But it is coherent to suppose that these properties have a special nature that is tied to consciousness. They might themselves be phenomenal properties, or they might be proto‐phenomenal properties: properties that collectively constitute phenomenal properties when organized in the appropriate way. Russellian monism is an important view on the mind–body problem. I think that it is certainly not ruled out by the conceivability argument and by related arguments. If Russellian monism is true, then when we conceive of zombies, we hold fixed the structural properties of physical systems in the actual world, but not their intrinsic properties (which are proto‐phenomenal properties). If we consider these intrinsic proto‐ phenomenal properties to be physical properties, then Russellian monism will qualify as a Page 10 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism form of physicalism. But because it relies on speculation about the special nature of the fundamental properties in microphysics, it is a highly distinctive form of physicalism that has much in common with property dualism, and that many physicalists will want to reject.1 In any case, we can now close the loophole in the previous argument as follows: (1) P&∼Q is conceivable. (2) If P&∼Q is conceivable, P&∼Q is 1‐possible. (3) If P&∼Q is 1‐possible, P&∼Q is 2‐possible or Russellian monism is true. (4) If P&∼Q is 2‐possible, materialism is false. —————— (5) Materialism is false or Russellian monism is true. This argument is valid. I discussed the case for premises (1), (2), and (4) earlier, and I have just now argued for premise (3). I think that (5) is the proper conclusion of the conceivability argument. For the reasons given above, such arguments (and also related arguments such as the knowledge argument and the property‐dualism argument) cannot exclude Russellian monism, and Russellian monism is arguably a form of physicalism, if a distinctive and radical kind. So the possibility of Russellian monism needs to be explicitly acknowledged as an option in the conclusion. (p. 323)

A couple of minor notes on the argument. First, to be fully explicit the argument might take the truth of Q as a premise. If Q were false, the ground for accepting (4) would collapse. In the less explicit version of the argument above we can consider the truth of Q part of the case for accepting premise (4). In fact, for reasons given earlier, the case for (4) requires that Q is a positive truth about consciousness. Alternatively, one can remain silent on whether Q is a positive or negative truth, and handle this matter by conjoining P with a ‘that's‐all’ clause asserting that the world is a minimal world in which P (or, equivalently, by building such a that's‐all clause into P). Second, it is worth noting that (contrary to a common supposition), the assumption that Q has the same primary and secondary intensions is not necessary for the argument for (5) to go through. To see this we can consider the version of the argument where we adjoin a ‘that's‐all’ clause to P. From (1) and (2) we can derive the conclusion that there is a minimal world verifying P in which the primary intension of Q is false. If P has the same primary and secondary intensions, then this world will be a minimal P‐world in which the primary intension of Q is false. This world must differ from our world, because the primary intension of Q is true in our world. (There is a small loophole here arising from the possibility that this world differs merely in the location of the centre of the relevant centred world. I discuss this loophole in the expanded version of this paper.) It follows that there is a minimal P‐world that is not a duplicate of our world, so that physicalism is false of our world. It could be that strictly speaking physicalism will be true of consciousness, because P necessitates Q, but physicalism will be false of properties closely associated with consciousness; namely, those associated with the primary

Page 11 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism intension of Q. We might think of this sort of view as one on which phenomenal properties are physical properties that have non‐physical properties as modes of presentation. Alternatively, if P has different primary and secondary intensions, then by the reasoning given in the earlier discussion of premise (3) one can conclude that either there is a minimal world satisfying P in which the primary intension of Q is false (which again entails the falsity of physicalism), or that the primary intension of Q is necessitated by the structural and intrinsic profiles of physics in our world, but not by the intrinsic profiles alone. This view can be considered another form of Russellian monism, in that the intrinsic properties of physics in our world are crucial for constituting the properties associated with the modes of presentation of consciousness. So if Q has distinct primary and secondary intensions, then one will have to formalize premises (3) and (4) somewhat differently, but the argument for (5) will still work just as well.

(p. 324)

18.4 Objections

For reasons of space I will here pass over objections to premise 1. Six such objections are discussed in the expanded version of this chapter: the objection from analytic functionalism, the objection that zombies are prima facie but not ideally conceivable, an objection based on expanding the conception of the physical (Stoljar 2001), the objection that zombies presuppose epiphenomenalism (Perry 2001), the objection based on the fact that zombies appear to make judgements about consciousness (Thomas 1998; Kirk 1999; Lynch 2006), and the objection that zombies are negatively but not positively conceivable (Ashwell 2003; Marcus 2004). I will also pass over some hard‐to‐classify objections, including the conditional‐concepts objection (Hawthorne 2002; Stalnaker 2002; Braddon‐Mitchell 2003), the zombie‐parity objection (Balog 1999), the indexical objection (e.g. Ismael 1999; Perry 2001), and objections to two‐dimensional semantics (e.g. Soames 2004). Again, these objections are discussed at length in the expanded version of this chapter. Instead, I will concentrate here on objections to the crucial premise (2). It is this premise that bridges the epistemic and modal domains, and it is this premise and associated principles that have attracted the most in‐depth philosophical discussion. Premise (2) says that if P&∼Q is conceivable, P&∼Q is 1‐possible. This premise can be seen as an instance of the general conceivability–possibility thesis CP: CP: If S is conceivable, S is 1‐possible.

Page 12 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism Here ‘conceivability’ should be understood as ideal primary conceivability, of either the negative or positive variety (I always take ‘ideal primary’ as understood from here on). The two versions of the thesis that result are equivalent to theses CP− and CP+, discussed earlier. Thesis CP− is equivalent to the claim that if ∼S is not a priori, S is 1‐possible. The positive version CP+, holding that if S is positively conceivable, S is 1‐possible, is somewhat weaker than the negative version, as positive conceivability entails negative conceivability but the reverse is not obviously the case. Much of my discussion will apply equally to both CP+ or CP−, so I will often just speak of CP, except where the distinction is relevant.

The case for premise (2) largely derives from the case for CP, and from here on I will mostly focus on the general principle rather than the specific premise. Of course, if it turns out that the general principle needs to be restricted to a certain class of sentences to be plausible, then the question will arise as to whether P&∼Q falls into that class. Why believe CP? In the first instance, the thesis is plausible because there are no clear counter‐examples to it. Principles linking conceivability and possibility have been widely accepted in the history of philosophy, but have more recently been questioned because of various counter‐examples, such as the Goldbach case (both Goldbach's conjecture and its negation are conceivable but only one is possible) and especially the Kripke cases (‘Hesperus is not Phosphorus’ is conceivable but not possible). But CP accommodates these examples straightforwardly, with the idealization (p. 325) accommodating Goldbach cases, and the primary/secondary distinction accommodating Kripke cases. If it handles these cases, then the central sources of resistance to conceivability–possibility principles is undermined. But, of course, there may be other possible sources of resistance. Before proceeding, it is useful to clarify CP by making clear what a counter‐example to it would involve. According to the two‐dimensional analysis, ordinary Kripkean a posteriori necessities such as ‘Water is H2O’ and ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ have a necessary secondary intension but a contingent primary intension. That is, such statements are 2‐ necessary but 1‐contingent: there are centred possible worlds (a Twin Earth world, or a world with distinct morning and evening stars) that verify their negations. When S is an a posteriori necessity of this sort, with a contingent primary intension, we might say that S is a weak a posteriori necessity. By contrast, we can say that an a posteriori necessity is a strong a posteriori necessity, or just a strong necessity, iff S has a necessary primary intension. Strong necessities are a posteriori necessities that are verified by all centred metaphysically possible worlds. It is not easy to give examples of strong necessities, as all of Kripke's a posteriori necessities appear to be weak necessities. But I will discuss some putative candidates in what follows. It is easy to see that CP− is equivalent to the thesis that there are no strong necessities. If S is negatively conceivable but not 1‐possible, then ∼S will be a strong necessity. If S is a strong necessity, then ∼S will be negatively conceivable but not 1‐possible.

Page 13 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism In so far as CP+ is potentially weaker than CP−, the relationship between CP+ and the thesis that there are no strong necessities is not as clear. Certainly any counter‐example to CP+ will yield a strong necessity, but the reverse is not obviously the case. To handle this we might define two classes of strong necessities, according to whether they provide counter‐examples to CP+ or merely to CP−. Let us say that a negative strong necessity is a statement S such that S is 1‐necessary and 2‐necessary but ∼S is negatively conceivable. The latter condition is equivalent to the requirement that S is not a priori, so negative strong necessities are equivalent to strong necessities as defined above. A positive strong necessity is a statement S such that S is 1‐necessary and 2‐necessary while ∼S is positively conceivable. Then all positive strong necessities are negative strong necessities, but the reverse is not trivially the case. CP− and CP+ are then equivalent to the theses that there are no negative strong necessities and that there are no positive strong necessities respectively. What would a strong necessity involve? To get an idea, consider a philosophical view on which it is metaphysically necessary that an omniscient being (e.g. God) exists, but on which it is not a priori that such a being exists. Then according to this view, ‘An omniscient being exists’ (or O) is an a posteriori necessity. Like all a posteriori necessities, O is 2‐necessary, and ∼O is negatively conceivable (and also positively conceivable, if we add the plausible claim that it is positively conceivable that there is no omniscient being). If O were an ordinary a posteriori necessity, then O would be 1‐ contingent: there would be a metaphysically possible world verifying ∼O. But if there is no omniscient being, then it seems that there is no such world. (p. 326) ‘There is an omniscient being’ does not seem to have any difference in its primary and secondary intensions, so if a world satisfies O, it verifies O. So given that O is 2‐necessary, O is 1‐ necessary. It follows that if this philosophical view is correct, then O is a strong necessity: it is at least a negative strong necessity, and given the positive conceivability claim above, it is a positive strong necessity. One could put the matter by saying that there is an epistemically possible scenario verifying ∼O, but no metaphysically possible world verifying ∼O. Here a scenario can be understood as corresponding to a maximal a priori coherent hypothesis, in the way that worlds correspond to maximal metaphysically possible hypotheses. (I give a formal treatment of scenarios in Chalmers 2004 and (forthcoming b), but here I will leave the notion intuitive. (One might call this sort of scenario a negative scenario, since it corresponds to a maximal negatively conceivable hypothesis. One could also define a positive scenario so that it corresponds to a maximal positively conceivable hypothesis.) The notion of scenarios is not defined in terms of metaphysical possibility, and in particular it is not assumed that scenarios correspond to metaphysically possible worlds. But nevertheless it is plausible that there is an intimate relationship. For any a posteriori necessity S there will be a scenario verifying ∼S. For example, as ‘Water is H2O’ is not a priori, there will be a scenario verifying ‘Water is not H2O’. That is, there will be some maximal a priori coherent hypothesis H (perhaps involving the assumption that the watery stuff is made of XYZ, and so on) such that if we accept H, we Page 14 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism should accept ‘Water is not H2O’. For ordinary a posteriori necessities these scenarios will correspond closely to centred metaphysically possible worlds, so that there will be a centred world verifying ∼S. For example, ‘Water is not H2O’ is verified by a centred XYZ‐ world, where the individual at the centre is and has always been surrounded by clear, drinkable XYZ in the oceans and lakes. There is little reason to doubt that such a world is metaphysically possible, and there is an intuitive sense in which it qualitatively matches the scenario that we imagine when we entertain the hypothesis that water is not XYZ. When S is a strong necessity, by contrast, there will be a scenario verifying ∼S, but this scenario will correspond to no metaphysically possible world. (When S is a positive strong necessity, there will be a positive scenario verifying ∼S; when S is a negative strong necessity, there will be a negative scenario verifying ∼S.) For example, given the theist view outlined above, there will be a (negative and positive) scenario verifying ‘There is no omniscient being’, involving some maximally detailed hypothesis under which there is no such being. But on this view there is no centred world that corresponds to this scenario, and there is no centred world that itself verifies ‘There is no omniscient being’. We might put this intuitively by saying that on this view the space of (centred) metaphysically possible worlds is smaller than the space of epistemically possible scenarios, at least in the relevant respect. On this view, there are scenarios that correspond to no world. To bring this back to the mind–body case: take the paradigmatic type‐B materialist who holds that premise (1) is true, premise (2) is false, and materialism is true. On this view, the material conditional P ⊃ Q (which is itself the negation of P&∼Q) is a strong necessity. The truth of materialism implies that it is 2‐necessary, the truth (p. 327) of (1) implies that it is a posteriori and its negation is 1‐conceivable, but the falsity of (2) implies that its negation is 1‐necessary. On this view, there will be a scenario verifying P&∼Q, including various specific zombie scenarios. But these scenarios will correspond to no metaphysically possible world. Note that the analogue of CP with scenarios instead of worlds is close to trivial: if S is conceivable in the relevant sense, there will automatically be a scenario verifying S (at least if the notions of a scenario and of verification are unproblematic). Even a type‐B materialist and a believer in strong necessities can accept that principle. They must simply deny that all scenarios correspond to worlds. So CP might be seen as equivalent to the thesis that for every scenario there is a corresponding world. My view is that for every scenario there is a corresponding world, and that there are no strong necessities. In The Conscious Mind I gave the following reasons for this: (i) strong necessities cannot be supported by analogy with other a posteriori necessities; (ii) they involve a far more radical sort of a posteriori necessity than Kripke's, requiring a distinction between conceptual and metaphysical possibility at the level of worlds; (iii) they lead to an ad hoc proliferation of modalities; (iv) they raise deep questions of coherence; (v) they will be brute and inexplicable; and (vi) the only motivation to posit a

Page 15 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism strong necessity in the mind–body case is the desire to save materialism. I still accept most of these reasons, but there is more to say. In the last decade or so numerous objections to CP have been proposed. These objections fall into a number of classes. The first, and largest, involves attempts at exhibiting clear cases of strong necessities. The second involves attempts at explaining how there might be strong necessities in the phenomenal case (if not elsewhere), by analysing the nature of phenomenal concepts. The third involves general philosophical objections. I will discuss the objections in the first class in the section that follows.

18.5 Are there Counter‐examples to CP? I will discuss a number of putative counter‐examples to CP in turn. A number of others are discussed in the expanded version of this chapter: objections from essential modes of presentation, from distinct homophonous expressions (Block 2007), from demonstratives (Schiffer 2003), from dancing qualia (Hawthorne 2007), from inscrutable truths, from the deeply contingent a priori (Hawthorne 2004), from disquotational truths (Yablo 2002), and from response‐enabled concepts (Yablo 2002).

18.5.1 Kripke Cases. It is occasionally proposed that some Kripkean a posteriori necessities are in fact strong necessities. In particular, it is sometimes proposed that coextensive names (p. 328) such as ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’ may have the same primary intension as well as the same secondary intension. If so, ‘Cicero is Tully’ is a strong necessity (as it is clearly a posteriori). In response: When we entertain the hypothesis that Cicero is not Tully, this hypothesis corresponds to specific scenarios that we can elaborate. In particular, the relevant scenarios may involve the hypothesis that the causal chains associated with the names ‘Cicero’ and ‘Tully’ pick out different historical individuals. A scenario like this certainly corresponds to a centred metaphysically possible world: there are certainly worlds where the causal chains associated with these words functions in this way. And it seems clear that if we discovered that our world were such a world we would reject the hypothesis that Cicero is Tully. So such a world seems to verify ‘Cicero is not Tully’ (although it may not satisfy ‘Cicero is not Tully’). Worlds like this can be found for any Kripkean a posteriori necessity S (as Kripke himself pointed out, in effect), and such worlds will always verify ∼S. One might resist the claim that the world in question verifies S by rejecting the claim that there is an a priori entailment (for the speaker in question) from a description of the world in question to S. In response, I think that the sort of considerations in Chalmers Page 16 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism and Jackson (2001) strongly suggest that these entailments are a priori at least in principle. But even if one rejects this claim, there clearly remains some distinctive epistemic relation between the world in question and ‘Cicero is not Tully’: in particular, it remains the case that if one accepts (hypothetically) that the actual world is qualitatively just like the world in question, and reflects on this hypothesis, then one will reject the claim that Cicero is not Tully. (Note that this is quite unlike the situation that the theist thinks obtains in the God case, where there is no world that stands in this inferential relation to ‘There is no God’.) So if one rejects a priori entailments, one can use this sort of inferential relation to define primary intensions, and ordinary Kripkean necessities will always have a primary intension that is false at some world.

18.5.2 Ordinary Macroscopic Truths Another class of examples comes from the suggestion that consciousness is not alone in its failure to be a priori entailed by microphysical truths. Block and Stalnaker (1999) have suggested that many ordinary macroscopic truths, such as ‘Water boils at 100 degrees’ (or W), are not a priori entailed in this way. If so, then P&∼W is at least negatively conceivable. But P&W is not possible (at least if water and its properties supervene on the microphysical), and it is not clearly 1‐possible, either. If it is not, then P&∼W is a counter‐example to CP−. In response: Chalmers and Jackson (2001) argue that these macroscopic truths are a priori entailed by P, or at least by PQTI, a conjunction of full physical, phenomenal, ‘that's all’, and indexical information. Of course P&∼Q, P&∼T, and P&∼I may be negatively conceivable, but the latter two are clearly also 1‐possible, while the former is precisely the main topic of dispute. So any failures of entailment by P associated (p. 329) with the failure of entailment to Q, T, or I give no further support to the existence of strong necessities. Such support would require at least a truth M such that PQTI does not a priori entail M, and such that PQTI ⊃ M is 2‐necessary and 1‐necessary. The arguments in Chalmers and Jackson (2001) suggest that at no ordinary macroscopic truths M are like this. In any case, even if one rejects the a priori entailment thesis here, these cases will yield at best exceptions to CP− (i.e. negative strong necessities), not exceptions to CP+ (i.e. positive strong necessities). Even if W above is like Q in that P&∼W and even PQTI&∼W is negatively conceivable, PQTI&∼W is not positively conceivable: ‘water‐zombies’ are not positively conceivable in the way that zombies are positively conceivable. So this sort of case leaves CP+ unthreatened.

18.5.3 Unknowable Mathematical Truths

Page 17 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism Perhaps the most challenging cases for CP− are mathematical truths M such that M is true (and so necessarily true and 1‐necessarily true) but not knowable, and so not knowable a priori. If there are such cases, M is a negative strong necessity (though not a positive strong necessity, as ∼M is not positively conceivable). Here one might appeal to unprovable true mathematical sentences, such as those whose existence is entailed by Godel's theorem. In response: Unprovability in a given system does not entail non‐apriority. For example, the consistency of Peano arithmetic is not provable in Peano arithmetic, but is still plausibly knowable a priori. One can make the case (see Chalmers 2002) that all true statements of arithmetic are knowable a priori at least under an idealization (i.e. our failure to know them a priori is due to certain limitations of our cognitive systems). One might worry about higher set theory, such as the continuum hypothesis, but here it is far from clear that such sentences are determinately true or false, and it is also far from clear that they are not knowable a priori under an idealization. So although these cases provide an interesting challenge to CP−, they do not provide clear counter‐examples to CP−. And, as in the previous case, there is no challenge to CP+ here.

18.5.4 Laws of Nature According to some philosophical views, laws of nature are not just naturally necessary but are metaphysically necessary. Shoemaker (1998) holds such a view, and suggests that it may provide a counter‐example to CP. In response: On some varieties of this view, laws of nature follow a version of the Kripkean model. That is, if mass in the actual world obeys certain laws, then nothing in any counterfactual world counts as mass unless it obeys exactly those laws, so any law involving mass will be necessary. This might hold because (p. 330) of the semantics of mass (which require that a counterfactual property have the same nomic role as actual mass in order to qualify as the referent of ‘mass’), or it might hold because of the metaphysics of mass (according to which properties such as mass have their nomic profile essentially, as on Shoemaker's view). On these models we need not deny that there are worlds that correspond to the scenario we conceive when we conceive that mass obeys different laws: it is just that such worlds will contain ‘schmass’ rather than mass. I think that it is implausible that the modal profile of ‘mass’ and/or the essential properties of mass are this precise (see Fine 2002 and Sidelle 2002 for arguments), but in any case, this model does not provide a counter‐example to CP. In this case, a schmass world may verify the hypothesis that the relevant law of nature is false, so laws of nature are not strong necessities. To yield strong necessities this sort of view must hold that not only are there no worlds where mass obeys different laws, but there are also no related worlds where something else, ‘schmass’, obeys those different laws. Here the relevant sort of view is one according to which the fundamental properties and laws of all worlds are the Page 18 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism fundamental properties and laws of our world (and on which these laws are not knowable a priori). In effect, this restricts the space of metaphysically possible worlds to the space of naturally possible worlds. If this view is correct, then a fundamental law will be a strong necessity: there will be no world corresponding to the scenario that we conceive when we conceive what is false. I think that there are no good reasons to accept this extremely strong view of laws of nature, and that there are good reasons to reject it. The best reasons to take seriously the hypothesis that laws of nature are necessary come from the Kripke and Shoemaker models above. But nothing in these models supports the strong view, or yields a strong necessity. Rather, the CP thesis can itself be taken as a reason to reject the view.

Page 19 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism

18.5.5 A Necessary God I have already noted that the existence of strong necessities is entailed by a theist view on which an omniscient being (or an omnipotent being, or a perfect being) exists necessarily but on which the existence of such a being is not knowable a priori. If we say that a god is by definition an omniscient being (or a perfect being, or whatever), then ‘A god exists’ will be a strong necessity. In response: I think that theist views of this sort are to be rejected. If the existence of such a god is knowable a priori, then it may exist necessarily. But if it is not, then one should conclude that such a being exists at best contingently. I cannot go over the arguments for believing in a necessary god here, but they all rest on highly contentious premises, and, once again, CP itself provides an argument against these views. The best way to defend the existence of a necessary god is to argue that a world without such a being is not even conceivable. Even if one believes that the existence of a god provides a strong necessity, it is not clear that this sort of strong necessity undermines the case against materialism. The debate over materialism uses necessity as a criterion of ontological distinctness: the question of whether physical truths necessitate phenomenal truths is relevant (p. 331) precisely in so far as it bears on the question of whether the phenomenal involves nothing ontologically ‘over and above’ the physical. But a variety of necessity in which the existence of a god is necessary will not be well suited to this role. On such a view, the existence of a god will be necessitated by physical truths, but such a god will presumably nevertheless be ontologically non‐physical. So if the only strong necessities are strong necessities of this sort, connecting ontologically distinct existences, they are no help to physicalism. Under this assumption, then, if P&∼Q is conceivable, Q will be something over and above the physical, either because it is necessitated by the physical or because it is tied to the physical only by this sort of strong necessity. Something similar applies to views on which laws of nature are strong necessities. Even on such views laws presumably connect ontologically distinct properties: if there is a fundamental law connecting properties A and B, this will not ground any sort of ontological reduction of one property to the other. Indeed, if this view is correct, then a dualist view with fundamental phenomenal properties and fundamental laws connecting them to the physical will itself be a view on which the phenomenal is necessitated by the physical. So, again, strong necessities of this sort are no help to the physicalist.

Page 20 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism

18.5.6 Meta‐modal Claims Yablo (1999) adapts the God case to provide an intriguing argument against CP. According to Yablo, it is at least conceivable that there is a necessarily existing god. It is also conceivable that there is no necessarily existing god. So if G is ‘It is necessary that there is an omniscient being’, then both G and ∼G are conceivable. If so, then by CP both G and ∼G are 1‐possible. There appears to be no relevant distinction between the primary and secondary intensions of the expressions involved, so it follows that G and ∼G are 2‐ possible, or (metaphysically) possible simpliciter. So it is possible that it is necessary that there is an omniscient being, and it is possible that it is not necessary that there is an omniscient being. But this is a contradiction, at least given S5 as the logic of the metaphysical modality. If it is possible that S is necessary, then S is necessary, so it is not possible that S is not necessary. In response: One could respond by denying S5, or by finding relevant two‐dimensional structure, but I think these moves are unpromising. One could also respond, more promisingly, by making the observation about the ontological relevance of this sort of necessity above. But I think it is best to deny that it is conceivable that there is a necessarily existing god, at least in the relevant sense of conceivability. Perhaps it is prima facie negatively conceivable that there is such a being, in that we cannot obviously rule it out a priori, but I do not think it is conceivable in any stronger sense. I can certainly form no clear and distinct conception of such a god (like many, I was suspicious of the idea the moment I heard about it as a student), and continued rational reflection reveals all sorts of problems with the idea. Once one accepts that it is conceivable that there is no god (and this seems like a much stronger intuition, at least to me), this has a strong tendency to undermine the coherence of the hypothesis that a god exists necessarily. (p. 332)

The problematic issues here arise because of the double modality: we are conceiving not just of non‐modal qualitative features of worlds, but also of what is possible or necessary within those worlds. Conceiving of a god (an omnipotent, omniscient, and benevolent being, say) is arguably not too hard; but to conceive in addition that the being exists necessarily, we have to conceive that the space of possible worlds is such that this god exists in each of them, despite the conceivability of a godless world. That is, we have to conceive that CP is itself false. This is what does all the work in the example: if it is conceivable that CP is false, then (by CP!) it is possible that CP is false. CP is surely necessarily true if it is true at all, so it follows from the possible falsity of CP that CP is false. Another way to respond to this sort of argument is to restrict the conceivability– possibility thesis to claims about the distribution of non‐modal properties within worlds, leaving double modals outside its scope. I think this response would be defensible, and not entirely ad hoc. (CP would then apply to worlds considered non‐modally, but not to Page 21 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism ‘cosmoses’ of possible worlds.) But I prefer to hold on to the stronger thesis, by denying that it is conceivable that CP is false. I hold that CP is a priori, although highly non‐trivial, like many theses in philosophy (an a priori argument for CP is given in Chalmers 1999, and in the expanded version of this chapter). If this is correct, then CP is not conceivably false on ideal rational reflection, and it is not ideally conceivable that a necessarily existing god exists.

18.5.7 The Conceivability of Materialism A closely related meta‐modal argument (Marton 1998; Sturgeon 2000; Frankish 2007) that is specific to the mind–body domain proceeds as follows. (i) It is at least conceivable that materialism is true about consciousness. So (ii) it is conceivable that P ⊃ Q is necessary. By CP (and setting aside two‐dimensional structure), it follows that (iii) it is possible that P ⊃ Q is necessary. But from this it follows (using S5) that (iv) P ⊃ Q is necessary. Using CP and S5 one can equally infer from the fact that (v) it is conceivable that P ⊃ Q is not necessary to the conclusion that (vi) P ⊃ Q is not necessary. But (iv) and (vi) are contradictory. So one should reject CP. My response here parallels the response in the god case. It may be prima facie negatively conceivable that materialism is true about consciousness, but it is not obviously conceivable in any stronger sense. Many people have noted that it is very hard to imagine that consciousness is a physical process. I do not think this unimaginability is so obvious that it should be used as a premise in an argument against materialism, but, likewise, the imaginability claim cannot be used as a premise either. And if I am right that CP is a priori, then there is an a priori argument that P ⊃ Q is not necessary, so that it will not even be ideally negatively conceivable that P ⊃ Q is necessary.

(p. 333)

18.6 Conclusion

None of the attempts above provides a clear counter‐example to CP. In most cases I think there are reasonably straightforward independent grounds for rejecting the claim that the cases in question provide strong necessities. Perhaps the most serious challenges come from mathematical cases such as the continuum hypothesis and from meta‐modal cases. These are the cases where, in advance of commitment to CP, independent reasoning does not clearly settle whether or not strong necessities are involved. Still, these are cases where the initial situation is unclear, rather than cases where there is a clear counter‐example. If one can argue for CP independently, then these cases are not too much of a threat. It is also worth noting that cases such as these seem to work best as challenges to CP− rather than to CP+, so that CP+, which is all that is required for the argument against materialism, is relatively unthreatened. We have also seen at various points along the way Page 22 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism that even if one takes certain cases to involve strong necessities, the existence of such strong necessities will still be compatible with modified versions of CP (say, a version involving ontological necessities in the law/god cases, or a version involving non‐modal sentences in the meta‐modal cases) that will be strong enough for the anti‐materialist argument to go through. So where the consideration of counter‐examples to CP is concerned, the anti‐materialist seems to be on reasonably strong ground. Materialists can also object to CP in other ways: for example, by giving theoretical arguments for why it is false without relying on counter‐examples, or by giving an explanation of why there should be special counter‐examples in the case of consciousness. The second strategy has been especially popular, with a number of theorists arguing that special treatment in the case of consciousness is warranted by the special nature of phenomenal concepts (e.g. Loar 1997; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Papineau 2002). I discuss objections of this sort in the expanded version of this chapter, and also give a theoretical argument for the truth of CP, arguing that it is grounded in constitutive links between the modal and rational domains.2

References Ashwell, L. (2003), ‘Conceivability and Modal Error’, MA thesis (University of Auckland). Balog, K. (1999), ‘Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind–Body Problem’, Philosophical Review, 108: 497–528. Block, N. (2007), ‘Max Black's Objection to Mind‐Body Identity’, in T. Alter and S. Walter, (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 249–306. (p. 334)

Block, N., and Stalnaker, R. (1999), ‘Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap’, Philosophical Review, 108: 1–46. Braddon‐Mitchell, D. (2003), ‘Qualia and Analytical Conditionals’, Journal of Philosophy, 100: 111–35. Chalmers, D. J. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1999), ‘Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54: 473–96. —— (2002), ‘Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?’ in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 145–200. —— (2003), ‘The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief’, in Q. Smith and A. Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 220–72. Page 23 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism —— (2004), ‘Epistemic Two‐dimensional Semantics’, Philosophical Studies, 118: 153–226. —— (2005), ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument’, in P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa, and D. Stoljar (eds.), There's Something About Mary (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 269–98. —— (forthcoming a), The Character of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (forthcoming b), The Nature of Epistemic Space, in A. Egan and B. Weatherson (eds.), Epistemic Modality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Chalmers, D. J., and Jackson, F. (2001), ‘Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation’, Philosophical Review, 110: 315–61. Fine, K. (2002), ‘The Varieties of Necessity’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 253–82. Frankish, K. (2007), ‘The Anti‐zombie Argument’, Philosophical Quarterly, 57: 650–66. Hawthorne, J. (2002), ‘Advice to Physicalists’, Philosophical Studies, 109: 17–52. —— (2004), ‘Deeply Contingent A Priori Knowledge’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 247–69. —— (2007), ‘Dancing Qualia and Direct Reference’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 195–209. Hill, C., and McLaughlin, B. (1999), ‘There are Fewer Things than are Dreamt Of in Chalmers' Philosophy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59: 445–54. Ismael, J. (1999), ‘Science and the Phenomenal’, Philosophy of Science, 66: 351–69. Jackson, F. (1998), From Metaphysics to Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Kirk, R. (1999), ‘Why There Couldn't Be Zombies’, Aristotelian Society Supplement, 73: 1– 16. Loar, B. (1997), ‘Phenomenal States (Second Version)’, in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 597–616. Lynch, M. (2006), ‘Zombies and the Case of the Phenomenal Pickpocket’, Synthese, 149: 37–58. Marcus, E. (2004), ‘Why Zombies are Inconceivable’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82: 477–90. Marton, P. (1998), ‘Zombies vs. Materialists: The Battle for Conceivability’, Southwest Philosophy Review, 14: 131–8. Page 24 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism Papineau, D. (2002), Thinking About Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Perry, J. (2001), Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Schiffer, S. (2003), The Things We Mean (Oxford: Oxford University Press) (sect. on ‘two‐dimensional semantics and propositional‐attitude content’). (p. 335)

Shoemaker, S. (1998), ‘Causal and Metaphysical Necessity’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79: 59–77. Sidelle, A. (2002), ‘On the Metaphysical Contingency of Laws of Nature’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 309–36. Soames, S. (2004), Reference and Description: The Case Against Two‐dimensionalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Stalnaker, R. (2002), ‘What is it Like to be a Zombie?’ in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 385–400. Stoljar, D. (2001), ‘The Conceivability Argument and Two Conceptions of the Physical’, Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 393–413. Sturgeon, S. (2000), Matters of Mind: Consciousness, Reason, and Nature (London: Routledge). Thomas, N. J. T. (1998), ‘Zombie Killer’, in S. Hameroff, A. Kaszniak, and A. Scott (eds.), Toward a Science of Consciousness II (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 171–7. Yablo, S. (1999), ‘Concepts and Consciousness’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54: 455–63. —— (2002), ‘Coulda, woulda, shoulda’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 441–92. (p. 336)

Notes: (*) An expanded version of this article is forthcoming in my The Character of Consciousness (Oxford University Press), and is also available online at http://consc.net/ papers/2dargument.html. Some material in this paper is drawn from Chalmers (1999) and (2002). (1) A related position arises from views on which laws of nature are necessary (e.g. Shoemaker 1998), and on which there is a lawful connection between physical properties and phenomenal properties in our world. Such a view may hold that it is essential to physical properties that they have this nomic profile, so that there is no world satisfying Page 25 of 26

The Two‐Dimensional Argument Against Materialism P&∼Q. Some versions of this view will deny (2), and are discussed later in the chapter. But other versions may accept (2), holding that there is a world verifying P&∼Q, but will hold that it involves distinct ‘schmysical’ properties that lack this nomic profile. The resulting view resembles Russellian monism in some respects, but differs from the usual form in taking the connection between physical and phenomenal properties to be nomic in the first instance. Because it turns on this nomic connection, this view does not provide any loophole for materialism: at best, it yields a version of property dualism on which the laws of nature connecting physical and phenomenal properties are necessary. (2) In the expanded version of this chapter I also consider the relation between the arguments I have discussed here and other anti‐materialist arguments, including the knowledge argument, the property‐dualism argument, Kripke's modal argument, and Descartes's argument from disembodiment.

David J. Chalmers

David J. Chalmers is Professor of Philosophy and ARC Federation Fellow, Director of the Centre for Consciousness, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University, Canberra.

Page 26 of 26

Intentional Systems Theory

Oxford Handbooks Online Intentional Systems Theory   Daniel Dennett The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0020

Abstract and Keywords Intentional systems theory is in the first place an analysis of the meanings of such everyday ‘mentalistic’ terms as ‘believe’, ‘desire’, ‘expect’, ‘decide’, and ‘intend’: the terms of ‘folk psychology’ that we use to interpret, explain, and predict the behaviour of other human beings, animals, some artefacts such as robots and computers, and indeed ourselves. In traditional parlance we seem to be attributing minds to the things we thus interpret, and this raises a host of questions about the conditions under which a thing can be truly said to have a mind, or to have beliefs, desires, and other ‘mental’ states. According to intentional systems theory, these questions can best be answered by analysing the logical presuppositions and methods of our attribution practices, when we adopt the intentional stance toward something. Keywords: intentional systems theory, folk psychology, mentalistic terms, human behaviour, mental states, intentional stance

Page 1 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory INTENTIONAL

systems theory is in the first place an analysis of the meanings of such

everyday ‘mentalistic’ terms as ‘believe’, ‘desire’, ‘expect’, ‘decide’, and ‘intend’: the terms of ‘folk psychology’ (Dennett 1971) that we use to interpret, explain, and predict the behaviour of other human beings, animals, some artefacts such as robots and computers, and indeed ourselves. In traditional parlance we seem to be attributing minds to the things we thus interpret, and this raises a host of questions about the conditions under which a thing can be truly said to have a mind, or to have beliefs, desires, and other ‘mental’ states. According to intentional systems theory, these questions can best be answered by analysing the logical presuppositions and methods of our attribution practices, when we adopt the intentional stance toward something. Anything that is usefully and voluminously predictable from the intentional stance is, by definition, an intentional system. The intentional stance is the strategy of interpreting the behaviour of an entity (person, animal, artefact, whatever) by treating it as if it were a rational agent who governed its ‘choice’ of ‘action’ by a ‘consideration’ of its ‘beliefs’ and ‘desires’. The scare‐quotes around all these terms draw attention to the fact that some of their standard connotations may be set aside in the interests of exploiting their central features: their role in practical reasoning, and hence in the prediction of the behaviour of practical reasoners.

19.1 The Three Stances The distinctive features of the intentional stance can best be seen by contrasting it with two more basic stances or strategies of prediction: the physical stance and the (p. 340) design stance. The physical stance is simply the standard laborious method of the physical sciences, in which we use whatever we know about the laws of physics and the physical constitution of the things in question to devise our prediction. When I predict that a stone released from my hand will fall to the ground, I am using the physical stance. In general, for things that are neither alive nor artefacts the physical stance is the only available strategy, though there are important exceptions, as we shall see. Every physical thing, whether designed or alive or not, is subject to the laws of physics and hence behaves in ways that in principle can be explained and predicted from the physical stance. Whether the thing I release from my hand is an alarm clock or a goldfish, I make the same prediction about its downward trajectory, on the same basis. Predicting the more interesting behaviours of alarm clocks and goldfish from the physical stance is seldom practical. Alarm clocks, being designed objects (unlike the stone), are also amenable to a fancier style of prediction: prediction from the design stance. Suppose I categorize a novel object as an alarm clock. I can quickly reason that if I depress a few buttons just so, then some hours later the alarm clock will make a loud noise. I don't need to work out the specific physical laws that explain this marvellous regularity; I simply assume that it has a particular design—the design we call an alarm clock—and that it will function properly, as Page 2 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory designed. Design‐stance predictions are riskier than physical‐stance predictions, because of the extra assumptions I have to take on board: that an entity is designed as I suppose it to be, and that it will operate according to that design; that is, it will not malfunction. Designed things are occasionally misdesigned, and sometimes they break. (Nothing that happens to, or in, a stone counts as its malfunctioning, since it has no function in the first place, and if it breaks in two, the result is two stones, not a single broken stone.) When a designed thing is fairly complicated (a chainsaw in contrast to an axe, for instance) the moderate price one pays in riskiness is more than compensated for by the tremendous ease of prediction. Nobody would prefer to fall back on the fundamental laws of physics to predict the behaviour of a chainsaw when there was a handy diagram of its moving parts available to consult instead. An even riskier and swifter stance is the intentional stance, a subspecies of the design stance, in which the designed thing is treated as an agent of sorts, with beliefs and desires and enough rationality to do what it ought to do given those beliefs and desires. An alarm clock is so simple that this fanciful anthropomorphism is, strictly speaking, unnecessary for our understanding of why it does what it does, but adoption of the intentional stance is more useful—indeed, well‐nigh obligatory—when the artefact in question is much more complicated than an alarm clock. Consider chess‐playing computers, which all succumb neatly to the same simple strategy of interpretation: just think of them as rational agents who want to win, and who know the rules and principles of chess and the positions of the pieces on the board. Instantly your problem of predicting and interpreting their behaviour is made vastly easier than it would be if you tried to use the physical or the design stance. At any moment in the chess game, simply look at the chessboard and draw up a list of all the legal moves available to the computer (p. 341) when its turn to play comes up (there will usually be several dozen candidates). Now rank the legal moves from best (wisest, most rational) to worst (stupidest, most self‐defeating), and make your prediction: the computer will make the best move. You may well not be sure what the best move is (the computer may ‘appreciate’ the situation better than you do!), but you can almost always eliminate all but four or five candidate moves, which still gives you tremendous predictive leverage. You could improve on this leverage and predict in advance exactly which move the computer will make—at a tremendous cost of time and effort—by falling back to the design stance and considering the millions of lines of computer code that you can calculate will be streaming through the CPU of the computer after you make your move, and this would be much, much easier than falling all the way back to the physical stance and calculating the flow of electrons that results from pressing the computer's keys. But in many situations, especially when the best move for the computer to make is so obvious it counts as a ‘forced’ move, you can predict its move with well‐nigh perfect accuracy without all the effort of either the design stance or the physical stance. It is obvious that the intentional stance works effectively when the goal is predicting a chess‐playing computer, since its designed purpose is to ‘reason’ about the best move to make in the highly rationalistic setting of chess. If a computer program is running an oil refinery, it is almost equally obvious that its various moves will be made in response to its Page 3 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory detection of conditions that more or less dictate what it should do, given its larger designed purposes. Here the presumption of excellence or rationality of design stands out vividly, since an incompetent programmer's effort might yield a program that seldom did what the experts said it ought to do in the circumstances. When information systems (or control systems) are well designed, the rationales for their actions will be readily discernible, and highly predictive—whether or not the engineers that wrote the programs attached ‘comments’ to the source code explaining these rationales to onlookers, as good practice dictates. We needn't know anything about computer programming to predict the behaviour of the system; what we need to know about is the rational demands of running an oil refinery.

Page 4 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory

19.2 The Broad Domain of the Intentional Stance The central epistemological claim of intentional‐systems theory is that when we treat each other as intentional systems, using attributions of beliefs and desires to govern our interactions and generate our anticipations, we are similarly finessing our ignorance of the details of the processes going on in each other's skulls (and in our own!) and relying, unconsciously, on the fact that to a remarkably good first approximation people are rational. We risk our lives without a moment's hesitation when we (p. 342) go out on the highway, confident that the oncoming cars are controlled by people who want to go on living and know how to stay alive under most circumstances. Suddenly thrust into a novel human scenario, we can usually make sense of it effortlessly, indeed involuntarily, thanks to our innate ability to see what people ought to believe (the truth about what's put before them) and ought to desire (what's good for them). So second‐nature are these presumptions that when we encounter a person who is blind, deaf, self‐destructive, or insane we find ourselves unable to adjust our expectations without considerable attention and practice. There is no controversy about the fecundity of our folk‐psychological anticipations, but much disagreement over how to explain this bounty. Do we learn dozens or hundreds or thousands of ‘laws of nature’ along the lines of ‘If a person is awake, with eyes open and facing a bus, he will tend to believe there is a bus in front of him’ and ‘Whenever people believe they can win favour at low cost to themselves, they will tend to cooperate with others, even strangers’, or are all these rough‐cast laws generated on demand by an implicit sense that these are the rational responses under the circumstances? In favour of the latter hypothesis is the fact that whereas there are indeed plenty of stereotypic behaviour patterns that can be encapsulated by such generalizations (which might, in principle, be learned seriatim as we go through life), it is actually hard to generate a science‐fictional scenario so novel, so unlike all other human predicaments, that people are simply unable to imagine how people might behave under those circumstances. ‘What would you do if that happened to you?’ is the natural question to ask, and along with such unhelpful responses as ‘I'd probably faint dead away’ comes the tellingly normative ‘Well, I hope I'd be clever enough to see that I should … ’. And when we see characters behaving oh so cleverly in these remarkably non‐stereotypical settings, we have no difficulty understanding what they are doing and why. Like our capacity to understand entirely novel sentences of our natural languages, our ability to make sense of the vast array of human interactions bespeaks a generative capacity that is to some degree innate in normal people. We just as naturally and unthinkingly extend the intentional stance to animals, a non‐ optional tactic if we are trying to catch a wily beast, and a useful tactic if we are trying to organize our understanding of the behaviours of simpler animals, and even plants. Like the lowly thermostat, as simple an artefact as can sustain a rudimentary intentional‐ Page 5 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory stance interpretation, the clam has its behaviours, and they are rational, given its limited outlook on the world. We are not surprised to learn that trees that are able to sense the slow encroachment of green‐reflecting rivals shift resources into growing taller faster, because that's the smart thing for a plant to do under those circumstances. Where on the downward slope to insensate thinghood does ‘real’ believing and desiring stop and mere ‘as if’ believing and desiring take over? According to intentional‐systems theory, this demand for a bright line is ill‐motivated.

Page 6 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory

19.3 Original Intentionality versus Derived or ‘as if’ Intentionality (p. 343)

Uses of the intentional stance to explain the behaviour of computers and other complex artefacts are not just common; they are universal and practically ineliminable. So it is commonly accepted, even by the critics of intentional‐systems theory, that such uses are legitimate, so long as two provisos are noted: the attributions made are of derived intentionality, not original or intrinsic intentionality, and (hence) the attributions are, to one degree or another, metaphorical, not literal. But intentional‐systems theory challenges these distinctions, claiming that (1) there is no principled (theoretically motivated) way to distinguish ‘original’ intentionality from ‘derived’ intentionality, and (2) there is a continuum of cases of legitimate attributions, with no theoretically motivated threshold distinguishing the ‘literal’ from the ‘metaphorical’, or merely ‘as if’, cases. The contrast between original and derived intentionality is unproblematic when we look at the paradigm cases from everyday life, but when we attempt to promote this mundane distinction into a metaphysical divide that should apply to all imaginable artefacts, we create serious illusions. Whereas our simpler artefacts, such as painted signs and written shopping lists, can indeed be seen to derive their meanings from their functional roles in our practices, and hence not have any intrinsic meaning independent of our meaning, we have begun making sophisticated artefacts such as robots, whose trajectories can unfold without any direct dependence on us, their creators, and whose discriminations give their internal states a sort of meaning to them that may be unknown to us and not in our service. The robot poker player that bluffs its makers seems to be guided by internal states that function just as a human poker player's intentions do, and if that is not original intentionality, it is hard to say why not. Moreover, our ‘original’ intentionality, if it is not a miraculous or God‐given property, must have evolved over the aeons from ancestors with simpler cognitive equipment, and there is no plausible candidate for an origin of original intentionality that doesn't run afoul of a problem with the second distinction, between literal and metaphorical attributions.

The intentional stance works (when it does) whether or not the attributed goals are genuine or natural or ‘really appreciated’ by the so‐called agent, and this tolerance is crucial to understanding how genuine goal‐seeking could be established in the first place. Does the macromolecule really want to replicate itself? The intentional stance explains what is going on, regardless of how we answer that question. Consider a simple organism —say a planarian or an amoeba—moving non‐randomly across the bottom of a laboratory dish, always heading to the nutrient‐rich end of the (p. 344) dish, or away from the toxic end. This organism is seeking the good, or shunning the bad—its own good and bad, not those of some human artefact‐user. Seeking one's own good is a fundamental feature of any rational agent, but are these simple organisms seeking or just ‘seeking’? We don't

Page 7 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory need to answer that question. The organism is a predictable intentional system in either case. By exploiting this deep similarity between the simplest—one might as well say most mindless—intentional systems and the most complex (ourselves), the intentional stance also provides a relatively neutral perspective from which to investigate the differences between our minds and simpler minds. For instance, it has permitted the design of a host of experiments shedding light on whether other species, or young children, are capable of adopting the intentional stance—and hence are higher‐order intentional systems. A first‐ order intentional system is one whose behaviour is predictable by attributing (simple) beliefs and desires to it. A second‐order intentional system is predictable only if it is attributed beliefs about beliefs, or beliefs about desires, or desires about beliefs, and so forth. A being that can be seen to act on the expectation that you will discover that it wants you to think that it doesn't want the contested food would be a fifth‐order intentional system. Although imaginative hypotheses about ‘theory of mind modules’ (Leslie 1991) and other internal mechanisms (e.g. Baron‐Cohen 1995) have been advanced to account for these competences, the evidence for the higher‐order competences themselves must be adduced and analysed independently of these proposals about internal mechanisms, and this has been done by cognitive ethologists (Dennett 1983; Byrne and Whiten 1988) and developmental psychologists, among others, using the intentional stance to design the experiments that generate the attributions that in turn generate testable predictions of behaviour. The intentional stance is thus a theory‐neutral way of capturing the cognitive competences of different organisms (or other agents) without committing the investigator to overspecific hypotheses about the internal structures that underlie the competences. (A good review of the intentional stance in cognitive science can be found in three essays in Brook and Ross (2002)—by Griffin and Baron‐Cohen, Seyfarth and Cheney, and Ross.) Just as we can rank‐order chess‐playing computers and evaluate their tactical strengths and weaknesses independently of any consideration of their computational architecture, so we can compare children with adults, or members of different species, on various cognitive sophistications in advance of having any detailed hypotheses about how specific brain differences account for them. We can also take advantage of the intentional stance to explore models that break down large, sophisticated agents into organizations of simpler subsystems that are themselves intentional systems, subpersonal agents that are composed of teams of still simpler, ‘stupider’ agents, until we reach a level where the agents are ‘so stupid that they can be replaced by a machine’—a level at which the residual competence can be accounted for directly at the design stance. This tactic, often called ‘homuncular functionalism’, has been widely exploited in cognitive science, but it is sometimes misunderstood. See Bennett and Hacker (2003) for objections to this use of the intentional stance and Dennett (2007) for a rebuttal. (p. 345) Hornsby (2000) offers a more nuanced discussion of the tensions between the personal and subpersonal levels of explanation.

Page 8 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory A natural reaction to the intentional stance's remarkable tolerance of penumbral or metaphorical (or, to some critics, downright false) attributions is to insist on hunting for an essence of belief (and desire, etc.) that some of these dubious cases simply lack. The task then becomes drawing the line, marking the necessary and sufficient conditions for true believers. The psychologist David Premack (1983), for instance, has proposed that only second‐order intentional systems, capable of beliefs about beliefs (their own and others') can really be counted as believers, a theme that bears similarity to Davidson's claims (e.g. 1975) about why animals are not really capable of thought. A more elaborately defended version is Robert Brandom's attempt to distinguish ‘simple intentional systems’ (such as all animals and all existing artefacts, as well as subpersonal agencies or subsystems) from ‘interpreting intentional systems’ in Making it Explicit (1994). Brandom argues that only social creatures, capable of enforcing norms, are capable of genuine belief. An alternative is to turn the issue inside out, and recognize that the ‘true’ cases are better viewed as limiting cases, extreme versions, of an underlying common pattern. Consider a few examples of the use of intentional terms, spread across the spectrum: A. When evolution discovers a regularity or constancy in the environment, it designs adaptations that tacitly presuppose that regularity; when there is expectable variation instead of constancy, evolution has to go to the expense of specifying the adaptive response to the various different conditions. B. When a cuckoo chick hatches, it looks for other eggs in the nest, and if it finds them, it tries to push them out of the nest because they are in competition for the resources it needs. The cuckoo doesn't understand this, of course, but this is the rationale of its behaviour. C. The computer pauses during boot‐up because it thinks it is communicating with another computer on a local area network, and it is waiting for a response to its greeting. D. White castled, in order to protect the bishop from an anticipated attack from Black's knight. E. He swerved because he wanted to avoid the detached hubcap that he perceived was rolling down the street towards his car. F. She wanted to add baking soda, and noticing that the tin in her hand said ‘Baking Soda’ on it, she decided to open it. G. Holmes recalled that whoever rang the bell was the murderer, and, observing that the man in the raincoat was the only man in the room tall enough to reach the bell rope, he deduced that the man in the raincoat was the culprit, and thereupon rushed to disarm him.

Page 9 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory The last example is a paradigm of rational belief, but even in this case the attribution leaves a great deal of the reasoning inexplicit. Notice, too, that in the other cases of quite unproblematic, unmetaphorical human belief, such as (E), the swerving case, it is unlikely that anything like an explicit representation of the relevant beliefs and (p. 346) desires (the propositional attitudes) occurred in the driver's stream of consciousness. Had it not been for his beliefs about the relative danger of swerving and being hit by an object, he would not have taken the action he did; he would not have swerved to avoid a sheet of paper, for instance, and he would not have swerved had he believed there was a bus in the lane he swerved into, but it is not clear how, if at all, these guiding beliefs are represented unconsciously; there are so many of them. Similarly, the cook in (F) may have quite ‘unthinkingly’ opened the tin of baking soda, but she would not have opened a tin of loose tea or molasses had her hand fallen on it instead. Attributing a large list of beliefs to these agents—including propositions they might be hard‐pressed to arteculate— in order to account for their actions is a practice as secure as it is familiar, and if some of these informational states don't pass somebody's test for genuine belief, so much the worse for the claim that such a test must be employed to distinguish literal from metaphorical attributions. The model of beliefs as sentences of Mentalese written in the belief box, as some would have it, is not obligatory, and may be an artefact of attending to extreme cases of human belief rather than a dictate of cognitive engineering.

19.4 Objections Considered Although the earliest definition of the intentional stance (Dennett 1971) suggested to many that it was merely an instrumentalist strategy, not a theory of real or genuine belief, this common misapprehension has been extensively discussed and rebutted in subsequent accounts (Dennett 1987, 1991, 1996). The fact that the theory is maximally neutral about the internal structures that accomplish the rational competences it presupposes has led to attempted counter‐examples. (1) The Martian marionette (Peacocke 1983). Suppose we found an agent (called ‘The Body’ by Peacocke) that passed the intentional‐stance test of agency with flying colours but proved, when surgically opened, to be filled with radio transceivers; its every move, however predictable and explicable by our attributions of beliefs and desires to it, was actually caused by some off‐stage Martian computer program controlling the otherwise lifeless body as a sort of radio‐controlled puppet. The controlling program ‘has been given the vast but finite number of conditionals specifying what a typical human would do with given past history and current stimulation; so it can cause The Body to behave in any circumstances exactly as a human being would’ (Peacocke 1983: 205). This is no counter‐example, as we can see by exploring the different ways the further details of the fantasy could be fleshed out. If the off‐stage controller controls this body and no other, then we were certainly right to attribute the beliefs and desires to the person whose body we have surgically explored; this person, like Dennett in ‘Where am I?’ (Dennett 1978), simply keeps his (silicon) brain in a non‐traditional location. If, on the other hand, the Martian program has more (p. 347) than one (pseudo‐)agent under Page 10 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory control, and is coordinating their activities (and not just providing in one place n different independent agent‐brains), then the Martian program itself is the best candidate for being the intentional system whose actions we are predicting and explaining. (The Martian program in this case really is a puppeteer, and we should recast all the only apparently independent beliefs and desires of the various agents as in reality the intended manifestations of the master agent. But of course we must check further on this hypothesis to see if the Martian program is in turn controlled by another outside agent or agents or is autonomous.) What matters in the identification of the agent to whom the beliefs and desires are properly attributed is autonomy, not specific structures. Of course a bowl of structureless jelly or confetti is not a possible seat of the soul, simply because the complex multi‐track dispositions of a mind have to be realized somehow, in an information‐processing system with many reliably moving (and designed) parts. (2) The giant look‐up table (Block 1982): Having used the intentional stance to attribute lots of clever thoughts, beliefs, and well‐informed desires to whoever is answering my questions in the Turing test, I lift the veil and discover a computer system that, when opened, turns out to have nothing in it but a giant look‐up table, with all the possible short intelligent conversations in it, in alphabetical order. The only ‘moving part’ is the alphabetic string‐searcher that finds the next canned move in this pre‐played game of conversation and thereupon issues it. Surely this is no true believer, even though it is voluminously predictable from the intentional stance, thereby meeting the conditions of the definition. There are several ways of rebutting this counter‐example, drawing attention to different foibles of philosophical method. One is to observe that the definition of an intentional system, like most sane definitions, has the tacit rider that the entity in question must be physically possible; this imagined system would be a computer memory larger than the visible universe, operating faster than the speed of light. If we are allowed to postulate miraculous (physics‐defying) properties to things, it is no wonder we can generate counter‐intuitive ‘possibilities’. One might as well claim that when one opened up the would‐be believer one found nothing therein but a cup of cold coffee balanced on a computer keyboard, which vibrated in just the miraculously coincidental ways that would be required for it to type out apparently intelligent answers to all the questions posed. Surely not a believer! But also not possible. A more instructive response ignores the physical impossibility of the ‘Vast’ (Dennett 1995) set of alphabetized clever conversations, and notes that the canning of all these conversations in the memory is itself a process (an R&D process) that requires an explanation (unless it is yet another miracle or a ‘cosmic coincidence’). How was the quality control imposed? What process exhaustively pruned away the stupid or nonsensical continuations before alphabetizing the results? Here it is useful to consider the use of the intentional stance in evolutionary biology:

Page 11 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory Francis Crick, one of the discoverers of the structure of DNA, once jokingly credited his colleague Leslie Orgel with ‘Orgel's Second Rule’: Evolution is cleverer than you are. Even the (p. 348) most experienced evolutionary biologists are often startled by the power of natural selection to ‘discover’ an ‘ingenious’ solution to a design problem posed by nature. When evolutionists like Crick marvel at the cleverness of the process of natural selection they are not acknowledging intelligent design! The designs found in nature are nothing short of brilliant, but the process of design that generates them is utterly lacking in intelligence of its own. (Dennett 2006: 37–8) The process of natural selection is a blind, foresightless, purposeless process of trial and error, with the automatic retention of those slight improvements (relative to some challenge posed by the world) that happen by chance. We can contrast it with intelligent design. Now how did the giant look‐up table consisting of all and only clever conversations come to be created? Was it the result of some multi‐zillion‐year process of natural selection (yet another impossibility) or was it handcrafted by some intelligence or intelligences? If the latter, then we can see that Block's counter‐example is a close kin to Peacocke's. Suppose we discovered that Oscar Wilde lay awake nights thinking of deft retorts to likely remarks and committing these pairs to memory so that he could deliver them if and when the occasion arose ‘without missing a beat’. Would this cast any doubt on our categorization of him as an intelligent thinker? Why should it matter when the cogitation is done, if it is all designed to meet the needs of a time‐pressured world in an efficient way? This lets us see that in the incompletely imagined case that Block provides it might not be a mistake to attribute beliefs and desires to this surpassingly strange entity! Just as Peacocke's puppet does its thinking in a strange place, this one does its thinking at a strange time! The intentional stance is maximally neutral about how (or where, or when) the hard work of cognition gets done, but guarantees that the work is done by testing for success. In the actual world, of course, the only way to deliver real‐time cleverness in response to competitively variegated challenges (as in the Turing Test) is to generate it from a finite supply of already partially designed components. Sometimes the cleverest thing you can do is to quote something already beautifully designed by some earlier genius; sometimes it is better to construct something new, but of course you don't have to coin all the words, or invent all the moves, from scratch.

Coming from the opposite pole, Stich and others have criticized the intentional stance for relying on the rationality assumption, making people out to be much more rational than they actually are (see e.g. Stich 1981; Nichols and Stich 2003; Webb 1994). These objections overlook two facts. First, without a background of routine and voluminous fulfilment of rational expectations by even the most deranged human beings, such unfortunates could not be ascribed irrational beliefs in the first place. Human behaviour is simply not interpretable except as being in the (rational) service of some beliefs and desires or other. And second, when irrationality does loom large, it is far from clear that there is any stable interpretation of the relevant beliefs (see e.g. Dennett 1987: 83–116; 1994: 517–30).

Page 12 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory

(p. 349)

19.5 Summary

Intentional systems theory is a theory about how and why we are able to make sense of the behaviours of so many complicated things by considering them as agents. It is not directly a theory of the internal mechanisms that accomplish the roughly rational guidance thereby predicted. This very neutrality regarding the internal details permits intentional systems theory to play its role as a middle‐level specifier of subsystem competencies (subpersonal agents, in effect) in advance of detailed knowledge of how they in turn are implemented. Eventually we arrive at intentional systems that are simple enough to describe without further help from the intentional stance. Bridging the chasm between personal‐level folk psychology and the activities of neural circuits is a staggering task of imagination that benefits from this principled relaxation of the conditions that philosophers have tried to impose on (genuine, adult) human belief and desire. Intentional systems theory also permits us to chart the continuities between simpler animal minds and our own minds, and even the similarities with processes of natural selection that ‘discover’ all the design improvements that can thereby be discerned. The use of the intentional stance in both computer science and evolutionary biology, to say nothing of animal psychology, is ubiquitous and practically ineliminable, and intentional‐ systems theory explains why this is so.

References Baron‐Cohen, S. (1995), Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Bennett, M. R., and Hacker, P. (2003), Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience (Oxford: Blackwell). Block, N. (1982), ‘Psychologism and Behaviorism’, Philosophical Review, 90: 5–43. Brandom, R. (1994), Making it Explicit (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Brook, A., and Ross, D. (2002) (eds.), Daniel Dennett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Byrne, R., and Whiten, A. (1988) (eds.), Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intelligence in Monkeys, Apes, and Humans (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Davidson, D. (1975), ‘Thought and Talk’, in S. Guttenplan (ed.), Mind and Language: Wolfson College Lectures, 1974 (Oxford: Clarendon), 7–23. Dennett, D. (1971), ‘Intentional Systems’, Journal of Philosophy, 68: 87–106.

Page 13 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory —— (1978), Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press/Bradford). —— (1983), ‘Intentional Systems in Cognitive Ethology: The “Panglossian Paradigm” defended’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6: 343–90. —— (1987), The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). (p. 350)

Dennett, D. (1991), ‘Real Patterns’, Journal of Philosophy, 87: 27–51.

—— (1994), ‘Get Real’, Philosophical Topics, 22: 505–68. —— (1995), Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life (New York: Simon & Schuster). —— (1996), Kinds of Minds (New York: Basic). —— (2006), ‘The Hoax of Intelligent Design, and How It was Perpetrated’, in J. Brockman (ed.), Intelligent Thought: Science Versus the Intelligent Design Movement (New York: Vintage), 33–49. —— (2007), ‘Philosophy as Naïve Anthropology’, in D. Robinson (ed.), Neuroscience and Philosophy: Brain, Mind, and Language (New York: Colombia University Press), 73–95. Griffin, R., and Baron‐Cohen, S. (2002), ‘The Intentional Stance: Developmental and Neurocognitive Perspectives’, in A. Brook and D. Ross (eds.), Daniel Dennett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 83–116. Hornsby, J. (2000), ‘Personal and Subpersonal: A Defence of Dennett's Early Distinction’, Philosophical Explorations, 3: 6–24. Leslie, A. (1991), ‘The Theory of Mind Impairment in Autism: Evidence for a Modular Mechanism of Development?’ in A. Whiten (ed.), Natural Theories of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 63–78. Nichols, S., and Stich, S. (2003), Mindreading (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Peacocke, C. (1983), Sense and Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Premack, D. (1983), ‘The Codes of Man and Beasts’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6: 368. Ross, D. (2002), ‘Dennettian Behavioural Explanations and the Roles of the Social Sciences’, in A. Brook and D. Ross (eds.), Daniel Dennett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 140–83. Seyfarth, R., and Cheney, D. (2002), ‘Dennett's Contribution to Research on the Animal Mind’, in A. Brook and D. Ross (eds.), Daniel Dennett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 117–39. Page 14 of 15

Intentional Systems Theory Stich, S. (1981), ‘Dennett on Intentional Systems’, Philosophical Topics, 12: 39–62. Webb, S. (1994), ‘Witnessed Behaviour and Dennett's Intentional Stance’, Philosophical Topics, 22: 457–70.

Daniel Dennett

Daniel C. Dennett is university professor and Austin B. Fletcher Professor of Philosophy at Tufts University. He is also the co-director of the Center for Cognitive Studies there. His most recent book on free will is Freedom Evolves (2003) and among his recent articles are “Toward a Science of Volition,” with W. Prinz and N. Sebanz, in Disorders of Volition, edited by N. Sebanz and W. Prinz (2006), and “Some Observations on the Psychology of Thinking about Free Will,” in Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will, edited by John Baer, James C. Kaufman, Roy F. Baumeister (OUP, 2008).

Page 15 of 15

Wide Content

Oxford Handbooks Online Wide Content   Frances Egan The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0021

Abstract and Keywords Wide or externalist content is individuated in part by reference to features of a subject's external surroundings, by her physical environment or the community with which she shares a language. Externalists hold that physically identical subjects might have thoughts with different, wide, contents. Internalists either deny that content is wide, claiming that all content supervenes on intrinsic physical states of the subject, and is hence narrow, or insist, at the very least, that the content that individuates a subject's thoughts in predictions and explanations of her behaviour must supervene on her intrinsic properties. This article begins by discussing the arguments for and against wide content. It then argues that genuinely explanatory content is wide. Keywords: wide content, externalist content, physical environment, physical states, intrinsic states, mental state

THOUGHTS

are individuated both by their attitude type and by their content. A thinking

subject might bear different attitudes to the same content—she might, for example, both believe and fear that the conflict in the Middle East will not be resolved—or the same attitude to different contents—she might believe, say, that the Devils will win the Stanley Cup and that it will snow tomorrow. Wide or externalist content is individuated in part by reference to features of a subject's external surroundings, by her physical environment or the community with which she shares a language. Externalists hold that physically identical subjects might have thoughts with different, wide, contents. Internalists either deny that content is wide, claiming that all content supervenes on intrinsic physical states of the subject, and is hence narrow, or insist, at the very least, that the content that individuates a subject's thoughts in predictions and explanations of her behaviour must supervene on her intrinsic properties. I begin by discussing the arguments for and against wide content. I then argue that genuinely explanatory content is wide. Page 1 of 19

Wide Content

20.1 Arguments for Wide Content The existence of wide content is established by several well‐known arguments. The arguments share a common structure: we are asked to consider physically identical subjects in various contexts where, it is suggested, certain features of the context determine different contents for the subjects' thoughts. Hilary Putnam (1975) argued that the meaning of natural‐kind terms is determined, in part, by the nature of the subject's physical environment. Putnam asks us to (p. 352) consider a world, Twin Earth, in which the vocable ‘water’ is used to refer to the liquid filling this world's oceans and streams, a liquid superficially similar to water, though chemically quite different. Call this liquid ‘XYZ’. Imagine two subjects, Oscar and his physically identical counterpart, Twin Oscar, circa 1750, before the development of modern chemistry.1 Each subject utters the form of words ‘Cold water is refreshing on a hot day’. According to Putnam, the meanings of the two utterances are different, in virtue of the fact that they are used to refer to different substances—H2O by Oscar and XYZ by Twin Oscar. If Putnam is right, the internal, psychological state of the speaker is insufficient to determine the meaning of natural‐kind terms; the nature of the environment also plays a meaning‐determining role. As Putnam famously put it, ‘meanings just ain't in the head’. Moreover, on the assumption that a subject's utterances express his thoughts, the twins' thoughts have distinct contents, in virtue of the distinct concepts expressed by their use of the vocable ‘water’. Tyler Burge (1978) argued that the contents of many thoughts are determined, in part, by community standards of correctness. A medically unsophisticated subject, Alf, believes that he has arthritis in his ankles, wrists, and, as it happens, his thigh. When informed by his doctor that arthritis is a disease of the joints, Alf gives up the belief that he has arthritis in his thigh. We can compare Alf with a second subject, Twin Alf, who has an identical history, non‐intentionally described. Twin Alf belongs to a linguistic community that uses the vocable ‘arthritis’ to refer to an ailment that affects the thigh as well as the joints. Both Alf's and Twin Alf's use accord with this community's use. Burge concludes that the beliefs that Alf and Twin Alf would express using the form of words ‘Arthritis is painful’ have different contents. (On the assumption that beliefs have their contents essentially, Alf and Twin Alf have different beliefs.) The content of thoughts ascribable using general terms such as ‘arthritis’ is determined, in part, by community‐wide social and linguistic practice, and is therefore wide. An argument originally due to Gareth Evans (1982) establishes that thoughts involving singular reference—so called object‐involving thoughts—have wide content. My belief that this glass (imagine me pointing to a specific glass in front of me) is empty depends constitutively upon the existence of a particular glass. My perceptual contact with this glass puts me in a position to make a singular demonstrative judgement that this glass is

Page 2 of 19

Wide Content empty, a judgement that my Twin Earth counterpart, pointing to a different glass, is not in a position to make. Her judgement has a different wide content. The content of object‐ involving thoughts is the least controversial type of wide content and will not be discussed further.

Page 3 of 19

Wide Content

20.2 Arguments against Wide Content The externalist interpretation of the thought experiments has been disputed by many. Internalists argue that the twins’ thoughts share a single narrow content (p. 353) no matter what the context. Because the Putnam and Burge arguments appeal to different aspects of the thinker's context—the physical environment and the social or linguistic context respectively—they raise somewhat different issues and so will be discussed separately. It has been suggested that the difference in Oscar's and Twin Oscar's physical environments does not give rise to a difference in the contents of their thoughts, because both believe something like the following: the clear potable liquid that fills the oceans and streams is refreshing. The revised belief contents are assumed to supervene on intrinsic properties of subjects. The issue, more generally, is whether the twins’ concepts include within their extension not only the liquid that fills their local oceans and streams (H2O and XYZ respectively) but also anything phenomenally indistinguishable from this liquid. If, as Crane (1991) and Segal (2000) have argued, the twins’ concepts apply to the ‘watery’ substance in their worlds in virtue of the relatively superficial properties shared by the two substances, then they have the same concept, and Putnam's argument fails to establish the existence of wide content. The fact that nobody in 1750 was in a position to provide a distinguishing description of the two liquids appears to undermine the claim that the concepts in question express natural kinds, or kinds distinguished by a hidden nature, as Putnam's argument requires, rather than more superficial kinds or ‘motleys’, what Locke called ‘nominal kinds’. This, however, is a mistake. As Putnam (1975) argued convincingly, whether the twins’ terms express natural‐kind concepts or more superficial kind concepts is an empirical question turning on the referential intentions of the speaker. Archimedes knew nothing about the chemical composition of the substance he called χρυϛoϛ, but if he would have rejected as a genuine instance of the kind something that possessed only the observable properties of gold—if he would have agreed that all that glitters is not gold—then χρυϛoϛ for Archimedes indeed expressed a natural‐kind concept (arguably, the concept gold). The speaker need have only a vague conception of a shared hidden nature or structure determining the kind; she need not have any idea what that hidden nature in fact is. Whether a speaker has such a conception in mind can normally be determined by investigating the speaker's use of the term under a wide range of circumstances. This process would include querying the speaker about what she would say in various counterfactual circumstances. (‘If it looked like gold but in fact was made out of a high‐ tech synthetic would it be gold?’) We can imagine a population which, having no interest in the hidden nature or structure of objects and substances, intends by their use of such vocables as ‘water’, ‘gold’, and ‘aluminium’ to refer to things that possess only the observable properties of water, gold, and aluminium. Their use of these terms would be

Page 4 of 19

Wide Content much like our use of ‘table’ or ‘chair’, expressing relatively superficial kinds (in this case, functional kinds) or motleys, rather than natural kinds.2 (p. 354)

It is worth noting, however, that a speaker's (or a community's) referential intentions may not be determinate enough, in advance of theory development and scientific discovery, to determine whether a particular sample falls within the extension of a given concept. The notion of hidden nature or structure that a speaker has in mind and that governs her use of a concept may be too vague to settle whether objects with similar microstructures (say, isotopes of the same element) would fall under the speaker's concept. But indeterminacy in the concept's extension does not, as Segal (2000) suggests, turn it into a motley concept.3 , 4 The externalist interpretation of Burge's thought experiment has also been challenged. Crane (1991) and Segal (2000) have argued that a single content ascription is true of Alf and Twin Alf, one that reflects what we might call their personal conception of how things are. Alf's concept, on this view, is idiosyncratic, relative to his linguistic community; it is the same concept as Twin Alf's. (Twin Alf is assumed to be a linguistically competent member of his own linguistic community.) We might call this shared, narrow, concept ‘narthritis’, to distinguish it from arthritis, the concept that applies only to the joints. Burge's assumption that the community's concept should be attributed to Alf despite his partial or inadequate understanding of that concept is simply wrong, on this view. Rather than having a false belief that he has arthritis in his thigh, Alf believes, truly, that he has narthritis in his thigh, that the narthritis in his ankles is getting worse, that aspirin relieves the symptoms of narthritis, and so on. He also has the false metalinguistic belief that the vocable ‘arthritis’, in the mouths of his cohort, expresses the concept narthritis. As noted above, whether a speaker's use of a term expresses a natural‐kind concept can normally be determined by investigating the speaker's behaviour under a wide range of circumstances. It is not clear that the present dispute can be settled in quite as straightforward a fashion. Burge cites Alf's ‘post‐correction’ behaviour—specifically the fact that when informed by his doctor that arthritis is a disease of the joints Alf regards himself as having been mistaken about arthritis—as evidence that his concept, all along, is the same as the community's. But an internalist interpretation of Alf's post‐correction behaviour is just as plausible: Alf does intend to deploy in speech and thought the same concepts as his cohort, but his deference to the doctor should be construed not as evidence that prior to correction he did in fact deploy the community's concept, but rather as a change in concept, bringing his own usage into line with his cohort. In any event, the situation seems quite unlike the natural‐kind case. It is not clear that anything in Alf's behaviour, or dispositions to behaviour (including his disposition to retract his claim about his thigh if experts tell him that one can't have that sort of ailment in the thigh) is sufficient to determine whether, prior to correction, the belief that Alf would express by his use of the vocable ‘arthritis is painful’ has the same content as it would

Page 5 of 19

Wide Content have in the mouths of his cohort, or whether it has some idiosyncratic content reflecting his personal conception of things. (p. 355)

It might be objected that the internalist interpretation of Alf's post‐correction behaviour requires, implausibly, that a subject's concepts can change without the subject being aware that they have done so.5 But this is not an objection that an externalist can make. The use of the vocable ‘arthritis’ in Alf's community might shift somewhat without Alf's knowledge. On Burge's view, Alf's concept would change, even though he isn't aware of the change. Even if the concepts in question are assumed to correspond to the subject's personal conception of things, there should be nothing troubling in the idea that a subject's concepts can change without her being aware of that fact. ‘Concept’ is a theorist's term of art. Alf is fully aware that his beliefs have changed. After correction by the doctor he is disposed to utter the form of words ‘I no longer believe that arthritis can occur in the thigh’. On some accounts of concepts—in particular on the internalist account under consideration, but more generally on holist conceptions of concepts—this change in Alf is sufficient to constitute a change in his concept, but there is no reason to think that the subject should be aware of that.6 Some authors have argued that the thought‐experiments do not force a choice between wide and narrow content; in some circumstances it is correct to ascribe both kinds of content, each answering to different practical and theoretical interests. According to Loar (1988), Alf and his linguistic cohort can be described as believing that arthritis is painful; they share what Loar calls ‘social content’, which is sensitive to environmental and social factors and is therefore wide. Social content is captured by the content‐ascribing that‐ clauses that we use to attribute propositional attitudes. But content‐ascribing that‐clauses do not correspond, one‐to‐one, to belief contents, as these are individuated in common‐ sense psychological explanation. So it does not follow that Alf and his cohort have the same belief contents as these are individuated by common‐sense psychology. Loar cites a number of examples in support of his claim. He asks us to consider a diary which we know was written by either an earthling or a Twin Earthling, although we do not know which. One entry says: ‘No swimming today; the water is too rough’. We would explain the diarist's behaviour as follows: because she believes that the water is rough, and that if the water is rough one should not swim, she believes that one should not swim. If the explanation is challenged on the grounds that we don't know whether she has any water beliefs at all, then, according to Loar, we would likely produce a paraphrase of the original explanation that makes no commitment about the nature of the liquid in question. We might say, for example, ‘She believes that the local sample of the liquid that fills the oceans and lakes is rough’. In other words, we would produce a single explanation that subsumes the beliefs of both earthlings and Twin Earthlings, rather than two explanations, one adverting (p. 356) to water and one to XYZ. On Loar's view, the original explanation attributes to the diarist only a certain way of conceiving of things; in particular, it attributes mental states that are interrelated (and related to stimuli and Page 6 of 19

Wide Content behaviour) in specified ways, but involves no commitment about the environmental or social context in which the beliefs are embedded, and to which content‐ascribing that‐ clauses are sensitive. For the purposes of predicting and explaining behaviour, Loar argues, beliefs are individuated by their role in perception, inference, deliberation, and action. Moreover, this complex role—what is often called ‘conceptual role’—determines a kind of content, what Loar calls ‘psychological content’.7 The beliefs that Alf and Twin Alf express by their utterance of the word forms ‘arthritis is painful’, prior to Alf's correction by his doctor, play the same role in their mental lives; they therefore have the same psychological content. The kind of content relevant for common‐sense psychological explanation, Loar concludes, is narrow. We shall return to Loar's claim in the next section when we consider the explanatory role of content attributions. Noam Chomsky (1992, 1995) has been highly critical of the methodology used to establish the existence of wide content. The externalist thought‐experiments, he claims, make illegitimate appeal to speakers' intuitions about such notions as reference, extension, and true of, technical notions about which speakers can have no theory‐neutral intuitions (1992: 225; 1995: 42). Moreover, speakers' intuitions about such things as whether a liquid superficially identical to water counts as the same liquid are highly sensitive to contextual factors. Change the circumstances or pragmatic presuppositions of the Twin Earth story, he suggests, and judgements will change accordingly. Chomsky doubts that ‘any general or useful sense can be given to such technical notions as “wide content” (or any other notion fixing “reference”) in any of the externalist interpretations’ (1992: 225). Chomsky is surely right to point out the lability of the intuitions upon which the externalist interpretation of the thought‐experiments depends, though his rejection of the whole externalist programme is an extreme and unwarranted reaction. Care must be taken in attributing beliefs to subjects simply on the basis of the conventional meanings of the words they utter.8 The seemingly innocuous assumption appealed to earlier—that a subject's utterances express her thoughts—does not by itself support the attribution of wide content to the subject's mental states.9 Moreover, we have seen from the discussion of Putnam's Archimedes example that empirical investigation of a subject's behaviour in a wide range of circumstances is sometimes necessary to determine whether a subject has a natural‐kind concept in mind. The investigation will probe just how a subject's judgements are sensitive to contextual factors. But the context‐sensitivity of our intuitions and judgements about such matters does not itself undermine the existence of wide content or render the methodology deployed in the thought‐experiments problematic.

(p. 357)

Page 7 of 19

20.3 The Explanatory Role of Content

Wide Content Various authors have expressed doubts that wide content is well suited to serve the goals of psychological explanation. Barbara Von Eckart questions the legitimacy of at least some types of wide content: How could certain subtle features of the linguistic practices of persons around you influence the content of your mental representations when those features do not directly impinge on you in any way? (1993: 264)10 The argument presupposes that only features that causally affect the subject could be relevant to mental content. By hypothesis, differences in the environmental or social context of twins make no difference to their surface stimulations, and so, the reasoning goes, such features could affect their inner states only by some sort of ‘action at a distance’ (see, for example, Block 1986: 625; Fodor 1987: 40). At very least, it is claimed, such causal connections as do hold between the environment or social context and intentional agents do not seem to be of the right sort to affect their mental states. But, as Burge and others have noted, the presupposition is false. Contextual or relational properties can affect the type‐individuation of an object or state without affecting it causally. The birth of a child can make a woman an aunt without the two ever coming into causal contact.

While there is nothing metaphysically suspect about wide content, the underlying worry is that it is nonetheless ill suited to play an explanatory role in psychology. Proponents of narrow content have argued that there is no distinctive explanatory work for wide content to do. Segal (1989) is concerned explicitly with the content attributed in computational theories of cognitive capacities. He argues that David Marr's theory (1982) of early visual processing attributes narrow content to the states and structures it posits. The argument depends upon general considerations that, if true, would apply to any account of cognitive mechanisms.11 Moreover, the intuition underlying the argument is shared by many who think that, whatever the differences in their physical or social environments, twins are psychologically identical and should be treated as such by any theory interested in explaining their behaviour or cognitive capacities. Segal argues that unless subjects differ in their discriminative and recognitional abilities there is no motivation for positing different contents. Describing a Twin Earth scenario where distinct environmental conditions, C1 on earth and C2 on Twin Earth, cause identical internal states, non‐intentionally described, to be tokened in twin subjects, he says: Ascriptions of representations require top‐down motivations. These motivations come from finding some use or purpose to which the content is put. So to motivate the attribution of (p. 358) [distinct environment‐specific contents] rather than … [narrow contents] we would have to find some purpose that the more specific content could serve, but that the vaguer [narrow] contents could not … What would this be? Nothing that issued in any discriminative ability, or recognitional

Page 8 of 19

Wide Content ability that could be detected by any tests of the sort employed by the theorist of vision. For the twins are twins, and will be the same in every testable respect. (1989: 205) He goes on to say that positing distinct contents would violate Ockham's razor:

There would just be no point in invoking the two contents, where one would do. For there would be no theoretical purpose served by distinguishing between the contents. (1989: 206) There is, in fact, an important theoretical purpose served by the ascription of wide content in theories of cognitive mechanisms. Spelling this out will require a little stage‐setting. I will then consider whether the point carries over to common‐sense psychological explanation.

The semantic interpretation of a computational mechanism specifies which properties are tracked by the posited structures when the mechanism is functioning properly in its normal environment. An interpretation of a computational system is given by an interpretation function that specifies a mapping between equivalence classes of physical states of the system—in so‐called ‘classical’ devices these will be symbols or data structures—and elements of some represented domain. To interpret a device as a visual system is to specify a mapping between states of the device and tokenings of visible properties such as changes of depth in the scene. To interpret a device as an adder is to specify a mapping between states of the device and numbers. The specified states of the device are thus construed, under the interpretation, as representations of changes in depth or of addends and sums. Whether a computationally characterized device succeeds in computing, say, the depth of objects and surfaces in the scene from information about the disparity of points in the retinal image depends on whether its internal states co‐vary with changes of depth in the environment. This requires a certain fit between the mechanism and the world. In the actual world the fit is a product of natural selection. Let us call a visual mechanism adapted to the terrestrial environment ‘Visua’ and the distal property it tracks—changes of depth—‘C1’.12 A given computational mechanism would not enhance fitness in every environment. Being an adaptation is a contingent property of a computationally characterized system. We can imagine a duplicate of Visua, Twin Visua, appearing spontaneously (perhaps by random mutation) in a world to which it is not adapted. Imagine that the counterfactual world, E2, is different enough from the actual world that Twin Visua's states track some distal property other than changes in depth. Call this property ‘C2’. Since Visua and Twin Visua are physical duplicates, the two mechanisms have the same discriminative and recognitional abilities. Visua would track C2 if it were transported to E2. Twin Visua will contribute to the fitness of the (p. 359) organism containing it only if C2 is a useful property to track or represent in E2. C2 is some function of surfaces, local light, and local

Page 9 of 19

Wide Content optical laws, but tracking C2 might not allow the organism containing Twin Visua to recover what is where in the scene. If it does not, we might wonder whether it is even appropriate to call Twin Visua a visual mechanism.13 The important question for present purposes is ‘What do Visua's and Twin Visua's internal states represent?’. It is natural to say that Visua represents C1—changes of depth. It is in virtue of tracking changes in depth in the scene that Visua contributes to the organism's successful interaction with its environment. Perhaps it is also natural to say that Twin Visua represents the distinct property C2. In any case, it would be odd to say that Visua represents some more general property C3 that subsumes both changes of depth (C1) and the strange and (from the terrestrial perspective) unnatural property C2.14 In other words, there is a clear rationale for attributing to Visua and Twin Visua distinct, environment‐specific, wide contents that make apparent the contribution of the mechanism to the success of the organism in its normal environment, rather than an unperspicuous narrow content that does not. To summarize: Visua and Twin‐Visua are type‐identical computational mechanisms. The computational characterization that specifies a mechanism's basic causal operations subsumes both of them. This environment‐general characterization allows us to predict and explain how a mechanism would behave in counterfactual worlds. But it doesn't tell us what the mechanism would represent in other environments. The content‐determining correlations are those that obtain between states of the device and property tokenings in the local environment. The correlations that obtain in counterfactual environments, where the objects, properties, and laws may be quite different, are not relevant to the semantic interpretation of the mechanism. I claimed above that it is natural to ascribe environment‐specific contents to cognitive mechanisms. The reason is not hard to find. The questions that antecedently or pretheoretically define a cognitive theory's domain are typically framed in terms that presuppose the organism's success in its normal environment. We want to know how the organism can recover the depth and orientation of the objects in the scene from information in two‐dimensional retinal images. The cognitive theorist sets out to answer questions that are already framed in environment‐specific terms. If the mechanism's states are interpreted as representing depth and orientation, rather than more general properties determined by correlations that obtain in counterfactual environments, then the theory is poised to answer these questions. (p. 360)

The semantic interpretation of a computational mechanism can be responsive to these explanatory and pragmatic considerations, addressing the questions that initially motivated the search for and development of the theory, only because a computational characterization provides an environment‐independent characterization of the basic operations, or functional architecture, of the device.15 As noted above, this Page 10 of 19

Wide Content characterization, which for present purposes we can call a ‘formal’ characterization,16 provides the basis for predicting and explaining its behaviour in any environment. The semantic interpretation can serve our more parochial interests. A complete computational account of a cognitive mechanism comprises two independent components, a fully general formal characterization of the causal structure of the mechanism, and an environment‐specific semantic interpretation. Computational accounts do not need narrow contents to specify the causal structure of the system. The formal component of the theory does that. Let us return to Visua and Twin Visua. Suppose now that the property tracked by Twin Visua in E2—C2—is a useful property for an organism in E2 to detect. Twin Visua therefore contributes to the fitness of the organism containing it. Imagine that an enthusiastic editor on earth (E1), always on the lookout for new markets, asks the theorist responsible for characterizing Visua to produce a textbook that could be marketed and sold in both E1 and E2. Since the formal component of the theory that specifies Visua's basic causal operations will characterize Twin Visua's as well—Visua and Twin Visua are formally identical mechanisms—the theorist needs only to produce a single semantic interpretation that specifies what this formally characterized mechanism will represent in E1 and E2. Since the mechanism does not track C1 in E2 or C2 in E1, neither C1 nor C2 is a plausible candidate. Rather, an interpretation appropriate to both worlds would take the mechanism to represent the more general property C3 that subsumes both C1 and C2.17 Notice, first, that the content C3 is a wide content. The new semantic interpretation specifies what the mechanism represents in E1 and E2, but not what a physically indistinguishable mechanism might represent in some third environment E3. (This follows by an iteration of the reasoning above.) While nonetheless wide, C3 is, in a sense, narrower than either C1 or C2; C3 prescinds from the environmental differences between E1 and E2. The explanatory interests served by the new interpretation are less local, less parochial, than those served by the original interpretation, which was designed to address questions posed in vocabulary appropriate to earth. Whereas the old interpretation answered such pretheoretic questions as ‘How is the organism able to recover the depth of objects in the scene’ by positing representations of depth, the new interpretation provides the basis for answering this question and an analogous question framed in vocabulary appropriate to E2—‘How is the organism able to recover information about C2?’—by positing representations of the more general (p. 361) property C3, and supplying auxiliary assumptions about how C3 is related to the locally instantiated properties C1 and C2. As it happened, the overeager editor was somewhat surprised that sales of the new interplanetary textbook on earth fell off rather sharply from the first edition, designed solely for the local market. Besides introducing a new vocabulary containing such unfamiliar predicates as ‘C3’, the new edition required cumbersome appendices appropriate to each world, explaining how to recover answers to questions about the

Page 11 of 19

Wide Content organism's performance in its local environment, questions that motivated the search for an explanatory theory in the first place. Readers complained that the new edition was much less ‘user‐friendly’. The editor was therefore dissuaded from his original idea of commissioning an intergalactic version of the text, which would provide a genuinely narrow semantic interpretation that would specify what Visua would represent in any environment.18 He came to realize that a semantic interpretation of the basic causal processes of a mechanism is primarily a gloss that allows a theory to address local explanatory interests. Any gloss that shows that the theory is doing its job will be couched in a vocabulary that is perspicuous for the local audience with these interests. The moral is that a truly intergalactic cognitive science would not be representational. So what about common‐sense psychological explanation? This sketch of the role of content attribution in cognitive science does not carry over straightforwardly to common‐ sense psychological explanation primarily because content attribution in our folk practices must do double duty. Nonetheless there are crucial similarities. Beliefs and desires must be construed as causally efficacious states of subjects to play the predictive and explanatory roles required of them in our folk practices. Whereas computational theories characterize the states they posit in both formal and semantic terms, folk psychology characterizes propositional attitudes only by their contents.19 Unlike the states involved in the highly modularized, informationally encapsulated processes characterized by our most promising computational theories, propositional attitudes have very complex functional roles which include, typically, accessibility to consciousness. We must rely on content ascriptions to ‘get at’ the complex functional roles in virtue of which propositional attitudes figure in predictions and explanations of behaviour. Normally content serves this purpose quite well. The state that is typically caused by looking out of a window on a rainy day, and that typically causes (in conjunction with other propositional attitudes) umbrella‐carrying behaviour, can be referred to as the belief that it is raining. Identifying this state by its content allows us to infer quite a bit about how it (p. 362) will interact with environmental conditions and other internal states to produce additional mental states and behaviour. A moral of Loar (1988) is that content‐ascribing that‐clauses are not perfectly suited to serve the purposes of psychological explanation. Consider the diarist again. According to Loar, we would explain the diarist's behaviour by producing a single explanation that subsumes the beliefs of the diarist and her twin. In this context we don't really care what kind of liquid the subject is thinking about—information that is typically made available by a content‐ascribing that‐clause, such as that the water is too rough. What is relevant for predicting and explaining the diarist's behaviour is the causal role of her belief, its pattern of actual and potential interaction with stimuli, behaviour, and other mental states. This narrowly construed causal role, Loar claims, determines a kind of content

Page 12 of 19

Wide Content that captures the way that the subject and her twin conceive of things, considered independently of their environments. The internalist intuition that the twins are identical in psychologically relevant respects is compelling. But respecting this intuition does not require that they share some narrow content; it requires only that they share some psychological states. As Loar himself notes (1988: 105), a ‘more minimal’ lesson to be drawn from the examples is that the predictive and explanatory schema of common‐sense psychology individuate propositional attitudes narrowly, by their (narrowly conceived) causal roles, but not necessarily that causal role determines a second kind of content. Since we don't have a way of specifying the shared psychological states of the diarist and her twin directly, in ‘intrinsic’ terms that spell out precisely the psychologically relevant causal potential of the states, we must find a content ascription that applies to both the diarist and her twin. Such an ascription is not hard to find: the diarist refrained from swimming because she believed that the ocean (lake, river, or whatever) was too rough. But there is no reason to think that the content so attributed is narrow. It is, in a sense, narrower; the content ascription prescinds from the environment‐specific information supplied by the that‐clause that the water is too rough, so it attributes a more minimal environmental commitment. But it does not abstract away entirely from the subject's external surroundings, as it would if it were genuinely narrow. And, just as in the computational case discussed above, it is unlikely that contents that applied intergalactically—to subjects in any environment whatsoever— would serve the complex role required of content. Folk thought and talk about intentional agents are couched in terms that presuppose the local environments in which they are situated. We are not interested simply in the bodily movements of subjects considered in isolation from the objects and properties that make up their world. Wide‐content glosses on the (narrowly individuated) internal states that cause intentional behaviour allow environmentally situated creatures such as ourselves to understand these states in terms of their publicly available normal causes and effects. Content ascribing that‐clauses—purveyors of wide content—allow us to ‘get at’ the causal roles, in virtue of which propositional attitudes figure in predictions and explanations of behaviour, only indirectly and imperfectly, as the thought‐experiments illustrate. It does not follow that there is a second type of content—so‐called ‘psychological content’ that is supposedly narrow—that does the job perfectly. (p. 363) Even if we can construct such a notion by various devices, and for various theoretical purposes,20 there is no reason to think that the notion actually plays a role in our common‐sense practices, or that it would serve the other purposes of content as well as ordinary content, which is wide in varying degrees. We can use a wide content ascription to ‘sneak up on’ the narrowly individuated causal role shared by the diarist and her twin, or Oscar and Twin Oscar, or Alf and Twin Alf, withdrawing to a more minimally committed, but still wide, content when the occasion requires. The diarist example indicates that wide content can be too fine‐grained to capture what is relevant for psychological explanation. A second example from Loar (1988) suggests that it can be too coarse‐grained. Imagine that, some months before we encounter him in Page 13 of 19

Wide Content Burge's story, Alf visits Paris and hears of a disease called ‘arthrite’ that affects the joints. Not realizing that ‘arthritis’ and ‘arthrite’ are intertranslatable, and being a bit of a hypochondriac, Alf comes to believe that he has two problems with his ankles, one called ‘arthritis’, which he later comes to believe has spread to his thigh, and a second ailment called ‘arthrite’. Loar claims that Alf has two beliefs with distinct causal powers. Alf's ‘French’ belief that he has arthritis in his ankles does not interact in the appropriate way with his ‘English’ belief that if he has arthritis in his ankles he should take aspirin, although his ‘English’ belief that he has arthritis in his ankles does. There are two distinct states with different interactive potential, but only one belief ascription—the belief that he has arthritis in his ankles—available to pick out the distinct states. Loar concludes that Alf's ‘arthritis’ and ‘arthrite’ beliefs have distinct ‘psychological’ contents, determined by their distinct causal roles. Once again, a more minimal conclusion is preferable. Alf does seem to have two distinct states with different causal roles. It is not hard to find distinct content‐ascribing that‐ clauses that characterize the difference in the causal roles and hence serve to pick out the underlying states. We might say ‘He thinks that the original problem with his ankles can also occur in muscles and bones, but that the new disorder affects only the joints’. There is no reason to think that the content ascribed thereby is narrow. We can say, with Loar, that the distinct content ascriptions capture ‘the way the subject himself conceives of things’ (1988: 108). The subject conceives of himself as having two distinct problems with his ankles. But ‘the way the subject conceives of things’ is not a name for narrow content. To summarize. Content plays a role in our common‐sense explanatory practices that it does not play in computational accounts of cognitive mechanisms. It allows us to refer to the causal roles in virtue of which propositional attitudes figure in predictions and explanations of behaviour.21 This is the primary job of content ascription in common‐ sense, as opposed to scientific, psychology, but it is a job that that‐clauses—purveyors of wide content—do only imperfectly. When necessary, as in the examples discussed by Loar, we can refine our practice, relying on more elaborate that‐clauses that reveal aspects of the causal roles of the underlying states that are (p. 364) relevant for prediction and explanation. But the content attributed when we try to characterize the way the subject conceives of things is still wide. Content ascription serves other purposes in our common‐sense practices besides enabling the prediction and explanation of behaviour. Some of these roles exploit the environmental or contextual specificity that is the hallmark of wide content. I shall mention two. As several authors have noted (see, for example, Field 1978; Loar 1981, 1988; Schiffer 1981), we make use of the fact that people's beliefs are often reliable indicators of the way the world is. As Field (1978) puts it:

Page 14 of 19

Wide Content [W]e are constantly using our opinions about other people's beliefs in forming opinions about the world. The fact that a child believes that he has done something I won't like (a fact that can often be inferred from his behaviour) gives good reason to think he has done something I won't like; the fact that most physicists believe that there are gravitational waves … is good reason for me to believe that there are gravitational waves; and so forth. (1978: 103) On occasion, when the point of a belief ascription is to convey information, a speaker might ascribe a content that she knows does not capture the way the subject conceives of things. One might say, for example, that Perry White, the editor of the Daily Planet, thinks that Superman has real literary talent. White, of course, does not know that his star reporter, Clark Kent, is Superman, but the belief ascription serves its purpose—conveying information about Clark Kent/ Superman—as long as the audience knows that Clark Kent is Superman.

Burge (1978) identifies another use of content ascribing that‐clauses. They constitute a standard by reference to which a subject's grasp of the commitments of public discourse may be evaluated, and her intellectual responsibilities with respect to that discourse assessed. Thus, we can hold an individual answerable to the community standard, and subjects can hold themselves so answerable, even when they have only incompletely mastered the elements within the standard. Alf, in Burge's original thought‐experiment, can take himself to have been wrong about arthritis, and to have been corrected by his doctor. This purpose of content attribution—providing a normative standard against which individual behaviour can be evaluated—can be at cross purposes with the goal of predicting and explaining behaviour. It is this tension that gives rise to the dispute over the correct interpretation of Burge's example. Prediction and explanation will fail when the subject falls short of the standard, if we read the subject's mental states directly off his words. If we want to predict and explain the subject's behaviour, we must look for a distinct, and typically more elaborate, that‐clause that better captures the causal role of the subject's psychological state. As Loar would put it, we try to characterize ‘the way the subject himself conceives of things’. But, I have argued, the content attributed is still wide. Notice that these two uses of content presuppose local interests. The information conveyed by a belief attribution is often about the local environment. In the above case, it is about Superman, not his twin in some other world. A subject's competence (p. 365) will be evaluated by the standards of the local linguistic community. When the goal of content ascription is the prediction and explanation of behaviour, I have argued, content ascribing that‐clauses are used to pick out the causal roles of our beliefs and desires, properties shared by twins. All of these purposes are served by wide content. We are sometimes interested explicitly in how the subject would behave if the world were different in various ways, and the relevant that‐clauses may prescind from some features of the environment, as they do in the diarist case. So content can be wide in varying degrees.

Page 15 of 19

Wide Content Genuinely narrow content, content that supervenes on the intrinsic states of the subject and so would apply in any environment, is an idealization along this dimension. But it is too general and too abstract to bear an explanatory burden.22

References Bach, K. (1987), Thought and Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Block, N. (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 615–78. Brown, J. (1998), ‘Natural Kind Terms and Recognitional Capacities’, Mind, 107: 275–303. —— (2003), ‘Externalism and the Fregean Tradition’, in A. Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 431–55. Burge, T. (1978), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. Chalmers, D. (2002), ‘The Components of Content’, in Chalmers, Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 608–33. Chomsky, N. (1992), ‘Explaining Language Use’, Philosophical Topics, 20: 205–31. —— (1995), ‘Language and Nature’, Mind, 104: 1–61. Crane, T. (1991), ‘All the Difference in the World’, Philosophical Quarterly, 41: 1–26. Egan, F. (1995), ‘Computation and Content’, Philosophical Review, 104: 181–203. —— (1999), ‘In Defense of Narrow Mindedness’, Mind and Language, 14: 177–94. Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Field, H. (1978), ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis, 13: 9–61; repr. in N. Block (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, ii (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981), 78–114. Page references are to the reprint. Fodor, J. (1980), ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3: 63–109. —— (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Loar, B. (1981), Mind and Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1988), ‘Social Content and Psychological Content’, in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought (Tucson, Ariz.: University of Arizona Press), 99–110. Page 16 of 19

Wide Content Marr, D. (1982), Vision (New York: Freeman). Patterson, S. (1990), ‘The Explanatory Role of Belief Ascriptions’, Philosophical Studies, 59: 313–32. Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 215–71. Schiffer, S. (1981), ‘Truth and the Theory of Content’, in H. Parret and J. Bouverese (eds.), Meaning and Understanding (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter). (p. 366)

Segal, G. (1989), ‘On Seeing What Is Not There’, Philosophical Review, 98: 189–214. —— (2000), A Slim Book about Narrow Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2003), ‘Ignorance of Meaning’, in A. Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 415–30. Von Eckart, B. (1993), What Is Cognitive Science? (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Notes: (1) As many commentators have noted, we must ignore the fact that humans are largely composed of water. (2) These people would have little interest in basic science, which, of course, seeks to explain the observable properties of things by appeal to underlying nature or structure. We might imagine them to be served by a distinct population responsible for developing and maintaining the useful objects that keep the society running. This group would speak a different language, with genuine natural‐kind terms. (3) It is likely that the shapes of most of our natural‐kind concepts are in flux, as empirical discoveries and developments in theory force a revision of their extensions. (4) For further discussion of the issues in the last two paragraphs see Brown (1998). (5) See the discussion in Brown (2003) of Segal's suggestion (2000: 77) that Alf's concepts have undergone a ‘natural evolution’. (6) A radically holist view of concept individuation, according to which any change of belief involving the vocable ‘arthritis’ would count as a change in concept, is, of course, highly controversial. But the view under consideration here is not radically holist. It is not implausible to think that a subject who believes that ‘arthritis’ refers to a disease of the joints and the bones has a different concept. (7) And what Segal (2000, 2003) calls ‘cognitive content’.

Page 17 of 19

Wide Content (8) This is one moral of Loar (1988), but the point is also made by Bach (1987), Patterson (1990), and Crane (1991). (9) Chomsky himself is sceptical about the notion of a ‘shared public language’ and so would reject the idea that the subject's utterances have wide meaning (see Chomsky 1995). (10) Von Eckart raises the worry, but it is not clear that she actually endorses the sentiment expressed in the quote. (11) I argue in Egan (1995) that Marr's theory attributes wide contents to the posited computational structures. Nothing in the present discussion will turn on the interpretation of Marr's theory. (12) This is an adaptation of an example from Segal (1989). (13) If Twin Visua is not a visual mechanism, then of course Visua is a visual mechanism only contingently. I argue in Egan (1999) that computationally characterized mechanisms subserve cognitive functions such as vision or parsing only contingently. (14) An internalist might claim that Twin Visua represents C1, but this seems unmotivated, since Twin Visua's states may never co‐vary with C1 in E2. E2 is not a world where Twin Visua (or Visua, for that matter) sees depth. (15) See Egan (1999) for the argument that computational characterization is individualist or narrow. (16) Following Fodor's usage (1980). (17) C3 may be understood as the disjunction of C1 and C2, or as a determinable that has C1 and C2 as determinates. (18) Instead the editor commissioned an environment‐specific (wide) semantic interpretation for each world, to accompany the environment‐neutral (narrow) formal account of the mechanism. (19) Proponents of the ‘representational/computational theory of mind’ (RTM) are hopeful that scientific psychology will eventually provide a formal specification of the complex functional roles of propositional attitudes, and hence will ‘vindicate’ folk psychology (see Fodor 1987: ch. 1). According to the RTM, propositional attitudes will be revealed as relations to sentences in a language of thought. At present, though, folk psychology must continue to get by without a formal specification of the mechanics of thought. (20) Chalmers's epistemic content (2002) is one proposal. (21) The formal component of computational theories, rather than the content component, specifies the relevant functional architecture of the system.

Page 18 of 19

Wide Content (22) Thanks to Brian McLaughlin and Robert Matthews for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Frances Egan

Frances Egan is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey.

Page 19 of 19

Narrow Content

Narrow Content   Gabriel Segal The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0022

Abstract and Keywords The notion of narrow content arises from Hilary Putnam's well-known article ‘The Mean­ ing of “Meaning” ‘. Putnam raised the question of whether the meaning of a word in a giv­ en subject's mouth is fixed by the subject's psychological states in (what he termed) ‘the narrow sense’. According to Putnam, a psychological state is narrow if a subject's being in that state does not presuppose the existence of anything outside the subject. The idea is that a narrow psychological state is intrinsic to the subject: it does not in any essential way require the subject to stand in any particular relations to anything in her environ­ ment. Keywords: narrow content, Hilary Putnam, meaning of a word, psychological states, subject, narrow sense

Introduction: Twin Earth and Narrowness THE notion of narrow content arises from Hilary Putnam's well‐known article ‘The Mean­ ing of “Meaning” ’ (1975). Putnam raised the question of whether the meaning of a word in a given subject's mouth is fixed by the subject's psychological states in (what he termed) ‘the narrow sense’. According to Putnam, a psychological state is narrow iff a subject's being in that state does not presuppose the existence of anything outside the subject. The idea is that a narrow psychological state is intrinsic to the subject: it does not in any essential way require the subject to stand in any particular relations to any­ thing in her environment.1 To address his question about meaning Putnam introduced his famous Twin Earth experi­ ment, which I will briefly recapitulate. Putnam invited us to conceive of a planet that is exactly like earth in 1750, except that the transparent, odourless, tasteless, wet stuff that fills oceans and rains from the sky is not H2O but has a different chemical composition that we can call ‘XYZ’. We imagine a typical 1750 Earth subject, Oscar. And we imagine that he has a ‘twin’ on Twin Earth, an exact duplicate in all intrinsic respects, a molecule‐

Page 1 of 15

Narrow Content for‐molecule replica. We now consider whether the meaning of the word ‘water’ is the same in the two Oscars' vocabularies. (p. 368)

Putnam argued that it is not. When Oscar says ‘water’ he is referring to water; that is, H2O. When Twin Oscar says ‘water’ he is referring to twin water (‘twater’), which is not H2O, hence not water. And this difference of reference entails a difference in meaning. By hypothesis, the twins' narrow psychological states are the same. So meaning is not deter­ mined by narrow psychological states. The Oscar example was designed to show that the meaning of natural‐kind terms, such as ‘water’, depends in part on the underlying nature of samples that the term is used to talk about. Putnam then provided a second Twin Earth thought experiment designed to show that the meaning of words can also depend on social factors in a subject's environment. Putnam can't tell the difference between elms and beeches. He knows of nothing that dis­ tinguishes the two, bar their names. We imagine a twin Putnam on a twin Earth that is just like Earth except that there elms are called ‘beeches’ and beeches are called ‘elms’. When Putnam says ‘elm’ he means elm. When Twin Putnam says ‘elm’ he means beech. So what the subjects mean by ‘elm’ is not fixed by their narrow psychological states, but depends in part on how other people in their environments use their words. Putnam summed up his conclusion with a slogan: cut the pie any way you like, meanings just ain't in the head. Catchy as the slogan is, it is not particularly accurate. What the thought experiments are supposed to show is that meanings are partly individuated by re­ lational factors. They may be compared to sunburn, as Donald Davidson (1987) points out. Subjects cannot be sunburned unless they have been affected by the sun. But it wouldn't be appropriate to conclude that sunburn is not a condition of the skin. Putnam himself did not extend his line of reasoning to psychological states themselves. But others did (e.g. Burge. 1982; McGinn 1982). Consider the belief that Oscar expresses when he says, for example, ‘It is good to drink cold water on a hot day’. What he believes is that it is good to drink cold water on a hot day. When Twin Oscar utters the same word forms he is not expressing a belief about water, a substance he has never encountered or heard about. Rather, he is expressing the belief that it's good to drink cold twater on a hot day. Burge (1979) also developed a variant of the elm/beech type of thought‐experiment. He asked us to imagine a subject (who has come to be called ‘Alf’) who has a fairly typical set of beliefs about arthritis. He believes that arthritis is a painful condition, that his grandfa­ ther suffered from it, that he himself has arthritis in his wrists and ankles. One day he wakes up with a new pain and worries that his arthritis has spread to his thigh. In fact, by definition, arthritis is an inflammation of the joints. It is thus impossible to have arthritis in the thigh. We can now imagine a Twin Earth which is just like Earth, except that there the medical profession and educated lay people use ‘arthritis’ more liberally than we do, so that it can be truly applied to certain conditions outside the joints. Twin Alf is just like Page 2 of 15

Narrow Content Alf in all intrinsic respects. According to Burge, Twin Alf does not worry that he has arthritis in his thigh. When Twin Alf says ‘arthritis’ his word does not express the concept of arthritis. Rather, it expresses a concept that applies to the wider group of ailments. The content of (p. 369) the twins’ ‘arthritis’ concepts and the beliefs they express when they use the term ‘arthritis’ is partly determined by their social environment.

21.1 Notions of Content One of the thoughts driving the idea that the content of a concept or belief is partly rela­ tional is the connection between content and truth. Oscar's ‘water’ concept is true of H2O but not true of XYZ. Had Oscar encountered a glass of XYZ and said ‘that's water’, the be­ lief he would have expressed would have been false. Had Twin Oscar produced the same word forms in the same context, the belief he would have expressed would have been true. If Putnam says of an elm ‘That's an elm’ then he expresses a true belief. If Twin Put­ nam says of an elm ‘That's an elm’ he expresses a false belief. Or so it is widely held. To make the idea vivid, consider a simple thought experiment involving a singular con­ cept. John and Mary are friends. When John says ‘Mary likes thought‐experiments’ his concept refers to Mary and what he says is true if and only if Mary likes thought experi­ ments. On Twin Earth, Twin John and Twin Mary are friends. When Twin John says ‘Mary likes thought experiments’ he expresses a concept that refers to Twin Mary and what he says is true iff she likes thought experiments. It should be obvious that the referential, or truth‐conditional, content of John's concept of Mary is individuated partly, or wholly, in terms of its relation to the individual Mary. Con­ tent that is individuated partly, or wholly, by relational factors is called ‘broad’ (or ‘wide’). Content that is not thus relationally individuated, that is wholly intrinsic to the subject, is called ‘narrow’ (after Putnam's ‘psychological states in the narrow sense’). Narrow con­ tent would be shared by twins. There are three basic positions that one might hold in respect of broad and narrow con­ tent. Externalism is the view that at least some concepts have broad content and do not also have a narrow content. Two‐factor theories hold that all concepts have narrow con­ tent, and at least some have broad content as well. Thus, for example, Oscar's and Twin Oscar's ‘water’ concepts have different referential content, which is broad, but also have a shared narrow content. (Two‐factor theories are sometimes classified as internalist, and I shall adopt that terminological convention for the sake of convenience.) Radical inter­ nalism is the view that all concepts have narrow content and none has broad content. Each of the three basic positions has a number of variants. Thus, externalists divide over the question of whether the only kind of broad content is referential. Nathan Salmon (1986) and Scott Soames (1987) have defended the claim that singular concepts have on­ ly referential content. And Jerry Fodor (1994) (having previously argued for a two‐factor theory: Fodor 1987) has applied a version of the view to both singular and general con­ cepts, the latter being held to refer to properties. John McDowell (1977) and Gareth Page 3 of 15

Narrow Content Evans (1982) have defended the view that Fregean sense is often broad. And Burge (1979) has argued that the Fregean sense of (at least (p. 370) some) general concepts (such as arthritis) is broad. Internalists also divide over what kind of thing narrow content is. For the remainder of this chapter I will be concerned with arguments for narrow content (Section 21.2) and theories of narrow content (Section 21.3).

21.2 Arguments for Narrow Content The idea that twins' concepts have some kind of shared narrow content has some intu­ itive appeal if one thinks about matters from the twins' point of view. Even if it is the case that Oscar and Twin Oscar are thinking about different things when they deploy their ‘water’ concepts, it is natural to think that the way in which the concepts present the stuffs to them is the same. The way their thoughts present the world to them is the same (see Blackburn 1984; Loar 1987). As far as I know, however, it is impossible to turn this rather vague intuition into an argument. I will focus on arguments relating to psychological explanation. I will discuss three of these.

21.2.1 Causal Powers The following argument is adapted from Fodor (1987). Arguments about the nature of content should be constrained by the role that content plays or would play in scientific psychology. Taxonomy in science always respects causal powers, in the sense that items with the same causal powers are classified together. The psychological states of twins have the same causal powers. Therefore, they would be classified together. Therefore they would be ascribed the same content. So content is narrow. There is something immediately suspicious about that argument. For it appears to entail that scientific taxonomies never recognize relational properties. Thus, any two items that are intrinsically exactly similar have the same causal powers. So any two items that are intrinsically exactly similar should be classified together, even if they differ in their rela­ tional properties. But plenty of scientific taxonomy recognizes relational properties. Tax­ onomy by species in biology, for example, is sensitive to a creature's ancestry. If my neighbour's cat has a twin on a Twin Earth, that twin is not a cat, even though the two an­ imals have identical causal powers. If the planet Mars has an exact duplicate floating in a void somewhere far, far away, that object is not a planet, because, by definition, planets have to be gravitationally bound to a star. Fodor was, of course, aware of the legitimacy of relational taxonomy. He endeavoured to take this into account by allowing for taxonomy by relational properties that ‘affect causal powers’. Being a planet is a taxonomic property because ‘whether you are a planet af­ fects your trajectory, and your trajectory determines what you can bump into; so whether

Page 4 of 15

Narrow Content you are a planet affects your causal powers, which is all that individualism [i.e. internal­ ism] asks for’ (Fodor 1987: 43). (p. 371)

But internalism requires that twins be classified together. So if Fodor's argument is to be an argument for internalism then it must be understood along the following lines. Rela­ tional properties are only taxonomic when they affect causal powers. The relational prop­ erties that distinguish twins in the relevant cases do not affect their causal powers. Therefore twins ought to be classified together. Therefore their psychological states have the same content. But when do relational properties affect causal powers? Fodor returned to this question in Fodor (1991). At that point he thought that just about any contingent relational proper­ ty could affect causal powers because you could build a detector for it. Consider Fodor's example of the properties of being an H‐particle and being a T‐particle. Something is an H‐particle at a time t, iff it is a particle and Fodor's dime is heads up at t. Something is a T‐particle at time t iff it is a particle and Fodor's dime is tails up at t. One wouldn't initial­ ly think that being an H‐particle affects a thing's causal powers. But according to Fodor (1991) it does. We could build a machine that detects H‐particles. An H‐particle would cause the machine to register ‘H’ while a T‐particle would not. Analogously one could build a detector that could detect water thoughts: a water thought would cause it to register W, say, and a twater thought would not. So, Fodor argued, the question that is relevant to internalism is thus not ‘Do the twins' thoughts have different causal powers?’, but rather ‘Do they have different causal powers in respect of the effects that matter to psychology?’. Now ‘water’ thoughts and ‘twater’ thoughts do have different effects. For example, if someone believes that it's good to drink cool water on a hot day and that the 25th of July will be a hot day, then, if they consider the matter, these beliefs will cause them to believe that it will be good to drink cool water on the 25th of July. If someone has the correspond­ ing beliefs about twater, then they will be caused to believe that it will be good to drink cool twater on the 25th of July. Similarly, if someone wants to drink some water this might cause them to try to find some water, whereas if someone wants to drink some twater this might cause them to go looking for some twater. What we need to know is whether the difference between the effects is due to a differ­ ence between the causal powers of water thoughts and twater thoughts or due to some­ thing else. By way of comparison: since I have a brother I have the power to have a son who has the property of being a nephew. My siblingless twin lacks that power. His son would not be a nephew. But, intuitively, the difference between these effects is not due to a difference between my and my twin's causal powers. Reflection on that sort of case led Fodor to propose that a difference between properties of causes that correlates with a difference between effects is a difference of causal power Page 5 of 15

Narrow Content only if it is not conceptually necessary that causes which differ in that way have effects which differ in that way. Thus, the difference between me and my twin that correlates with my having a son who is a nephew and him having a son who is not a nephew is not a difference between our causal powers, because it (p. 372) is conceptually necessary that someone who has a brother can have a son who is a nephew and someone who lacks a sibling cannot.2 Fodor then argued that the difference between water thoughts and twater thoughts is like the difference between me and my siblingless twin. It is conceptually necessary that wa­ ter beliefs cause further water beliefs rather than twater beliefs and that water desires cause water‐seekings rather than twater‐seekings. Hence, the difference doesn't count as a difference of causal power. I will mention three objections to the argument. The first objection begins with the observation that the differences among the effects of water thoughts and twater thoughts are not confined to intentional ones. If Oscar seeks water and Twin Oscar seeks twater, then Oscar is likely to find water and Twin Oscar is likely to find twater. Fodor dismisses this sort of case quickly on the grounds that it is ac­ counted for just in terms of context. If Oscar were in his twin's context (i.e. on Twin Earth) then his seeking water would eventuate in his finding twater, and if Twin Oscar were in Oscar's context then he'd find water. But even if it is true that if the twins switched contexts they would have the same effects, it could still be the case that the different effects that the twins have in their different contexts is due to a difference between the twins' causal powers. To explain this, it will help to back up a bit. It is in fact not obvious that just about any relational property can affect causal powers just because one could build a detector for it. Indeed, Fodor no longer believes this (and he has persuaded me, pace Segal (forthcoming)). What causes an H‐particle detector to register an ‘H’? First, the particle's being a particle. And sec­ ond, Fodor's dime being heads up. And that is it. The particle's being such that Fodor's dime is heads up is not a causal power of the particle, because it makes no separate con­ tribution. The causal story is fully told in terms of the particle's being a particle and the dime's being heads up. But it is important to notice that relational properties can affect causal powers. Consider, for example, a ship's being anchored to the seabed. Clearly, this affects its causal powers: it can resist being moved by the currents. A twin ship that was not anchored could not do this. And notice that there is no way of decomposing the property of being anchored into a conjunction of intrinsic properties of the ship and ship‐independent properties of the environment. (The example and the point are due to Williamson 1998.) It may be that being about water is more like being anchored to the sand than like being an H‐particle. It certainly involves causal relations between a mental state and water, and thus fails to decompose into a conjunction of intrinsic properties of the mental state and mental‐state‐independent properties of the environment (see Williamson 1998). Thus, for Page 6 of 15

Narrow Content all of Fodor's clever argumentation, it remains possible that differences of broad content make for differences of causal powers (and ones that are relevant to psychology). (p. 373)

The second objection to Fodor's argument is that the premise which says that taxonomy in science respects causal powers may well be false. It seems plausible, for example, that there is no difference between the causal powers of a cat and those of a twin cat. But they would still count as members of different biological species. In general, one would expect some sciences to be exclusively concerned with the causal structure of their do­ mains, and one would expect other sciences to have other concerns. Science is not a monolith. The third objection goes like this. If we accept the standard view of the Twin Earth exper­ iments, then we should accept that folk psychology attributes wide contents. Fodor's view was that a scientific psychology would have to attribute narrow contents, because of the ‘taxonomy by causal powers’ constraint. But it is not obvious either that there could be a scientific psychology that respects the constraint or that, if there were such, it would tax­ onomize by content. Maybe the only content is broad content, and scientific accounts of cognition will appeal to, say, neurological properties or non‐intentional computational ones (as Stephen Stich (1983) argued).3

21.2.2 Empty Concepts A second argument for narrow content centres on the existence of empty concepts: con­ cepts that lack an actual extension. To explain this argument it will help to bring in a new example. In the eighteenth century George Stahl (extending a theory of combustion origi­ nated by Johann Becher) developed a theory of the calcination and corrosion of metals which proposed that metals were made of substances called ‘calx’ and ‘phlogiston’. The theory turned out to be wrong: there are no such substances as calx and phlogiston. Now let us consider two Twin Earths, T1 and T2, each inhabited by a twin Stahl (T‐Stahl1 and T‐Stahl2). Let us suppose that each of these T‐Stahls proposes a theory that looks just like Stahl's actual theory and that these theories are true of their worlds. Finally, let's suppose that different substances play the phlogiston roles on T1 and T2, phlogiston1 and phlogiston2 respectively. It is reasonable to assume that the difference between phlogis­ ton1 and phlogsiton2 is of the sort that a follower of Putnam would take to be a difference of kind identity, like the difference between XYZ and H2O. So according to the standard externalist line, ‘phlogiston’ has different meanings on T1 and T2 and expresses different contents in the mouths of Stahl1 and Stahl2. The argument proceeds as follows. Stahl's ‘phlogiston’ concept has a cognitive content. Some radical externalists (such as Ruth Millikan; see Millikan 1984) might deny this. But the denial flies in the face of good psychology. One simply cannot explain Stahl's sophisti­ cated theorizing behaviour without attributing to him a concept of phlogiston. (Indeed Millikan 2004 concedes that while he doesn't have (p. 374) a concept of phlogiston he does Page 7 of 15

Narrow Content have a ‘conception’ of it. I would argue that if a conception is not a concept, then it can­ not do the explanatory work it needs to do.) But then the possibility arises that T‐Stahl1 and T‐Stahl2 have concepts with the same content as Stahl's actual concept. And, indeed, a psychological theory that attributed the same cognitive content to all three Stahls' concepts would have an advantage over one that did not, since it would have greater generality and could account for the cognitive and behavioural similarities among the twins. Good methodology therefore suggests that the content of the three Stahl's concepts is the same.4

21.2.3 Loar's Argument The third argument for narrow content is due to Brian Loar (1987) (and was developed and defended in Segal 2000). It is designed to show, pace Burge, that the content of psy­ chological states is not individuated by the linguistic environment. Recall Alf, who ap­ peared to believe that he had arthritis in the thigh. Suppose that prior to visiting his doc­ tor and learning the correct definition of ‘arthritis’ Alf travels to France. There he learns of a condition called ‘arthrite’, coming to know that it is an inflammation of the joints and the joints alone. He does not realize that ‘arthrite’ and ‘arthritis’ are synonymous, and continues to believe that arthritis can affect the thigh. Given his epistemic state, Alf might be disposed to assert ‘I have arthritis in my thigh’ and to deny ‘I have arthrite in my thigh’. In order to explain this, we have to suppose that Alf associates two concepts with different cognitive contents with the two words ‘arthrite’ and ‘arthritis’.5 Yet the concepts' socially individuated Burgean content is the same.6

21.3 What is Narrow Content? There are, then, some reasons to believe that the cognitive content of concepts is narrow. The question then arises what narrow content might be like. The answer to that question depends largely on whether narrow content is one factor in a two‐factor account or the only factor in a one‐factor account. I will discuss two‐factor accounts (p. 375) first. I will take it that a two‐factor theorist accepts the view of broad content inspired by Putnam and Burge, and holds some sort of causal theory of broad content and proposes that rep­ resentations with broad content have narrow content as well.

21.3.1 Narrow Content as Functional Role The functional role of a psychological state is the causal role it plays in its owner's psy­ chology, such as might be specified by the Ramsey sentence of some psychological theory that talked about the state.7 To be a functionalist about some domain of psychological properties is to hold that properties in that domain can be identified with functional roles. Some functionalists are externalists who identify broad content with functional role (Har­ man 1987). And some internalists are functionalists about narrow content, and hold that

Page 8 of 15

Narrow Content narrow contents can be identified with functional roles (e.g. Block 1986). We might call the view ‘narrow functionalism’. There are two very different forms narrow functionalism might take. The first would fol­ low the standard form of a functional reduction. A standard functional reduction of a range of properties appeals to a theory that already has a vocabulary that specifies the properties and details a range of causal relations among their possessors. For example, a functionalist about chemical properties appeals to the theory of chemistry. This theory has terms for the chemical properties and tells us about how chemicals interact. Func­ tionalism then says that chemical properties can be identified with the causal roles as­ cribed to the possessors of those properties by chemistry—properties that could be speci­ fied, say, by Ramsey's method. Run‐of‐the‐mill narrow functionalism would take the same form: it would refer to a theory that specifies narrow contents and details a range of causal relations among their possessors and claim that narrow contents could be identi­ fied with the functional roles given by that theory. The problem for run‐of‐the‐mill narrow functionalism is that we don't seem to have the required theory to appeal to. The second form of narrow functionalism—named directly reductive narrow functionalism (or ‘DRNF’) in Segal (2000)—attempts to finesse this difficulty. The idea behind DRNF is that we could abstract an account of narrow functional roles from a psychology that attributes broad contents. On the face of it, this seems plausible. Suppose for example that the following are fragments of psychological theories that apply to 1750 earth and Twin Earth subjects: If x is thirsty then x will desire to drink some water and if x desires to drink some wa­ ter and x believes that there is some water in a glass in his hand then x will try to drink the water. If x is thirsty then x will desire to drink some twater and if x desires to drink some twa­ ter and x believes that there is some twater in a glass in his hand then x will try to drink the twater. Then we might abstract some narrow functional roles by, for example, replacing the con­ tent specifications with variables: (p. 376)

If x is thirsty then x will desire P1 and if x desires P1 and x believes P2 then x will try P3. The narrow content of, for example, the thought that there is some water in a glass in one's hand would then be identified with the role of the thought characterized by P2 in the schematic theo­ ry.

Segal (2000) made two objections to DRNF, neither of which is persuasive. The first objection was that there is no way to distinguish aspects of a concept's function­ al role that go with its content from those that don't. So, for example, we can imagine near‐twin subjects who have exactly the same propositional attitudes, but one of whom has more memory‐buffer space than the other. The functional roles of their concepts will then differ. Page 9 of 15

Narrow Content And indeed there are indefinitely many features of a cognitive system that might affect the functional role of a concept without affecting its content. In order to specify the en­ tire functional role of a concept, one would have to specify its role in every possible cog­ nitive system and this would seem to be beyond the scope of any proper psychological theory. But the objection is not persuasive because the narrow content of a concept could per­ haps be identified not with its total functional role but with some appropriate and natural sub‐part of that role, such as its role in inference. The second objection was that a concept's content is what explains its functional role, so the content cannot be identical with that functional role. But no argument was given for this claim, and it is highly contentious. It is a common and respectable view that many theoretical terms are functionally defined by their role in the relevant theory. And there is no particular reason to suppose that the terms of psychology are not like that.8 So perhaps DRNF is true. But it doesn't help much because we have no vocabulary for as­ cribing functional roles and theorising about them.

21.3.2 Narrow Content as Epistemic Intension David Chalmers (2002) has offered an account of narrow content as ‘epistemic intension’. This account can be seen as the most developed of a family of proposals all of which en­ deavour to adapt the traditional notion of an intension to internalist purposes. An inten­ sion is a function from possible worlds to extensions. So, for example, the intension of ‘the British Prime Minister in the year 2005’ is (roughly speaking) a function that maps each possible world on to the particular individual who serves as the British Prime Minis­ ter in 2005 in that world (and otherwise on to nothing). The intension of ‘the British Prime Minister in the year 2005 is (p. 377) male’ is a function that maps each possible world on to ‘the true’ iff the British Prime Minister in the year 2005 in that world is a male in that world, otherwise on to ‘the false’. Classical intensions are not narrow. The in­ tension of the earth term ‘water’ maps each possible world on to H2O, while the intension of the Twin Earth term ‘water’ maps each possible world on to XYZ.9 But there have been various attempts to account for narrow content in terms of some non‐classical kind of in­ tension—one that would, for example, assign the same function to ‘water’ and Twin ‘wa­ ter’.10 An epistemic intension is a function from epistemically possible worlds to extensions. While there is no metaphysically possible world in which Hesperus is not Phosphorus, it is epistemically possible that Hesperus is not Phosphorus: for all you know a priori, it might indeed be the case that Hesperus isn't Phosphorus. And it seems reasonable to suppose that there is a set of possible worlds that in some natural way correspond to this thought that you are entertaining—roughly speaking, those worlds that are like the actual world, but in which your ‘Hesperus’ concept refers to a heavenly body that appears early in the evening and your ‘Phosphorus’ concept refers to a quite distinct heavenly body that brings light in the morning. In Chalmers's terms, these worlds ‘verify’ the thought that Page 10 of 15

Narrow Content Hesperus is not Phosphorus. There is also a set of epistemically possible worlds that ‘fal­ sify’ the thought that Hesperus is not Phosphorus: roughly speaking, those worlds, includ­ ing the actual one, in which a single heavenly body appears both in the morning and the evening and is the referent of your two concepts. Thus, we can see the epistemic inten­ sion of a thought as a function from epistemically possible worlds to truth‐values. In fact, Chalmers's story is a little more complicated than that, involving possible worlds as observed from particular points in space and time. Entertain the possibility that water is not H2O. There is a possible world in which some planets are rife with H2O and others are rife with XYZ. If you were on an H2O planet, then the world would verify the thought you are entertaining. If you were on an XYZ planet, then that same world would falsify the thought. So we need a notion of a ‘centred’ world, a world plus a spatio‐temporal location within it. We can call these centred worlds ‘scenarios’ (roughly following Chalmers's own terminology). For each thinker there is a set of scenarios that constitutes their epistemic space: the set of possibilities that is not ruled out for them a priori. Every a posteriori belief of the thinker's rules out some possibilities a priori, while leaving others a priori open. The for­ mer set of scenarios verify the thought believed, the latter set falsify it. Intuitively, to see whether a given scenario, S, verifies a thought, T, one considers whether the hypothesis that S is actual is a priori consistent with T. If it is, then S verifies T, if it is not, then S fal­ sifies T. Chalmers argues that narrow content is epistemic intension. This account has some intu­ itive appeal. The narrow content of a thought ought to correspond to (p. 378) how things are presented by the thought to the subject's subjective point of view. Prima facie, epis­ temic intensions appear to be decent candidates to play that role. But the account be­ comes less plausible when the technical details are fleshed out a little. What exactly is it for a scenario to verify or falsify a thought? Chalmers's answer goes as follows. Every scenario has a canonical description, D. To consider the hypothesis that a scenario, S, is actual is to consider the hypothesis that D is the case. D consists in an ob­ jective description of S along with an indexical description of the thinker's location in S. An objective description contains only ‘semantically neutral’ terms. Roughly speaking, a semantically neutral term is one that is not subject to Twin Earth experiments with cor­ rect externalist interpretations. Thus, it is one that would mean the same in the lan­ guages of any twins, no matter how their environments differed. More precisely, a seman­ tically neutral term is one with narrow extension conditions; that is to say, extension con­ ditions that are not fixed by anything outside the subject's skin. (According to Chalmers, most names, natural‐kind terms, indexicals, and terms used deferentially are not semanti­ cally neutral.) If D is a canonical description of S, then S verifies T if the hypothesis that D is the case implies S, and S falsifies T if the hypothesis that D is the case contradicts S. So corresponding to any thought T there is one set of canonical descriptions delimiting the scenarios that verify T and another set delimiting the scenarios that falsify T. The stip­ Page 11 of 15

Narrow Content ulation that all the descriptions in the sets must be semantically neutral is required if epistemic intensions are to be narrow. The problem with this account is that it is implausible that the requisite semantically neu­ tral descriptions exist. Consider a modest and trusting subject, Angelica. Angelica has a thought she would express by saying ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’. What is the epistemic in­ tension of her thought? To a first approximation it is verified by those scenarios satisfying the description: ‘The heavenly body that first appears in the evening is identical with the heavenly body that brings light in the morning’. But suppose that Angelica uses ‘heavenly body’, ‘first’, ‘evening’, ‘identical with’, ‘light’, and ‘morning’ deferentially. Then this de­ scription is not semantically neutral. But then what semantically neutral descriptions might fit the bill? On the face of it, there aren't any. In fact, Chalmers stipulates the descriptions are formulable in an idealized language. But there is no guarantee that any idealized language will contain the required descriptions. Remember that the scenarios at issue are those that are a priori consistent with Angelica's thought that Hesperus is Phosphorus. It is reasonable to suppose that no set of semantically neutral descriptions that she herself understands would precisely delimit the epistemic intension of her thought. The alternative would be that the descriptions are largely formulable in terms that she does not understand. But we would not expect those to capture the space of possibilities delimited by Angelica's own thoughts and concepts.11 (p. 379)

21.3.3 Narrow Content as Ordinary Content

Segal (2000) defends a one‐factor account of narrow content of non‐singular concepts. I argued that it is a mistake to trust the externalist intuitions generated by the standard Twin Earth thought experiments and that it is a mistake to think that, for example, Oscar's and Twin Oscar's ‘water’ concepts have different extensions. Rather, both extend over both water and twin water and any other suitably watery substance. The problem for this view is that it does not provide a satisfactory account of Putnam's ‘elm’ and ‘beech’ concepts. According to the standard externalist account of the ‘elm’/‘beech’ case, Putnam's ‘elm’ concept extends over elms and elms only, while Twin Putnam's ‘elm’ concept extends over beeches and beeches only; mutatis mutandis for their ‘beech’ concepts. If we are to treat this case on the suggested model for ‘water’ we would have to conclude that both concepts extend over both elms and beeches and any other elm‐like trees. But that just seems wrong. It thus looks as though some non‐classical sort of intension would be a better candidate for narrow content, some kind of function from possible worlds to extensions.

21.4 Conclusion There are, then, powerful arguments that cognitive content is not individuated in terms of the natural and social environment in the way that broad content is, according to stan­ Page 12 of 15

Narrow Content dard externalist lines. There is therefore reason to think that cognitive content is narrow. There is, however, at the time of writing, no satisfactory account of narrow content. It is possible that narrow content could be identified with functional role. There is however, at the time of writing, no account of what a psychological theory that attributes functional roles would be like.

References Blackburn, S. (1984), Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Block, N. (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, Midwest Studies in Phi­ losophy, 10: 615–78. Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. —— (1982), ‘Other Bodies’, in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object: Essays on Inten­ tionality (Oxford: Clarendon), 97–120. Chalmers, D. J. (2002), ‘The Components of Content’, in Chalmers, Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 608–33. —— (2006), ‘The Foundations of Two‐Dimensional Semantics’, in M. Garcia‐Carpintero and J. Macia (eds.), Two‐Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 55–140. Davidson, D. (1987), ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60: 441–58. (p. 380)

Dennett, D. (1982), ‘Beyond Belief’, in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object: Essays on Intentionality (Oxford: Clarendon), 1–96. Evans, G. (1982), ‘The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Fodor, J. (1987), Psychosemantics (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press/Bradford). —— (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1991), ‘A Modal Argument for Narrow Content’, Journal of Philosophy, 88: 5–26. —— (1994), ‘The Elm and the Expert (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Harman, G. (1987), ‘(Non‐solipsistic) Conceptual Role Semantics’, in E. LePore (ed.), New Directions in Semantics (London: Academic), 55–81. Kripke, S. (1972), ‘Naming and Necessity’, in D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.), Seman­ tics of Natural Language (Reidel: Dordrecht), 253–355.

Page 13 of 15

Narrow Content Loar, B. (1987), ‘Social Content and Psychological Content’, in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought: Proceedings of the 1985 Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy, 99–139. McDowell, J. (1977), ‘The Sense and Reference of a Proper Name’, Mind, 86: 159–85. McGinn, C. (1982), ‘The Structure of Content’, in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object: Essays on Intentionality (Oxford: Clarendon) 207–58. Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2004), On Clear and Confused Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Minneapolis, Minn.: Uni­ versity of Michigan Press), 131–93. Salmon, N. (1986), Frege's Puzzle (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Soames, S. (1987), ‘Direct Reference, Propositional Attitudes and Semantic Content’, Philosophical Topics, 15: 47–87. Segal, G. (1997), ‘Content and Computation: A Critical Notice of Jerry Fodor's The Elm and the Expert, Mind and Language, 12: 491–501. —— (2000), A Slim Book about Narrow Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2003), ‘Ignorance of Meaning’, in A. Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 415–30. —— (forthcoming), ‘Keep Making Sense’, Synthese. Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case against Belief (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). White, S. (1982), ‘Partial Character and the Language of Thought’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63: 647–65. Williamson, T. (1998), ‘The Broadness of the Mental: Some Logical Considerations’, Philo­ sophical Perspectives, 12: 389–410.

Notes: (1) It is actually very difficult to formulate the notion of narrowness in a satisfactory way. All kinds of issues come up. For example, what is the modal force of ‘presuppose’ or ‘in any essential way require’ (or ‘individuated in terms of’ as used below)? What are the boundaries of the subject? (The skin is not the right boundary, since it imposes a distinc­

Page 14 of 15

Narrow Content tion between say, the subject's heart and her husband that is not wanted in this context.) Unfortunately, there is no space to discuss these issues here. (2) Actually I am oversimplifying here: Fodor's condition is more complicated than that. But the details don't matter for present purposes. (3) Fodor himself gave up his arguments for narrow content in Fodor (1994), I think largely because he came to believe that a science that attributed broad contents could formulate good, predictive generalizations. For a critique of Fodor (1994) see Segal (1997). (4) The conclusion of the argument is that the twins' phlogiston concepts have a shared content. It does not quite follow that the content is narrow. But at least it undermines the idea that the cognitive content of a natural‐kind concept depends partly on its extension. (5) That is to say we need to adopt a roughly Fregean criterion of difference for concepts: If a subject sincerely asserts a sentence, S, and denies a sentence S′, then he expresses different thoughts by S and S′. And since ‘I have arthritis in my thigh’ and ‘I have arthrite in my thigh’ differ only in the words ‘arthritis’ and ‘arthrite’, we can infer that Alf asso­ ciates different concepts with those particular words. I defend the roughly Fregean crite­ rion in Segal (2003). (6) The conclusion is that cognitive content is not individuated partly by social factors in the way Burge describes. Again it does not quite follow that cognitive content is narrow. But again a reason for thinking that it is broad is undermined. (7) More properly: the functional role of a psychological state that matters in this context. A psychological state will have other sorts of functional role as well. (8) See my ‘The Causal Inefficacy of Content’ (forthcoming) for some considerations in favour of a functional account of cognitive content. (9) At least according to many, who follow Kripke (1972) in holding that ‘water’ is a rigid designator. (10) For proposals in this ballpark see Dennett (1982), White (1982), Fodor (1987), and Loar (1987). (11) For more extensive discussion of Chalmers's proposal see Chalmers (2006).

Gabriel Segal

Gabriel Segal is Professor of Philosophy at King's College London.

Page 15 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics

Oxford Handbooks Online Information‐Theoretic Semantics   Fred Dretske The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0023

Abstract and Keywords Informational semantics takes the primary — at least the original — home of meaning to be the mind: meaning as the content of thought, desire, and intention. The meaning of beliefs, desires, and intentions is what it is we believe, desire, and intend. The sounds and marks of natural language derive their meaning from the communicative intentions of the agents who deploy them. As a result, the information of chief importance to informational semantics is that occurring in the transactions between animals and their environments. So for informational semantics the very existence of thought and, thus, the possibility of language depends on the capacity of (some) living systems to transform information (normally supplied by perception) into meaningful (contentful) inner states like thought, intention, and purpose. Keywords: informational semantics, meaning, natural language, communicative intentions, perception, information

INFORMATION‐THEORETIC

semantics is an attempt to ground meaning—as meaning is

understood in the study both of language and of mind—in an objective, mind‐ (and language‐) independent notion of information. It is typically part of a larger philosophical effort to naturalize mentality—to understand thought and its expression in language as just another strand in the fabric of material affairs. If symbols are the bearers of meaning, the things in the world that have meaning, information‐theoretic semantics locates the primary source of this meaning in the relations these symbols bear to the world they are, or purport to be, about. These symbol– world relations can be described in explicitly information‐theoretic terms (source, signal, noise, receiver, etc.), as occurs in Dretske (1981), or they can be described in more general causal terms (Stampe 1977, 1986; Matthen 1988; Fodor 1990; Israel and Perry 1990). However it may be expressed, though, the basic idea is that the primary Page 1 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics determinant of a symbol's meaning is those situations in the world about which symbols carry, or are supposed to carry (more about this important qualification in a moment), information, those situations in the world of which the symbols are (in normal conditions) reliable signs. Since, according to some (e.g. Dretske 1986; Israel and Perry 1990), the information an event carries is what its occurrence indicates, informational semantics is sometimes referred to as indicator semantics: what a symbol means is what, in certain central cases, it indicates, or is supposed to indicate, or normally indicates, about other parts of the world. Theories of this sort are to be contrasted with conceptual‐role, procedural, or (p. 382) consumer semantics—theories that locate the meaning of a symbol not (or not only) in upstream causes, but also (and sometimes primarily) in the downstream effects these symbols have on other symbols and on the behaviour of the system in which they occur (Block 1986; Papineau 1987; Millikan 1989). Informational semantics takes the primary—at least the original—home of meaning to be the mind: meaning as the content of thought, desire, and intention. The meaning of beliefs, desires, and intentions is what it is we believe, desire, and intend. The sounds and marks of natural language derive their meaning from the communicative intentions of the agents who deploy them. As a result, the information of chief importance to informational semantics is that occurring in the transactions between animals and their environments. So for informational semantics the very existence of thought and, thus, the possibility of language depends on the capacity of (some) living systems to transform information (normally supplied by perception) into meaningful (contentful) inner states like thought, intention, and purpose.

22.1 Information The word ‘meaning’ is ambiguous. Two of its possible meanings (Grice 1989) are: (1) non‐ natural meaning—the sense in which the English word ‘fire’ stands for or means fire; and (2) natural meaning—the way in which smoke (not the word ‘smoke’, but smoke itself) means (indicates, is a sign of) fire. Non‐natural meaning, the kind of meaning theories of meaning (like information‐theoretic semantics) are supposed to be theories of, has no necessary connection with truth. The words ‘Jim has the measles’ mean that Jim has the measles whether or not Jim has the measles. Natural meaning, on the other hand, requires the existence of the condition meant: if Jim does not have the measles, the red spots on his face do not mean (indicate) that he has the measles. Perhaps all they mean is that he has been eating too much candy. Natural meaning, what an event indicates, what it is a sign of, is a relation between the sign and what it signifies that does not depend on anyone recognizing or identifying what is meant. It does not depend on conscious beings at all. Expanding metal (e.g. the mercury in a thermometer) indicates or means that the temperature is increasing whether or not anyone knows that this is what it means. A particular cloud formation means a cold front is approaching even if (because no one is aware of its meaning) it does not mean this to anyone. We found out that this is what it Page 2 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics means. Unlike non‐natural meaning, what things indicate, what they mean in a natural sense, is something we learn about events by patient investigation. We learn what tracks in the snow (or a cloud chamber) mean; we do not, as we do with words and other conventional symbols, assign them their meaning. Information, as this is used in informational semantics, is akin to natural meaning. It is what the signal, some event occurring at a ‘receiver’ (an animal's brain, for instance), indicates about conditions existing at a causal ‘source’ (perhaps an object in the animal's environment). It might, for instance, mean (indicate, carry the (p. 383) information) that the object is moving, that it is located between two other objects, or that it is changing colour. The information carried by a signal, as so understood, is a fact—the fact expressed by the true proposition describing what the signal indicates about the source. So if e, an event at the receiver, indicates that s, an object at the source, is moving to the left, this fact about s is the information e carries about s. To speak about information is to speak about facts—the true propositions about a source that we (if properly atuned) can come to know about that source by receipt of a signal carrying that information. That, indeed, is why information is such an important commodity. It is why we, human beings, pay money (for tuition, for instance) to obtain it, why (in wartime) people are tortured in order to extract it from them, and why billions are spent on scientific instruments to obtain increasingly precise and exotic forms of it. The tendency in computer science to construe information as anything—whether true or false—capable of being stored on a hard disk is to confuse non‐natural meaning (or perhaps just structure) with genuine information. It leaves it a mystery why information should be thought a useful commodity. Information booths are not merely places where one goes to hear people utter meaningful sentences. They are places you go expecting people to utter meaningful true sentences about the topics they dispense information about. Thinking of information in terms of natural signs and what they indicate makes it clear that information depends on a system of stable relations existing between signal and source. It isn't enough, for instance, that s, an object at a source, always happens to be moving whenever a particular type of event, e, occurs at the receiver. That isn't enough to make e indicate that s is moving. No, for e to mean (in the natural sense) that s is moving, for e to carry this piece of information, e must depend on s's movement in a particularly reliable way. Circumstances must be such that in these circumstances only s’s movement will result in e. If, in these conditions, something else can result in e, then the occurrence of e does not mean that s moved. The ringing of my telephone doesn't indicate, doesn't, therefore, carry the information, that you are calling me simply because, in point of fact, you are the only person who ever calls me. What is relevant is not whether anyone else ever does call me, but whether anyone else might call me—even if only someone dialing a wrong number or a bothersome telemarketer. If it might be someone else, then the ringing phone does not indicate that you are calling me. At most it means that it is probably you.

Page 3 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics Another way of expressing this relation between source and receiver, the relation on which the flow of information depends (one I adopted in Dretske 1981 in order to make clear its connection with the mathematical theory of information and cognitive science in general), is to say that e, some event at a receiver, carries information about an object, s, at the source—the information, say, that s is F—only if conditions are such that e raises the probability of s's being F to 1. It isn't enough to raise the probability to something less than 1—to 0.99 for instance. That isn't good enough. The reason it isn't good enough is that the relation in question (whether called information, indication, or natural meaning) is a transitive relation: if a indicates (means, carries the information) that b, and b indicates (means, carries the information) that c, then a must indicate (mean, carry the information) (p. 384) that c. If force on the restraining spring means that an electrical current is flowing in the circuit, and current flow in the circuit means there is a voltage difference, then force on the spring indicates a voltage difference. If Sally's expression indicates she is interested, and interest indicates (at least partial) understanding, then Sally's expression indicates (at least partial) understanding. This is why no signal can carry the information that water is freezing without carrying all the information carried by freezing water—that, for example, the temperature is at or below 32 °F. Setting the probability (required for the transmission of information) at anything less than 1 would not preserve this transitivity. It is not (in general) true that if the probability of b, given a, is (at least) 0.99, and the probability of c, given b, is also (a least) 0.99, then the probability of c, given a, is also (at least) 0.99. It may be less than 0.99. So if we are going to use probability at all to express the relations in question, those relations between source and receiver that enable events at the receiver to carry information about the source, we must express these as probabilities of 1. Nothing less than 1 maintains the transitivity of this indicator (natural meaning, informational) relation. It may be thought that this sets the bar too high. In our messy unpredictable world probabilities seldom, if ever, reach a value of 1. If information requires a probability of 1, then we seldom, if ever, get information. This worry betrays a misunderstanding. The probabilities in question, whether they are probabilities of 1, 0.99, or 0.5, are assigned against a background of stable circumstances, circumstances that can, but are assumed not to, change for purposes of fixing what can happen. In normal circumstances the ring of my doorbell carries information: it indicates or means that someone is at my door. It does so despite the fact that in different conditions—when there is a short circuit in the wiring, when there is an infestation by poltergeists, when squirrels have been trained to push doorbell buttons—a doorbell can be made to ring without anyone (a person) pushing the doorbell button. But in normal circumstances, circumstances that include the actually existing wiring and the absence of poltergeists and trained squirrels, there is nothing else besides someone pressing my doorbell button that can make my doorbell ring. So in these circumstances the ring indicates that someone is at my door. It carries this information. It makes the probability of someone's being at my door 1. It makes the probability 1 whether or not we know it is 1. If it doesn't make the probability 1, if there is, unknown to us, a small probability that my doorbell is ringing when no one is at my door (there is a

Page 4 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics trained squirrel that ranges freely in the neighbourhood), then the ring does not indicate that someone is at my door. All it indicates is that someone is probably there. It might be the squirrel.

Page 5 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics

22.2 Meaning Semantics is the study of meaning in so far as meaning is understood to be non‐natural meaning: the kind of meaning in which ‘smoke’ means smoke (not fire); the (p. 385) kind of meaning in which a prophet can say, and thus mean, that the end is near without the end actually being near; the kind of meaning in which something in a person's head, for instance a perceptual experience or a belief, can mean (represent) one line to be longer than another even though the lines are of equal length. Information, as we have just described it (i.e. as indication or natural meaning), obviously cannot be equated with meaning in this (non‐natural) sense. Nothing can carry the information that one line is longer than another, nothing can (naturally) mean or indicate that this is so, unless, in fact, the line is longer than the other. So an information‐theoretic semantics, if it is to do the job, if it is to provide a plausible theory of non‐natural meaning, must supplement or combine information as this is presently being understood with some other ingredient to capture the targeted concept. There is some disagreement about what this additional idea or ingredient might be, but, whatever it is, it must somehow manage to convert natural signs of F, things that carry information about the F‐ness of things, into things, symbols, which do not (or need not) carry such information. The favoured way of doing this is by appealing to the sort of ‘norms’ generated by things having a certain function. The basic idea is modelled on the way we give certain objects—measuring instruments, for instance—the power to mean, in a non‐natural way, that something is so‐and‐so by giving these objects the job or function of ‘telling us’ (carrying the information) that something is so‐and‐so. A speedometer can say or represent that a car is going 60 mph when it isn't. What gives the instrument the power to mean, non‐naturally, that the car is going 60 mph is the fact that it has a certain informational function (a function we—designers, makers, and users—give it): the function of telling us, providing us with information, about the speed of the car. When it is doing its job, it tells us how fast the car is going. If, because of mechanical difficulties, the instrument ceases to do its job, it nonetheless still ‘says’ (represents) that the car is going a certain speed, but it now misrepresents the speed. It (by pointing at the numeral ‘60’) says something false. It exhibits a form of non‐natural meaning. No one, however, gives our brains an information‐carrying function in the way that we give measuring instruments their information‐carrying functions. So if this is to be a model for how our brains acquire (in the form of experience and thought) the power to mean that something is so (whether or not it is so), the power to think that one line is longer than another when it isn't, the information‐carrying functions must be (what we may call) natural functions—perhaps biological functions—functions that do not depend on or derive from us in any way. To smuggle in functions that, in whatever way, depend on our purposes in the way the functions of speedometers depend on them is to smuggle in at the very beginning of the analysis the very thing—the kind of meaning associated with

Page 6 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics human purposes and thought—that our theory of meaning is supposed to be an analysis of. Setting aside for the moment questions about the existence of natural functions (I return to this in the next section), the idea would be to equate meaning or representational content with an element's information‐carrying function. The functions convert natural signs into non‐natural symbols. If event type E has tokens, (p. 386) e 1,e 2,… which, in normal circumstances, are natural signs that s is F, and if E acquires, through an appropriate history, the function of carrying this information, then tokens of that type thereafter mean, in a non‐natural way, that s is F even when s isn't F. They mean (non‐ naturally) this because that is what they are supposed to mean (naturally). The norm invoked by speaking of this as something they are supposed to mean is given by their information‐carrying function. They are supposed to mean this in the same way hearts are supposed to pump blood. Just as a cashier, someone whose job is to operate the cash register, can be asked to sweep floors, a symbol for F, something whose job it is to indicate F, can be pressed into kinds of service unrelated to its information‐carrying function. It might appear, for instance, in a desire for F, a fear of F, or just idle thought about F. Once we have a word for F in the language of thought, this word can now occur in mental questions (I wonder whether that is an F), commands (Give me an F), and hopes (I hope that is an F), as well as assertions (judgements that something is an F).

22.3 Problems and Promises That is the good news. Now for some bad news. How bad the news is depends on how intractable the following problems are. I make suggestions here and there, but sometimes, with the customary excuse about lack of space, I provide nothing more than a promise about how an answer might go. The ultimate plausibility of information‐theoretic semantics depends on there being detailed and convincing solutions to these problems.

22.3.1 Natural Functions I spoke above of natural functions, the kind of function a thing has that is independent of anyone's recognition and/or attribution of that function. Stop signs and speedometers have functions, but they are not natural functions. As we all know, what stop signs and speedometers are supposed to do, or what we are supposed to do with them, derives from the collective purposes, desires, and beliefs of their designers, makers, and users. Information‐based semantics needs something else. It needs natural functions, functions that (to avoid circularity) are independent of collective (or individual) purposes and beliefs. Where are these functions? What is it in nature that gives the visual systems of animals the function of providing information about optical surroundings? What makes Page 7 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics the provision of information something the eyes, ears, and nose are for? Granted they do supply information; we couldn't survive without it. The question is whether there is any sense in which they are supposed to supply it. The presumption is, of course, that the functions have their source in natural selection and learning. If the heart is supposed to pump blood and the liver is supposed (p. 387) to clean it, if these are the functions of these bodily organs created by a process of natural selection, why can't the eyes and ears and associated neural systems also have duties—in particular, information they are supposed to provide? Or if during operant conditioning, a pervasive form of learning, internal indicators of those stimulus conditions with which reinforced behaviour is to be coordinated come to exercise control over behaviour (the only way this kind of learning can be successful), why isn't it thereafter the job, the function, the purpose of these indicators (e.g. perceptual states) to provide information about the stimulus conditions on which the acquired behaviour depends? It isn't important that the word ‘function’ be used to describe what these organs or systems develop to do. Some people seem to think that the word ‘function’ (in the sense of ‘purpose’, not in the sense of ‘causal role’) is only really appropriate when applied to systems to which human beings, given their special interests, have assigned a purpose.1 According to this view, there is, independent of our interests, nothing the eyes, ears, and nose are for, nothing that they are supposed to be doing. We needn't, however, quarrel over the word ‘function’. What is important for the purposes of information‐theoretic semantics is that there be a set of circumstances, or perhaps a kind of history, that, independent of human interests, grounds descriptions of animals and their parts as ill, sick, broken, damaged, injured, diseased, defective, flawed, infected, contaminated, or malfunctioning. If the truth of these descriptions is independent of our interests and purposes,2 then there is a way natural systems are supposed to be, or supposed to behave, that is independent of how we conceive them. There would, therefore, be a perfectly natural sense in which, given appropriate development, the information‐ processing systems in animals would be able to make mistakes—able, that is, to mean that something was so when it wasn't. Misrepresentation, the sine qua non of non‐natural meaning, would thus become possible in a perfectly natural way. It is hard to see why this much isn't available.

22.3.2 The Disjunction Problem In order to mean, in the non‐natural way we are trying to understand, that s is F, it must be possible for something to mean this when s isn't F. It doesn't have to be a dog for me to think and say it is. Symbols (linguistic or mental) that mean dog don't have to be caused by dogs. They can be caused by wolves or (Fodor's example3) cats‐on‐a‐dark‐night—things one might mistake for a dog. But anything that means or indicates, anything that carries the information, anything that is a sign, that s is a dog (p. 388) has to be caused by a dog.4 This is the fundamental difference between natural and non‐natural meaning.

Page 8 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics This seems to create a problem. How can you convert something that is a sign of F, something that indicates that F, something that (carrying information about F‐ness) can only be caused by an F, into something, a symbol for F, that can be caused by non‐Fs? Fodor (1990: 60) was certainly right that almost all attempts to solve this problem rely on distinguishing two contexts—one (call it the pure or normal context) in which the symbol for F is only caused by Fs (thus carrying information about the F‐ness of a source) and one, call it the impure context, in which it can be caused by a variety of non‐Fs (those, for instance that look like Fs), thus making misrepresentation (and, therefore, non‐natural meaning) possible. The symbol type gets its information‐carrying function, and thus its meaning, in the first context, when it is carrying information. This gives it a meaning that it takes to the impure context, a context in which, given its acquired function, it now means F (what it has the function of indicating) without anything necessarily being F. The problem is to understand how ‘pure’ cases are possible, the conditions in which something can indicate dog while, at the same time, being capable of being caused (in the impure condition) by a wolf. If in impure conditions the symbol can be caused by a wolf (or anything else one might mistake for a dog), then why wouldn't it have been caused by a wolf in the pure case if, contrary to fact, a wolf had appeared there? If it would have been caused by a wolf had a wolf appeared in the pure condition, then how, in the normal or pure case, can the symbol indicate, how can it carry the information, that something is a dog? All it really seems to indicate, given the constraints on information described earlier, is a disjunctive (hence the ‘disjunction’ problem) fact, the fact that s is either a dog or a wolf. If that disjunctive fact is, indeed, the information it really carries, then the information the symbol acquires the function of carrying must be this disjunctive information. According to information‐theoretic semantics, then, this disjunctive fact is what the element comes to (non‐naturally) mean. If that is what it non‐naturally means, however, then instances of the symbol caused by wolves in the impure condition are not misrepresentations. The cause—a wolf—actually is what the symbol's meaning says it is; namely, a wolf or a dog. So we have not achieved what we were after; that is, a symbol, something that can mean dog when it is caused by, and thus applied to, a wolf. A lot of ink has been spilt on this problem, and nothing I can say in the space of a few paragraphs is going to settle matters, but I think it worth emphasizing that natural meaning, indication, and, therefore, information (of the relevant sort) are all context‐ dependent notions. Something can indicate F in one set of circumstances, (p. 389) not in another. Certain coloration and markings on the bird indicate that it is a blue jay, but these signs can (be made to) occur on an object that is not a blue jay. If circumstances are such that fake jays (non‐blue jays that have the same colour and markings) are a genuine possibility, then coloration and markings of that sort do not indicate that the bird is a blue jay. They only indicate something disjunctive in character—that it is either a blue jay or a fake jay. Readers familiar with recent developments in epistemology will recognize these points as part of the ‘relevant‐possibility’ theme in theories of knowledge. Recognizing a blue jay at the bird feeder does not require that one be able to distinguish real blue jays from fake jays—not if fake jays are not, as they usually aren't, relevant possibilities under Page 9 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics normal viewing conditions. That is why knowing there is water (i.e. H2O) in the creek does not require being able to distinguish H2O from XYZ (a molecularly distinct substance found on Twin Earth that looks like water). Not if XYZ is not, as it clearly is not if it is found only on Twin Earth, a relevant possibility. If, on the other hand, XYZ is actually found in some lakes and streams on earth, then you don't know the water you see is water even if it is water. It might, for all you can tell, be XYZ. Quite independently of theories of meaning, then, we must recognize that something can carry information about dogs (blue jays, water) in one context, not in another. There are pure contexts, contexts in which dogs have to be taken as the only relevant cause of (the symbol) DOG, and impure contexts, contexts in which wolves, cats‐on‐a‐dark‐night, and perhaps even drugs in the bloodstream might be causing DOG. This being so, I see no problem in appealing to this distinction in a theory of meaning. A symbol acquires the function of carrying information in one context, a pure context, and it is used in contexts, impure contexts, in which it may or may not carry the information it has the function of carrying, contexts in which it can, therefore, get things wrong. My own view is that the pure contexts are those in which an information‐carrying element is incorporated into a control system, a context defined by that time in which the information (relevant to an organism's adaptive behaviour) ‘gets its hand on the steering wheel’ (see Dretske 1981, 1988). But there are other possibilities.

22.3.3 The Grain Problem Not only do information‐carrying functions give physical systems (and, therefore, the central nervous system) the power to misrepresent the world—thus serving as one way natural meaning is converted into non‐natural meaning—they also hold promise of solving a related problem that any naturalized semantics faces: the problem of grain. Non‐natural meaning individuates propositions in a very fine‐grained way. Thus, for instance, ‘b is 32 °F’ means (non‐naturally) something different from ‘b is 0 °C’, even though these are merely two different ways of picking out the same temperature: the freezing point of water. In saying that b is 32 °F one does not say that b is 0 °C. One who believes that b is 32 °F does not necessarily believe that b is 0 °C. These are two distinct beliefs, distinct meanings, distinct mental contents. Yet (p. 390) if something is a sign (indicates, carries the information) that b is 32 °F it must be a sign (indicate, carry the information that) b is 0 °C. We may not know it carries this information, of course, but it nonetheless carries it. If the probability, given the signal, of b being 32 °F is 1, then the probability that b is 0 °C is also 1. Natural meaning does not carve things up as finely as does non‐natural meaning. This appears to be a problem for theories like information‐theoretic semantics that propose to analyse non‐natural meaning in terms of natural meaning. Non‐natural meaning and natural meaning have different grains. And so they do, but information‐theoretic semantics is not making the mistake of identifying non‐natural meaning with natural meaning. Non‐natural meaning is being identified with an object's information‐carrying function, and it is reasonably clear that Page 10 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics information‐carrying functions can carve up propositional space in a more finely grained way than does information. Of the many things a heart does, only one of these, pumping blood, is its biological function. So too, perhaps, although an internal state is indifferent to how the facts it carries information about are described (that b is 32 °F or 0 °C), it may have the function of carrying this information in terms of a value on a Fahrenheit rather than a centigrade scale. Enc (1982) gives the example of a mechanical device that, given the way it does its job (by counting lines, not angles), has the function of detecting trilaterals, not triangles, even though, geometrically speaking, these are the same. If it is possible for functions to pull apart, in this way, facts that are, informationally speaking, equivalent, non‐natural meanings and informational functions could exhibit the same propositional grain.5 There would therefore be no principled objection to equating non‐ natural meaning, as this appears in the form of thought and intention, with information‐ carrying functions even though information and meaning (of the sort being analysed) have very different grains.

22.4 Epiphenomenalism If there really are semantic engines, systems whose behaviour (some of it anyway) is driven (explained) by the semantic properties of their internal states, a theory of meaning should reveal just how meaning gets its hands on the steering wheel. How does meaning achieve this causal relevance? If the neurobiological properties of internal events are not enough to explain why we do some of the things we do—the purposeful actions—how do the semantic properties, the content or meaning of internal events (i.e. what we believe, intend, and desire), figure in causal explanations of behaviour? (p. 391)

The problem of finding a genuine explanatory role for meaning in the behaviour of intentional (i.e. semantic) systems is especially difficult for semantic theories that locate the source of meaning in the extrinsic or relational properties of the internal events that presumably have meaning. If a theory says that the meaning or content of internal events derives from the way these symbols are related—functionally, informationally, causally, or whatever—to (usually) external affairs, then it should be possible for physically indistinguishable events, symbols that have all their intrinsic properties in common, to have quite different meanings. This should be possible in the same way it is possible for identical twins, say, to have different histories. According to orthodox thinking about causality, however, the causally relevant properties of an object are local or intrinsic. Physically indistinguishable objects (a real $100 bill and a perfect forgery, say), placed in the same circumstances, will have exactly the same effects on the rest of the world. They will have different histories, but these historical (extrinsic, relational) differences will be masked or screened off by their current physical constitution. And so it is with meanings in so far as meaning supervenes on history. What will be causally relevant to the effects of

Page 11 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics symbols in a system will not be their history—and, therefore, their meaning. It will be their physical (intrinsic) properties. Information‐theoretic semantics has this problem in spades, since it locates the meaning of a symbol in the history of that symbol, in what kind of information it was, at some point in the past, developed to carry, and history is obviously not a local, not an intrinsic, and, therefore, not (according to orthodox theory) a causally relevant property. Every other semantic theory (and this seems to be most theories) that locates the meaning of a symbol in its extrinsic or relational properties has the same problem. This problem is most often dramatized by Davidson's swampman example. Lightning strikes a swamp creating a duplicate of Donald Davidson, a being that is physically indistinguishable from Davidson but one having a completely different history. Does one's theory of meaning assign the same meanings, the same content, to the internal states of this duplicate being as it does to Donald Davidson? If so, then history is irrelevant to the assigned meanings. If not, then the duplicate has no thoughts. It is a zombie. The second choice seems to be inconsistent with scientific materialism. The first choice is inconsistent with information‐ theoretic semantics. Conclusion? Information‐theoretic semantics is inconsistent with scientific materialism. This wouldn't be so bad for some theories, but for information‐ theoretic semantics it is a disaster, since it was proposed as a materialistically acceptable account of meaning. Some philosophers (e.g. Paul Churchland 1981; Patricia Churchland 1986) take this problem to be insurmountable and construe semantic explanations of behaviour, folk‐ psychological explanations couched in terms of the content or meaning of internal events, as, at best, a façon de parler, a convenient verbal heuristic that will eventually (when we know enough) be replaced by scientific (neurobiological) explanations of behaviour. Others (e.g. Dennett 1987) acknowledge the instrumental or heuristic nature of semantic explanations, but take the heuristic—the intentional stance—to be unavoidable. Still others argue for a genuine relevance (p. 392) for meaning in a variety of different ways: Fodor (1987) identifies an alleged kind of meaning, narrow meaning, that is intrinsic to the events that have it; Dretske (1988) argues that the behaviours to be explained by meaning are not the bodily movements that are best explained by neurobiology, but, rather, causal processes that result in bodily movements (which are best explained by the extrinsic properties of the internal causes); Kim (1996) identifies a kind of causality, supervenient causality, that extrinsic properties (and, therefore, meanings) can participate in; Burge (1989) defends the causal relevance of semantic properties by arguing that genuine causal explanations are those that are actually given and accepted in our daily explanatory practice (a practice loaded with semantic explanations). Perhaps, though, the best defence against the charge of epiphenomenalism is to say that although the problem is real enough, it is not just a problem for information‐theoretic semantics. It is a problem for any theory of meaning—and this seems to be all theories of meaning—in which meaning resides in a symbol's extrinsic or relational properties. In philosophy everybody's problem isn't anybody's problem.

Page 12 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics

References Ariew, A., Cummins, R., and Perlman, M. (2002) (eds.), Functions (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Block, N. (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 615–78. Burge, T. (1989), ‘Individuation and Causation in Psychology’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 70: 303–22. Churchland, P. M. (1981), ‘Eliminative Materialism and Propositional Attitudes’, Journal of Philosophy, 78: 67–90. Churchland, P. S. (1986), Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Dennett, D. (1987), The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Dretske, F. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1986), ‘Misrepresentation’, in R. Bogdan (ed.), Belief: Form, Content, and Function (Oxford: Clarendon), 17–36. —— (1988), Explaining Behaviour. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Enc, B. (1982), ‘Intentional States of Mechanical Devices’, Mind, 91: 161–82. Fodor, J. (1984), ‘Semantics, Wisconsin Style’, Synthese, 59: 231–50. —— (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Grice, P. (1989), Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Israel, D., and Perry, J. (1990), ‘What Is Information?’, in P. P. Hanson (ed.), Information, Language, and Cognition (Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press), 1–19. Kim, J. (1996), Philosophy of Mind (Boulder, Col.: Westview). Matthen, M. (1988), ‘Biological Functions and Perceptual Content’, Journal of Philosophy, 85: 5–27. Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Page 13 of 15

Information‐Theoretic Semantics (p. 393)

—— (1989), ‘Biosemantics’, Journal of Philosophy, 86: 281–97.

Papineau, D. (1987), Reality and Representation (Oxford: Blackwell). Stampe, D. (1977), ‘Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2: 42–63. —— (1986), ‘Verificationism and a Causal Account of Meaning’, Synthese, 69: 107–37.

Notes: (1) For an excellent collection of essays debating this issue see Ariew et al. (2002). (2) Is an animal sick or diseased, or is its leg broken, only if we, human beings, deem it so? That doesn't sound right. If these conditions really are independent of our (or, indeed, anyone's) beliefs and interests, then there is a way things are supposed to be that is, in the appropriate sense, natural or objective in the way required by information‐theoretic semantics. (3) It was Fodor who first raised the disjunction problem (1984). See also Fodor (1990). (4) This isn't strictly true, since a signal can carry the information that s is F without being caused by s's being F. There are causal arrangements (e.g. common causes) in which e carries the information that s is F without being caused by s's being F. The claim in the text, though, is close enough to being true for the purposes at hand. Nothing can indicate or mean (naturally) that s is a dog, nothing can carry this information about s, unless, in fact, s is a dog. (5) See Dretske (1981: 215–22) for a similar discussion of how to distinguish, on information‐theoretic grounds and compositional considerations, the concept (and, therefore, belief that something is) WATER from the concept (belief that something is) H2O despite the (metaphysically) necessary equivalence of water with H2O. Fred Dretske

Fred Dretske is Professor Emeritus, Stanford University.

Page 14 of 15

Biosemantics

Oxford Handbooks Online Biosemantics   Ruth Garrett Millikan The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0024

Abstract and Keywords The term ‘biosemantics’ has usually been applied only to the theory of mental representation. This article first characterizes a more general class of theories called ‘teleological theories of mental content’ of which biosemantics is an example. Then it discusses the details that distinguish biosemantics from other naturalistic teleological theories. Naturalistic theories of mental representation attempt to explain, in terms designed to fit within the natural sciences, what it is about a mental representation that makes it represent something. Frequently these theories have been classified as either picture theories, causal or covariation theories, information theories, functionalist or causal-role theories, or teleological theories, the assumption being that these various categories are side by side with one another. Keywords: biosemantics, mental representation, teleological theories, mental content, naturalistic theories, information theories

‘BIOSEMANTICS’ was the title of a paper on mental representation originally printed in the Journal of Philosophy in 1989. It contained a much‐abbreviated version of the work on mental representation in Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Millikan 1984). There I had presented a naturalist theory of intentional signs generally, including linguistic representations, graphs, charts and diagrams, road‐sign symbols, animal communications, the ‘chemical signals’ that regulate the functions of glands, and so forth. But the term ‘biosemantics’ has usually been applied only to the theory of mental representation. Let me first characterize a more general class of theories called ‘teleological theories of mental content’ of which biosemantics is an example. Then I will discuss the details that distinguish biosemantics from other naturalistic teleological theories.

Page 1 of 14

Biosemantics Naturalistic theories of mental representation attempt to explain, in terms designed to fit within the natural sciences, what it is about a mental representation that makes it represent something. Frequently these theories have been classified as either picture theories, causal or covariation theories, information theories, functionalist or causal‐role theories, or teleological theories, the assumption being that these various categories are side by side with one another. But they are not. Teleological theories are specific forms of one or another, or of some combination, of the other kinds of theories. What teleological theories have in common is not any view about the nature of representational content; that is, about what makes a mental representation represent something. What they have in common is only a view about how falseness in representations is possible. Roughly, the idea is this. You tell the teleologist what you think makes some item in the head, some facet or activity of the brain, into a representation of some facet of the world, say, into a belief that it is raining. The teleologist may well agree with your theory about this. But then she will go on to point out (typically this is so) (p. 395) that your theory is really, at root, a story only about what it is for a mental state or activity to represent truly or correctly. You need to add a story about what a representation is like that represents falsely. And she will claim that this is very easy to do. Assume that the brain was designed, by evolution or learning, to make or to learn to make representations of the kind you have described. But what it was designed to do will not always be what it in fact does. Difficult environmental circumstances, even circumstances that merely fail to be ideal, often cause temporary failures for biological systems. Systems designed to produce representations will sometimes fail to produce them correctly. Sometimes they will produce items that behave in the mind/brain as though they represented something, but that in fact do not represent anything. These are false representations. They are ‘false’ in the dictionary sense of ‘not genuine or real’, ‘resembling but not accurately or properly designated as such’, the sense in which false faces and false fronts are false. That is, teleological theories are best understood as denying that there IS any state of affairs or occurrence being represented when one thinks falsely or that there IS any object at all that is being represented when one thinks emptily, say, when seeming to think about ‘phlogiston’ or ‘the ether’. Similarly, there IS no object, not even an inner one, being seen when one has a hallucination. Mistaken representations, rather than representing peculiar objects, things called ‘intentional contents’, are just representations that are failing to represent. False representations are representations yet fail to represent in the same way that something can be a can opener but be too blunt, hence fail to open cans or—and this is a better analogy—something can be a coffee maker yet fail to make coffee because the right ingredients were not put in or it was not turned on. They are ‘representations’ only in the sense that the biological function of the cognitive systems that produced them was to make representations. Thus, falsehood is explained by the simple fact that biological purposes often go unfulfilled, and the ghostly realm of intensions, reified meanings, non‐

Page 2 of 14

Biosemantics existent objects of thought, intentional objects, propositional contents, and so forth is cleanly swept away. Strictly speaking, you can't represent something that doesn't exist. But much work still remains. The teleologist must give an account of biological functions and of functions derived from learning that can support the view that the mature brain has the production of representations, representations of quite specific kinds, as one of its functions. The account I have given ultimately rests these functions on a variety of different kinds of selection, the most fundamental being natural selection. That story can be found in Millikan (1984: chs. 1–2; 1993: chs. 1–2: 2002). In Millikan (2004: ch. 1 n. 2) it is defended against the claim that human intelligence could have been a genetic accident rather than a trait selected for. The other main work that remains is to explain what it is for some facet or activity of the brain to be a representation of some affair in the world. What teleological theories do not have in common is any agreed‐on description of what representing is. They do not agree on what an organism that is representing things correctly, actually representing things, is doing, hence on what it is that an organism that is misrepresenting is failing to do. Teleological theories, just as such, are not theories of mental (p. 396) content. Failure to grasp this last point has led many to take a dismissive attitude toward teleological theories. How, they ask, could the question whether my current thought is the thought that grass is green rather than the thought that aardvarks bark be a matter that is settled in part by reference to evolutionary history or to my past learning history? But a teleological theory, just as such, makes no attempt to explain what makes your thought be a representation that grass is green or that aardvarks bark. A prior theory of what (correct) representation is is needed for that. To the shell that is ‘teleosemantics’, then, it is necessary to add a description of what successful representing, actual representing, is like. The main work of this article is to explain what representing is according to ‘biosemantics’. Above I suggested that the teleologist can take any naturalistic theory of representation at all and turn it into a teleological theory of content. But there is a catch. If the teleologist anchors the notion of function in selection, the theory of representation adopted must allow us to explain how producing inner representations might sometimes benefit an organism. Otherwise it will be a mystery why any organism would contain systems designed by selection to make representations. Surely such a requirement is reasonable, but on careful consideration it turns out to be quite confining. Many naturalistic accounts describe the relation of a representation to what it represents as a simple dyadic relation. This is true, for example, of classical causal or covariational theories, of classical informational theories and of classical picture theories. C. S. S. Peirce, on the other hand, claimed that the representing relation is essentially triadic, involving first the representation (a ‘sign’), second something represented, and third an ‘interpretant’. If producing inner representations benefits an organism, presumably this will be because the organism uses them in some way. There must be a part of the organism, or some activity of the organism, that understands or interprets these Page 3 of 14

Biosemantics representations. Peirce spoke of the interpretant of a sign as being another sign, but taking this at face value would produce a regress. The interpreter of an inner sign cannot be supposed merely to translate the sign into another inner sign which is again translated, and so forth. ‘Interpreting’ a sign must ultimately consist in some independently useful activity. According to biosemantics there are several different kinds of process that use representations. Most theories of representation deal with descriptive representations only—with representations that are designed to represent facts. But directive representations are certainly equally important—representations that tell what to do. And the most primitive and fundamental kind of representation, I believe, faces both ways at once, saying at the same time what the case is and what to do about it. For example, the dance of the honey bee tells where the nectar is and at the same time where the watching bees are to go. I call this last a ‘pushmi‐pullyu’ representation after Hugh Lofting's charming two‐headed creature by that name (Millikan 1996). Pushmi‐pullyu representations simultaneously describe and direct. Better, since the term ‘representation’ suggests to many people something more fancy than the simplest examples I have in mind (in particular, it may suggest symbolic forms that are ‘calculated over’) I prefer to call the inner signs that I describe ‘intentional icons’ (Millikan 1984)—I will explain why in a minute. Representations that (p. 397) are calculated over—that participate in inference processes—are just one very fancy kind of intentional icon. Below are diagrams of each of the three basic kinds of intentional icon. I will discuss them in turn. In each of the diagrams there is a producer and an interpreter or ‘consumer’. These have been designed by natural selection or by learning to cooperate with one another. Perhaps each resides in a separate organism; for example, one is part of a dancing bee, the other part of a sister watching bee. Or perhaps they correspond merely to two different functions performed within the same brain. What the producer does helps the consumer to perform functions that loop back to make both the producer and the consumer more likely to survive or to maintain their current settings (selection through learning) or to proliferate. The presence of each is part of the normal mechanism by which the other helps itself to survive or proliferate, and this cooperation is no accident but the result of past selection or learning that operated on both together.

Click to view larger Fig. 23.1 Descriptive intentional icons

Page 4 of 14

Biosemantics In each diagram the producer produces a sign that will be true or satisfied only if it maps on to some affair or affairs Click to view larger (the plural is for pushmi‐ Fig. 23.2 Directive intentional icons pullyu icons) in the world in accordance with certain ‘semantic’ rules. These are rules of correspondence between signs and world affairs that have been instantiated in the past when the consumer and producer or their ancestors have succeeded in performing their (p. 398) cooperative Click to view larger function(s). Consider the Fig. 23.3 Pushmi‐Pullyu intentional icons bee dance. Suppose that the activities of the dancing and the watching bees fulfil their cooperative function of directing the watching bee to a supply of nectar in the normal way; that is, through the characteristic mechanisms that have accounted in the past for success and subsequent selection of the dance‐making and dance‐using bee apparatuses. In such cases the dancing bee performs a dance that maps by a certain rule, first, on to the location of nectar. Second, it maps on to the direction and duration of the flight produced in watching bees. In each case, had certain variables in the dance been different—the angle, the speed—the nectar would have needed to be in a different place and the watching bees would have needed to go in a different direction or to a different distance for the dance to serve its purpose in the normal way. The semantic rules of ‘beemese’ are defined by the way in which the set of possible well‐formed bee dances maps on to the set of possible nectar locations to determine an isomorphism between these domains, an isomorphism that holds when the bee dance works properly through historically normal mechanisms. Similarly, another isomorphism holds between the set of possible dances and the set of destinations that will result if watching bees find nectar through historically normal mechanisms. The value of a system of representation lies in its productivity, which always depends on an isomorphism between the domain of the signs in the system and the domain of their signifieds. Mappings or isomorphisms are an essential feature of each kind of sign system illustrated. The signs are like abstract pictures. This is why (following Peirce) I (p. 399) call them ‘icons’. Intentional icons are produced by systems designed to make abstract pictures or icons that will map coincident with predetermined mapping rules to which their consumers are adjusted. When the systems in which they are embedded are

Page 5 of 14

Biosemantics functioning normally, they will picture in accordance with these rules, and they are then said to be ‘true’ or to be ‘satisfied’. I had best add to this that no limit need be placed on the complexity of the semantic‐ mapping functions that might map intentional icons on to the states of affairs they represent. Isomorphisms can be defined by functions that are as bizarre, as grue‐like, as you please. A bizarrely coded secret message from a CIA agent can be as much an ‘icon’ or ‘picture’ that maps on to a certain world affair in accordance with a definite semantic‐ mapping function as any bee dance, sentence, or diagram. Intentional icons must be things apt for use by icon users, but icon users can be very idiosyncratic in their habits. For example, if mental representations are systems of brain happenings or brain states that map on to represented world affairs, no a priori limitation on the kinds of brain happenings or states involved or on the complexity of the mappings employed is implied. Every representation is in some kind of code. The complexity of the code is irrelevant. On the other hand, any intentional icons in the brain would of course have to come with inner interpreters that knew how to read them; that is, interpreters that could be guided by them reliably to fulfil their own functions. Simple codes relying on only a few principles, if they were also highly productive, tapping into rich natural isomorphisms between the domains of the signs and the signifieds, would seem much the most likely to be preferred by natural selection. The semantic rule associated with a descriptive intentional icon determines a condition or state of affairs that must obtain if the consumer is to perform its tasks, whatever they may be, in the normal way. The consumer varies its activities systematically according to variations in the icons presented to it. The result is that the consumer's activity conforms or is adapted to the condition or state of affairs represented by the icon so that it can perform its functions properly given that condition. Descriptive intentional icons are designed to stand in for world affairs, typically affairs outside the organism or organisms involved, and to vary according to these world affairs, controlling internal or external behaviour as needed to adapt to these affairs. Thus, the bee dance is, in part, a descriptive intentional icon because if the watching bees are to achieve their function of finding nectar by reacting to the dance in the normal way it needs to correspond by a certain rule to a fact about nectar location. (We need not assume it takes any thought on a watching bee's part to react appropriately; so we need not assume that the dance is interpreted by translating it into another sign.) Similarly, consider my belief that there is yogurt in the refrigerator. Which are my belief‐using systems? Some, at least, are the systems that make practical inferences and turn the conclusions into practical action. My belief that there is yogurt in the refrigerator can help these systems to perform their function of guiding me into activities helping to fulfil my desires and plans (to eat yogurt, to make breakfast for a guest, etc.) in a normal way (not by serendipitous accident) only if there is yogurt in the refrigerator. (p. 400)

Page 6 of 14

Biosemantics Notice that the content of the descriptive icon is not determined by reference to the kind of tasks that it (with the help of its consumer(s)) normally performs. The icon may be called on to promote a whole series of functions, but each of these will be fulfilled normally only if the icon is ‘true’. If the consumer works in part by making inferences, the content is not determined by any particular set of inferences its consumer is disposed to make. It is determined by the fact that whatever inferences its consumer makes when functioning properly, the result will be (non‐accidental) true belief or successful action only if it actually represents according to a certain correspondence rule. This means that its content is not determined by its conceptual role. Note also that in the case of descriptive icons the producer's job is primarily to make an icon that corresponds by the right rule to a state of affairs. If the producer succeeds in this task, whether through the normal mechanisms of icon production or by freakish accident, the intentional icon is still true. Truth does not rest on whether the means of production was normal. For example, a belief can be true without being knowledge. Taking a classic case first introduced by Dretske (1986), consider the magnetosome of a northern‐hemispheric ocean bacterium that normally works by being pulled toward magnetic north, hence toward geomagnetic north, hence away from aerated surface water which is lethal to these bacteria. The magnetosome's pointing in a certain direction is an intentional icon of the direction of lesser oxygen because that is what it needs to correspond to for the bacterium's resultant motion to serve its proper function. If the magnetosome points in the direction of lesser oxygen because, serendipitously, a bar magnet under it is pointed in the right direction, then it tells the truth by accident rather than through normal mechanisms, but it still tells the truth. On the other hand, if a bar magnet attracts the bacterium to its destruction by pointing it towards oxygen, what the magnetosome says is false despite its being produced through a normal mechanism. Attributions of truth and falsity do not rest on whether descriptive icons are produced by normal mechanisms, but only on normal mechanisms associated with their use. (An icon's function cannot be to have been produced by something! Functions are effects, not causes.) Of course, Dretske is right that the magnetosome that directs the bacterium in the wrong direction because a bar magnet is held over it is not broken or malfunctioning. In that sense it is functioning ‘perfectly properly’ (Dretske 1988). But it doesn't follow that it is succeeding in performing all of its functions, any more than a perfectly functional coffee maker is performing all its functions when it is turned on but no coffee has been put in it. Very often things fail to perform their functions, not because they are damaged, but because the conditions they are in are not their normal operating conditions. Directive intentional icons that correspond to world affairs by their normal correspondence rules are usually said to be ‘satisfied’ rather than ‘true’. The semantic rule associated with the icon determines a condition or state of affairs that its consumers are to produce. The consumer's job is to bring it about that a state of affairs corresponds by rule to the icon. Its job is to ‘obey’ the producer's ‘orders’. (Equally, of course, it is the job of the producer to give orders that will benefit both it and the consumer.) Thus, the bee dance is, in part, a directive intentional icon because it will correspond by a certain Page 7 of 14

Biosemantics rule to the direction of flight of the watching bees (p. 401) if their dance‐interpreting apparatuses succeed in serving their functions normally. Suppose that you have a desire to eat yogurt. The systems designed to be moved by your desires—the ‘consumers’ of your desires—are the systems that make practical inferences eventually turning the conclusions into practical action. If your desire to eat yogurt affects these systems as designed, it will guide them to effect the fulfilment of your desire to eat yogurt. The chief function of a desire is to get itself fulfilled. This is not to say that, on average, desires do get themselves fulfiled. On average they generally get eaten up by bigger opposing desires first, or perhaps no means are known to fulfil them. It is very common for a trait or capacity to have been selected because it sometimes performs a useful function, occasional performance being better than none. The point is that people would not have the capacity mentally to represent various states of affairs as desirable unless these desires were sometimes fulfilled. The capacity would otherwise be useless. Thus, the cooperation between producer and consumer in the production and use of intentional icons can be accomplished in any of three basic ways. It may be that the producer is the one primarily responsible for making the icon correspond to a certain state of affairs; it may be that the consumer is the one primarily responsible; and in the case of pushmi‐pullyu icons it is the responsibility of the producer to make the icon correspond to one kind of affair and the consumer's job to make it correspond to another. In each of these basic cases, granted the cooperation between producer and consumer comes about through the normal causal mechanisms, the intentional icon will also be a ‘local natural sign’ carrying ‘local natural information’ about the affair or affairs to which it corresponds (Millikan 2004: chs. 3–4). Local natural signs are, in part, abstract pictures of what they represent. Although there is not room to unpack the notion of local natural information here, I mention this because it follows that when intentional systems are functioning normally in accordance with normal explanations, intentional icons represent both by being pictures of what they represent and by carrying natural information as to what they represent. For example, a bee dance is often a local natural sign both of where there is nectar and of where the watching bees will go. In the fundamental sense, actually representing involves both picturing and carrying natural information. As such it is not a matter determined by a history of selection. Representing intentionally, however, is a matter of having a certain kind of history. Also, attributions of truth or falsity and of satisfaction or unsatisfaction make sense only by reference to function, hence by reference to a history of selection. The terms ‘true’ versus ‘false’ and ‘satisfied’ versus ‘unsatisfied’ do not apply to natural signs, the most basic kind of representations. A common question raised about informational theories of representation concerns how mental representations can carry ‘information about a distant causal antecedent … without carrying information about the more proximal members of the causal chain … through which this information … is communicated’, for it seems that such representation skips … over (or ‘sees through’) the intermediate links in the causal chain in order to represent … its more distant causal antecedents” (Dretske 1981: 158). Similarly, there is a worry about how abstract representations are possible—ones that carry only the information, say, that an object is triangular (p. 402) and not also that it is isosceles or Page 8 of 14

Biosemantics equilateral. These problems do not arise for the theory of intentional icons. Information carried by normally operating intentional icons is a form of natural information. It does not follow that all of the natural information carried by an intentional icon is carried intentionally. The information that a natural sign carries intentionally is only the information it is its function to carry, the information that its cooperative interpreters know how to use. This information may be very abstract, and it may be about very distal affairs. If its consumers are so designed that they can use only the information that something is triangular, then that is all the information that the icon carries intentionally. If they are so designed as to use only the information that a predator is near, then the intentional icon will not intentionally carry information about any more proximal affairs, such as patterns on the retina. Similarly, not every stimulus that an organism discriminates on the way to producing an intentional icon is represented intentionally. Nor must an organism be capable of infallibly discriminating the distal objects, properties, or kinds that it intentionally represents from all others that are similar. It needs only a fallible capacity to recognize some natural signs or other of these things under some local conditions. Possibly it even gets things wrong a large part of the time because a large part of the time supporting conditions on which its mechanisms of icon production rest are absent. Similarly, the rabbit's danger thump may be elicited more commonly when rabbit danger is absent than present. (What matters is the converse—that when danger is present it should usually be elicited.) The basic theory of representing on which biosemantics rests is a picture theory and an informational theory, but equally it is a functionalist theory. The basic idea is that what makes something into a representation, for example into a mental representation, is not, of course, what it is made of, but what functions it performs and/or how it performs these functions. Items that function in certain ways are representing, and if they have been designed to function in these ways they are representing ‘intentionally’. They are representing, that is, in accordance with natural purposes and such that they can be said to be true or false, satisfied or unsatisfied. (The intimate connection of functions that have been selected for with purposes is argued in Millikan 1984; 2004: ch. 1.) According to biosemantics, basic mental representations always represent complete states of affairs. Mental terms are not endowed with meaning first and then used to build mental sentences. ‘What makes the mental term “horse” stand for horses?’ is not the place to begin. Parts and aspects of complete intentional icons represent parts and aspects of complete states of affairs only as abstracted from completed icons. This general point is most apparent, perhaps, with the simplest and most common cases of pushmi‐pullyu intentional icons, exemplified by nearly all animals' signals and also by the ubiquitous chemical signals running in the bloodstream that direct responses from various organs and cells. These signals, taken along with their times of occurrence and sometimes with their places of occurrence, are intentional icons because variations in the times and places of occurrence correspond to variations in the times and places of the complete affairs represented. For example, the time and place of the (p. 403) mother Page 9 of 14

Biosemantics hen's food call to her chicks descriptively shows the time and place of food and directively tells the time and place her chicks are to come. But it is evident that there is no sense in which a particular time stands for itself or a particular place for itself outside the context of some such signal. Similarly, in telling what direction the bacterium is to go the direction in which its magnetosome points stands for itself, but there is no prior sense in which a direction stands for itself. The biosemantic account also implies that there are not and could not be intentional icons that lacked attitude. Rejected is the Fregean idea that first a proposition is represented, then an intentional attitude added. Intentional icons always have, as such, functions and their functions automatically create attitudes. Hypothetical thinking, for example, or just thinking of possibilities, is an extremely sophisticated activity, and one that is only possible for a creature that sometimes uses the results in the production of ordinary descriptive and directive representations. It is because thoughts ‘of possibilities’ have the function of sometimes turning into more basic kinds of representations that they exist as representations at all. Similarly, desires are intentional icons only because they are designed to turn, under certain conditions, into full‐blown intentions, whose functions are to effect their own fulfilment more directly. There would be no benefit in the capacity to have desires if desires did not sometimes travel the whole route through intention into action. Intentional icons represent complete states of affairs. This implies that they represent not only properties but also the things that have those properties. When produced normally, intentional icons also carry natural information corresponding to what they represent. This implies that there can be natural information as to what things have what properties —including what individuals have what properties. Contrast Dretske's description of the natural information carried by signals. As Dretske describes the matter, although a signal can carry the information that an individual x is F, there is no part or aspect of the signal that carries the information that it is x that is F. For example, the petrol gauge on your car may carry the information that your petrol tank is half full, but no aspect of the signal indicates which tank is half full (Dretske 1981, 1988). You have to know that independently. The petrol‐gauge reading does not represent its subject, nor could it on Dretske's theory of natural information, because there are no natural laws that pertain to any individuals just as such. A necessary and central feature of the theory of local natural information (Millikan 2004) is that it explains how a natural sign can signify which individual it carries information about. The result is an explanation of how intentional representations of individuals are possible, something for which, to my knowledge, no other naturalized theory of intentionality accounts. A common question raised about the programme of biosemantics is how representations such as human beliefs and desires, which in numerous instances are entirely unique to the individual who has them, can have acquired functions through a process of selection. In outline the answer is straightforward. Compare the design of a camera. A camera is not designed to take any particular picture, but to vary the picture it produces depending on the scene in front. If a particular pattern is in front, it will function properly if it Page 10 of 14

Biosemantics produces a likeness of that pattern. Similarly, of course, (p. 404) one's eyes are not designed to see any particular object but, roughly speaking, to see whatever object lies in front of them. If a particular person is in front of your open eyes, it is a function of your eyes to help produce an accurate perception of that person. Similarly, the function of an adding machine is not to give any particular answer, but to give the sum of the numbers put into it. Natural selection has designed cognitive systems not to turn out particular products, say particular beliefs and desires, but to turn out quite different beliefs and desires depending on environmental circumstance. In the case of human beliefs and desires, however, the matter is considerably more complicated than with the camera. In order to turn out beliefs that will vary depending on states of affairs in the environment and in order to tune the systems that use these beliefs during practical and theoretical deliberation and in the production of useful action, humans must first develop adequate empirical concepts. Indeed, to complete the biosemantic programme a rather long story needs to be told about conceptual development. We must explain how the producers and consumers of beliefs and desires can learn or be tuned to employ empirical concepts cooperatively without actually practising together through the production of concrete actions. We must explain how their representation, production, and use dispositions can be tailored in advance to fit one another. That story is told in Millikan (1984: chs. 15–19; 2000: esp. ch. 7; 2004: p. IV, esp. ch. 19). Many critical questions about the biosemantic theory first presented in 1984 and 1989 have come and gone, but there are three that have been especially tenacious. I will say a word about each. What an intentional icon represents descriptively is an affair to which it must correspond if it's consumers are to perform their functions by normal mechanisms. They will perform their functions through normal mechanisms only if external conditions are such as to allow these mechanisms to operate properly. Taking for her example the female‐hoverfly detector in a male hoverfly's visual system, Karen Neander (1995) has objected that among the external conditions needed for the detector's consumers to perform all their functions are that the female is fertile and that she won't be eaten before she reproduces, hence that on the biosemantic theory these facts about the female must be part of what is represented by the detector in the male's visual system. What this overlooks, however, is that an intentional icon must also have a producer and that it must be a function of the producer to make an icon that corresponds to the condition it represents. If the producer has a function there must be a normal mechanism by which it performs that function. This, however, would require the male hoverfly's visual systems to be sensitive to natural signs of fertility in female hoverflies and of liability not to be eaten. But on no theory of information, certainly not on the theory of local natural information, does the male hoverfly use or even encounter any such natural information (Millikan 2004: ch. 6). A second question concerns the possibility of biological systems whose jobs are to produce false representations. For example, people who are overconfident may be more successful at performing certain tasks than people who evaluate their skills correctly. Notice first, however, that it will not be the falseness per se, but only the high confidence Page 11 of 14

Biosemantics that contributes to success. If one is completely and perfectly competent (p. 405) at a task, there certainly will be no gain in believing one is not! Notice second that there are many biological systems that ride piggyback on systems developed earlier for quite different purposes. If there actually were systems whose jobs were to distort certain beliefs they would have to ride on more general systems whose basic jobs were to produce true beliefs. Otherwise there would be no semantic rules in place according to which the distorted beliefs would be false. The various concepts out of which any beliefs are formed are designed to serve purposes in arbitrary belief contexts. The systems responsible for concept development tune these concepts and the systems that normally use them for general purpose use, not for any one specific use such as increasing one's confidence. The semantics of mental representation is productive. That is what the ‘picturing’ or ‘mapping’ guarantees. Third, consider Pietroski's tale about the kimus and the snorfs (1992). The kimus are attracted by the red sunrise glowing over their local mountain so that they climb up it each morning. Thus, they conveniently avoid their chief predators, the snorfs, who pass by each morning below. Moreover, this is how the attraction to red light got selected for in kimus. Those not attracted by red light got eaten. On the biosemantic view, Pietroski claims, ‘kimus climb the hill because they believe the hill is snorf‐less’, and when they approach red things that are not snorfs ‘they are acting on the belief that the area in question is snorf‐free’ (1992: 276). Given that kimus ‘can't reliably discriminate snorfs from non‐snorfs’, (ibid.), it is implausible, he claims, that the kimus have any beliefs about snorfs. In summary, on the biosemantic account [a] system can have the belief that P is instantiated without having any systematic ability to tell whether P is instantiated (in a given region at a given time). Indeed, instantiations of P can be completely irrelevant to the system's tokening of the belief that P is instantiated. The corresponding intentional explanations of such a system's behaviour will … be very implausible. (Pietroski 1992: 268) What Pietroski describes in the kimus seems to be a simple tropism. They are attracted to red the way a moth is attracted to light. Apparently they have neural pushmi‐pullyu intentional icons or signals that tell where the snorfs are fewer and hence where to go. Of course these icons are not at all like beliefs. Beliefs are formed only after the acquisition of concepts, which generally rest on multiple ways of recognizing. Further, the functions of beliefs involve participation in inference. (For a discussion of empirical concepts and of inference see Millikan 2000.) Pietroski seems to assume that an ‘intentional explanation’ of an animal's behaviour must not only be a belief–desire explanation but must also be a straightforward causal explanation. Why intentional explanations are causal but not straightforward is explained in Millikan (1993, 2007). Moreover, full intentional explanations do not begin with the presence of intentional representations, but explain also how the intentional representations get formed. The red light is definitely involved in an ‘intentional explanation’ of how the kimus avoid snorfs.

Page 12 of 14

Biosemantics Finally, there are no distal objects or stimuli that any organism has the capacity to discriminate under all conditions. All successful discrimination of distal affairs (p. 406) depends on merely local natural information. Local natural information rests on correlations that are not perfect but that are not accidental either, for they must persist throughout a spatio‐temporal region for a reason (Millikan 2004: chs. 3–4). On this analysis the kimus do get local natural information each morning about the direction of fewer snorfs. Similarly, although there is no causal connection, the correlation between magnetic north and lesser oxygen used by the anaerobic bacteria persists in the northern hemisphere for a reason. It carries local natural information about the location of lesser oxygen. The intentionality that characterizes pushmi‐pullyu icons responsible for simple tropisms of this kind is the limiting case of intentionality. It is intentionality in the way zero is a number. If your theory doesn't count in these cases you will find that it fails to account for any of the obvious cases either.

References Dretske, F. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1986), ‘Misrepresentation’, in. R. Bogdan (ed.), Belief: Form, Content, and Function (Oxford: Clarendon), 17–36. —— (1988), Explaining Behaviour (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Millikan, R. G. (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge Mass. MIT Press). —— (1989), ‘Biosemantics’, Journal of Philosophy, 86: 281–97. —— (1993), ‘Explanation in Biopsychology’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 211–32; repr. in Millikan, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press); and in C. Macdonald and G. Macdonald (eds.), Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), (pts VII– X). —— (1996), ‘Pushmi‐pullyu Representations’, Philosophical Perspectives, 9: 185–200; repr. in L. May and M. Friedman (eds.), Mind and Morals (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), 145–61. —— (2000), On Clear and Confused Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2002), Biofunctions: Two Paradigms, in R. Cummins, A. Ariew, and M. Perlman (eds.), Functions: New Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 113–43.

Page 13 of 14

Biosemantics —— (2004), Varieties of Reference: The Jean Nicod Lectures 2002 (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2007), ‘An Input Condition for Teleosemantics?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 436–455. Neander, K. (1995), ‘Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning’, Philosophical Studies, 79: 109–41. Pietroski, P. M. (1992), ‘Intentionality and Teleological Error’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73: 267–82.

Ruth Garrett Millikan

Ruth Garrett Millikan is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut.

Page 14 of 14

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes

Oxford Handbooks Online A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes   Robert J. Matthews The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0025

Abstract and Keywords The chief virtue of a measurement-theoretic account of the attitudes, besides getting right the semantic nature of attitude predicates, is precisely that, as Davidson suggests, it enables one to embrace the very plausible relational conception of attitude attributions without thereby having to embrace the much more dubious relational conception of the attitudes themselves. To be a non-relationalist about the attitudes one does not, as Quine, Fodor, and others have assumed, have to be a non-relationalist about attitude predicates. It is entirely possible that propositional attitudes are monadic properties of their possessors, even though they are predicated of individuals by means of relational predicates. Keywords: attitudes, relational conception, attitude predicates, propositional attitudes, monadic properties, relational predicates

Page 1 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes

24.1 Introduction: The Basic Idea THE

sentences by which we canonically attribute propositional attitudes have a relational

logical form: the main‐clause verb of sentences of the form x believes (desires, etc.) that S expresses a dyadic relation between the possessor of the attitude and the particular that is the referent of the that‐clause, a particular that many have presumed to be the psychological ‘object’ of the attitude (i.e. the belief, desire, etc.). Yet it has proved notoriously difficult to specify both the nature of these particulars to which possessors of propositional attitudes are supposedly related and the nature of the relation that they bear to these particulars, especially if one holds, as proponents of a relational conception of the attitudes do, that these particulars are both causally efficacious (in the production of behaviour and other thoughts) and also semantically evaluable. The difficulty is only compounded when one undertakes to explain in terms of the nature of these particulars the various semantic puzzles that have driven so much philosophical theorizing about the attitudes, especially when one undertakes such an explanation in the context of a formal semantics for natural language. (p. 408) It is symptomatic of this difficulty that philosophers have variously held that these particulars are Fregean senses, Russellian propositions, sentences of a public language, sentences of a language of thought, or perhaps even more exotic entities such as Richard's ‘Russellian annotated matrices’ (RAMs) (1990) or Larson and Ludlow's ‘interpreted logical forms’ (ILFs) (1993). Beginning in the late 1970s, a number of philosophers began to argue that our difficulty understanding the nature of the attitudes stems from our misunderstanding the natural‐ language predicates by which we attribute propositional attitudes. In particular, they argued that propositional‐attitude predicates function very much like the numerical‐ measure predicates by which we attribute physical magnitudes (e.g. has a mass of 5 kg), that in fact propositional‐attitude predicates are a kind of measure predicate (see Churchland 1979: 105; Field 1981: 113–14; Stalnaker 1984: 8–11; Dennett 1987: 123–5; Davidson 1989; Matthews 1990, 1994, 2007; Beckermann 1996).1 Seen in this way, the sentences by which we attribute propositional attitudes are indeed relational in form, and hence do express relations, but the relations that such predicates express are not relations that are in any way constitutive of the possessor's possession of the propositional attitudes attributed by these predicates. To say that a subject has a certain propositional attitude is no more to say that the subject stands in a substantive psychological relation to the particular that is the referent of the that‐clause than is to say that an object has a temperature of 30 °C to say that the object stands in a substantive physical relation to the number 30. Rather, it is to attribute to that subject a certain psychological state or property which is specified by means of its location in a representational domain, in just the way that we specify the temperature of an object by means of its location on a numerical scale. The referents of that‐clauses, like numbers, are simply abstract entities used to represent measurement‐theoretically the

Page 2 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes propositional attitudes of those to whom these attitudes are attributed. They are not, in any sense, the psychological ‘objects’ of these states. Philosophers attracted to the idea that attitude predicates might be a kind of measure predicate have been so attracted for a variety of reasons. Churchland (1979) sees in the idea a way of avoiding what he regards as a metaphysically vexing commitment in psychology to propositions. Field (1981) finds in it not simply a way of avoiding any commitment in psychology to propositions, but also the possibility of a representationalist solution to Bretano's problem of the intentionality of propositional attitudes. Stalnaker presents what he calls the ‘measurement analogy’ as a way of blunting the intuitive force of what he terms the ‘linguistic picture’ of propositional attitudes (defended by Field, Fodor, and others), a view which he describes as ‘undertak[ing] to explain thought by speech’ (1984: 5). As Stalnaker sees it, the measurement analogy makes conceptual room for the ‘pragmatic picture’ of the attitudes that he favours, according to which propositional attitudes ‘should be understood primarily in terms of the role that they play in the characterization and explanation of (p. 409) action’ (1984: 4). Dennett (1987) and Davidson (1989) see in the measurement idea not simply a way of avoiding a vexing commitment in psychology to abstract objects but also a way of avoiding altogether a relational account of the attitudes. Both find in it the possibility of a non‐relational, non‐ representationalist account of the attitudes. Dennett points out (1987: 125n.) that while we attribute a particular mass to an object by relating that object to a particular real number, we don't suppose that the object's having the mass that it does is a matter of its being related to some particular. Having the mass that it does is an intrinsic (monadic) property of the object; relating the object to some particular number is just a way of specifying the property in question. Perhaps, Dennett suggests, the same is true for propositional attitudes: we attribute them to an individual by relating that individual to a particular, but propositional attitudes are not themselves relations that their possessors bear to particulars. Davidson, for his part, insists that it does not follow from the fact that we specify what a thinker thinks by relating him to a certain object that the thinker bears any psychological relation to that object. We are, he says, ‘free to divorce the semantic need for content‐specifying objects from the idea that there must be any objects at all with which someone who has an attitude is in psychic touch’ (1989: 9; my emphasis). According to Davidson, the analogy then between measuring weight and attributing states of belief is this: Just as in measuring weight we need a collection of entities that have a structure in which we can reflect the relations between weighty objects, so in attributing states of belief (and other propositional attitudes) we need a collection of entities related in ways that will allow us to keep track of the relevant properties of the various psychological states. … we needn't suppose that there are such entities as beliefs. Nor do we have to invent objects to serve as the ‘objects of beliefs’ or what is before the mind or in the brain. For the entities we mention to help specify a

Page 3 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes state of mind do not have to play any psychological or epistemological role at all, just as numbers play no physical role. (1989: 11) The chief virtue of a measurement‐theoretic account of the attitudes, besides getting right the semantic nature of attitude predicates, is precisely that, as Davidson suggests, it enables one to embrace the very plausible relational conception of attitude attributions without thereby having to embrace the much more dubious relational conception of the attitudes themselves. To be a non‐relationalist about the attitudes one does not, as Quine, Fodor, and others have assumed, have to be a non‐relationalist about attitude predicates. It is entirely possible that propositional attitudes are monadic properties of their possessors, even though they are predicated of individuals by means of relational predicates.

In this brief chapter it is not possible to present a detailed exposition and defence of the idea that attitude predicates are measure predicates, nor of the import of this idea for our conception of the attitudes themselves.2 I will instead attempt only to sketch the general outlines of a measurement‐theoretic account, explaining in only (p. 410) the briefest terms why the account seems plausible, how the account might go, and what its implications might be for our conception of propositional attitudes. I begin with some brief comments about numerical‐measurement theory upon which the account is based.

24.2 Numerical‐Measurement Theory Numerical measurement is the systematic assignment of real numbers to objects in order to represent those of the object's properties, which we call ‘magnitudes’, that are capable of instantiation in different degrees. Such numerical assignments are possible because the physical magnitudes to be measured satisfy certain well‐defined empirical conditions that guarantee the existence of a numerical assignment on the reals that preserves the relevant empirical relations among quantities of a given magnitude. Specifically, quantities of a particular physical magnitude have a relational structure that can be represented by a mathematical relational structure on the reals that assigns to every quantity of such magnitude a real number that is the representative of this quantity and furthermore ‘respects’, in the formal sense spelled out in Matthews 2007, the empirical relations that obtain among quantities of the magnitude. Having made such an assignment, we can attribute a particular quantity of some magnitude to an object simply by attributing to that object a magnitude‐type specifying relation to the numerical representative of that quantity (e.g. having a mass of 5 kg). And we can reason ‘surrogatively’, as Swoyer (1987) puts it, about the empirical relations among these quantities by reasoning directly about the numerical relations that hold among their representatives (concluding, for example, that a mass represented by 5 on the kilogram scale is greater than a mass represented by 4 on that same scale because 5 is greater than 4).

Page 4 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes Numerical‐measurement theory traces its origins to work in the late 1800s and early 1900s on extensive magnitudes such as mass and length.3 This early work focused almost exclusively on what has come to be called the ‘representation problem’: the problem of specifying the conditions that an empirical system must satisfy in order for there provably to exist an assignment of real numbers to objects that respects the empirical relations among quantities of these magnitudes. Numerical‐measurement theory does this by proving a so‐called representation theorem, typically by proving that the numerical relational structure on the reals is homomorphic (in a sense of this term that is stronger than that employed in set theory) to the empirical relational structure of the represented quantities of the measured physical magnitude. But the assignment of numbers to quantities is not unique: there will be different numerical assignments, that is different scales (e.g. metric and avoirdupois scales for weight, the centigrade and Fahrenheit scales for temperature), each (p. 411) of which faithfully represents all the relevant empirical facts about the magnitude being measured. Measurement theory proves that a certain set of distinct assignments of numbers to quantities are all equally faithful representations of the empirical facts by proving a so‐called uniqueness theorem, where this theorem provides a formal characterization of the class of homomorphisms all of which specify relation‐respecting representations of physical magnitudes on the reals.

24.3 Generalization of Measurement Theory to Propositional‐Attitude Predicates A seminal paper by Suppes (1951) defined the path that much subsequent work in measurement theory has taken. It not only integrated previous work on the representation and uniqueness problems, but also, and more importantly for present purposes, provided an analytical model that could easily be extended to the study of other forms of measurement. This model was subsequently extended not only to the measurement of non‐extensive magnitudes such as temperature, but also to domains of representation such as analytical geometry, where the properties of objects that get represented are not magnitudes and the domain in which they get represented is not that of the reals. Arguably the model might, as Suppes and Zinnes (1963) first suggested, also be extended to the linguistic representation of propositional attitudes. A measurement‐theoretic account of propositional‐attitude predicates assumes that such predicates effect a systematic assignment of representative entities to propositional attitudes of a particular attitude type (say, believing), where these representative entities are specified by the that‐clauses of attitude predicates in much the way that representatives of quantities of a physical magnitude are specified by the numeral in numerical‐magnitude predicates. Given such an assignment, we can attribute a specific attitude of that attitude type to an individual simply by attributing to that individual a relation to the entity that is the representative of that specific attitude. And because the

Page 5 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes relational structure of these representatives respects the relevant empirical relations among attitudes, we can reason surrogatively about relations among attitudes by reasoning directly about relations among their representatives.

Page 6 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes

24.4 Some Reasons why Attitude Predicates Might be Measure Predicates Whether attitude predicates are measure predicates can be answered definitively only by determining whether it is possible to provide a measurement theory for (p. 412) these predicates that proves the requisite representation and uniqueness theorems. The best we can do here is offer some reasons for thinking that they might be such. To begin with, there are a number of striking similarities that these predicates bear to numerical‐ magnitude predicates. First, like the numerical terms that figure in numerical‐magnitude predicates, the that‐clauses in propositional‐attitude predicates appear to be singular terms. One can quantify over them and form wh‐questions that question the argument position occupied by the that‐clause. Second, just as the numbers that are the referents of the numerical terms in numerical‐magnitude predicates function as representatives of the magnitudes that these predicates attribute, the referents of that‐clauses appear to function as representatives of the attitudes that they attribute. The that‐clauses of propositional‐attitude predicates serve to individuate different attitudes of the same type in much the way that numerical terms serve in numerical‐magnitude predicates to individuate one quantity of a magnitude from other quantities of the same magnitude. Third, just like the referents of the numerical terms in numerical‐magnitude predicates, the references of that‐clauses in propositional attitude predicates appear to be abstract particulars. Fourth, the scheme by which these representatives are specified, like that by which the numerical representatives of the quantities are specified, is both productive and systematic, in such a way that the domain of representatives can be effectively enumerated by a recursive procedure. Fifth, the individuation of propositional attitudes by their representatives, like the individuation of quantities of magnitudes by theirs, depends, at least in part, on their place within a relational structure that has these representatives as its domain. Put another way, they are the representatives that they are, in part because of their relations to one another. It is this exploitation of structural relations among the representatives of propositional attitudes that presumably explains why different natural languages, say English and German, can assign different representatives to the same propositional attitude and yet nonetheless preserve the same empirical relations among propositional attitudes, in much the way that different numerical scales can assign different numbers to the same quantity of a magnitude and yet nonetheless preserve the same empirical relations among quantities. Finally, both sorts of predicate seem to be quite similar extensions, each within their respective domains, of a pervasive common‐sense predication scheme. On this scheme we individuate the capacities (skills, traits, and dispositions) of persons, animals, and even inanimate objects along two orthogonal dimensions. One dimension has to do with the object or event that is the focus or target of the individual's capacities; the other dimension has to do with the particular relation that the individual bears to that object or event. (Thus, people can be flag wavers, firefighters, stock traders, and so on; animals Page 7 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes can be anteaters, nest builders, and disease carriers, etc.; and inanimate objects can be can openers, typewriters, dishwashers, and the like.) Numerical‐magnitude predicates and propositional‐attitude predicates preserve this two‐dimensional relation‐to‐an‐object character of the common‐sense scheme, but the specific nature of both the object and the relation is changed. In the common‐sense scheme we attribute a capacity (skill, etc.) to an individual (say, firefighting) by (p. 413) specifying (i) the object or event towards which exercises of this capacity are directed (fires), and then (ii) the sort of relation that the individual bears to this object or event in the course of exercising the capacity in question (fighting). In the extensions of this scheme to physical magnitudes or propositional attitudes we again attribute a property to an individual by specifying an object and a relation to that object. But the object now serves as a representative of the particular property being attributed, and the relation serves to type‐identify the property being attributed (e.g. as a quantity of mass, or as a kind of belief). The common‐sense scheme has become a kind of indexing scheme for specifying and individuating certain internal states and properties of individuals. These several similarities that propositional‐attitude predicates bear to numerical‐ magnitude predicates don't establish that the former are measure predicates, but they do provide reasons for taking seriously the idea that these predicates might be a kind of measure predicate. And these reasons become more compelling when one considers certain troubles with the relational conception of the attitudes that seem to force even relationalists towards a measurement‐theoretic account of the attitudes. Recall that on the relational conception propositional attitudes are relations between the possessor of the attitude and an entity that is the ‘object’ of the attitude. But in working out a formal semantics for attitude attributions, a number of contemporary relationalists, notably Richard (1990) and Larson and Segal (1995), have concluded that relationalists get into trouble if they identify the referent of the attribution's that‐clause with the object to which the possessor of the attitude supposedly stands in some psychological relation. It is difficult to find objects of a sort that can account for the usual semantic puzzles (e.g. failures of substitution) and at the same time be the sort of object to which the possessors of propositional attitudes can plausibly be said to bear a psychological relation. It is equally difficult to explain the context‐sensitivity of attitude reports on the assumption that the referent of the that‐clause is an object that is both semantically evaluable and causally efficacious. These relationalists have attempted to avoid these difficulties by distinguishing the referent of the that‐clause, what Richard calls the ‘semantical object’ of the attitude, from the object to which the possessor of the attitude is psychologically related, what Richard calls the ‘psychological object’ of the attitude. Distinguishing semantical from psychological objects of the attitudes enables relationalists to avoid certain difficult problems that afflict traditional relational views, but it raises two obvious question: How do the semantical objects manage to represent the psychological objects, and how do users know just what psychological state is being attributed? To answer these questions, it looks as if relationalists need a measurement theory for attitude predicates. Because without such an account of how the semantic objects manage to track the psychological ones, relationalists have no account of how Page 8 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes attitude attributions manage to be informative. Indeed, without such an account, even the claim to find support for the relational conception in the logical form of attitude attributions is in trouble, since relationalists lose all justification (p. 414) for reading the logical form of attitude attributions back on to the attitudes themselves. So it looks as if relationalists and non‐relationalists alike need a measurement‐theoretic account of attitude predicates. There are other, more specific, reasons why both relationalists and non‐relationalists might want such an account. First, it might provide a ‘solution’ to the problem of the intentionality of propositional attitudes by showing us that intentionality is no more a problem for propositional attitudes than is ‘numerality’ a problem for physical magnitudes: intentionality might just be a feature of our particular way of representing propositional attitudes rather than a property of the attitudes themselves. Second, it might explain what Fodor (1987) calls the ‘striking parallelism’ between the causal relations among propositional attitudes and the semantic relations among their contents: on a measurement‐theoretic account, the causal relations respect the semantic ones, not because cognitive architecture somehow contrives to enforce such respect, but simply because of the measurement‐theoretic representation relation between propositional attitudes and their natural‐language representatives. The parallelism that Fodor finds so striking might turn out to be no more remarkable than the strict parallelism that obtains between the empirical relations among quantities of physical magnitudes and the numerical relations among their numerical representatives on the reals. The measurement‐theoretic account might also explain why this parallelism holds not only for what Fodor (1987) calls ‘core cases’ of propositional attitudes but even for those ‘derivative cases’ which admittedly don't satisfy his so‐called Representational Theory of Mind. But if relationalists concede the need for a measurement‐theoretic account of attitude predicates, then they must also concede the possibility that, in an analogous fashion to the numerical‐measure predicates used to attribute physical magnitudes, attitude predicates might be relational without the attitudes themselves being relational.

24.5 What a Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Attitude Predicates would Look Like A fully developed measurement‐theoretic account of attitude predicates would provide: (i) a specification of the representing relational structure of our natural‐language representations of propositional attitudes (an analogue of the numerical relational structures of our natural‐language representations of physical magnitudes); (ii) a specification of the represented empirical relational structure of propositional attitudes (an analogue of the represented empirical relational structure of the physical magnitudes); (iii) a characterization of the set of morphisms that map the represented Page 9 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes empirical relational structure into the representing relational structure which is its image; and (iv) a proof of a representational theorem and (p. 415) uniqueness theorem for this set of morphisms so characterized. And because much of our puzzlement focuses on attitude attributions, the account should also provide an explanation of (v) why we should have developed the particular attribution practices we have, and (vi) why we should expect the various puzzles that have so dominated philosophical theorizing about the attitudes. We might even go on to speculate, as some philosophers have done, as to (vii) the intrinsic nature of propositional attitudes that would explain why they have the empirical structure that they do, understanding that such speculation would not, strictly speaking, be part of a measurement‐theoretic account of the attitudes. We cannot at present specify either the relational structure of our natural‐language representations of propositional attitudes or the empirical relational structure of propositional attitudes themselves with the precision needed to support the proof of the requisite representation and uniqueness theorems. But we can provide enough by way of a characterization to get some sense of how the proofs might go, and what they might entail as regards the nature of propositional attitudes (see Matthews 2007). In the space remaining here I shall focus on the empirical structure of the attitudes that I believe emerges out of a measurement‐theoretical account of the attitudes, a structure that seems to me to support a non‐relational conception of the attitudes. I begin by saying something about the structure of our natural‐language representation of propositional attitudes; that is, the structure in which the empirical structure of the attitudes finds its image.

Page 10 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes

24.6 The Structure of our Natural‐Language Representations of Propositional Attitudes This formal relational structure will consist of a domain of objects, the ‘representatives’ of specific propositional attitudes, and various relations (including monadic properties) defined on that domain. Given the various linguistic properties of the that‐clauses of attitude attributions that we are able to exploit in individuating propositional attitudes of a given attitude type (e.g. Jones may believe that JFK went to /hahvahd/, but not that he went to /harverd/; he may believe that e. e. cummins was a great poet, but not that E. E. Cummins was, and so on), it seems reasonable to conclude that the representatives of propositional attitudes are entities with all the syntactic, semantic, pragmatic, phonological, phonetic, and even orthographic properties of utterances. Call these entities, which are basically interpreted logical forms (ILFs)4 on steroids, ‘interpreted utterance forms’ (IUFs, for short.) They are arguably just the sort of rich linguistic entity that Davidson (1968) had in mind as the entities (p. 416) that speakers use to ‘samesay’ what others said. Of course, we intuitively don't think of the representatives of propositional attitudes in such linguistic terms. We rather think of the representative of a propositional attitude as something like a ‘state of affairs’ described in a particular way, specifically as the state of affairs to which possessors of the attitude are characteristically related in quite specific behavioural ways. Thinking of IUFs as states of affairs under a description seems to involve nothing more than a harmless reification of the IUF, though it is a reification that is important for understanding why we specify propositional attitudes in this particular way. And it is clearly a reification that facilitates our surrogative reasoning about propositional attitudes. There is a lot to be said about the properties and relations defined over the IUFs that are the representatives of propositional attitudes, but basically IUFs have all the properties and relations of utterances of the sentences for which they are IUFs, including semantic, inferential, syntactic, pragmatic, phonological, phonetic, and even orthographic properties and relations. These properties and relations are exploited differentially in the individuation of particular attitudes depending upon the context of utterance of the attitude attribution.

24.7 The Empirical Structure of the Attitudes The empirical structure of the attitudes is similarly a formal relational structure consisting of a domain of objects or properties of some sort, and various relations (including monadic properties) defined over this domain. But this structure is not given in anything like the way that the structure of our natural‐language representations of the attitudes is given. It must be inferred, both from the structure of our natural‐language Page 11 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes representations of the attitudes, on the assumption that the relations defined on the domain of the latter ‘respect’ the empirical relations defined over the psychological states that are the attitudes, and from the explanatory role of propositional attitudes in common‐sense explanations of behaviour and thought. The objects that constitute the empirical domain could, as proponents of Fodor's Representational Theory of Mind would have it, be mental representations. But there is, I believe, little empirical reason to suppose this to be the case. If we ask ourselves what minimally must be true of these psychological states that are the attitudes if they are to be the sorts of states that both find an image in our natural‐language representations of the attitudes and also exhibit the causal properties that they do in the production of behaviour and thought, it seems enough that these attitudes be certain psychological ‘aptitudes’ of their possessors. By this I mean simply that they must be states apt to produce certain characteristic effects, both in the sense that they are the sort of states that can produce such effects and in the sense that in the appropriate context they do produce such effects, where these effects include both the (p. 417) behaviour and the other mental states that we take to be the characteristic effects of propositional attitudes. There might be more to these states than just being aptitudes for the characteristic effects that we associate with propositional attitudes, but nothing about common‐sense propositional‐attitude explanatory practice or the nature of our natural‐language representations of the attitudes would seem to require it, not even, I would argue, the intentionality or semantic evaluability that we philosophers associate with the attitudes. Assuming that these aptitudes which are the attitudes are simply states that involve the instantiation of a property at a time, then the mapping of propositional attitudes into their natural‐language representatives will be (like the case of the mapping of physical magnitudes into their real‐number representatives) a trans‐type mapping of properties into objects, in this case of aptitudes into IUFs. The relations defined over this domain of aptitudes will consist of various causal and material constitutive relations, relations that find their image primarily in the inferential relations defined over IUFs. There is obviously a lot more that needs to be said to motivate this account of the empirical structure of the attitudes. Most crucially, we need at very least informal sketches of both a representation theorem and a uniqueness theorem to convince us that this account captures what we intuitively take to be the conceptually salient features of propositional attitudes, especially given that the account does not attribute to these aptitude states any intentional or semantic properties of the sort presumed by the Representational Theory of Mind. We also need to be convinced that this account can handle all the usual semantic puzzles about propositional attitudes, puzzles that are the focus of so much philosophical discussion. We can get some sense of why the proposed measurement‐theoretic account might be able to handle these puzzles by noting that it has all the explanatory and individuative resources of the traditional accounts, but like the relationalist accounts mentioned above that distinguish between the semantic and psychological objects of the attitudes, this account apportions those resources differently

Page 12 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes between the attitudes and their natural‐language representations. So let us simply assume here that the account can be filled out in roughly the way described, and then look at some of its implications for how we conceive of the attitudes.

24.8 Some Implications of the Proposed Measurement‐Theoretic Account The proposed account offers a relational account of propositional‐attitude predicates, but a non‐relational account of the attitudes themselves. Propositional attitudes are simply monadic properties of their possessors, even if, as seems virtually certain, the possessors of propositional attitudes turn out as a matter of empirical (p. 418) fact to have the aptitudes that they do in virtue of their having (or being in) certain representational/ informational states. The point here is that we must distinguish sharply between the attitudes and the cognitive representational/informational states that are their basis. Non‐relational accounts of the attitudes are hardly new, but the measurement‐theoretic account shows in a way that previous non‐relational accounts could not that such accounts are fully compatible with a relational account of attitude predicates, thus undercutting much of the motivation for relational accounts of the attitudes. The proposed account is clearly realist about the attitudes, inasmuch as on this account propositional attitudes are aptitudes for the behavioural and cognitive effects that we characteristically associate with the attitudes. But the account is not realist about the semantic/intentional contents of propositional attitudes. The semantic properties that we intuitively associate with the attitudes turn out to be properties of our natural‐language representations of the attitudes, and not of the attitudes themselves. Propositional attitudes turn out to have semantic properties in just the way that physical magnitudes have numerical properties: given our canonical way of representing propositional attitudes by means of an IUF that specifies a state of affairs to which the possessor of the attitude is behaviourally related in certain characteristic ways, we are no more able to conceive of propositional attitudes in non‐linguistic terms than we are able to conceive of physical magnitudes in non‐numerical terms. And yet propositional attitudes no more have the linguistic properties of the IUFs that are their linguistic representatives than do physical magnitudes have the numerical properties of their numerical representatives. Although propositional attitudes turn out not to have the semantic properties that we intuitively conceive of them as having, they do turn out to have a kind of intentionality, but again not the sort of intentionality that we might associate with linguistic entities. Rather, theirs is a kind of behavioural intentionality: they have intentionality in the sense that they are aptitudes for, among other things, behaviours that are directed towards (in the case of desire‐like states) or sensitive to (in the case of belief‐like states) the states of affairs in terms of which we represent and specify them.

Page 13 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes Because the account remains realist about propositional attitudes, it in no way impugns Gricean intention‐based semantic programmes that propose to account for the intentionality of natural language in terms of the possession by speakers of certain propositional attitudes. Nor does the account impugn the broad outlines of recent translationalist accounts of linguistic competence, including semantic competence, according to which knowing a language is knowing how to translate between sentences in a natural language and sentences in a language of thought, provided that such accounts are stripped of their commitment to any particular representationalist account of the attitudes. The proposed account is also fully consistent with the idea that representations play an essential role in all sorts of cognitive processing. It is even consistent with the idea that as a matter of empirical fact possession of propositional attitudes requires the possession of various sorts of representations. The account only denies (p. 419) that propositional attitudes are to be identified with any such representations, that any such representations are constitutive of the attitudes. If this is correct, then to the extent that cognitive psychology is computational, and as such traffics in representations of one sort or another, then propositional‐attitude psychology is not, as some claim, proto‐cognitive (or proto‐computational) psychology. And precisely because propositional‐attitude psychology turns out not to be proto‐computational, it entails nothings as regards human cognitive computational architecture, classical or otherwise, beyond of course the very minimal requirement that, whatever that architecture, it must be capable of supporting those aptitudes that the account identifies with the attitudes. But this, it seems, is a requirement that can seemingly be met by many different sorts of computational architecture, so that possession of propositional attitudes turns out to be compatible with a wide variety of architectures. Where the proposed account diverges most sharply from received relational conceptions of the attitudes is first and foremost in its unwillingness simply to read back on to the attitudes properties of their natural‐language representations. And from this unwillingness arises the stark minimalism that characterizes the measurement‐theoretic account of the attitudes. Of course, it might turn out as a matter of empirical fact that there is much more structure to propositional attitudes than this account concedes, but if this is so, then this fact cannot be discerned either in our natural‐language representations of the attitudes or in the common‐sense explanatory practice in which propositional attitudes play their role. Nor, I would argue, is it to be discerned in the role that propositional‐attitude attributions play in cognitive‐psychological theorizing, though this is a claim that can't be defended here (see Matthews 2007).

References Beckermann, A. (1996), ‘Is there a Problem about Intentionality?’, Erkenntnis, 51: 1–23.

Page 14 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes Churchland, P. (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Davidson, D. (1968), ‘On Saying That’, Synthese, 19: 130–46. —— (1989), ‘What is Present to the Mind?’, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 36: 3–18. Dennett, D. (1987), ‘Beyond Belief’, in Dennett, The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 116–211. Díez, J. (1997), ‘A Hundred Years of Numbers: An Historical Introduction to Measurement Theory 1887–1990’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 28: 167–85, 237–65. Field, H. (1981), ‘Postscript to “Mental representation”’, in N. Block (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, ii (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 112–14. Fodor, J. (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Larson, R., and Ludlow, P. (1993), ‘Interpreted Logical Forms’, Synthese, 95: 305–55. Larson, R., and Segal, G. (1995), Knowledge of Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Matthews, R. (1990), ‘The Measure of Mind’, report no. 57/1990, Research Group on Mind and Brain, ZiF (Centre for Interdisciplinary Research) (Bielefeld). (p. 420)

Matthews, R. (1994), ‘The Measure of Mind,’ Mind, 103: 131–46.

—— (2007), The Measure of Mind: Propositional Attitudes and their Attribution (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Richard, M. (1990), Propositional Attitudes: An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Stalnaker, R. (1984), Inquiry (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Suppes, P. (1951), ‘A Set of Independent Axioms for Extensive Quantities’, Portugaliae Mathematica, 10: 163–72. Suppes, P., and Zinnes, J. (1963), ‘Basic Measurement Theory’, in R. Luce, D. Krantz, and E. Galanter (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, i (New York: Wiley) 1–76. Swoyer, C. (1987), ‘The Metaphysics of Measurement’, in J. Forge (ed.), Measurement, Realism and Objectivity (Dordrecht: Reidel), 235–90.

Notes:

Page 15 of 16

A Measurement‐Theoretic Account of Propositional Attitudes (1) Suppes and Zinnes (1963: 7) were perhaps the first to suggest the possibility of a measurement‐theoretic account of ‘attitude statements’. Swoyer (1987: 281–3) offers a sketch of how the idea that attitude predicates are measure predicates might be developed. (2) For a detailed development of a measurement‐theoretic account of the attitudes see Matthews 2007. (3) For an excellent historical account of the development of numerical‐measurement theory see Díez 1997. (4) See Larson and Ludlow 1993 and Larson and Segal 1995.

Robert J. Matthews

Robert J. Matthews is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey.

Page 16 of 16

The Normativity of the Intentional

Oxford Handbooks Online The Normativity of the Intentional   Ralph Wedgwood The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0026

Abstract and Keywords Many philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative. (This claim is the analogue, within the philosophy of mind, of the claim that is often made within the philosophy of language, that meaning is normative.) The first two sections of this article give a brief clarification of what this claim that ‘the intentional is normative’ actually means. The third section considers a number of arguments that philosophers have advanced in favour of this claim; as the discussion reflects, many of these arguments are inconclusive at best. However, the last section gives a sketch of a different argument, which the author regards as a persuasive argument for this claim. Keywords: philosophy of mind, normativity, philosophy of language, meaning, intentional, persuasive argument

MANY

philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative. (This claim is the

analogue, within the philosophy of mind, of the claim that is often made within the philosophy of language, that meaning is normative.) In the first two sections of this chapter I shall give a brief clarification of what this claim that ‘the intentional is normative’ actually means. In the third section I shall consider a number of arguments that philosophers have advanced in favour of this claim; as we shall see, many of these arguments are inconclusive at best. However, in the last section I shall give a sketch of a different argument, which I regard as a persuasive argument for this claim.

25.1 ‘The Intentional is Normative’—What Does that Mean?

Page 1 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional What is meant here by ‘the intentional’? For present purposes we may take the intentional to be a subset of the mental. Many mental states—indeed, some philosophers would say all mental states—are about something; they are ‘concerned with’ or ‘directed towards’ something. For example, some of my beliefs are about Iraq; some of my intentions are about travelling to Ireland; and some of my fears are about snakes. As many philosophers put it, these mental states all have intentional content, and so may be called ‘intentional states’ (see Searle 1983: esp. ch. 1). (p. 422)

What does ‘normative’ mean? For the purposes of this chapter I hope that it will be sufficient if we just start with the assumption that the paradigmatic normative terms are ‘ought’, ‘should’, ‘right’, ‘wrong’ and their closest equivalents in other languages. In addition to terms like ‘ought’, ‘should’, ‘right’, and ‘wrong’, I shall assume that terms like ‘correct’, ‘incorrect’, ‘rational’, and ‘irrational’ are also normative terms. Of course, the interpretation of these terms is philosophically controversial.1 My own view is that, as most formal semanticists would agree (see especially Kratzer 2002), most of these terms are context‐sensitive, and express different concepts in different contexts. Thus, there is not just the ‘ought’ of morality, but also the ‘ought’ that is relative to some particular goal or purpose, the ‘ought’ of rationality, and many others. It may be possible to give a deeper account of what unifies all normative concepts.2 For present purposes, however, it will probably be enough if we base our grasp of what normative concepts are simply on our intuitive understanding of terms like ‘ought’. What then does the claim that the intentional is normative amount to? The answer to this question may depend, in part, on what is the correct sort of semantics for normative concepts. First, suppose that a broadly truth‐conditional or factualist semantics for normative concepts is correct. According to this sort of semantics, whenever propositions involving these normative concepts are true, they are true in virtue of corresponding normative facts; and it is convenient to suppose that these normative facts must involve corresponding normative properties and relations.3 Then we can interpret the claim that the intentional is normative as the claim that in giving an account of the essence or nature of intentional states we must mention these normative properties or relations.4 Equally, in giving an account of the nature of an intentional fact—an account of what the intentional fact consists in, as some philosophers would say—we must state some normative fact. In that sense, intentional facts are partially constituted by normative facts.5 On this understanding, then, the claim that the intentional is normative is a metaphysical claim concerning the nature or essence of intentional states, or concerning (p. 423) the constitution of intentional facts. It is not a semantic thesis about the meaning of intentional terms, or a conceptual thesis about what is built into our concepts of intentional states. Such semantic or conceptual theses could be true even if the

Page 2 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional corresponding metaphysical thesis is false. It could be that even if we ordinarily think of intentional states as states that we ‘ought’ to be in under such‐and‐such circumstances, the nature or essence of those states can be explained in wholly non‐normative terms. The claim that the intentional is normative may have to be understood a bit differently if an expressivist account of normative concepts (instead of a broadly truth‐conditional or factualist account) is correct. According to the expressivist, although it is perfectly all right for everyday conversation to talk about ‘normative facts’ or ‘normative properties and relations’, no such normative facts, properties, or relations are capable of playing a real explanatory role in an account of the essence or nature of any part of reality itself. So, on this expressivist understanding of normative concepts, the claim that the intentional is normative would seem to express a sort of anti‐realism about intentional mental states. This sort of anti‐realism about the mental raises some very delicate and difficult issues.6 In order to avoid getting embroiled in these issues, I shall just assume, at least for the purposes of the rest of this chapter, that a broadly truth‐conditional or factualist account of normative terms and concepts is correct. If the claim that the intentional is normative is true, then it must be possible, at least in principle, to give an account of the nature of our intentional mental states in partly normative terms. In fact, such normative accounts of the nature of intentional states could take many forms. For example, some of these accounts may claim that the intentional is actually reducible to the normative; that is, that there is a correct reductive account of the nature of intentional states, and any such account must mention normative properties or relations (compare e.g. Brandom 1994).7 Other accounts may claim merely that the normative and the intentional must each be mentioned in giving any account of the other, so that the two domains of properties and relations are essentially interdependent, without either of the two being reducible to the other. These normative accounts could also differ in many other ways as well. In what follows, however, I shall abstract from all these differences between these normative accounts of intentional states. I shall also not take the time to explore the metaphysical and methodological implications of the claim that the intentional is normative. Instead, I shall focus on examining the reasons that philosophers have put forward in favour of this claim.

25.2 What Sort of Account is Called for, Anyway? (p. 424)

In the last two sections of this chapter I shall consider various arguments in favour of the claim that the intentional is normative. But before doing that I shall consider a rather abstract objection that can be made against this claim. Why should there be any informative ‘account’ of the intentional at all? Perhaps intentional mental states are wholly irreducible properties of thinkers, of which no informative ‘account’ can be given. Some philosophers accept a strong form of naturalism, according to which it must be Page 3 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional possible, at least in principle, to give a reductive account of the intentional in wholly naturalistic, non‐normative terms. But the claim that there is a reductive account of this sort hardly supports the claim that there is also a normative account of the intentional. Thus, such normative accounts of the intentional may seem to be a curious compromise, half‐way between a fully reductive naturalistic approach and the quietist or minimalist approach that denies that any informative account of the intentional can be given. It seems to me that there is a problem with the doggedly quietist approach. This is because of a plausible point about the relation between the intentional states that we are in and our dispositions. (When I refer to our ‘dispositions’ here, I do not mean to focus exclusively on our behavioural dispositions; I mean to include our mental dispositions as well, such as our dispositions to revise our beliefs, intentions, and other attitudes, in response to various conditions.) This point is an analogue of the point that is sometimes expressed by the slogan ‘meaning is use’: just as the meaning of a linguistic expression is determined by the ways in which the members of the relevant linguistic community are disposed to use the expression in discourse, so too the identity of a concept is determined by the ways in which we are disposed to use that concept in thought. For example, suppose that a community has a concept in their repertoire that they are all disposed to apply, quite systematically, to cats and only to cats; the experiences on which they base their judgements involving this concept are precisely the sorts of experiences that we would use to recognize something as a cat; and they treat everything that falls under this concept as belonging to a single natural kind. Now consider the supposition that in this case, this concept is in fact the concept of a bicycle, so that almost all of these thinkers' beliefs involving this concept are irrational and false. This supposition appears absurd (compare Fricker 1991). In general, it seems that if there is a community the members of which possess a concept that they are disposed to use in their reasoning in exactly the same ways as we are disposed to use a certain concept in our repertoire, then their concept must be the same as ours. So it seems that there must be something about the thinker's dispositions—together perhaps with certain facts about his environment and the dispositions of other thinkers in his linguistic community—that determines the identity of the concepts that figure in the thinker's thoughts. (p. 425)

Similarly, if there is a community that has a type of attitude that they are disposed to form and revise in just the same way as we are disposed to form and revise our beliefs, it would be absurd to suppose that this attitude is in fact the attitude of disbelief—so that almost all of their attitudes of this type are incorrect and irrational. Again, something about our dispositions with respect to an attitude type must determine exactly which attitude type it is that figures in our thoughts. However, if it is true that facts about the thinker's dispositions determine which concepts and attitude types figure in the thinker's thoughts in this way, then there surely must be some account of the precise way in which these dispositions determine this (see Boghossian 1991: 66). The bare claim that the thinker's dispositions determine which Page 4 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional concepts and attitude types figure in the thinker's thoughts is compatible with infinitely many different precise ways in which these dispositions might determine this. Surely there must be some general principle that captures the specific role that these dispositions play in determining this. Otherwise it will remain utterly mysterious why these dispositions determine this in the specific way in which they do, rather than in any of the infinitely many other possible ways. So it seems that there must, at least in principle, be some explanatory account of how the thinker's dispositions determine what intentional states he is in. There is no reason why this account should take the fully reductive form of giving an account of intentional states in terms of dispositions that are characterized in wholly non‐intentional, non‐normative terms. On the contrary, there is no objection to characterizing these dispositions in general intentional terms—that is, precisely as mental dispositions, dispositions to form certain attitudes involving certain concepts in certain circumstances—so long as our characterization of these dispositions does not presuppose the identity of the particular concepts and attitude types that they involve. It may well be a completely primitive and irreducible feature of me that I use concepts and have attitudes at all. However, it cannot be an irreducible feature of me that I am using a concept that refers to cats (as opposed to referring to dogs or to cows, for example); that must be explained in terms of the dispositions that I have with respect to this concept.8 So the explanatory account that seems to be called for could take the following form. It could start out by presupposing that we are dealing with a thinker who has attitudes towards contents that are composed of concepts.9 But it would start by treating these attitudes and concepts as initially uninterpreted. That is, it would start with a ‘neutral’ characterization of the thinker's intentional dispositions—a characterization of the thinker's dispositions with respect to these attitudes and concepts that does not in any way presuppose the exact identity of these attitudes and (p. 426) concepts. Then this account could articulate certain principles concerning the nature of various attitudes and concepts, which would enable us to identify the thinker's attitudes and concepts—say, as the attitude of belief, or as the concept of water—on the basis of such a neutral characterization of the thinker's intentional dispositions (along with further facts about the thinker's natural and social environment). In what follows I shall assume that all adequate accounts of the nature of our intentional mental states take this form. Certain normative accounts of the intentional could certainly accommodate this point. For example, such an account might consist of two parts. The first part would give an account of the different attitudes and concepts in terms of certain normative principles governing them. The attitude of belief, for example, might be identified as that attitude that it is correct or appropriate to take towards a proposition just in case that proposition is true; the concept ‘if’ might be identified as that concept for which certain sorts of inference are rational (such as inferences that are instances of modus ponens); and similar accounts could be given of other concepts and types of attitudes. Second, there would have to be an account of what has to be true of a thinker if she is to possess those concepts or to be capable of having those attitudes. Here the account could say, very roughly, that the right Page 5 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional way to interpret the thinker must be the most charitable reading of her dispositions, the way that makes thinkers' dispositions emerge as most rational and most sensitive to the norms that apply to the intentional states that they are in.10 So a normative account of the intentional could satisfy the demand for an explanatory account of how exactly thinkers' dispositions (together with their environment) determine which intentional states they are in. But what reason is there to think that any such account is true?

25.3 Some Questionable Arguments for the Normativity of the Intentional 25.3.1 The Entailment Argument Some philosophers try to argue for the claim that the intentional is normative by pointing out that facts about one's intentional states entail normative facts. Then they argue that this entailment shows that the intentional is in itself essentially normative.11 (p. 427)

For example, the argument might be elaborated as follows. Necessarily, anyone who believes p is committed to believing ‘p or q’. That is, it is a necessary truth, applying to everyone, that one ought not simultaneously to believe p and consciously to refuse to believe ‘p or q’ (that is, to consider whether or not ‘p or q’ is the case, and yet to fail to believe ‘p or q’). But how else are we to explain why this is a necessary truth, unless this truth logically follows from principles that are essential to or constitutive of all beliefs whose content is of the form ‘p or q’? And if a normative truth follows from these principles, mustn't these principles themselves mention normative properties or relations? One might start by questioning whether it really is true in general—let alone necessarily true—that one ought not simultaneously to believe p and consciously to refuse to believe ‘p or q’. What if a powerful demon will destroy the world unless you simultaneously believe p and consciously refuse to believe ‘p or q’ (see Byrne 2002)? The best response to this sort of objection, I think, is to insist that there are different sorts of oughts involved here. It is still a ‘mistake’ of some kind simultaneously to believe p and consciously to refuse to believe ‘p or q’—even if the demon will destroy the world unless you commit this mistake. But now the proponent of this argument must say more about what exactly this sort of ‘ought’ means. It may be that it just means: ‘ought, in order to achieve the goal of believing the truth and nothing but the truth (about any question that one has actually considered)’. If so, then we can give a simple explanation Page 6 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional of why it is necessary that we ‘ought’, in this sense, to avoid simultaneously believing p and consciously refusing to believe ‘p or q’: this is necessary because it is necessary that if p is true, so is ‘p or q’. This explanation appeals only to the meaning of this sort of ‘ought’, and to the connection between these intentional states and their truth‐conditions. It seems to make no appeal to the claim that the intentional is in itself intrinsically normative.12 Moreover, even if the sort of ‘ought’ that is involved here is not susceptible to any such deflationary interpretation, we still do not have a sound argument for the normativity of the intentional. As Paul Horwich writes: [A] property may have normative implications without itself being normative. For example, killing is prima facie wrong; none the less one can presumably characterize ‘x kills y’ in entirely non‐normative terms. … It might be possible for our most basic normative principles to have the form (x)(Dx → Nx) where ‘D’ describes some state of the world and ‘N’ specifies what ought or ought not to be done in that situation. Thus the normative implications of a meaning property leave it entirely open that its nature is completely non‐normative.

(1998: 188–93) In this way, the ‘entailment’ of normative facts by facts about one's intentional states could be explained by the existence of certain fundamental normative axioms. But there is no reason to suppose that these normative axioms are constitutive of or (p. 428) essential to the intentional states that they apply to. So the entailment argument seems not to be a persuasive argument for the normativity of the intentional.

25.3.2 The Interpretation Argument Some philosophers argue for the claim that the intentional is normative on the basis of considerations concerning interpretation. This argument is based on two premises. According to the first premise, the central or canonical way of ascribing mental states to others is to attempt to ascribe those mental states that make best sense of them and of their behaviour—where making best sense of them requires following a principle of charity, ascribing those mental states that give the most charitable possible interpretation of them and their behaviour (see esp. Davidson 1980: 221; 1984: 153). Furthermore, according to this first premise, this principle of charity must be understood in normative terms: to interpret someone charitably is to interpret her as forming beliefs and intentions in a rational way, and as having at least a disposition to have experiences, desires, and emotions that really are correct or appropriate, and so on.13

Page 7 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional According to the second premise, the canonical method of ascribing mental states to others must proceed by attempting to track those facts about them that really make it the case that they have the mental states in question. The first premise appears to imply that this canonical method attempts to track certain normative facts about the subjects who are being interpreted; namely, normative facts about what is the most charitable interpretation of them. So it must be these normative facts that make it the case that they have those mental states; and so a version of a normative account of the intentional is true. Both premises of this argument can be questioned. The second premise seems too quick to assume that what is fundamental to our canonical method of coming to know some fact must also be fundamental to the nature of that fact itself. The ‘canonical method’ could still provide us with true beliefs about the mental states of others, even if it were only a contingent fact about us that we tend to form beliefs and intentions in rational ways, and to have experiences and desires that are correct or appropriate. In that case, the normative facts that guide our interpretation would generally lead us to the truth about the mental states of thinkers in the actual world, but they would not be in any way constitutive of the mental states themselves. The first premise could also be questioned. Perhaps the principle of charity can be formulated in entirely non‐normative terms. For example, perhaps we can define which interpretation is most charitable in purely logical terms, as the interpretation that makes the subjects emerge as much as possible as believing the truth, and conforming to certain standards of consistency and probabilistic coherence in their beliefs and preferences. Or perhaps interpretation should follow not a principle of charity but a principle of humanity, ascribing those mental states that make the subjects (p. 429) emerge as much as possible like statistically normal human beings (see Grandy 1973). No doubt, if we have independent reasons for accepting that the intentional is normative, then it will become much more plausible that the canonical method of interpretation involves following a normative principle of charity. But in the absence of such independent reasons we have not been given much reason to accept the first premise of the argument. So the interpretation argument seems dialectically ineffective as an argument for the claim that the intentional is normative.

25.3.3 The Argument from the Alleged Failure of Non‐Normative Dispositionalism Many of the philosophers who claim that the intentional is normative try to support their claim by arguing against the obvious alternative—what I shall call the ‘non‐normative‐ dispositionalist’ view, according to which the nature of our intentional states is determined by features of our dispositions that can be specified in wholly non‐normative terms.

Page 8 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional Here I shall just discuss the two most challenging objections that any non‐normative dispositionalist theory must face. Both objections stem from the point that if the nature of a given concept is determined by our dispositions to form beliefs and other attitudes involving that concept, then those dispositions must surely also fix the extension or reference of that concept. But it may seem that there are at least two reasons why our dispositions cannot fix the extension of our concepts. First, as Kripke famously insisted, it appears, at least offhand, that our dispositions are finite, whereas the extension of many concepts—at least if we include their extensions across all possible worlds—is infinite (1982: 26). For example, the extension of the symbol ‘+’ is a function whose domain and range are both infinite. In consequence, the arguments and values of this function include numbers that are so vast that I have no dispositions whatsoever with respect to them. So how can my finite dispositions for using this symbol fix on a unique infinite function—the addition function—out of all the infinitely many such functions that there are? Second, we all have dispositions to make mistakes. Our mistakes are not random; on the contrary, our mistakes are typically quite systematic. The non‐normative dispositionalists face a dilemma here. On the one hand, they could be ‘holists’ and claim that all our dispositions for using a concept are equally involved in determining the concept's extension. Alternatively, they could reject holism and try to draw some distinction between those dispositions that fix the concept's extension and those that do not. But according to Kripke, the first horn of the dilemma is hopeless. It is natural to assume that if one's dispositions for using a concept determine the concept's extension, then they must determine it in such a way that one's disposition to form beliefs involving the concept in certain circumstances guarantees that those beliefs are true in those circumstances. But if all one's dispositions for using a given concept are equally involved in determining the concept's extension, then one cannot be disposed to form false beliefs at all. Indeed, if it is (p. 430) true, as some philosophers assume, that however one uses a concept, one must have been disposed to use it in that way, then as Kripke put it this ‘holistic’ dispositional account amounts to ‘an equation of performance and correctness’ (1982: 21). Thus, the first horn of the dilemma seems to lead to the absurd Protagorean claim that all beliefs are true. However, the second horn of the dilemma looks almost equally daunting. How exactly is the non‐normative dispositionalist to distinguish between the extension‐determining dispositions and all the other dispositions that we have with respect to a given concept? Perhaps if we could appeal to a normative distinction—say, between rational and irrational dispositions—we could answer this challenge. But it is quite unclear how to formulate this distinction in wholly non‐normative terms, without simply presupposing what the extension of the concept is. As challenging as these objections are, it is possible that some non‐normative dispositionalists will be able to answer them. Regarding the first objection, it is not obvious that our dispositions really are ‘finite’ in the way that the objection assumes. Page 9 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional Until recently many philosophers assumed that dispositions can be analysed by means of counterfactuals: according to this sort of analysis, to be disposed to ϕ in circumstances C is to be such that if one were in circumstances C one would ϕ. But recently this view has been shown to have many counter‐intuitive consequences (see for example Bird 1998; Fara 2005). Dispositions are more plausibly regarded as being closer to ceteris paribus laws, where laws may be regarded as nomic connections between properties. For an object to have a disposition is for it to fall within the domain of the ceteris paribus law in question. If the law is a connection between properties, then the disposition is just as ‘infinite’ as those properties are. So, for example, the relevant disposition with respect to the concept ‘+’ may be the disposition to accept an inference precisely in response to the fact that one has considered an inference of a certain general form. For example, in the case of the concept ‘+’, perhaps the relevant dispositions are as follows. First, one is disposed to respond to the state of considering any proposition of the form ‘n + 0 = n’ by accepting that proposition. Second, one is disposed to respond to the state of considering any inference of the form ‘n + m = k; therefore, n + m′ = k′’ (where n′ is the successor of n) by accepting that inference. Now these ‘forms’ are exemplified not just by those propositions and inferences that one is capable of considering but by infinitely many propositions and inferences.14 It is, one might claim, these general forms, to which one's disposition responds, that fix the extension of the concept. Regarding the second objection, several different responses are possible. First, proponents of the ‘holistic’ form of non‐normative dispositionalism may reject Kripke's assumption that if our dispositions to use a concept determine a concept's semantic value, then our disposition to form a belief involving the concept in certain (p. 431) circumstances must guarantee that the belief is true in those circumstances. Holists influenced by Davidson might say that the correct interpretation of the concept is the one that ‘maximizes’ the true beliefs that the thinker is disposed to form using that concept; but it does not have to guarantee that every belief that the thinker is disposed to form using that concept is true (see Davidson 2001: 137). Alternatively, non‐normative dispositionalists might reject holism, and claim that it is possible to distinguish between (i) the dispositions that are essential to possessing the concept and (ii) the dispositions that are not essential to possessing the concept, in wholly non‐normative terms. For example, they might claim that the disposition that fixes the concept's extension is the disposition that is causally the most basic to one's use of the concept.15 This notion of the disposition that is the ‘most basic’ to one's use of a concept is hard to explicate precisely. But it may be that something like Jerry Fodor's notion of ‘asymmetric dependency’ helps here (1990: 90–2). The other dispositions, which do not fix the concept's extension, depend upon the extension‐fixing dispositions in a way in which the latter dispositions do not depend upon the former. It may be then that the non‐normative dispositionalist can give a wholly non‐normative distinction between the extension‐determining dispositions and the other dispositions that we have with respect to a given concept, without simply presupposing what the extension of the concept is. For

Page 10 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional these reasons, then, this Kripke‐inspired argument also seems not to be a persuasive argument for the normativity of the intentional.

25.4 An Argument for Normative Dispositionalism In this final section I shall give a sketch of a different sort of argument for the claim that the intentional is normative. I have argued above (in Section 25.2) that some sort of dispositionalism must be true. I shall now argue that only a normative sort of dispositionalism can give an adequate account of the nature of intentional mental states. Suppose that one of your dispositions with respect to the use of a concept F is a disposition to use the concept in an irrational way, such as a disposition to engage in some fallacious form of reasoning. Then the holist would have to admit that it is partly in virtue of this disposition that you possess the concept F. This disposition is part of what it is about you that makes it the case that you possess the concept F. In effect, this disposition is an essential part of what realizes your possession of F.16 (p. 432)

However, it seems doubtful to me that one's possession of a concept can rest on an irrational disposition in this way. If this really could be the case, then there could be a thinker who possesses a concept at least partly in virtue of an irrational disposition of this sort. But then the thinker's possession of the concept would be at least partly founded in irrationality, and any use that the thinker makes of this concept would depend on or be underlain by this irrationality. It seems most doubtful whether this could be the case. The possession of a concept is a cognitive power or ability—not a cognitive defect or liability.17 Thus, it seems to me that if one possesses a concept, the dispositions in virtue of which one possesses it must be rational dispositions. In general, the dispositions that determine the identity of the concepts (and of the types of attitude) that figure in one's thoughts must be rational dispositions. More specifically, it may be that the disposition that determines the identity of a concept that figures in one's thoughts is whatever is causally the most basic of one's rational dispositions with respect to the concept. Thus, if we are told that there is a concept C that figures in a thinker's thoughts, and we are also told (in terms that do not presuppose the identity of C) what is the most basic of the rational dispositions that the thinker has with respect to C, then this information will be enough to determine which concept C is. This makes it plausible, it seems to me, that for each concept there is some specific rational disposition that is essential to possessing the concept. For example, in the case of the concept ‘if’, it seems impossible for there to be a thinker who possesses the concept ‘if’ without having any disposition for rationally accepting modus ponens inferences Page 11 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional (whereas it certainly seems possible for there to be superhuman thinkers who possess the concept ‘if’ but have no disposition to engage in any fallacious forms of reasoning involving this concept). If this disposition really is essential to possessing the concept, then it will be impossible for any thinker to possess the concept without possessing it in virtue of having this disposition. As I have argued, the dispositions in virtue of which we possess a concept must be rational dispositions. So if a disposition is essential to possessing a concept, it must be impossible for this disposition not to be a rational disposition: it must be an essentially rational disposition. Now some philosophers may think that this still does not show that an account of what is essential to a given concept will have to mention normative properties or relations (such as the properties or relations that are referred to by the term ‘rational’). According to these philosophers, it is possible for such an account to single out the relevant essentially rational disposition by some purely non‐normative feature—where this other feature guarantees that the disposition in question is a rational disposition, but is not equivalent to its being a rational disposition. (p. 433)

However, there is a reason for thinking that these dispositions cannot in fact be specified without mentioning normative properties or relations.18 It seems plausible that the relevant rational dispositions are all dispositions to form or revise one's mental states in some rational way. In a broad sense of the term, they are dispositions for certain forms of rational reasoning. For example, one sort of rational reasoning might lead one from having a visual experience that presents an object in a certain distinctive way (in the absence of any positive reason to believe one's experiences to be unreliable) to one's forming a belief that predicates the concept ‘… is yellow’ of the object in question. A disposition for this sort of reasoning might be essential to possessing the concept ‘… is yellow’. Other sorts of rational disposition might be dispositions to accept rational deductive or inductive inferences, or to engage in rational sorts of practical reasoning. For example, one simple sort of rational practical reasoning might be the kind that leads from having a rational belief of the form ‘All things considered, I ought to ϕ’ to forming an intention to ϕ. It may be that a disposition for this sort of reasoning is essential to possessing the concept that is expressed by the relevant kind of ‘ought’. As these examples suggest, there seems not to be any way to specify the relevant sorts of rational reasoning without mentioning normative properties or relations. The specification that I have just given of the sort of reasoning that leads from visual experiences to beliefs of the form ‘x is yellow’ included a proviso ‘in the absence of any positive reason to believe one's experiences to be unreliable’; in specifying this sort of reasoning in this way, I mentioned the normative relation of having a reason to believe something. Similarly, my specification of the sort of reasoning that leads to an intention to ϕ is restricted to cases in which one has a rational belief that all things considered one

Page 12 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional ought to ϕ; in specifying this type of reasoning in this way, I have mentioned the normative relation of rationally believing something. The reason for specifying these sorts of reasoning in this normative way is clear. These sorts of reasoning, like most if not all others, are defeasible. That is, even if one is in the ‘input’ mental states for this sort of reasoning, certain defeating conditions must be absent if it is to be possible to form a rational belief or intention by means of this form of reasoning. But the nature of defeating conditions is precisely that they are those conditions that make it irrational in the circumstances to form the belief or intention in question in response to these input mental states. There seems to be no way of specifying these defeating conditions without mentioning normative properties or relations. For a sort of reasoning to be essentially rational, then, it seems that its input conditions must include the absence of defeating conditions as such. It would not be enough if its input conditions included only the absence of certain defeating conditions, but not the absence of defeating conditions as such. Then there would be cases (p. 434) in which this sort of reasoning would be irrational: in these cases, this sort of reasoning would involve treating certain conditions as if they constituted a reason for a certain revision to one's beliefs or other attitudes when in fact, on account of the presence of defeating conditions, they did not. Equally, it would also not be enough if this sort of reasoning were markedly oversensitive, so that its input conditions included not just the absence of defeating conditions but also the absence of various additional factors that were in fact quite irrelevant to the rationality of the sort of reasoning in question. Then this sort of reasoning would be irrational in a different way: it would involve treating certain conditions as relevant when they are not in fact relevant at all. For this reason it seems that these essentially rational forms of reasoning cannot be specified without mentioning the absence of defeating conditions as such—which in effect involves mentioning certain normative properties and relations. But, as I have argued, the dispositions that are essential to possessing concepts, and to being capable of the various types of attitude, must be dispositions to engage in such essentially rational forms of reasoning. So it seems that the dispositions that are essential to possessing concepts (and to being capable of attitude types) cannot be specified without mentioning normative properties or relations. Some philosophers might suggest that one could still be disposed to reason in accordance with these essentially rational forms of reasoning even if the normative properties or relations do not have to be mentioned in specifying these dispositions themselves. For example, one might have a host of separate dispositions, such that the net effect of all these separate dispositions is that one forms and revises one's beliefs and other attitudes in just the same way as one would if one had a disposition that actually responded to the normative facts themselves. However, if all these dispositions really are quite separate and causally independent of each other, then it seems that it could just be a fluke that the net effect of all these dispositions is that one forms and revises one's attitudes in a rational way. But in that case it actually seems to me quite doubtful whether the Page 13 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional manifestation of these dispositions can really count as rational thinking at all. Indeed, this case seems in effect to be the case that was originally described by Ned Block and has since come to be known as the ‘Blockhead’, which seems not be engaged in rational reasoning at all.19 So it seems most plausible that if there are any dispositions that are essential to possessing concepts (and to being capable of attitude types), these dispositions must respond precisely to normative facts; hence, these dispositions cannot be specified without mentioning such normative properties or relations. Some other philosophers might insist that it is still bound to be possible, at least in principle, by using some highly complex psychological terms, to specify these essentially rational forms of reasoning in wholly non‐normative terms. But I do not have to deny this.20 I have said that we cannot specify these rational dispositions without (p. 435) mentioning normative properties or relations; I have not said that we cannot specify these rational dispositions without using normative terms. It may well be possible, in principle, to mention these normative properties or relations by means of some complex psychological terms. Even if these normative properties or relations can be specified in purely psychological terms, it would still be an interesting and surprising fact that any adequate account of the nature of intentional mental states has to mention these normative properties or relations—so long as these normative properties or relations can only be specified by means of highly complex psychological terms. This is because it would still be an interesting and surprising fact if the property or relation referred to by this particular complex psychological term has to be mentioned in any adequate account of the nature of intentional mental states. It certainly seems that if there are any purely psychological terms that refer to the absence of defeating conditions, they will be immensely complex. Defeating conditions, after all, can come from anywhere: from experience, from memory, from the testimony of others, or even from elaborate deductive reasoning or scientific theorizing. So the only simple way of specifying what these conditions all have in common is in normative terms —as conditions that make it irrational to reason in certain ways. Even if there is also some more complex way of specifying these defeating conditions in non‐normative terms, my argument would not be undermined if the only simple way to specify the dispositions that are essential to possessing certain concepts, or to being capable of certain attitude types, is by using normative terms. As I argued in Section 25.2 above, there must be some account that explains how the thinker's dispositions determine which concepts and attitude types figure in his thoughts. As I have argued in this section, the prospects for a purely non‐normative dispositionalism are dim. So since some sort of dispositionalism must be true, then (at least so long as it seems that a normative sort of dispositionalism could avoid the problems that other theories face) we have a good reason to accept the claim that I have been considering here: the claim that the intentional is normative.

Page 14 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional

References Bird, A. (1998), ‘Dispositions and Antidotes’, Philosophical Quarterly, 48: 227–34. Block, N. (1978), ‘Troubles with Functionalism’, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9: 261–326. Boghossian, P. (1989), ‘The Rule‐following Considerations’, Mind, 98: 507–49. —— (1991), ‘Naturalizing Content’, in B. Loewer and G. Rey (eds.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell), 65–86. Brandom, R. (1994), Making It Explicit (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Byrne, A. (2002), ‘Semantic Values?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 201–7. Child, T. W. (1993), ‘Anomalism, Uncodifiability, and Psychophysical Relations’, Philosophical Review, 102: 215–45. Davidson, D. (1980), Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (1984), Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (2001), ‘Radical Interpretation’, in Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 125–40. (p. 436)

Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon).

Fara, M. (2005), ‘Dispositions and Habituals’, Noûs, 39: 43–82. Fine, K. (1995), ‘Senses of Essence’, in W. Sinnott‐Armstrong, D. Raffman, and N. Asher (eds.), Modality, Morality, and Belief: Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 53–73. Fodor, J. A. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Fricker, E. (1991), ‘Analyticity, Linguistic Practice and Philosophical Method’, in K. Puhl (ed.), Meaning Scepticism (Berlin, New York: de Gruyter), 231–3. Gibbard, A. (1994), ‘Meaning and Normativity’, Philosophical Issues, 5: 95–115. —— (1996), ‘Thought, Norms, and Discursive Practice’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56: 699–717. Grandy, R. (1973), ‘Reference, Meaning, and Belief’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 439–52. Horwich, P. (1998), Meaning (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Page 15 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional Hurley, S. (1989), Natural Reasons (Oxford: Clarendon). Kratzer, A. (2002), ‘The Notional Category of Modality’, in P. Portner and B. Partee (eds.), Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings (Oxford: Blackwell), 289–323. Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1982), Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Lewis, D. (1974), ‘Radical Interpretation’, Synthese, 23: 331–44. Morris, M. (1992), The Good and the True (Oxford: Clarendon). Peacocke, C. (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Rosen, G. (1997), ‘Who Makes the Rules Around Here?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57: 163–71. —— (2001), ‘Brandom on Modality, Normativity and Intentionality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63: 611–23. Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Wedgwood, R. (2001), ‘Conceptual Role Semantics for Moral Terms’, Philosophical Review, 110: 1–30. —— (2002), ‘The Aim of Belief’, Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 267–97.

Notes: (1) For example, Robert Brandom argues that normative truths are in some sense ‘imposed’ by ‘human practices’ in his book Making It Explicit (1994: 46–50), whereas I would myself insist that there must be some fundamental normative principles that are simply necessary truths, and so wholly independent of all contingent facts about human practices. But I shall have to remain neutral about these philosophical controversies here. (2) Indeed, I have attempted to give such a unifying account elsewhere. Roughly, my idea is that what unifies all these normative concepts is that it is a constitutive feature of these concepts that they play a regulative role in certain rational practices (see Wedgwood 2002: esp. 268–9); for a more detailed account of a particular normative concept see Wedgwood (2001). (3) Philosophers of broadly nominalist sympathies may be reluctant to countenance such normative properties and relations. But the debate between nominalists and realists about properties and relations is clearly independent of the debates about the normativity

Page 16 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional of the intentional that we are focusing on here. For our purposes, speaking about properties and relations is useful for achieving generality; but it could in principle be dispensed with if it were necessary to do so. (4) To fix ideas, we may think of an ‘account of the essence or nature’ of something in roughly the same way as Kit Fine would conceive of a statement of the ‘constitutive essence’ of the thing (1995: 56). (5) Compare the interpretation of this claim given by Gideon Rosen (2001). (6) For an exploration of the possibility of combining an expressivist account of normative concepts with the claim that the intentional is normative see Gibbard (1994). Gibbard also interprets Brandom's Making It Explicit as articulating a view of this sort (see Gibbard 1996). (Other philosophers have interpreted Brandom differently: see Rosen 1997. I am not myself certain which interpretation of Brandom is correct.) In fact, I believe that there are very serious problems with this attempt to combine expressivism about normative concepts with the claim that the intentional is normative; but I cannot attempt to explain what these problems are here. (7) At least, this is how Gideon Rosen interprets Brandom in Rosen (1997). See also Morris (1992). (8) In effect, an account of what it is for a thinker to be using the concept cow may employ both the term ‘concept’ and the term ‘cow’, but it may not employ the phrase ‘the concept cow’ or ‘refers to cows’ or any variant thereof. It should conform to Christopher Peacocke's constraint, that an adequate account of a concept should take ‘the A(C) form’ (1992: 5–16). Compare Saul Kripke's insistence that an account of why a given name refers to a particular individual must not be ‘circular’ (1980: 68–70). (9) It may also be necessary to start out with presuppositions about the syntactic category that the various concepts belong to—whether they are general or predicative concepts, or singular concepts, or propositional operators, and so on. (10) For the idea that interpretation must be guided by a principle of charity see Davidson (2001). A normative theory could avail itself of this idea without accepting Davidson's full‐ blown ‘interpretivism’. As David Lewis suggests (1974), the reference to interpretation could just be taken as a way of dramatizing what is objectively constitutive of the intentional states in question. (11) This is very close to an argument that Kripke used to argue for the normativity of meaning (1982: 11, 21, 24, 37). (12) This objection, like the next, is due to Horwich (1998: ch. 8). (13) One philosopher who insists that the principle of charity (at least as it applies to the ascription of preferences) must be interpreted in evaluative terms is Hurley (1989: ch. 6).

Page 17 of 19

The Normativity of the Intentional (14) For this response to the ‘finitude’ objection see Peacocke (1992: ch. 5). It may genuinely be a certain property that one's disposition is responding to, even if one's dispositions are not perfect and do not respond to that property in absolutely every case. (15) This seems to me a much more promising route than the route that Paul Boghossian assumes the dispositionalist will take, of focusing on the thinker's dispositions under ‘optimal conditions’ (see Boghossian 1989). (16) More precisely, if the holist is right, it is essential to possessing the concept F that one's possession of the concept F supervenes on one's total set of dispositions for using the concepts in one's repertoire; and the minimal supervenience base for possessing F that you actually instantiate is one that includes your having this irrational disposition. This seems to imply that your having this irrational disposition is part of what realizes your possession of this concept. (17) Compare Gareth Evans's insistence that understanding a linguistic expression is a species of knowledge, and so cannot be based on false belief: ‘Truth is seamless: there can be no truth which it requires acceptance of a falsehood to appreciate’ (1982: 331). (18) When I speak of ‘specifying’ a disposition, I do not mean an exhaustive complete account of how this disposition works. I simply mean ‘picking out’ the disposition, by one of its essential or non‐accidental features. (19) Block's original example was of a machine that passes a ‘Turing Test’ simply by means of a huge ‘look‐up table’ (1978: 294–6). (20) I do not have to deny this; but there may still be reasons for denying it. For an argument for the claim that the conditions of rational belief and rational choice are ‘uncodifiable’ see Child (1993).

Ralph Wedgwood

Ralph Wedgwood is Professor of Philosophy, Merton College, Oxford.

Page 18 of 19

Concepts and Possession Conditions

Oxford Handbooks Online Concepts and Possession Conditions   Christopher Peacocke The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0027

Abstract and Keywords The first virtue of the rough characterization of concepts in terms of ways of thinking of objects and properties, and their role in that-clauses, is that it highlights the relation between concepts and reference. The second virtue of the initial characterization is that it establishes the prima facie relevance of what has come to be called Frege's Principle in the individuation of concepts. A third virtue of the initial characterization is that it brings out a phenomenon whose significance is insufficiently appreciated. There is a phenomenon of productivity for thought about mental states that is just as striking as the original phenomenon of the productivity of conceptual thought about the non-mental world. Keywords: thinking of objects, concepts and reference, Frege's Principle, individuation of concepts, conceptual thought, mental state

26.1 Introductory THE

large‐scale questions about concepts are the same as those one would ask about any

other apparent category of apparent entities, to wit: What are they? What do we need to understand about them? What can a good theory of them explain?

Page 1 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Unlike other domains, however, almost every philosophical claim about concepts is controversial. Perhaps the only two uncontroversial propositions in this territory are (a) that a good theory of concepts is fundamental to a wide range of philosophical issues and (b) that proposition (a) is about the only philosophical proposition about concepts on which there is general agreement. The disagreement exists because the nature of concepts is so closely tied to fundamental issues in the theory of thought, in metaphysics, and in epistemology. In this area the implied costs of error are high; and so are the potential rewards of correctness. I will highlight a number of open questions in the philosophical theory of concepts. To say that they are open is consistent (p. 438) with important contributions having been made to their resolution: it is just to say that they remain far from settled. To avoid a thicket of numbers, years, and references, all bibliographic information and citations are given at the end of the paper, section by section.

Concepts are commonly introduced as ways of thinking of objects, properties, or anything else on whose identity turns the truth or falsity of attributions of attitudes in that‐clauses. It can be true that Peter believes that elephants can swim without it being true that

Peter believes that long‐trunked pachyderms can swim. Hence, it is said, under this mode of introducing concepts, the concepts elephant and long‐ trunked pachyderm are distinct concepts. They are different ways of thinking of the same animals. The same applies, by the parallel reasoning, to establish the distinctness of the pairs of concepts pain and C‐fibre activation; 3 p.m. and now (even when used at 3 p.m.); and so forth.

This mode of introduction via ways of thinking and that‐clauses needs several refinements, but it also has important virtues. The first refinement it needs is something that takes account of the fact that there can be quite a loose connection between the concept someone is actually employing in thought, and the meaning of the words (even in context) that are used in a true attribution of propositional attitudes to the thinker. Sometimes the words in the language do not obviously express a specific concept, and have only something at the level of reference associated with them. Almost everyone believes this for proper names of persons and of cities, for instance. Such words can still be used in attribution of attitudes. Many recent writers, from quite varied theoretical backgrounds, have held that x believes that Fa means roughly

There is some concept α of a, and there is some concept ϕ of F, such that x believes ϕα. Further refinement is needed to take account of the fact that we commonly use that‐clauses in attributions of states where the content is plausibly non‐conceptual. It trips off the tongue to say that

The cat sees that the mouse has gone behind the sofa.

Page 2 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions But if we draw a distinction between conceptual and non‐conceptual content, and think that cats are capable only of states with non‐conceptual content, we have some work to do. Introducing concepts via that‐clauses will not relieve us of the non‐trivial, and interesting, task of saying what is distinctive of conceptual content, as opposed to non‐conceptual content. I call this ‘the characterization problem’. When we have a solution to the problem, we can use it to cut down the class of that‐clauses that are pertinent to the introductory explanation of concepts. If we do well in addressing the characterization problem, we may be able to bypass mention of that‐ clauses altogether. After all, the characterization in terms of that‐clauses is a (p. 439) linguistic characterization of something that is not at all obviously fundamentally linguistic. One may hope to dispense with any reference to language to public language at least—when we have a more theoretical characterization of conceptual content before us.

The first virtue of the rough characterization of concepts in terms of ways of thinking of objects and properties, and their role in that‐clauses, is that it highlights the relation between concepts and reference. On this intuitive, initial characterization, it is part of the nature of a concept that there is an answer to the question: What relation has to hold between the concept and something for the latter to be the former's reference? On certain neo‐Fregean views, the answer to this question actually individuates the concept. But on any view that has this mode of introduction as its starting point, the question must have an answer, whether individuative of the concept or not. The issue of the correct way of conceiving of the relation between a concept and its reference is, I will be arguing later, of enormous consequence for the philosophical theory of concepts. The second virtue of the initial characterization is that it establishes the prima facie relevance of what has come to be called Frege's Principle in the individuation of concepts. Concept A is distinct from the concept B iff a thinker can rationally judge some complete (truth‐evaluable) content containing the concept A without judging the corresponding content containing B. Were this not so, we could not use distinctness of concepts to explain, or at least to characterize, the difference between the belief with the content concerning elephants and the belief with the content concerning long‐trunked pachyderms. If concepts slice at least this finely, it will, apparently, be an obligation of a substantive theory of concepts to explain certain facts about informativeness and uninformativeness concerning particular concepts. A third virtue of the initial characterization is that it brings out a phenomenon whose significance is insufficiently appreciated. There is a phenomenon of productivity for thought about mental states that is just as striking as the original phenomenon of the productivity of conceptual thought about the non‐mental world. If a thinker possesses the concepts for forming the Thought that p, and has the concept of the propositional attitude ψ, then he is capable of judging contents of the form x ψ s that p. This holds for arbitrary contents p and attitudes ψ, whatever the constituents of p, and however complex p may be. This is something that calls for a correspondingly general explanation. It could be called ‘the second‐level productivity challenge’.

Page 3 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions The intuitive way‐of‐thinking and that‐clause mode of introducing concepts are very far from determining what concepts are. Very different kinds of entity, and in some cases fundamentally none at all, have been proposed as concepts by theorists who would accept these modes of introducing concepts. There are broadly three very different kinds of theory consistent with such approaches. (1) On theories of the first kind, concepts are abstract objects. This was the classical Fregean thesis: the concepts are amongst the inhabitants of the third realm, distinct, according to Frege, from both the physical and the mental. Frege said very (p. 440) little about what it is for a thinker to stand in a relation to an element of the third realm. The view of concepts as abstract objects does not need to have them standing in such proud isolation from thinkers as, apparently, Frege did (a). A concept considered as individuated by the condition a thinker must meet to possess the concept can still be an abstract object; but manifestly under that conception concepts are not individuated independently of their possible relations to thinkers (b). If there are such things as object‐dependent concepts, or property‐dependent concepts, by whatever reasoning, these will be what Quine called impure abstract objects, individuated in part by their relations to what they are concepts of (c). A theorist could also reject the idea that concepts are individuated by possession conditions, but still think they are individuated by some other relation to thinkers. You do not have to believe that concepts are individuated by possession conditions to reject Frege's conception of the third realm as utterly independent of thinkers. (2) According to theories of the second kind, concepts are mental representations. Mental representations are particulars located in time and space. These representations may have syntactic properties, and will have a variety of semantic properties, including conceptual content. Theorists of this second stripe are rarely concerned only with syntactic properties. They are commonly eager to acknowledge that two thinkers may have different mental representations of different syntactic types, but with the same conceptual content. (3) Under the third approach, talk of concepts is legitimized by a grammatical transformation from sentences that do not explicitly talk about concepts. This is a version of what Stephen Schiffer, the theorist who developed this approach, calls a ‘pleonastic’ conception. We may, on this view, legitimately rewrite John believes elephants can swim as

John stands in the belief‐relation to the Thought elephants can swim. We can equally rewrite it as

John believes the Thought consisting of the concept *elephants* in predicational combination with the complex concept *can swim*.

Page 4 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions But, on this view, there is no more to concepts than is legitimized by the underlying true sentences that legitimize talk of concepts. Talk of concepts is, to that extent, like talk about the average resident of New York and that resident's properties. It is a legitimate grammatical fiction; it is nothing more than that.

What is the relation between these three styles of approach? Now certainly there is nothing that is at once both an abstract object, and a mental particular, and a grammatical fiction. All the same, these three kinds of view should not be seen as in every case competing with the others. A theorist can recognize both the abstract and the mental representation views as legitimate classifications, each appropriately cited in explaining different phenomena. When, for example, we are concerned with timeless facts about what is informative in what circumstances, that is best explained by (p. 441) concepts conceived at the abstract level. The properties of particular mental representations are irrelevant to their explanation. When we are concerned with the contingencies of the interaction of particular mental representations in a particular type of mind, or in a particular species, or in a given individual, those contingencies will not be present in all possible mental representations with a given conceptual content. Correspondingly, it would be quite inadequate to try to cite only conceptual content considered on the abstract model in their explanation. It is tempting to generalize here. We can formulate the hypothesis that, in so far as explanation in either domain is feasible, purely philosophical explanation of timeless truths will appeal to the first conception of concept, and psychological explanation of wholly empirical phenomena will appeal to the second conception. That may be fine as far as it goes, but it is important to see that some of the most interesting and live interdisciplinary cases are neither purely philosophical nor wholly empirical. Take the case of the empirical explanation of a thinker's acquisition of a concept. That is an empirical phenomenon with a historical explanation. But a highly attractive view is that the explanation must take the form of showing how the thinker comes to meet the possession condition for a concept. That a given concept has a certain possession condition is not, on many conceptions, an empirical matter. So on any of those conceptions, the historical explanation of acquisition is a mixed case, drawing both on empirical facts and philosophical principles about what it is to possess a given concept. The third, pleonastic, conception is a radically different animal from the other two. It seems clear that the idea of concepts as having any explanatory power is one that the pleonastic conception must in a wide range of cases reject. This is acknowledged by its proponents, and I will return to consider this position separately.

26.2 Concepts and Rationality Anyone who uses Frege's informativeness criterion, at whatever level, as a necessary and sufficient condition for the distinctness of concepts is committed to the existence of some connection between identity of concepts and rationality. As a sufficient condition, the Page 5 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Frege criterion is simply a consequence of Leibniz's Law, that if x = y, then something is a property of x iff it is a property of y. Suppose concept C has the property of being an element of a complete content, formed by placing it in the frame A( ), that is informative, in given circumstances, for a thinker. If concept D lacks this property, that is, if A(D) is uninformative in those same circumstances, then C has a property D lacks: by Leibniz's Law, C is distinct from D. The only way of blocking this argument is by insisting that attitudes are not relations to complete contents built up from concepts. In the reverse direction, Frege's criterion is not a general law applicable to all entities. It is something specific to concepts that if C and D are distinct concepts, then there must be some circumstances or other and some frame A( ) or other, such that (p. 442) in those circumstances a thinker can rationally judge A(C) without rationally judging A(D). For any given concept there is a distinctive pattern that captures certain facts about rationality that involve the concept. It is distinctive of the concept red that a shade in a certain range, when experienced by the thinker in ordinary circumstances as the shade of a perceived object, makes it rational for the thinker to judge ‘That thing is red’ without any intervening inference. Experiencing a pain can make it rational for a thinker to judge ‘I'm in pain’ without any inference; whereas the same circumstances do not by themselves, without reliance on an inference, make it rational for the subject to judge ‘The person living at 27 Elm Street is in pain’ (not even if he is the person living at 27 Elm Street, for that rationally requires the further premise ‘I am the person living at 27 Elm Street’). If the thinker already accepts that p and that q, that can make it rational without further premises to conclude that p & q. That does not make it rational, without further inference, for the thinker to conclude that ∼(∼p v ∼q). We can summarize the distinctive facts about a concept's involvement in rationality in what we can call the concept's rationality profile. Take a concept C, and consider all the pairs such that in circumstances S it is rational for the thinker to judge A(C), without any intermediate inferences or transitions, if he possesses the concept C. The set of all such pairs I call the rationality profile of the concept C. We can also speak of the rationality profile of sets of concepts. The rationality profile of the pair of concepts C, D is the set of all pairs such that in circumstances S it is rational for the thinker to judge A′(C, D), without any intermediate inferences or transitions, if he possesses the concepts C and D. So the rationality profile of the pair of concepts pain and the first‐person concept I includes the pair . The point just made earlier was that the rationality profile of pain and the person living at 27 Elm Street does not include the pair . Is there an explanation of why a given concept, or pair of concepts, has the rationality profile it has? Is there an explanation of why sets of concepts have the rationality profile they do? It is better to have some explanation of such facts if we can attain it. Besides the virtue of achieving explanation of the eternal, timeless facts of rationality profiles, there is also a gain in psychological explanation if we can explain the rationality profile. The rationality profile is an open‐ended, and arguably infinite, set. If we can provide an Page 6 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions explanation of the profile, we will be on the way to explaining how finite thinkers can attain rationality (in so far as they can). We will also be on the way to explaining how thinkers can reliably classify some judgements as rational in the relevant circumstances and others as not. In attempting to explain some or all features of a rationality profile, we need to draw some distinctions between different explananda. First, some of what is included in a rationality profile will be capturing what it is rational to judge, where the rationality of the judgement is completely insensitive to the content of the judgement, and applies to a vast range of contents indifferently. So, for instance, it is widely held that, other things being equal, it is rational to take the deliverances of propositional memory at face value. If you seem to remember that p, then in the absence of reasons (p. 443) for doubt it is rational to judge that p. This will be reflected in the rationality profile of every concept. For that reason, the explanation of the rationality, if there is one, cannot be specific to the particular concepts comprising the content p. Explanation by the nature of particular concepts we should expect to be specific to phenomena displayed distinctively by those particular concepts. Even when we restrict our attention to phenomena displayed by specific concepts, we should distinguish between the goal of inclusion and the goal of exhaustion. To aim at exhaustive explanation is to try to explain all the facts about rationality specific to a concept by the nature of that concept. This is a bold and possibly extreme project. Its feasibility forms the subject matter of open question 1 in the philosophical theory of concepts; to wit: Can all aspects of rationality specific to a given concept or to a given type of concept be explained in terms of the nature or that concept, or of that type of concept? Here I mention open question 1, which is concerned with exhaustion, partly just to distinguish it from the goal of inclusion, according to which there are some facts about rationality specific to a concept that we can explain from the nature of a concept, even if not all such facts are thus explicable. To aim for inclusion seems to be a modest, reasonable enterprise.

A content is known only if it comes to be accepted by rational means. If concepts have a link with rationality, they are thereby pertinent to epistemology too. Open question 2 is: How should we conceive of the relation between concepts and knowledge? Some theorists go so far as to say that some concepts should be individuated in terms of the conditions under which certain contents containing them are known. One way of elaborating that approach is to hold that outright judgement aims at knowledge, so that individuating concepts in terms of certain judgements is necessarily individuating them in terms of contributions to conditions for knowledge. Open question 2 must include consideration of whether the connections between concepts and knowledge are deep or superficial, and, in either case, what their source is.

When we talk about an explanation of facts about rationality or knowledge drawing upon the nature of a concept, what do we, or what should we, mean? The nature of a particular concept will be given by a theory that says something specific about that concept, not Page 7 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions something applicable to all concepts. This will be a substantive theory of a specific concept. Such a substantive theory need not be reductive of the concept; it may be about concepts as abstract objects or about concepts as mental representations; it certainly need not offer a definition of the concept; and it need not aim to eliminate or reduce propositional‐attitude vocabulary to something else. A tempting model for constructing substantive theories of particular concepts is given by the distinction between primitive and derived rules in systems of natural deduction (most famously formulated, developed, and made objects of study by Gentzen and later Prawitz). For the case of some logical constants, the idea is that the primitive rules can already be transformed into statements of what (p. 444) substantively individuates those logical concepts. The introduction rule for the material conditional contributes to a statement of what it is to possess that concept: the thinker must find instances of that rule compelling, without any intermediate inference. That is why the move from a derivation of B from A to acceptance of the material conditional A→B is one a thinker must be rationally willing to make, according to this theory; whereas Pierce's Law, ((A → B) → A) → A, though a theorem of classical logic, is informative. It can be reached only by a series of steps that are individually compelling. For empirical concepts, we can consider how the model might be developed for Frege's example of Afla and Ateb. ‘Afla’ is introduced to refer to a mountain seen from one direction in one location, ‘Ateb’ for a mountain seen from an entirely different location. The thought ‘Afla = Ateb’ is informative; it would not be in the rationality profile for either the concept Afla, or the concept Ateb, or for the pair of them. ‘That's Afla’ would be in the rationality profile for Afla when the demonstrative expresses a perceptual‐ demonstrative concept of a mountain seen from the location at which the name was introduced. By a series of individually obvious steps, in this case using empirical information, one way of coming rationally to reach the truth that Afla = Ateb is to keep track of the mountain while travelling. At successive times the thinker makes judgements of the form ‘This is still Afla’ as he travels. Eventually our thinker reaches a judgement ‘This is still Afla’, where this most recent demonstrative expresses a perceptual‐ demonstrative concept for which ‘This is Ateb’ is in the rationality profile of the concept Ateb. If our thinker has come to learn ‘This is Afla’ and ‘This is Ateb’ (for the same demonstrative concept and context), he is in a position to infer ‘Afla = Ateb’. For any case to which the model of primitive and derived rules is to be applied, one must identify some plausible primitive rules, and explain how they account for those parts of the rationality profile of the concept that are subject to the explanation. If the concept has primitively rational uses beyond, for instance, the perception‐based cases, the possession condition must be expanded to cover them too (and their relation to the other primitive cases must be satisfactorily explained). Various observational concepts, logical concepts, and certain sensation concepts have been accorded treatments of this kind.

Page 8 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Even for the more limited goal of explaining inclusion, rather than exhaustion, there are at least three problems with the primitive/derived model of the nature of concepts as so far described, and they all raise deep issues. First, there are many examples of concepts which, it seems, cannot be fitted into the primitive/derived‐rule mould. Some concepts, and perhaps even some logical concepts, are such that all the primitive rules that are correct for them seem also to be informative. It seems that a thinker has to reflect, to work out that they are correct. This seems to be true even for so fundamental a concept as that of negation. The classical natural‐ deduction systems give an introduction rule for negation, commonly some form of reductio, and some form of double‐negation elimination as the elimination rule. Both of these are principles one has to reflect upon to appreciate their correctness. It is not at all like the acceptance of ‘That's Afla’ in the canonical (p. 445) circumstances of the name's introduction, or like ‘That's red’ where the perceptual demonstrative picks out an object given as having what is definitely a shade of red. Whatever the nature of this transition to a rational appreciation of these primitive laws about negation, in making the transition the thinker certainly seems to draw on his grasp of the concept of negation. It follows that understanding of negation should not be identified with willingness to accept instances of those rules. At the very least, grasp of negation explains rational acceptance of those rules (and nothing can explain itself). A different type of treatment of negation is that given by Rumfitt, in which deduction rules are given for propositions ‘signed’ with ‘yes’ or ‘no’. In this approach, some of the rules for negation do indeed have a much more primitive character, and the approach is of great logical interest. The sense of negation and the significance of ‘no’ seem, however, to be too tightly intertwined, even inextricable, for this to be a substantive explication of the concept of negation. (The problem of informativeness of the primitive rules also arises for connectives other than negation under this approach.) Second, there is what I have called ‘the phenomenon of new principles’. It seems that sometimes a thinker can come, by rational reflection involving a concept he grasps, to accept principles that do not follow from primitive principles he already accepts, by inferential principles he already accepts. That no natural number has infinitely many predecessors is arguably one such principle. Eventual acceptance of the epsilon‐delta style definition of the limit of a series of fractions is another. This definition was informative for those who had been using the notion of a limit for decades. The definition was not even know to Newton and Leibniz, the originators of the notion of the limit of a series. When there is such rational acceptance of a new principle, we need quite a different account of the identity and possession of a concept than is given in the primitive/derived‐rule model. One resource here is the idea that a thinker's grasp of a concept consists in tacit knowledge of some condition governing the concept. The reflective thinker draws on this tacit knowledge, or implicit conception, in classifying cases. But to articulate the content of the tacit knowledge explicitly, the thinker must

Page 9 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions engage in abductive inference from cases. This is equally what we have to do when we succeed in articulating syntactic and semantic rules of which we have tacit knowledge. The third problem with the primitive/derived‐rule model as so far described is that it fails to address a question that any positive theory of concepts must address. The primitive/ derived‐rule model is attempting to account for facts about rationality. But what is it for a judgement to be rational in given circumstances? What is the aim that is furthered by judging in accordance with primitive and derived rules for a concept? Even if there are some concepts for which the model of primitive and derived rules fully captures the facts about rationality specific to each of those concepts, we are still lacking an explanation of why this is sufficient for judgements made in accordance with those rules to be rational. It is here that we have to face the fundamental question of the relation between concepts on the one hand and truth and reference on the other.

(p. 446)

26.3 Concepts, Truth, and Reference

Truth has seemed to many theorists (though not to all) to be at least one of the aims of rational judgement. Amongst those who accept that truth is an aim of rational judgement, we can distinguish two radically different kinds of view. (1) There is the classical view that a substantive conception of truth and reference plays an ineliminable part in individuating conceptual content. On this view, if a concept is individuated on the primitive/derived‐rule model it is a real, non‐trivial task to show that judging in accordance with those rules furthers the goal of judging only what is true. (2) There is the view that although it is correct to accept the proposition that rational judgement aims at truth, this states no substantive constraint on a theory of conceptual content. There are many different varieties of this non‐substantive view. One variety holds that rationality consists in judging in accordance with certain rules or conceptual roles, of one sort or another. Under views of this sort there is no genuine task of showing that judging in accordance with the rules leads to true judgements. This type of view is commonly combined with a minimalist theory of truth in general, one that aims to say that there is no more to truth than can be explained in terms of a careful elaboration of the disquotational schema. (If more than that were involved in truth, there would still remain a substantive task of explaining the rationality of the conceptual roles and rules that are used in individuating concepts.) Conversely, of course, those who accept minimalist theories of truth and reference will agree that constraints involving reference and truth cannot play the same role in ratifying rules as rational that they do on the classical view. Variants of such a minimalism are held by such different thinkers as Brandom, Field, Harman, and Horwich.

Page 10 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions An even more radical rejection of the idea of explaining rationality by reference to features of intentional content is provided by thinkers who hold that no substantive theory of conceptual content, whether given in terms of truth‐conditions or in terms of some favoured kind of conceptual role, can be given at all. This highly sceptical position is found in the later writings of Schiffer, and in one of Johnston's early papers. Not all theorists accept even that truth is an aim of judgement. Some have said that the aim of assertion is warranted assertibility. A corresponding position in the theory of thought holds that judgement aims at warranted judgement. Sometimes this position has been held in combination with substantive theories of conceptual content (thus for example Davidson) and sometimes not. The problem for this position is that in general, warrant cannot be elucidated independently of reference and truth. For it is not plausible that we can unify the specific conditions that give warrant for judging a given content without mentioning the references of the concepts in the content. In general it is an empirical matter what warrants judgement of a given content. The empirical condition that must be met for something to be a warrant for the content is that it gives evidence that objects referred to in the content have the (p. 447) properties and relations specified in the content. I discuss this crux further in the next paragraph but one. Two types of challenge exist for those who hold that reference and truth have no substantial role to play in the individuation of concepts. One challenge for those who think that concepts can be individuated purely in terms of rules is to explain which sets of rules determine concepts. It is widely agreed that not all sets of rules determine concepts. Some theorists have argued that only rules that satisfy a conservative‐extension requirement succeed in determining concepts. If we formulate it at the level of language, the conservative‐extension requirement states that, after the introduction of a new expression and rules governing it to an old language and old set of rules, one cannot prove anything formulated purely in the old language that one could not prove without the new expression and new rules. The necessity and sufficiency of conservative extension as such a requirement has been disputed by those who argue for a more substantial role for reference and truth in the individuation of concepts. The issues are in part technical, and I will not discuss them in detail here. The other type of challenge is not technical. When we consider contents about the past, or about other places, or predications about objects currently perceived that concern the way they were at other times, we face a challenge if we do not invoke reference and truth in the explanation of concept possession. It seems that we understand such predications without thereby knowing what would be evidence for them, or what the consequences of their truth might be. Told that it rained here yesterday, or that it is raining in the north of Scotland now, or that this computer was made in Taiwan, or that some other creature is in pain, you have to work out what might be evidence for these various conditions. You also have to work out what would be consequences of their holding. Simply grasping these contents does not tell you what such evidence or consequences would be. It follows that no particular evidential conditions or conditions about consequences should be written into an account of what it is to grasp these conditions. This makes it a problem Page 11 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions what a conceptual‐role account of these contents that does not make reference to reference or truth could possibly be. By contrast, if we are allowed to use reference and truth in our account of content, we can give a highly intuitive account of grasp of content in all of these cases. For it to be raining here yesterday is for yesterday to have the same property as today has to have when it is raining here today; that is, the property referred to in ‘It's raining here today’ must be instantiated yesterday for the past‐tense thought to be true. For ‘This computer was made in Taiwan’ to be true, the same object referred to by ‘this computer’ must also have been made in Taiwan. And so forth. If we are allowed to use reference, truth, and identity in the explication of these contents, we have a simple explanation of what has to be grasped in understanding them. It is a prediction of this account that it is an empirical matter what would be evidence for the holding of these conditions. For it is an empirical matter what would be evidence that the same property was instantiated yesterday at this place; an empirical matter what would be evidence that this object was made in Taiwan; and so forth. This point incidentally also shows that we cannot even elucidate the conditions of warranted assertibility or judgement, at least for these contents, without involving reference and truth. (p. 448)

So here is open question 3 about concepts: What is the role of reference and truth in the individuation of concepts? Are the points we have just made for concepts of other times, other places, and other subjects of experience universal, applicable to all concepts at some point, or do they apply only to a special subclass? In either case, what is their epistemic significance?

26.4 Conceptual and Non‐Conceptual Content Earlier in this chapter I described the task of distinguishing conceptual content from non‐ conceptual content as ‘the characterization problem’. The content of perceptual states is the paradigm of non‐conceptual content. The nature of the perceptual content is naturally given in a quite different way from that of conceptual content. In the case of the spatial senses, such as vision, the content of a perception is given in part by specifying how the space around the perceiver has to be filled out for the perceptual state to be veridical. That is, the content is given in part by specifying a spatial type, as anchored to a particular subject and time. Even for non‐spatial senses, such as monaural hearing, the content is given in part by specifying how a period of time is filled out with events of certain kinds. This type of content seems quite different from the content of structured, complete propositional contents built up from concepts. These conceptual contents have a tree‐like structure. According to Frege's classical view, the tree‐like sentential

Page 12 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions structures of language ‘mirror’ the tree‐like structure of Thoughts built up from concepts (Frege's senses). Given this difference between perceptual content and conceptual content, it is natural to try to solve the characterization problem by saying that what is distinctive of complete conceptual contents is that their mental representations have sentence‐like structure. This suggestion seems however to be necessary but not sufficient for the content in question to be conceptual. In microbiology, it is not difficult to conceive of molecular structures that either command the building of, or contain information about, more complex molecules, where the commanding or informational molecules themselves have sentence‐like structure. But these would not be mental representations with conceptual content (although they certainly have some kind of content). So what more do we need to mention to attain a sufficient condition for the content's being conceptual? It cannot be a matter of the content's having objective correctness conditions. That is something that is present also in non‐conceptual content. The distinguishing feature cannot be the possibility in conceptual thought of one and the same object, or one and the same property, being given in different ways. There seem to be analogues of that distinction in non‐conceptual perceptual content. We can conceive of an animal that is not capable of conceptual thought seeing a shape as a square rather than as a regular diamond. We have also already noted that we (p. 449) equally use that‐clauses in ascribing perceptual content (a fact which, incidentally, means that the view that a concept can be extracted from any use of a that‐clause is incorrect). I suggest that conceptual contents are rather distinguished by the fact that their constituents are individuated in part by reference to the reasons that the subject may have for being in states involving them. The reasons may be described in terms of their relations to tacit knowledge of reference‐conditions. A thinker does not have reasons for being in perceptual states. A perception is not a mental action of the subject, unlike a judgement. A subject can intend to bring about a certain state of affairs specified by non‐ conceptual content, and of course may have reasons for that intention. But the content of his intention exists only because it also has a life, by which it is individuated, in the non‐ conceptual content of perceptual states. For perceptual states, the question of the subject's reasons for being in them does not arise. Conceptual content is commonly regarded as having various additional characteristics. It is content acceptance of which is rationally reviewable, critically assessable by the thinker. It is also often suggested that conceptual content, unlike objective perceptual content, is content that is conceived of by the thinker as objective. This allows us to formulate open question 4: Is there some unified explanation of the range of apparent characteristics of conceptual content? Do all these characteristics flow from the idea of concepts as individuated in part by reasons for being in states involving them?

Page 13 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions

26.5 Concepts and External Individuation Many concepts are externally individuated. This is a constitutive claim. It says that the relations to the world external to the subject's body (and sometimes to the subject's body itself) of mental states involving such a concept contribute to a determination of the identity of the concept—not the reference, but the concept under which the reference is thought about. Viewed from sufficient distance, one should not be at all surprised that concepts are externally individuated. Consider what is explained by intentional states with conceptual content, the states of intention, emotion, values, judgement, and desire. What is explained by such intentional states is a set of relational properties of a person. As the person goes through his day, these states will explain his relations to people—whom he seeks out, what he says to them; to locations, to buildings, to institutions; to objects, events, and states of affairs. Such relational explananda require relational explaining conditions. States that are not externally individuated would not by themselves be suitable to explaining relational facts. Since a subject could, empirically, be in such non‐externally individuated states but not bear any particular relations to external locations, people, and things, they could at best (p. 450) explain his actions described in environmentally neutral terms. They would not be up to explaining actions in relation to locations, people, and things our subject encounters. Correspondingly, they would not by themselves support counterfactuals or predictions about the subject's relations to these things, counterfactuals and predictions that we rely upon every hour as a result of our attributing intentional states with particular conceptual contents to our friends (and to our enemies). There are several ways in which external individuation of a concept can show up in a concept's possession condition. One of the most basic ways is for the concept to be individuated by its relations to perceptual states with non‐conceptual content, where that non‐conceptual content is itself externally individuated. That is arguably the case for basic spatial, temporal, and other observational concepts such as bent, spotted, yellow, preceded, and the like. The properties picked out by these concepts enter the representational content of spatial and temporal experience. What makes these properties the ones that enter the content of experience is, arguably, that when the perceiver is properly connected to the world around him, it is the instantiation of these properties that causes experiences with these contents, by and large. If an observational concept is individuated in part by the fact that someone who possesses it must be willing to apply it to an object presented in an experience with the corresponding non‐conceptual content, the external individuation of the non‐conceptual content will be transmitted to external individuation of the observational concept.

Page 14 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions This is not the only way external individuation may arise. Another famous way is for the possession condition for a concept to involve a commitment to its instances being of the same underlying natural kind as instances commonly encountered, even if that underlying kind is not yet known (Kripke, Putnam). Yet another is for a thinker's use of a concept, as ordinarily ascribed, to be deferential to whatever is meant by the term for the concept in his linguistic community (Burge). There may also be cases that we can describe as externalism within the mind itself. What makes the concept pain the concept it is is partly that the thinker is willing to apply the concept to himself in rational response to his own pains. Whether a thinker is in pain is something that supervenes on what is going on inside the boundaries of his body, including his brain. But if we imagine an internal boundary, between states with intentional contents, and the subjective conscious sensations like pains, it seems clear that what gives those intentional states contents involving the concept pain is their relations to sensations at the other side of the boundary. That is, we have what we can call a kind of internal externalism within the mind itself. There are many ramifications of the external individuation of concepts. One ramification concerns the nature of a subpersonal psychology that explains how thinkers come to be in conceptual states. If those states are externally individuated, so must at least some of the subpersonal states that explain how thinkers come to be in these conceptual states be externally individuated. This applies in particular to a subpersonal computational psychology. Another ramification concerns epistemic norms. Prima facie, by considerations similar to those already outlined, only externally individuated states can give a thinker reason to make judgements with conceptual contents that are externally (p. 451) individuated. This gives us a further question, which has to be regarded as still open, despite the contributions that have already been made to answering it in the recent literature; namely, open question 5: What is the correct account of the relation between external individuation of mental states, epistemic norms for judging given conceptual content, and the identity of the concepts in that content?

26.6 Pleonastic Conceptual Content? On the treatment of Schiffer, propositions (henceforth, Thoughts) are pleonastic entities. They are introduced by what he calls ‘something‐from‐nothing’ transformations. To say That Lassie is a dog is true is just an equivalent of

Page 15 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Lassie is a dog. The introduction of talk explicitly about Thoughts gives, according to Schiffer, a conservative extension of a theory that does not talk about them (with various technical qualifications). ‘Merely adding propositions does nothing to disturb the pre‐existing causal order; as properties are shadows of predicates, so propositions are shadows of sentences’ (2003: 71). If the pleonastic account is correct, much of the previous discussion of this chapter is misconceived. It is simply a mistake to think either that there can or that there need be a substantive theory of the nature of concepts. They no more have a substantive nature than does the average man.

According to this pleonastic conception, when someone utters a sentence stating that a subject stands in the belief relation to a Thought or proposition, then, to quote Schiffer: we first have a contextual determination of the criteria for truth‐evaluating the utterance, and it is these criteria which determine the referent of the that‐clause, and thereby (at least in part) the proposition asserted by the entire belief report. What this means is that in the case of the belief report, you don't evaluate the utterance by first determining the proposition expressed by it; rather, you first have contextually determined criteria of evaluation that are statable without reference to the proposition asserted by the belief report, and it is these contextually determined criteria which determine, as though by an afterthought, what proposition is asserted in the belief report. (2003: 74–5) Schiffer also argues that we know that propositions p and q are distinct because we know that it is possible for someone, for instance, to doubt p without doubting q. Our knowledge proceeds thus, rather than moving from the distinctness of the propositions to the possibility of doubting one without doubting the other (2003: 77).

The pleonastic conception faces the following objections. (p. 452)

The first objection flows from considerations of finitude. There are infinitely many sentences of the form ‘a believes that p’ that we understand, for each of the infinitely many possible substitutions for ‘p’. How do we finite beings have this infinitary capacity? If the contents expressed by the substituends for ‘p’ are, after they have been contextually determined, built up from finitely many conceptual constituents by finitely many modes of combination, we have a finitary basis for the infinitary capacity. But there is no such substantive composition by conceptual constituents on the pleonastic view. If what Schiffer calls the ‘contextually determined criteria for truth evaluation’ of a belief report do not rely on such substantively compositional Thoughts, they have not been finitely specified. One can compare the situation with the position of someone who says that there are contextually determined criteria for determining what it is that someone is saying when he utters the embedded sentence p. However much contextual determination goes on— and a lot does, I agree—if what is determined is not a structured Thought or proposition, Page 16 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions we have the classical problem of explaining how finite resources allow us to understand a potential infinity of sentences. The problem recurs for intentional contexts on the pleonastic view. To be fair to Schiffer, I should note that his view is that there is no problem for unembedded sentences either, as he argued, controversially, two decades ago. The second objection is that intuitively the criteria for evaluating the truth of, to take Schiffer's example, belief reports do plausibly rely on the attributee's meeting the possession condition for certain concepts, and his employing those concepts in his attitudes. If we attribute a first‐person belief to a thinker, the thinker must meet the possession condition for the first‐person way of thinking, and that way of thinking must be used by the thinker if, for instance, it is true that he believes ‘I am hungry’. It is the possession condition for the first‐person concept, and its role in his belief, that makes the difference between the criteria for evaluating the truth of the utterance ‘Peter believes he himself is hungry’ and the criteria for evaluating the truth of the utterance ‘Peter believes Smith is hungry’. Third, it should be agreed that one way, even in a sense a fundamental way, of coming to know that p and q are distinct Thoughts or propositions is to appreciate that someone can believe or doubt one without believing or doubting the other. But this fact can be explained on theories of conceptual content other than the pleonastic conception. The fact is a consequence of possession‐condition theories of concepts, when these are constrained by considerations of epistemic possibility, and take themselves as answerable to the goal of explaining examples of Frege's informativeness criterion. Possession‐ condition theories individuate a concept F by some condition of the form ‘F is that concept C to possess which a thinker must meet condition A(C)’, possibly with one or another favoured restriction on the condition A( … ). The concepts C quantified over here are already in the ontology being employed, and are conceived of as constituents of other complex contents of various kinds that may also be mentioned in the condition A( … ). Such complex contents would be mentioned if the possession condition for a logical concept speaks of the concept's role in certain logical transitions between complete contents of (p. 453) certain forms containing the concept, or speaks of tacit knowledge of contribution to a truth‐condition. So what individuates the concepts, on this approach, is not a condition which meets the requirement of the pleonastic conception. There is no involvement here of a something‐for‐nothing transformation. But still it follows from this kind of possession‐condition theory, and the constraints to which it is answerable, that a fundamental means of coming to know that thoughts or propositions are distinct, and a constraint on what individuates them, is that it is possible to judge or doubt one without judging or doubting the other. It is not only the pleonastic approach that offers an explanation of this fact. Space prevents a full consideration of the interesting issues about conservative extension. But I do briefly observe that if the considerations of the earlier section about external individuation of conceptual content and the role of conceptual states in explanation is correct, then it is not at all obvious that talk about mental states with conceptual content Page 17 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions conservatively extends talk which does not mention concepts. States with conceptual content allow the explanation of events under relational descriptions, descriptions under which they would not otherwise be explained; and similarly for environment‐involving counterfactuals about thinkers and their conceptual states.

26.7 Canonical ways of Thinking of Concepts Whenever we possess a concept, of whatever category, such as the singular concept that cat, the predicative concept is grey, the logical concept or, and so forth, we also have the ability to think of that concept in a canonical way—as the concept that cat, as the concept is grey, and so forth. We use these canonical concepts of concepts whenever we theorize about concepts. It is also arguable that, on any broadly Fregean approach to these issues, we use these canonical concepts of concepts when attributing attitudes to others. When we judge that Peter believes that that cat is grey, in the simplest case, in which Peter uses these concepts himself, we are referring to the concepts he employs, and we are using these canonical ways of thinking of these concepts. What is the relation between a concept and the canonical concept of a concept? This is a question to which we need an answer if we are fully to understand our capacity to attribute attitudes to others and to ourselves. An answer to the question faces several challenges. One is already visible. A concept seems somehow to determine a canonical concept of itself. Yet the canonical concept of a concept such as cat can hardly be identical with the concept cat itself. After all, they have different extensions: one refers to a concept, the other to cats. But concepts and their references stand in a many–one relation. If the canonical concept is not identical with the concept to which it refers, what then is the relation between them, and how are canonical concepts of concepts possible? That is open question 6. An (p. 454) answer to it must also explain how, whether we think of concepts as abstract objects or as mental representations, we are able to think about and, apparently, know things about concepts. As for every other domain, we must eventually be able to integrate our metaphysics, our epistemology, and our theory of thought for the domain of concepts themselves.

References Introductory On concepts (Frege's senses) as ways of thinking of things, tied to considerations of cognitive significance see Dummett, M. (1973), Frege: Philosophy of Language (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

Page 18 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Frege, G. (1892/1993), ‘On Sense and Reference’, repr. in A. Moore (ed.), Meaning and Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 23–42. —— (1918–1919/1977), ‘Thoughts’, in P. Geach (ed.), Logical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell), 1–30. For emphasis on the idea that a concept or sense is individuated by the fundamental condition for something to be its reference see Dummett, M. (1981), The Interpretation of Frege's Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press). For theories that in one way or another quantify over concepts or modes of presentation in their account of the attribution of attitudes in language see Crimmins, M., and Perry, J. (1989), ‘The Prince and the Phone Booth: Reporting Puzzling Beliefs’, Journal of Philosophy, 86: 685–711. Schiffer, S. (1992), ‘Belief Ascription’, Journal of Philosophy, 89: 499–521. For concepts as abstract objects individuated by their possession conditions see Peacocke, C. (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). For concepts considered primarily as mental representations see Fodor, J. (1998), Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong (Oxford: Oxford University Press). For a treatment of complete conceptual contents as pleonastic entities, and for a corresponding version of a minimalism about concepts and meaning see Johnston, M. (1988), ‘The End of the Theory of Meaning’, Mind and Language, 3: 28–42. Schiffer, S. (1987), Remnants of Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2003), The Things We Mean (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Concepts and Rationality For a conception of possession conditions as explaining some aspects of rationality profiles see Peacocke, C. (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2004), The Realm of Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Page 19 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions On judgement as aiming at knowledge see Peacocke, C. (1999), Being Known (Oxford: Oxford University Press). (p. 455)

Williamson, T. (2000), Knowledge and Its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University

Press). Wilson, J. C. (1926), Statement and Inference (Oxford: Oxford University Press). For natural‐deduction systems as the model on which some possession‐condition accounts are based, the classical source is Genzten, G. (1970), The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, ed. M. Szabo (Amsterdam: North‐Holland). Rumfitt's treatment of logical connectives by relating them to propositions signed by ‘yes’ or by ‘no’ is given in Rumfitt, I. (2000), ‘“Yes” and “No”’, Mind, 109: 781–823. Frege gives the example of Afla and Ateb in an apparently undated letter to Jourdain, which is reprinted in translation in A. W. Moore (ed.), Meaning and Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993). A collection of examples and a treatment that proposes implicit conceptions as significant for the individuation of some families of concepts is given in Peacocke, C. (1998), ‘Implicit Conceptions, Understanding and Rationality’, Philosophical Issues, 9: 45–88.

Concepts, Truth and Reference For the view that truth and reference play an ineliminable role in concept possession see Peacocke, C. (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2005), ‘Justification, Realism and the Past’, Mind, 114: 639–70. For the view that truth and reference play no fundamental role in concept possession and understanding, in addition to the works of Johnston and Schiffer listed above, see Brandom, R. (2000), Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Field, H. (1977), ‘Logic, Meaning and Conceptual Role’, Journal of Philosophy, 74: 379– 409.

Page 20 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions Harman, G. (1987), ‘(Non‐solipsistic) Conceptual Role Semantics’, in E. LePore (ed.), New Directions in Semantics (London: Academic), 55–81; repr. in Harman, Reasoning, Meaning and Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 206–33. Horwich, P. (1998), Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Conceptual and Non‐Conceptual Content On the non‐conceptual content of perception see Heck, R. (2000), ‘Nonconceptual content and “The space of reasons”’, Philosophical Review, 109: 483–523. Peacocke, C. (2001), ‘Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?’, Journal of Philosophy, 98: 239–64. For a contrary view see McDowell, J. (1994), Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

Concepts and External Individuation For writings on the external individuation of intentional content see Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. —— (2003) ‘Perceptual Entitlement’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67: 503–48. (p. 456)

Peacocke, C. (1993), ‘Externalist Explanation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian

Society, 93: 203–30. —— (2004), The Realm of Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Putnam, H. (1973), ‘Meaning and Reference’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 699–711.

Pleonastic Conceptual Content The principal sources are the books by Schiffer and the paper by Johnston cited above. For Schiffer's views on the explanation of the understanding of unembedded sentences see Schiffer, S. (1991), ‘Does Mentalese Have a Compositional Semantics?’, in B. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics (Oxford: Blackwell), 181–99.

Page 21 of 22

Concepts and Possession Conditions See the reply by Jerry Fodor in the same volume; and also the exchange between Schiffer and Peacocke in Mind and Language, 1 (1986); and for similar views see Horwich, P. (1998), Meaning (Oxford: Oxford University Press). On canonical concepts of concepts see Burge, T. (2005), Truth, Thought, Reason: Essays on Frege (Oxford: Oxford University Press), in particular the essay ‘Frege and the Hierarchy’ and the important ‘Postscript’. Peacocke, C. (2009), ‘Frege's Hierarchy: A Puzzle’, in P. Leonardi (ed.), Essays in Honor of David Kaplan (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Notes: (*) An earlier version of this chapter formed part of an overview presented at the joint Columbia–Rutgers Seminar on Concepts I gave jointly with Jerry Fodor in the fall of 2005; I thank him for comments and advice. For further development of some of the views in this chapter see my more recent book Truly Understood (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).

Christopher Peacocke

Christopher Peacocke, Columbia University and University College, London

Page 22 of 22

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content

Oxford Handbooks Online The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content   José Luis Bermúdez The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0028

Abstract and Keywords The terminology of the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction was originally introduced by Gareth Evans to clarify the relation between perceptual states and what Evans termed the ‘reasoning and concept-applying system’. Evans's basic idea that perceptual experiences represent the environment in a manner independent of the perceiver's conceptual repertoire has antecedents in Dretske's distinction between analogue content and digital content. This way of using the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction has been developed most systematically by Christopher Peacocke, who has argued that we need a notion of nonconceptual content in order adequately to explain the epistemological dimension of concept possession — an argument that, in turn, has attracted spirited critical discussion. Keywords: conceptual/nonconceptual distinction, Gareth Evans, perceptual states, perceptual experiences, analogue content, digital content

27.1 Domains of Application THE

distinction between conceptual and nonconceptual content has been brought into play

in a number of different contexts and to a number of different theoretical ends.

Page 1 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content

27.1.1 Characterizing the Content of Perceptual Experience The terminology of the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction was originally introduced by Gareth Evans (1982) to clarify the relation between perceptual states and what Evans termed the ‘reasoning and concept‐applying system’. Evans's basic idea that perceptual experiences represent the environment in a manner independent of (p. 458) the perceiver's conceptual repertoire has antecedents in Dretske's distinction (1981) between analogue content and digital content. This way of using the conceptual/ nonconceptual distinction has been developed most systematically by Christopher Peacocke, who has argued (1992) that we need a notion of nonconceptual content in order adequately to explain the epistemological dimension of concept possession—an argument that, in turn, has attracted spirited critical discussion (McDowell 1994; Brewer 1999). The basic idea that perception represents the world in a nonconceptual manner has been developed in different directions by other theorists. Michael Tye has used it in the service of a representational theory of consciousness (2000) and Mark Debellis has brought it into play to illuminate the distinctive character of musical experience (1995).

27.1.2 Characterizing the Content of Subpersonal Computational States The guiding assumption of contemporary cognitive science is that cognition is a form of information processing. Most mainstream ways of developing this basic tenet require subpersonal computational states to be representational, and ascriptions of content at the subpersonal level are not in any sense constrained by the concepts possessed by the thinker. Examples are the representational states involved in tacit knowledge of the rules of syntax. It is a fundamental tenet of a broadly Chomskyan approach to syntax, for example, that speakers are credited with tacit knowledge of a grammar for their language and that this tacit knowledge is deployed in understanding spoken language. Yet when linguists give theoretical specifications of the syntactic rules contained within the grammar, they frequently employ concepts that are not in the conceptual repertoire of the language user. A similar point holds for the representational states postulated in computational theories of vision such as Marr's (1982). The contents of such states are formulated in terms of concepts (such as the concept of a zero‐crossing) that are clearly not possessed by the average perceiver.

27.1.3 Characterizing the Contents Attributed to Non‐linguistic and Pre‐linguistic Creatures Contemporary developmental psychology, cognitive ethology, and cognitive archaeology have converged upon the practice of treating non‐linguistic and pre‐linguistic creatures as thinkers, behaving in ways that require psychological explanation in terms of content‐ bearing states (Bermúdez 2003). There is considerable controversy about how these Page 2 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content explanations should be understood. Some theorists (e.g. Fodor 1975) have argued that the representational states attributable to non‐linguistic creatures do not differ in any significant respect from those attributable to language‐using creatures, while others maintain that the explanatory practices should not be taken at face value (e.g. McDowell 1994). There is room, (p. 459) however, for a middle position, on which non‐linguistic creatures are genuinely capable of representing the world and acting in virtue of how they represent the world, even though there are significant differences between the types of representation available to non‐linguistic creatures and those available to language‐ using creatures. This middle position can in turn be developed in a number of ways. One of these identifies the significant differences at the level of content, claiming that only states with nonconceptual content are available to non‐linguistic creatures, with conceptual content reserved for language‐using creatures (although language‐using creatures may also be in states with nonconceptual content). This approach is adopted in Bermúdez (1998).

27.2 Formulating the Conceptual/ Nonconceptual Distinction 27.2.1 The State View versus the Content View The first question that one might ask, in light of the different appeals that have been made to the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction, is where exactly the distinction is to be located. Is it a distinction between two different types of content? Or is it a distinction between two different types of content‐bearing state? We can, following Heck (2000), term the first interpretation the content view and the second the state view.1 Suppose that we are thinking about what distinguishes perceptual experiences from the propositional attitudes (the first domain of application for the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction). According to the content view, there is a fundamental difference between the type of content that perceptual experiences can have and the type of content that beliefs and other propositional attitudes can have. According to the state view, in contrast, there is only one type of content. Perceptual experiences and propositional attitudes have contents of the same type. What distinguishes them is that states of the latter type are concept‐dependent while states of the former type are concept‐independent. A state type is concept‐dependent just if it is content‐bearing and it is impossible for a thinking and perceiving subject to be in a token state of that type without possessing the concepts required to specify the content of that token state. In contrast, a subject can be in states of a concept‐independent type even if she lacks all or some of the concepts required for an accurate specification of the relevant contents.

Page 3 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content Many of the arguments offered to support the thesis that perception has a nonconceptual character are arguments in support of the content view. So, for example, (p. 460) it has been argued on a number of occasions that perceptual experiences have a richness of grain that cannot be captured at the conceptual level—and there has been an extensive debate about whether, for example, demonstrative concepts such as that shade can capture the fine‐grained representational content of my experience of a colour swatch.2 The debate here (pace Byrne 2003) is surely about whether or not perceptions can have the same kind of content as beliefs. The issue is not about whether or not perceivers must have the conceptual abilities corresponding to the demonstrative concept that shade. All the questions about fineness of grain persist even if we stipulate that the perceiver in question possesses (and deploys) any potentially relevant demonstrative concept. The state view proposes a principled distinction between concept‐dependent state types and concept‐independent state types. Plainly, proponents of the distinction owe us an account of where it comes from. Why is it the case that beliefs do, while perceptions do not, respect the conceptual constraint? The most obvious answer is that the concept‐ independence of perceptual states is a function of their distinctive type of content. This answer is of course not available to the state‐view theorist, who only appears to have two possible lines of response. On the one hand, she can turn to the different functional roles of the respective state types. Alternatively, she can look to their different phenomenologies for an explanation of the difference between concept‐dependent and concept‐independent state types. The appeal to functional role appears to be restating the problem rather than providing an explanation. Since it is part of the functional role of belief that it is concept‐dependent (so that, for example, one cannot form beliefs about matters that are beyond one's conceptual grasp), and part of the functional role of perception that it is concept‐ independent (so that one can react to objects that one perceives even though one cannot conceptualize them), there seems to be no prospect of explaining concept‐(in)dependence in terms of functional role. The appeal to phenomenology is no more promising. There are significant phenomenological differences between beliefs and perceptions (in the eyes of many, after all, beliefs do not have any sort of phenomenology), but the state‐view theorist needs to tread carefully here. It is not open to her to claim that the phenomenological distinctiveness of perceptions has ramifications at the level of content. Although this might provide an explanation of why perception is concept‐independent, it would also collapse the state view into the content view (since we would be being given a way in which perceptual content differs from belief content). Suppose, then, that the phenomenological distinctiveness of perception does not have ramifications for the content of perception. It is now most unclear why that phenomenological distinctiveness should make the content of perception concept‐independent (or why the lack of it should make the content of belief concept‐dependent). (p. 461)

Page 4 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content I conclude, then, that the state view is unlikely to help us make sense of the conceptual/ nonconceptual distinction. Nonconceptual theorists are committed both to the thesis that perception is concept‐independent and to the claim that this concept‐independence is a function of the distinctive type of content enjoyed by perceptual experiences. In the remainder of the chapter I will be discussing different versions of the content view.

27.2.2 The Standard Characterization Here is a typical formulation of the conceptual/nonconceptual distinction from Michael Tye: To say that a mental content is nonconceptual is to say that its subject need not possess any of the concepts that we, as theorists, exercise when we state the correctness condition for that content. (2000: 62)3 There are two points to note. First, the characterization is purely negative (nonconceptual content is simply content that fails to satisfy a constraint upon conceptual content). Second, the characterization is indirect, proceeding via conditions upon the ascription of content, rather than by placing constraints upon the nature of nonconceptual content itself. As the examination of the state view in Section 27.2.1 makes clear, the standard characterization cannot be the whole story. We need an explanation of why nonconceptual content is not concept‐dependent.

The first step is to clarify the determinable of which both conceptual and nonconceptual content are determinates. How is the generic notion of content being understood? In particular, what is it to attribute content to a state? If we start from the basic principle, shared by both proponents and opponents of the general idea of nonconceptual content, that the content of belief is a paradigm of conceptual content, then it is easy to see that we are dealing with a notion of content that is richer than purely truth‐conditional content, since there are indefinitely many ways of giving the truth‐condition of a belief that fail to be concept‐dependent. Suppose I believe truly that my car is currently in the drive. Since there is presumably a complete microphysical description of that region of space–time, this description can be used to give a specification of the truth‐condition of my belief. As such it will count as nonconceptual. Plainly this is not the canonical way of specifying the content of my belief. At a minimum the canonical notion of content‐attribution in play here respects the following constraint: The perspectival constraint. In specifying the content of a representational state one aims to be faithful to how the thinker or perceiver apprehends what is being represented.

Page 5 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content The terminology of ‘apprehending’ is intended to be representational. It may be the case, for example, that perceptual experience has sensational properties that are not representational (as maintained in Peacocke 1983: ch. 1 and denied by those adopting representational theories of phenomenal character), but the perspectival constraint would not require that content ascriptions do justice to them. (p. 462)

There are ways of thinking about content that fail to respect the constraint. The currently popular identification of propositions with functions from possible worlds to truth‐values is a prominent example. Possible‐world semantics is intended to apply to all propositional attitudes and it is obvious that few believers who are not also professional philosophers will have any grip at all on the central theoretical concepts of possible‐worlds semantics. All content comes out as nonconceptual content in this sense (see Stalnaker 1998). With the perspectival constraint in play the point of the standard characterization is clearer. Non‐conceptual content, if there is such a thing, is content specifiable in a way that respects the perspectival constraint without being constrained by the conceptual capacities of the thinking and perceiving subject. It is also clearer what the opponent of nonconceptual content is claiming; namely, that the concepts a thinker or perceiver possesses fully determine how she apprehends the state of affairs she is representing.

27.2.3 An Example: Peacocke's Scenario Content The best way to see how the perspectival constraint might be satisfied in a concept‐ independent manner is through an example. The notion of scenario content developed by Christopher Peacocke is the most developed account available. Peacocke's account of the content of perceptual experience is based on the idea that the way a perceiver represents the environment should be specified in terms of all the ways of filling out the space around the perceiver consistent with that perceptual representation. We organize the space around the perceiver by specifying origins and corresponding axes based on the perceiver's body. There is a range of such origins, varying according to the modality in question. In the case of touch, for example, the possibilities include origins based on the centre of the palm of each hand, as well as certain other origins that capture the sensitivity to touch of the remainder of the body surface. Once we have selected a particular origin and defined a set of axes in terms of it we can identify points (or, rather, point types) in terms of their distance and direction from the origin. We can now complete the account of how space is ‘filled out’ (in the visual case) by first specifying for each point type whether there is a surface there and, if there is, then characterizing its hue, saturation, brightness, degree of solidity, orientation, and so on. Completing this characterization for a given origin and set of axes determines what Peacocke calls a scenario—namely, a class of ways of filling out space, any of which could be instantiated in the real world. The content of perception is given by positioning the scenario in the physical environment—that is, by assigning real‐world values (p. 463) to

Page 6 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content the origin and axes and determining a time. The positioned content is correct just if the volume of perceptually discriminable space around the perceiver at a specified time is a member of the class specified by the scenario. Peacocke's account is explicitly designed to satisfy the perspectival constraint. A positioned scenario is essentially a specification of how each minimally discriminable section of the distal environment looks to the perceiver—and the positioned scenario is correct just if the distal environment is the way it appears. Prima facie the notion of scenario content satisfies the standard characterization. The basic idea behind scenario content is that capacities for perceptual discrimination are not dependent upon conceptual capacities, and the machinery of scenario content is designed purely and simply to specify what it is that a perceiver is capable of perceptually discriminating, in a manner that is completely independent of the perceiver's conceptual capacities (if any).4 A theorist might employ complicated differential equations to capture, for example, how perceived brightness changes at particular points in the scenario. There is no requirement that the perceiver be capable of understanding those equations for them accurately to reflect how she perceives the environment (any more than a parachutist needs to understand the basic principles of gravitational acceleration in order to be capable of a competent free‐fall). And nor, one might think, need a perceiver have any idea of what saturation is in order to be able perceptually to discriminate and represent different degrees of saturation.

27.3 Is There such a thing as Nonconceptual Content? In Section 27.1 we saw that motivation for appealing to nonconceptual content has come from three different directions. Theorists have appealed to the notion in order (i) to capture the distinctive representational character of perception, (ii) to characterize the content of subpersonal computational states, and (iii) to explain how non‐linguistic and pre‐linguistic creatures can represent their environment. Let us look more closely at how opponents of the very idea of non‐conceptual content might object to each of these appeals.

Page 7 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content

27.3.1 Nonconceptual Content and Perceptual Experience John McDowell (1994) has been the most vocal and influential critic of the claim that perception has nonconceptual content. He offers two principal objections. The (p. 464) first is that the notion of non‐conceptual content is epistemologically problematic. If perceptual experiences lack conceptual content, McDowell argues, then they can have no role to play in justifying, as opposed simply to causing, perceptual beliefs. Attributing nonconceptual content to perceptual experiences is, according to McDowell, a sophisticated way of falling into the myth of the given. The second objection is that it is unnecessary to appeal to nonconceptual content, because there is no reason to think that capacities for perceptual discrimination do outstrip conceptual capacities. To support the second objection McDowell offers the following considerations: In the throes of an experience of the kind that putatively transcends one's conceptual powers—an experience that ex hypothesi affords a suitable sample— one can give linguistic expression to a concept that is exactly as fine‐grained as the experience, by uttering a phrase like ‘that shade’, in which the demonstrative exploits the presence of the sample. It is true that we do not have ready, in advance of the course our color experience actually takes, as many color concepts as there are shades of color that we can sensibly discriminate. But if we have the concept of a shade, our conceptual powers are fully adequate to capture our color experience in all its determinate detail. (1994: 56–7; 58) It is not easy to see why this line of argument should trouble the nonconceptual theorist, who is not committed to denying any of the claims made in these two passages. The question at issue is whether capacities for perceptual discrimination are constrained by the concepts possessed by the perceiver. It would be an objection to the nonconceptual theorist if, for example, it turned out to be the case that perceivers lacking the concept of saturation were unable to discriminate differences in saturation. But the simple fact (if fact it be) that a perceiver possessing the concept of saturation can give verbal expression to the discriminations that they are capable of making says nothing about the sources and origins of that discriminatory capacity. As far as I can see, the extensive literature stemming from McDowell's remarks has no bearing on the merits or otherwise of the case for nonconceptual content. The nonconceptual theorist is not committed to the claim that perceptual experience is ineffable.

McDowell's second point is more subtle and less discussed. It is, he thinks, a constraint upon any theory of perceptual experience that it explain how perceptual experiences can fall within what he terms ‘the space of reasons’. That is, an adequate theory of perceptual content must explain how the content of perception can stand in justificatory and inferential relations to perceptual beliefs and other propositional attitudes. Yet, McDowell argues, the type of experience without concepts envisaged by nonconceptual theorists

Page 8 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content cannot satisfy this constraint. Experience without concepts is blind, he claims. He explains: How should we cash out the image of blindness? To say that an experience is not blind is to say that it is intelligible to its subject as purporting to be awareness of a feature of objective reality: as a seeming glimpse of the world. And Evans himself insists that this can be so only against the background of an understanding of how perception and reality are related, (p. 465) something sufficient to sustain the idea that the world reveals itself to a perceiving subject in different regions and aspects, in a way that depends on the subject's movement through the world. Such a background can be in place only for a subject with a self‐conscious conception of how her experiences relate to the world, and we cannot make sense of that in the absence of conceptual capacities in a strong sense, a faculty of spontaneity. (1994: 54) Let us term a representation that is not blind in McDowell's sense a self‐consciously representational state. There is some plausibility in the claim that self‐consciously representational states are not available to creatures without conceptual capacities (and it becomes more plausible the more requirements one builds into the idea of self‐conscious representation). However, it is not clear that this is telling against the theorist of nonconceptual content. Nonconceptual theorists can argue that what McDowell calls self‐consciously representational states are not really experiences at all, but rather modes of reflection on one's experiences. Experiences themselves can be representational without being self‐consciously representational.

It is revealing in this regard that prominent nonconceptual theorists such as Peacocke have actually argued for a conclusion not dissimilar to McDowell's (see the debate about the autonomy of nonconceptual content referred to in n. 4). Peacocke's (1994) argument against the possibility of autonomous nonconceptual content is effectively that only creatures possessing a primitive version of the self concept can have self‐consciously representational states. When we bear in mind that an example of such a self‐consciously representational state for Peacocke would be the type of integrated spatial representation of the environment over time that cognitive psychologists call a cognitive map, it becomes clear that these self‐consciously representational states are not themselves perceptual experiences. And this seems more plausible than McDowell's position. Even if we think that no creature can be a genuine perceiver without some sort of understanding of the connections between perception and reality, why should we think that this understanding must somehow be part of the content of what is perceived?5 In fact, theorists of nonconceptual content tend to envisage a more circumscribed epistemological role for perceptual experiences with nonconceptual content than McDowell considers (Peacocke 1992, 2001). We can think of perceptual experiences with nonconceptual content as making available to the thinking and concept‐applying subject the perceptual basis for applying concepts to, and making judgements about, objects and properties in the perceived environment. Once again the intuitive idea is very simple. We can only apply concepts to objects and properties that we can perceptually discriminate, Page 9 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content and the perceptual discrimination of objects and properties must be distinct from the process of applying concepts if some applications and judgements are to be warranted and others not. Roughly speaking, a thinker is warranted in applying the concept of, say, a particular shade (p. 466) of colour to a property just if her perceptual experience makes that shade available in the appropriate manner. By extension, perceptual judgements are warranted just when they are appropriate responses to the world as it is presented in perception. The notion of warrant cannot get a grip here if we have not left open the possibility of a gap between how the world is presented in perception and the concepts that are deployed to think about it. Nonconceptual theorists maintain that there can be no such gap unless we allow that perceptual experiences have nonconceptual content. This epistemological justification for nonconceptual content is entirely compatible with the thesis that only conceptually articulated contents can stand in inferential and/or logical relations. Nonconceptual theorists do not have to claim that perceptual judgements are inferred from, or entailed by (or, even, made probable by) perceptual experiences with appropriate nonconceptual contents. The claim is simply that certain concepts (paradigmatically those classically known as observational concepts) have application conditions at the level of nonconceptual content—application conditions that can be given without mentioning the concept in question. Because of this states with nonconceptual content can provide reasons for perceptual judgements without standing in logical relations to them.

27.3.2 Non‐conceptual Content and Subpersonal Information Processing We can be briefer in discussing the case for nonconceptual content in the second domain of application. Even implacable opponents of the idea of nonconceptual content at the personal level are generally happy with ascriptions of nonconceptual content at the subpersonal level. McDowell, for example, remarks that ‘it is hard to see how cognitive psychology could get along without attributing content to internal states and occurrences in a way that is not constrained by the conceptual capacities, if any, of the creatures in question’ (1994: 55). Neither of the two lines of objection to claims about the nonconceptual content of perceptual experience can get any grip in this domain. The epistemological concerns raised by McDowell are completely beside the point in this area, since it is standardly taken to be characteristic of subpersonal information states that they are inferentially insulated from personal‐level states (whether perceptual experiences or propositional attitudes). There is a number of relations that might hold between the information‐ processing states of, say, the early visual system and personal‐level visual experiences— such as the relations of causation and realization—but no one has ever maintained that the reason‐giving relation might be one of them. Nor is there any temptation to try to

Page 10 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content interpret subpersonal information processing in terms of the thinking subject's conceptual capacities. Inferential insulation blocks this move also. There are two substantive issues that arise in this domain, however. First, there is the question of how content attributions at the personal and subpersonal levels (p. 467) are related. Unsurprisingly, McDowell is keen to make a sharp distinction between attributions of content at the personal and subpersonal levels. The latter involve, he thinks, only an ‘as‐if’ form of content that needs to be sharply distinguished from ‘genuine’ content, which McDowell takes to be content that falls within the ‘space of reasons’.6 An opposing view is taken by Bermúdez (1995), who sketches out a number of generic ‘marks’ of content and argues that they are satisfied by nonconceptual content no less than by conceptual content. The second issue is related. Suppose that we think that there are states with nonconceptual content at both the personal and the subpersonal level. Should they both be specified in the same way? Certainly, in the case of perceptual processing at the subpersonal level it would be easier to understand how these types of processing are related to personal‐level perceptual experience if there were at least structural parallels between the relevant content specifications. The machinery of scenario content is suited, as Peacocke has noted (1992: 65–6), for giving the content of the representations posited by theorists of early visual processing. Marr suggests, for example, that visual processing involves the construction of what he terms a 2.5D sketch, representing the orientation and depth of visible surfaces on retinocentric coordinates (1982). The content of the 2.5D sketch lends itself to specification in terms of values on certain specified dimensions at point types in a positioned scenario. Such a specification would be far more impoverished than a specification of the corresponding personal‐level perceptual experience but nonetheless continuous with it in a way that opens up the possibility of exploring connections between personal‐level experience and the underlying subpersonal information processing. On the other hand, however, the notion of nonconceptual content seems applicable to a much broader range of subpersonal computational states than those involved in perceptual processing. The processing involved in linguistic understanding is a case in point. Let us suppose, as is standardly assumed by linguists and many philosophers, that linguistic understanding involves tacit knowledge of some form of syntactic and/or semantic theory. It is plain that the tacitly known theories we might posit to explain linguistic understanding are completely unconstrained by the conceptual repertoire of the language user. And yet it is plausible to think that the axioms and rules of such theories correspond to the contents of subpersonal computational states. (Without such an assumption it is hard to see how we might develop a theory of language processing.) In order to characterize the content of such states we need to move beyond scenario content, making connections between the theory of nonconceptual content and accounts of tacit knowledge proposed by philosophers such as Evans (1981).7

Page 11 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content

(p. 468)

27.3.3 Nonconceptual Content and Non‐linguistic Creatures

In a sense the case discussed in Section 27.3.1 for thinking about the perceptual states of language‐using creatures in terms of nonconceptual content carries over straightforwardly to non‐linguistic creatures. However, thinking about non‐linguistic and pre‐linguistic creatures raises a new set of issues. As mentioned in Section 27.1.3, the pressure for attributing states with nonconceptual content to non‐linguistic creatures comes primarily from the explanatory practices of disciplines such as cognitive ethology and developmental psychology. This gives a very different emphasis from the domains of application that we have already discussed. When we are interested primarily in representations that explain behaviour, issues to do with the fine‐grained character of perception recede into the background (except, of course, where the behaviour to be explained exploits capacities for fine‐grained perceptual discriminations). What becomes important instead is representations of objects and properties in the distal environment. This raises interlocking questions. First, can there be nonconceptual perception of objects and properties in the distal environment? Second, are there any reasons to attribute to non‐linguistic creatures non‐perceptual representational states with nonconceptual content? In other words, do we need to go beyond accounts of nonconceptual content, such as scenario content, that are most naturally applicable to perceptual states (whether at the personal or at the subpersonal levels)? The first question immediately raises an issue that has been in the background up to now. No theorist has ever seriously denied that our perceptual experience outstrips our conceptual capacities with respect to such phenomena as colours, pitch, shape, and so on in the minimal sense that we do not have concepts corresponding to all the colours, pitches, and shapes we can perceptually discriminate (although of course philosophers such as McDowell have argued that this does not prevent perceptual experience from being brought within the realm of the conceptual). Yet it might much more plausibly be argued that perceivers have concepts for the different types of object and property that they are capable of perceptually discriminating. There is room for a minimal account of concept possession at the non‐linguistic level, on which possession of the concept F amounts to no more than the capacity appropriately to distinguish Fs from non‐Fs and to act appropriately in the presence/absence of Fs. On the minimal account of concept possession, the principal types of evidence for attributing psychological states to non‐ linguistic creatures would ipso facto be evidence for attributing to them conceptual abilities. It is clear that proponents of nonconceptual content at the non‐linguistic level need to place stronger requirements on concept possession. Some of the available accounts make it impossible for non‐linguistic creatures to possess concepts. Brandom, for example, has argued that possession of the concept of an F is a highly reflective ability that requires the capacity verbally to articulate one's reasons for making judgements involving the F Page 12 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content concept (1994, 2000). In fact, for theorists (p. 469) persuaded by arguments to the effect that any sort of higher‐order thought is unavailable at the non‐linguistic level (e.g. Bermúdez 2003: chs. 8–9), placing any sort of reflective requirement upon concept possession would effectively make all non‐linguistic content nonconceptual. Nonetheless, there are intermediate positions available. One might, for example, make it a requirement upon possession of the concept F that a thinker be capable of making certain canonical judgements and inferences in the presence of Fs, where those judgements and inferences are of a type available to some but not all non‐linguistic creatures whose behaviour might be explained in psychological terms.8 Suppose, then, that we are operating with an account of concept possession that allows us to attribute nonconceptual contents at the non‐linguistic level. Are these contents necessarily going to be perceptual contents? According to what Bermúdez (2003: ch. 3) terms the minimalist account of non‐linguistic thought, in giving psychological explanations of the behaviour of non‐linguistic creatures we do not need to go outside the sphere of perception. So, for example, Dummett has argued that the types of thinking of which non‐linguistic creatures are capable are all fundamentally perceptual in form, involving the manipulation of spatial images essentially tied to the perceptual context and to the possibilities that the environment affords for action. According to Dummett, the vehicles of what he terms proto‐thoughts are ‘spatial images superimposed on spatial perceptions’ (1993: 123). Similar views have been proposed by John Campbell (1994). If something like the minimalist view is correct then we do not need to go outside the realm of nonconceptual perceptual content in order to accommodate psychological explanation at the non‐linguistic level. We could, for example, make use of Peacocke's notion of scenario content (perhaps with the modifications suggested in Section 27.4 below). On the other hand, it might turn out to be the case (as I argue in Bermúdez 2003: ch. 3) that the requirements of psychological explanation at the non‐linguistic level take us beyond the resources of the minimalist conception—particularly when we are dealing with behaviours that involve instrumental reasoning about the likely consequences of actions and/or the tailoring of means to ends. Such an extension might involve explaining how there might be analogues of propositional attitudes (proto‐beliefs, say, or proto‐ desires) with nonconceptual content. Alternatively, it could be the case that the failure of the minimalist conception of non‐linguistic thought maps exactly on to the distinction between conceptual and nonconceptual content, so that the types of behaviour that resist explanation in terms of something like Dummett's ‘spatial images superimposed on spatial perceptions’ are precisely those that require explanation in terms of conceptual contents.

27.4 Developing the Account of Nonconceptual Content (p. 470)

Page 13 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content In this section I consider how the account of scenario content sketched out in Section 27.2.3 might need to be developed and modified in the light of the discussion in the previous section. The fundamental characteristic of scenario content is that it is completely punctate. A specification of scenario content specifies the values of certain properties at each point in the perceived environment discriminable by the relevant modality. It has nothing to say about larger‐scale properties of, for example, the visual field. Applications of nonconceptual content to the epistemology of concept possession and to explaining the behaviour of non‐linguistic creatures require us to think in terms of nonconceptual capacities for discriminating objects and properties in the distal environment. The punctate character of scenario content makes it unsuitable for characterizing these nonconceptual capacities. Can we refine the notion of scenario content to allow it to play these explanatory roles? Peacocke is aware of the limitations of scenario content and posits a further layer of nonconceptual content, which he terms proto‐propositional content. He writes: The contents at this second layer cannot be identified with positioned scenarios, but they are also distinct from conceptual contents. These additional contents I call protopropositions. These protopropositions are assessable as true or false. A protoproposition contains an individual or individuals, together with a property or relation. When a protoproposition is part of the representational content of an experience, the experience represents the property or relation in the protoproposition as holding of the individual or individuals it also contains. (1992: 77) The example that Peacocke gives of proto‐propositional content is the difference between perceiving a figure as a square and perceiving it as a diamond. This difference lies, he plausibly claims, in which axes of symmetry a perceiver finds most salient. When the salient axes of symmetry are those bisecting the sides then the figure is perceived as a square. When the salient axes of symmetry bisect the angles then the figure is perceived as a diamond.

Peacocke does not go into much detail as to what it is for an individual to be represented at the proto‐propositional level. However, the nonconceptual theorist clearly needs to explain what it is to perceive an object without conceptualizing it as an object, or as an object of a particular type. The nonconceptual theorist also needs to be able to do justice to differences in how objects are perceived by different types of perceiver (e.g. by pre‐ linguistic infants as opposed to by adult language users). What is it to perceive a portion of, say, the visual field as an individual? At a minimum it seems to involve perceiving that portion as a bounded segment and having certain expectations about how that bounded segment will behave. These expectations can, in the case of adult perceivers, be expected to track some of the (p. 471) basic properties of

Page 14 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content physical objects—what I have elsewhere termed canonical object‐properties (1998, 2003). The following are plausible candidates for the status of canonical object‐properties: • following a single continuous trajectory through space–time • continuing to exist when unperceived • having a determinate shape • only being able to undergo a fixed set of changes • being impenetrable • being apt to fall when unsupported • being internally causally connected • having mass • posing resistance to the touch • causally influencing and being influenced by other objects Many objects lack one or more object‐properties, and certain object‐properties may be reducible to others (any object that presents resistance is likely to be impenetrable). Some object‐ properties might not be expected to apply to all objects at all times. Objects that are lighter than air, for example, do not fall when unsupported, nor do flying birds. Nonetheless, the properties on this list correspond to higher‐order physical regularities that by and large govern the behaviour of physical objects.

The perceiver's implicit understanding of these regularities can be thought of as a naive physics. At a minimum we can see this implicit understanding as consisting in a set of perceptual expectations, manifestable in action and in surprise. Perceivers typically act in ways that reflect their naive physics, and show surprise when physical regularities are breached and their expectations thwarted. By working backwards from these manifestations it is generally possible to identify the object‐properties to which perceivers are perceptually sensitive and that determine how they parse the perceived environment.9 This sensitivity is both nonconceptual and part of the content of perception.10 This basic idea of perceptual sensitivity to higher‐order physical regularities can be used in conjunction with Peacocke's model of scenario content to give a fuller picture of the nonconceptual content of perception—a picture that does justice to the range of explanatory tasks for which the notion of nonconceptual content has been invoked.

References Bermúdez, J. L. (1994), ‘Peacocke's Argument Against the Autonomy of Nonconceptual content’, Mind and Language, 9: 402–18. —— (1995), ‘Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to Subpersonal Computational States’, Mind and Language, 10: 333–69.

Page 15 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content —— (1998), The Paradox of Self‐Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2003), Thinking Without Words (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Brandom, R. (1994), Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representation, and Discursive Commitment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (2000), Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Brewer, B. (1999), Perception and Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Byrne, A. (2003), ‘Consciousness and Nonconceptual Content’, Philosophical Studies, 113: 261–74. Campbell, J. (1994), Past, Space and Self (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2005), ‘Information‐processing, Phenomenal Consciousness, and Molyneux's Question’, in J. Bermúdez (ed.), Thought, Reference, and Experience: Themes from the Philosophy of Gareth Evans (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 195–219. Cussins, A. (1990), ‘The Connectionist Construction of Concepts’, in M. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 368–440. Davies, M. (1989), ‘Tacit Knowledge and Subdoxastic States’, in A. George (ed.), Reflections on Chomsky (Oxford: Blackwell), 131–52. Debellis, M. (1995), Music and Conceptualization (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Dretske, F. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Dummett, M. (1993), The Origins of Analytical Philosophy (London: Duckworth). Evans, G. (1981), ‘Semantic Theory and Tacit Knowledge’, in S. Holtzman and C. Leich (eds.), Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule (London: Routledge), 118–32; repr. in Evans, Collected Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 322–42. —— (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Fodor, J., and Lepore, E. (1994), ‘What is the Connection Principle?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54: 837–45. Gopnik, A., and Meltzoff, M. (1997), Thoughts, Theories, and Things (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Page 16 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content Heck, R. (2000), ‘Nonconceptual Content and the “Space of Reasons”’, Philosophical Review, 109: 483–523. McDowell, J. (1994), Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Marr, M. (1982), Vision (Boston, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin). Martin, M. G. F. (1992), ‘Perception, Concepts, and Memory’, Philosophical Review, 101: 745–63. Miller, A. (1997), ‘Tacit Knowledge’, in B. Hale and C. Wright (eds.), Companion to the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Blackwell), 146–74. Peacocke, C. (1983), Sense and Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1989), ‘When is a Grammar Psychologically Real?’ in A. George (ed.), Reflections on Chomsky (Oxford: Blackwell), 111–30. —— (1992), A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1994), ‘Nonconceptual Content: Kinds, Rationales and Relations’, Mind and Language, 9: 419–29. —— (1998), ‘Nonconceptual Content Defended’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58: 381–88. (p. 473)

—— (2001), ‘Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?’, Journal of Philosophy, 98: 239–64. —— (2002), ‘Postscript to Peacocke 1994’, in Y. Guenther (ed.), Essays on Nonconceptual Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 309–22. Searle, J. (1990), ‘Consciousness, Explanatory Inversion and Cognitive Science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13: 585–642. Sedivy, S. (1996), ‘Must Conceptually Informed Perceptual Experience Involve Non‐ conceptual Content?’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26: 413–31. Slater, A., Morison, V., Somers, M., Mattock, A., Brown, E., and Taylor, D. (1990), ‘Newborn and Older Infants’ Perception of Partly Occluded Objects’, Infant Behaviour and Development, 13: 33–49. Spelke, E. S. (1990), ‘Principles of Object Perception’, Cognitive Science, 14: 29–56. Stalnaker, R. (1998), ‘What Might Nonconceptual Content Be?’, Philosophical Issues, 9: 339–52. Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Colour and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Page 17 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content

Notes: (1) For further discussion of the distinction between the state and content views see Byrne (2003). (2) Peacocke (1992: ch. 3) offers an influential presentation of the richness‐of‐grain argument. Further discussion can be found in McDowell (1994) (particularly lecture III and the afterword), Sedivy (1996), Peacocke (1998, 2001), and Brewer (1999). See Section 27.3.1 below. (3) Similar formulations can be found in Cussins (1990), Martin (1992), and Bermúdez (1995). (4) With regard to the parenthesis, Peacocke originally maintained that states with scenario content were only available to creatures possessing a certain minimal conceptual capacity (see Peacocke 1992: ch. 3 and his 1994 reply to Bermúdez 1994). He has since changed his view and accepted the possibility of what he terms autonomous non‐conceptual content (see Peacocke 2002). (5) Evans himself held that a subject's awareness of an objective world is a function of their possessing what he termed a ‘simple theory of perception and action’, which is not itself part of the content of perception. For further discussion of Evans's views in this area see Campbell (2005). (6) A similar conclusion can be found in Searle (1990). Searle maintains a connection principle to the effect that a state can only be genuinely representational if it is (at least potentially) accessible to consciousness, which clearly rules out subpersonal computational states. For critical discussion see Fodor and LePore (1994). (7) See also Davies (1989), Peacocke (1989) and, for a general overview of theories of tacit knowledge, Miller (1997). (8) The account of concept possession developed in Peacocke (1992) fits this description. Peacocke requires concept possessors to make judgements and inferences for reasons, but does not in general require that those reasons be subject to reflective scrutiny. (9) There is an extensive psychological literature, for example, on the implicit understanding of naive physics, particularly in infants and young children (see e.g. Spelke 1990). It is known that infants at relatively early stages of development fail to be perceptually sensitive to certain fundamental object‐properties. For example, it seems to be the case that neonates do not perceive continuously moving centre‐occluded objects as a single individual with a hidden part (Slater et al. 1990). We know also that infants divide up the perceived array in a way that does not map at all cleanly on to how objects in the perceived situation actually behave. For example, it is well documented that three‐month‐ old infants parse the perceived array in accordance with the principle that single

Page 18 of 19

The Distinction Between Conceptual and Nonconceptual Content individuals are spatially connected bodies that retain their connectedness when they move. But this often leads them to take to be a single object what is really a composite (Gopnik and Meltzoff 1997). (10) Note that this is not the same as the simple theory of perception mentioned in n. 5.

José Luis Bermúdez

José Luis Bermúdez, Dean of the College of Liberal Arts, and Department of Philosophy, Texas A&M University

Page 19 of 19

Intentionalism

Oxford Handbooks Online Intentionalism   Tim Crane The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0029

Abstract and Keywords In recent years there has been considerable debate over whether all mental states are intentional; in particular, over whether all conscious mental states are intentional or entirely intentional. This article uses the term intentionalism for the general thesis that the nature of a conscious mental state is determined by its intentionality. (Intentionalism is sometimes called representationalism; the difference is purely terminological.) There are a number of ways of developing this general thesis; this article examines two of them. One is the view that the conscious character of a state of mind is determined by its intentional or representational content. The other is the view that the conscious character of a state of mind is determined by (what the article calls) its entire intentional nature. The article argues for the superiority of the second view over the first. Keywords: mental states, intentionalism, representationalism, state of mind, conscious character, philosophy of mind

Page 1 of 23

Intentionalism

28.1 Introduction THE

central and defining characteristic of thoughts is that they have objects. The object of

a thought is what the thought concerns, or what it is about. Since there cannot be thoughts which are not about anything, or which do not concern anything, there cannot be thoughts without objects. Mental states or events or processes which have objects in this sense are traditionally called ‘intentional’, and ‘intentionality’ is for this reason the general term for this defining characteristic of thought. Under the heading of ‘thought’ we can include many different kinds of mental apprehension of an object, among them relatively temporary episodes of contemplating or scrutinizing, as well as persisting states like beliefs and hopes which are not similarly episodic in character. These are all ways of thinking about an object. But even construing ‘thought’ in this broad way, it is clear that not all mental states and events are thoughts: sensations, emotions, and perceptual experiences are not thoughts, but they are also paradigmatically mental. Do these mental states and events have objects too? Or are there mental states and events which have no objects? The view that all mental phenomena have objects is sometimes called ‘Brentano's thesis’ or the thesis that intentionality is the ‘mark’ of the mental.1 Sometimes the name ‘Brentano's thesis’ is given to certain other views too; for example, to the view that only mental phenomena are intentional, or that all and only mental phenomena are intentional, or that nothing physical is intentional. These views are, however, distinct from the view that all mental phenomena are intentional. For holding that (p. 475) all mental phenomena are intentional does not imply that nothing non‐mental is.2 And holding that all mental phenomena are intentional does not imply (pace Dennett 1969) that nothing physical is intentional, since if physicalism were true, then the mental itself would be physical. What I am concerned with here, however, is the idea that all mental states are intentional, regardless of whether anything else is, or whether anything physical is. In recent years there has been considerable debate over whether all mental states are intentional; in particular, over whether all conscious mental states are intentional or entirely intentional. I will use the term intentionalism for the general thesis that the nature of a conscious mental state is determined by its intentionality. (Intentionalism is sometimes called representationalism; the difference is purely terminological. I prefer ‘intentionalism’.3) There are a number of ways of developing this general thesis; in what follows I shall examine two of them. One is the view that the conscious character of a state of mind is determined by its intentional or representational content. The other is the view that the conscious character of a state of mind is determined by (what I shall call) its entire intentional nature. I shall argue for the superiority of the second view over the first. But before doing this I need to explain what I mean by intentional nature and intentional or representational content.

Page 2 of 23

Intentionalism

28.2 Object, Mode, and Content I stipulated above that the object of an intentional state is what the state is about, or what it concerns, or what it is directed upon. The object of a thought can therefore be given in a correct answer to the question ‘What is this thought about?’. (This is why intentionality is sometimes called ‘aboutness’.) Hence, my thought that Odysseus was cast ashore at Ithaca while fast asleep is about Odysseus. But it is also about Ithaca, and maybe other things too. In other words, intentional states need not have only one object: the question ‘What is this intentional state about?’ (‘What are you thinking about?’) can have many answers, all of which may be correct. For some states of mind which are intuitively intentional or representational—in the sense that they intuitively seem to concern things other than themselves—the question ‘What is this intentional state about?’ is awkward or makes little sense. It is awkward, if not ungrammatical, to say ‘What is your desire for a bottle of inexpensive (p. 476) champagne about?’. A desire is a desire for something, not a desire about something. But clearly my desire concerns something other than itself, just as my thought about Odysseus concerns something other than itself. And it is the nature of this ‘concerning’ which is the focus of the study of intentionality. Hence, we should not become too attached to the words ‘about’ and ‘aboutness’ in describing intentionality. If we do, then we might find it hard even to understand the view that conscious states are intentional. For example, intentionalists say that a headache is an intentional state, but the question ‘What is your headache about?’ makes little sense. Here we can avoid this superficial problem by thinking of intentional states in a more general, abstract, and semi‐technical way to begin with: intentional states are ‘directed upon’ objects, and ‘objects’, by definition, are what intentional states are directed on. Sometimes intentionality is described even more abstractly as ‘self‐transcendence’: the idea being that intentional states are concerned with what transcends the state itself. Given what I mean by ‘object’, this is just another way of saying that intentional states have objects. So much should be uncontroversial. To say more, we have to start constructing a theory of intentionality. I begin with intentional objects. Intentional objects, as I think of them, have two distinctive characteristics. First, since intentional objects are what we think about, desire, or hope for, and we can think about or desire or hope for things that do not exist, it follows that some intentional objects do not exist. These can be called ‘mere intentional objects’. Remember that my use of ‘object’ here is just a stipulation meaning, whatever it is on which your state of mind is directed. So saying that there are mere intentional objects is another way of describing the uncontroversial fact that we can think about (hope for, etc.) things that do not exist; it is a further question how this fact should be understood. Some philosophers (e.g. Parsons 1980) think that we need a logical and metaphysical account of non‐existent objects; others believe that all apparent reference

Page 3 of 23

Intentionalism to such objects must be explained away in the style of Quine (1948). Here I simply note the fact and do not attempt to explain it. The second characteristic is related to the first. As indicated above by my talk of ‘self‐ transcendence’, intentional objects are not immanent in intentional states. That is, if an intentional object exists at all, its existence ‘transcends’ any intentional state which has it as its object.4 I mean this transcendence of the intentional object to imply that it is never essential to an intentional object that it is the object of any particular state of mind. (This applies even to those intentional states which are the objects of ‘higher‐order’ intentional states: my thought that p is independent from, and inessential to, the thought that I think that p.) Externalists about mental content may say that it is essential to certain states of mind that they involve a real relation to some real thing (e.g. water). But they do not think that it is essential to water that it is the object of any particular mental state. (p. 477)

Saying what the intentional object of a state of mind is does not yet tell us what the state of mind itself is, since the same intentional object can be the object of many different states of mind. In order to fully characterize different states of mind, we need to make two further distinctions. One is that the same object can be the object of a desire, a thought, a hope, and so on. This is what I call a difference in intentional mode.5 The other distinction is that the same object could be presented to the mind in different ways even when the mode is the same: my bottle of inexpensive champagne could also be thought of as a bottle of inexpensive famous sparkling wine from France. This kind of difference in the way the intentional object is presented is what I call a difference in intentional content. Every intentional state must have an intentional content in this sense. This is because the intentional object of a state is what the state is directed on; but a state cannot be directed on something without that thing being represented in one way or another. There is no such thing as a state of mind which has an object represented in no particular way. What could this possibly mean? The idea of representation itself implies representation in a particular way: in representing something in language or in pictures one has to choose some particular way of representing it. The particular way in which the intentional object is represented is what I call the content of the state. So for a state to have a content is for it to have an object represented in a particular way. Intentional content is representational content. Intentional states, then, involve both intentional mode and intentional content. But what is the relationship between the intentional content and the intentional object of a state? Different theorists have different views of this relationship. Some think that the content of an intentional state must determine its object; in other words, that states with the same content must have the same object. Someone who thinks this might then be led to think that even though its existence transcends the intentional state, the intentional object is nonetheless an essential part of the state, since states with different objects are different in their nature.6 Since I believe that many intentional states have the same Page 4 of 23

Intentionalism content regardless of whether their objects exist, I must reject the thesis that intentional content determines intentional object. On the conception of intentionality I favour, the intentional object is never part of the state. The nature of the intentional state is exhausted by its mode and content. In a famous passage Brentano gave some examples of the ‘intentional inexistence of an object’: ‘in presentation, something is presented, in judgement something is affirmed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired and so on’ (1874/1995: 88). This implies that the object of a presentation is what is presented, the object of love is what is loved, etc. However, given what I have just said about intentional objects, we should not characterize an intentional object as what (p. 478) is ϕ‐ed for any intentional mode ϕ. One reason is that what is believed, for example, is a proposition, and a proposition is not the intentional object of a belief. When someone believes something, the proposition that they believe exists (or so I say), but the object of their belief might not. There is a debate about the existence of propositions, but this is not the same issue as the issue of the existence of intentional objects. Those who are sceptical of propositions do not think that some of them exist and some of them do not. Also, the propositional content of a belief is, on most views, essential to it. But on the conception of intentionality I favour it's not the case that the existence of the object is essential to the intentional state. Finally, it is clear that the belief that Odysseus was cast ashore at Ithaca while fast asleep is about Odysseus (its object) and not about any proposition. The phrase ‘what is ϕ‐ed’ picks out a different intentional element for different intentional modes. In the case of fear, for example, we can say that what you fear is the object of your fear, not its content. If you are frightened of the dog around the corner, that is the object of your fear, that is what you are frightened of. Matters are different for hope, belief, and wonder, for example. What is believed, hoped, or wondered is the content of the belief, hope, or wonder. The lesson is that we cannot derive a systematic conception of intentional content and object from reflection on phrases like ‘what is believed/feared/ etc.’ alone. This whole way of thinking about intentionality allows for a number of different understandings of content. On a dominant view, for example, the contents of all intentional states are assessable as true or false; in other words, the content is propositional. There is an ongoing debate about the nature of propositions (see Salmon and Soames 1988; Schiffer 2003). Here all I will mean by ‘proposition’ is the content of an intentional state that is true or false. As we shall see, some philosophers think that all intentional content is propositional. Yet it seems to me that there are many intentional states whose contents are not assessable as true or false; for example, the object‐directed attitudes of love and hate (see Crane 2001: sect. 34; Montague (forthcoming)). Hence I reject the thesis that all intentional content is propositional. Although I will rely on this rejection later in the chapter, I will not defend it further.

Page 5 of 23

Intentionalism Another question about intentional content is whether it is conceptual or non‐conceptual. A state of mind has conceptual content when a subject needs to possess the concepts definitive of its content in order to be in that state. Some philosophers have claimed that certain experiences have non‐conceptual content, and I agree. But it is not a debate which needs to be settled in this context.

28.3 Two Kinds of Intentionalism Having clarified the elements of intentionality, in this section I will consider how these elements are employed in different developments of intentionalism: the idea that consciousness is a form of intentionality. One development of intentionalism (p. 479) is the view that the conscious character of a state of mind is determined by its intentional content alone. Chalmers (2004) calls this view ‘pure representationalism’. I am indebted to Chalmers's discussion, but, in keeping with my terminological decision of Section 28.1, I will call the view ‘pure intentionalism’. Pure intentionalism about consciousness is standardly expressed in terms of a close relationship between the phenomenal character of a state of mind and the state's representational content. A state has phenomenal character when there is something it is like to be in that state, while the representational content of a state is how it represents the world to be, and this is taken to be propositional (Byrne 2001: 7; Bain 2003: 507). Two versions of pure intentionalism are sometimes distinguished: strong pure intentionalism, which says that the phenomenal character of a mental state is identical with its representational content (see Tye 1995: 137), and weak pure intentionalism, which says that the phenomenal character of a state is determined by or supervenes on its representational content (see Byrne 2001: 7; McLaughlin 2003; Kind (forthcoming)). Taken literally, strong pure intentionalism is of dubious coherence. It says that the phenomenal character of an experience is identical with its representational content. The representational content of an experience, according to pure intentionalism, is a proposition. The phenomenal character of an experience is what it is like to have that experience. But how can what it is like to have an experience be identical to a proposition? Propositions are abstract objects—maybe Fregean thoughts, maybe modelled by sets of possible worlds or intensions or ordered n‐tuples of objects and properties—and what it is like to have experience is (arguably) a feature of an experience, a concrete event. How can a feature of a concrete event be identical to an abstract proposition? If we are to take strong intentionalists at their word, their claim makes little sense.7 However, we should interpret the claim with a charitable pinch of salt. Let's instead understand strong pure intentionalists as saying that for an experience to have a certain phenomenal character simply is for it to have a certain intentional content. Strong pure intentionalists should not say that the phenomenal character is identical with the content; Page 6 of 23

Intentionalism rather they should say that an experience's having phenomenal character is identical with its having a certain content. Weak pure intentionalism can then be expressed as follows: any two experiences which share intentional content will share phenomenal character. This is consistent with the identity claim made by strong pure intentionalists but does not imply it, since it allows that an experience could have non‐representational phenomenal properties which (for some reason) supervene on the experience's having the representational content it does. It seems to me that the distinction between strong and weak pure intentionalism is of little significance in the present context, and in what follows I will accordingly understand pure intentionalism as the weaker, supervenience claim. As noted, pure intentionalists tend to hold that all intentional content is propositional. Since I reject this thesis, this is one reason for rejecting pure intentionalism as (p. 480) usually understood. But maybe this thesis is not essential to pure intentionalism; it does not seem that there is anything in the essential idea behind pure intentionalism which implies that content must be propositional. So I want to concentrate here on a problem which is closer to the heart of pure intentionalism. In a recent paper (2003) David Bain defends the pure‐intentionalist view that the experience of pain represents damage to the body. Part of his defence involves addressing what he calls the ‘distinctiveness’ problem: how a pure intentionalist should characterize what is distinctive about pain sensations. At one point he expresses this problem in terms of how one can distinguish between (for example) seeing that one's body is disordered and somatosensorily feeling the same thing: The phenomenal difference between seeing disorder and somatosensorily feeling it cannot reside in the difference between the experiences’ contents, since their contents do not differ—both represent disorder. (2003: 516) Some pure intentionalists (e.g. Dretske 2000: 458) respond by insisting that such experiences must in fact differ in what they represent. Others (e.g. Tye 1995) say that the contents of the experiences themselves have different natures (for example, the content of a somatosensory experience is non‐conceptual). Bain's own view is that what is represented does not differ in these two cases, but that there is a difference in ‘modes of presentation’ (i.e. their Fregean content) (2003: 517–18).

These responses are really very similar: they all attempt to locate the differences in these experiences in their intentional contents. Yet it seems to me that there is a much simpler response available, which is unavailable to pure intentionalists like Bain and Tye (although it is quite within the spirit of their view). This simple response is that the difference between feeling one's leg to be damaged and seeing it to be damaged is just the difference between feeling and seeing. In other words, it is a difference in what Searle and I call mode, and what others would call attitude. We already know that sameness of content does not suffice for sameness of mental states in general; a belief and a hope

Page 7 of 23

Intentionalism might have the same content. So why should we expect that it suffices for sameness of phenomenal states, states which are distinguished by their phenomenal character? As outlined in Section 28.2 above, intentionality is directedness on an object, but there are three dimensions of variation in the ways one's states of mind might be directed upon an object: they may differ in their object, in their content, and in their mode.8 So since we know that, as a general rule, intentional states can differ in mode even when they share content, it is surely only to be expected that differences (p. 481) in mode might make a difference to the phenomenal character of states of mind. The point is even easier to appreciate when we consider concrete examples: it should not be surprising, for example, that seeing that it is raining and hearing that it is raining have different phenomenal characters, since seeing and hearing are different conscious modes or attitudes. So the simple answer to Bain's question is that what distinguishes feeling that one's body is damaged and seeing that one's body is damaged is the fact that in one case the fact is apprehended by the faculty of eyesight and in the other it is apprehended by the faculty of somatosensory perception. There may also be differences in content, but the point is that there is an obvious uncontentious difference that pure intentionalists like Bain and Tye overlook. (Of course, this does not explain what makes the products of these faculties conscious, but neither does pure intentionalism explain this. Bain's question was about what distinguishes the conscious character of these experiences, not about what makes them conscious in the first place.) Bain considers this response, but rejects it on the grounds that admitting that mode or sense modality contributes to phenomenal differences is ‘to give up without a fight’ (2003: 517). But this seems to put the cart before the horse. If we start off with an inclination in favour of intentionalism in general, perhaps inspired by the idea of unifying the phenomena of mind around the notion of a subject's point of view (see the next section) or by Dretske's idea that ‘all mental facts are representational facts’ (1995: xiii), then one should have an open mind about whether all mental facts are fixed by all the intentional or representational facts (mode plus content plus object) or whether they are fixed by content alone. A little reflection can show that all the intentional facts about a state of mind (including facts about mode) contribute towards fixing the phenomenal character. Moreover, saying this is not something which is in conflict with the motivation behind the general intentionalist view of the mind, as I shall explain in the next section. Therefore, I think we should reject pure intentionalism and deny that the phenomenal character of an experience is determined by its representational content alone.9 The alternative way of developing the view that all mental states are intentional is what I call (following Chalmers 2004) impure intentionalism.10 This says that the phenomenal character of an experience is determined by its entire intentional nature; in particular, by its mode and its content. The phenomenal character of an experience therefore supervenes on its intentional nature. There cannot be two experiences which are identical in their intentional nature but differ in their phenomenal character.

Page 8 of 23

Intentionalism Note that both pure and impure intentionalism are actually strengthenings of the original claim (which I called ‘Brentano's thesis’) that all mental states are intentional. For, someone could hold that all mental states are intentional but nonetheless reject intentionalism and representationalism if they were to hold that two experiences could be identical in their intentional nature but differ in their non‐intentional (p. 482) properties (sometimes called ‘qualia’). Call this the ‘qualia theory’. The qualia theory might be considered a version of the view that all mental states are intentional, but one that stops short of intentionalism by holding that there are non‐intentional properties which contribute to phenomenal character. Impure intentionalism, by contrast, insists on the determination of the phenomenal character of an experience by its intentional nature alone, and therefore implies the rejection of the qualia theory.11 So far we have only said what the doctrine of impure intentionalism is; we have not yet said anything about reasons for believing it. This will be the task of the next section.

28.4 The Motivation for Impure Intentionalism Impure intentionalism as a general thesis says that the entire mental character of a mental state is determined by its intentional nature. Resistance to pure and impure intentionalism comes primarily from those who think that there are aspects of conscious experience which are not determined by the intentionality of the experience; or even that there are conscious states which have no intentionality at all. Hence, the defence of any form of intentionalism depends upon the defence of intentionalism about consciousness.12 What positive reasons are there for believing that conscious states are entirely intentional at all? Pure intentionalists sometimes argue by appealing to what has come to be called the transparency of perceptual experience: the idea that introspective reflection on a perceptual experience reveals the external objects of experience and their features, and does not reveal intrinsic features of experiences themselves (Harman 1990; Tye 1995). There has been much discussion of the transparency of experience in recent years (see Martin 2002; Siewert 2003; Stoljar 2004). Here I shall understand it as the combination of these two claims: (i) that reflection on a perceptual experience reveals aspects of the external objects of experience; and (ii) that reflection on a perceptual experience does not reveal aspects of the experience itself. The first claim is relatively uncontroversial, although it does raise the question of what a defender of transparency should say about objects of experience which do not exist (see Johnston2004; Crane 2006a). It is the second claim which is normally disputed by those who reject transparency. These philosophers claim that in certain cases—e.g. blurry vision—one can come to be aware of something more than how one is representing the world to be, or of the objects of experience. When one sees something in a blurry way, one does not necessarily represent

Page 9 of 23

Intentionalism the world as blurry. Hence, the second transparency claim (ii) is false, and in so far as pure intentionalism implies this claim, pure intentionalism is false too. There are, of course, pure‐intentionalist responses to this kind of objection (Tye 2000). But given that we have already rejected pure intentionalism (Section 28.3), I will not pursue them here. Let's consider instead what someone might say who rejects pure intentionalism and the second transparency claim. There seem to be at least two possibilities. The first is the impure‐intentionalist response: that blurry vision and other such phenomena are part of the intentional character of the experience, since phenomena like this can result from the particular intentional mode of the experience: it is the particular way of being aware of the world, the particular acuity of one's visual perception, which (in addition to its content) determines the phenomenal character of the experience. After all, individuals differ in their perceptual acuity; it is hardly surprising that this should affect the phenomenal character of the experience. The second view is the qualia theory: that blurry vision and other such phenomena result from experiences having certain non‐intentional qualia, understood as properties which can vary independently of the intentional nature of an experience. It can be rather hard to see what is at issue in the debate between these two views. One reason for this is that it is not always clear exactly what non‐intentional qualia are supposed to be (for discussion see Dennett 1988; Martin 1998). But what does seem to be clearly in dispute is the truth of the supervenience thesis. Does fixing the intentional nature (mode and content) of the experience fix its phenomenal character? The impure intentionalist says yes, and the non‐intentionalist says no (Block 1990, 1996). To sharpen the debate, then, perhaps we do not need a positive account of qualia. Rather, we only need treat non‐intentionalism as a negative claim: the denial of the supervenience of phenomenal character on intentional nature. This puts the impure intentionalist on the defensive: they need to explain why intentional mode and content determine phenomenal character. One thing which is inadequate about the mere appeal to transparency and introspection is that it does not help us understand why it is that experience is wholly intentional. If we want to know why it is that phenomenal character is determined by intentional nature, then we don't just need a statement of what some philosophers take to be obviously true, we want some kind of understanding of the intrinsic connection between the idea of the intentional and the idea of phenomenal character. An analogy. It may well be that universal suffrage is a feature of all liberal democracies. Hence, being a state with universal suffrage supervenes on being a liberal democracy. But merely stating the supervenience connection will not explain why this is so; what we need is some explanatory connection between the idea of liberal democracy and the idea of universal suffrage. (p. 484)

Page 10 of 23

Intentionalism It will be helpful to return for a moment to pure intentionalism. Alex Byrne (2001) has provided a direct argument for pure intentionalism which does not simply appeal to either of the intuitions about transparency. Byrne's discussion is instructive, but it seems to me that his argument is ultimately unsuccessful. Nonetheless, a brief examination of the argument will indicate an underlying reason for believing in impure intentionalism. Byrne aims to defend the weak pure‐intentionalist supervenience claim: sameness of intentional content implies sameness of phenomenal character. Hence, if experiences differ in phenomenal character, they differ in content. He argues for this conclusion as follows: (1) If a (suitably idealized) subject has two consecutive experiences which differ in phenomenal character, then the subject will notice the difference. (2) If a subject notices a change in the phenomenal character of these experiences, then the way things seem to the subject will be different in each case. (3) But the way things seem to the subject is the content of the experience: if two experiences share a content then the way things seem is exactly the same in each experience. (4) Therefore if experiences differ in phenomenal character they differ in content. The key move in this argument is the step between (2) and (3). The idea is that if the way things seem to the subject changes so does the content, since the way things seem to the subject just is the content of the experience.

Now it is certainly plausible to say that ‘the way things seem to the subject’ can be read as a synonym for the content of an experience. But someone who doubts the pure‐ intentionalist supervenience claim can say that the ‘way things seem to the subject’ can be read in another way too: it can pick out aspects of the phenomenal character of the experience itself. It could be said that when one experiences something the world seems a certain way to the subject; but, in addition, having the experience also seems a certain way: ‘things’ covers both aspects of this seeming. Hence, an opponent of the supervenience claim can say that the argument equivocates between stages (2) and (3): in (2) the phrase ‘the way things seem’ picks out the content and aspects of the experience itself, while in (3) it picks out simply the content. Byrne's appealing argument therefore fails. Nonetheless, there is something we can learn from the failure of this argument. What Byrne's argument relies on is that in the case of perceptual experience at least the notions of how things seem to the subject and how an experience represents the world to be are intimately intertwined. Suppose I am asked how things perceptually seem to me now, and I give a description of this. Then suppose I am asked how my perceptual experience represents the world to be. It is reasonable to expect that I might give the same or a similar description (see Strawson 1979). Or, rather, if I did then I wouldn't obviously be failing to carry out the task asked of me. After all, how things seem to me in perceptual experience is at least a matter of how the world (p. 485) around me is

Page 11 of 23

Intentionalism experienced, and it is plausible (though not mandatory) to think of this world as represented by my experience.13 Someone might think that the descriptions must differ because ‘how things seem to me’ must refer to the ‘seeming’ itself and not what seems. But this would simply be a stipulation about how to use the phrase ‘how things seem’, and would therefore be deliberately ignoring the ambiguity I have drawn attention to. I am not saying that when you describe how things seem to you, you should only describe the objects of experience. If I say, because I am short‐ (or near‐) sighted, that a distant building looks blurred, I need not be describing the object as blurred. Rather, I am describing the object and how it seems to me. My point here is that describing accurately how things seem to you in perceptual experience will involve describing the objects of experience, even if it also involves other things as well. Byrne's argument trades on this fact. (The point is not just about the phrase ‘how things seem’: the same could be said for ‘what it is like’ and ‘how it is with me’; see Martin 1998.) Like Byrne, I have been talking about perception, and it may be thought that the situation is different where bodily sensations and some emotions are concerned. I will return to this question in the next section. But for the moment I would like to draw out what I see to be the moral of this discussion of Byrne's argument. I have claimed that Byrne's argument fails because the notion of how things seem to the subject may be read in two ways: as describing how the world seems to be and how the experiencing ‘seems’ to be, or what reflection on the experience itself yields. Hence, the step from (2) to (3) equivocates. But the fact that the notion has these two readings is very significant for impure intentionalism. For what we are trying to describe when we describe an experience is the subject's perspective on the world, the subject's point of view. A description of the subject's point of view is not a description of (e.g.) the arrangements of some ‘blank’ or ‘blind’ intrinsic properties; it is a description of a point of view on something. Already contained within the idea of how things seem to the subject is the idea of a perspective or point of view on ‘things’. The same is true for the idea of what it is like to have an experience. A description of what it is like to experience something visually is inevitably a description of what it is for this thing to be experienced. If you leave this out, you leave out part of what it is like for the subject, part of what makes the experience have the phenomenal character it does. This is why it is so easy for Byrne to move from talk about how things seem to the subject (‘what it is like’) to talk about the experience's representational content (‘how it represents the world to be’). Of course, the move is very natural, for few these days will deny that what it is like to have a perceptual experience is partly a matter of how the experience (p. 486) presents or represents the world to be.14 Many of Byrne's opponents will accept this, but they will nonetheless deny the supervenience thesis. However, the best explanation of the fact that the notions of how things seem and how things are represented to be are so close to one another, it seems to me, is that they have a common core. They describe what is captured at a more abstract level by the idea of Page 12 of 23

Intentionalism intentionality. These notions which are so useful to us in characterizing what it is, phenomenologically speaking, to have an experience are in fact inextricable from the notion of intentionality. The notion of intentionality, properly understood, is the notion of something being presented to the mind, the notion of a state of mind having an object (or what Martin 1998 has called a ‘subject‐matter’). If experience involves things seeming a certain way, they must seem a certain way to a subject; seeming is always seeming to some subject. What is presented to the subject (‘things’) is the subject matter of the experience. Hence, things seeming a certain way in experience is a kind of intentionality: the intentionality of experience. Impure intentionalism gives a better description of this than pure intentionalism, since impure intentionalism can accommodate the way in which the ‘seeming’ itself can enter into the phenomenal character of the experience. This is not supposed to be a demonstrative argument for impure intentionalism. What I have been trying to do is to motivate the application of the whole idea of intentionality from the two ideas appealed to by Byrne: how things seem to the subject and how things are represented as being. The ambiguity I noted in ‘how things seem to the subject’ is dismantled by impure intentionalism in terms of content (‘how things seem’) and mode (‘how things seem’). It is true that I have not shown that Block's non‐intentionalist construal of ‘how things seem’ in terms of qualia is incoherent. But I have shown how impure intentionalism would answer the non‐intentionalist challenge. There is a further reason for adopting impure intentionalism, which has been proposed by a number of writers recently and which deserves brief discussion here. This is the view that a (pure‐ or impure‐) intentionalist conception of mental phenomena will render them more amenable to a physicalist reduction (see Byrne 2001; Hellie 2002). According to a widespread view, there are two challenges which any physicalist account of mind faces: the reduction of content and the reduction of consciousness. An aspect of this widespread view is that while progress has been made in the attempt to reduce representational content—for example by explaining it in terms of information or causal covariation—little progress has been made in reducing consciousness. While content is widely considered to be based on causal relations to the environment, there is almost no consensus about the physical basis of consciousness. Some see the advantage of (pure or impure) intentionalism as offering a way out of this deadlock (Byrne 2001: 7). I am sceptical of this kind of motivation for intentionalism, for two reasons. First, I am sceptical about the prospects of reduction of intentionality. The fundamental (p. 487) doubts about misrepresentation which arose in the discussions of naturalized intentionality in the late 1980s have still not been answered (see Chalmers 2004 for a recent expression of scepticism). Second, even if prospects were better for a reductive account of intentionality than they actually are, this would not help with the problem of reducing consciousness, unless it were explained what it is about certain intentional states that made them conscious. Certain reductive pure‐intentionalist theories (like Tye's so‐called PANIC theory 1995) do attempt to address this question, by drawing attention to specific features of the intentional content of conscious states. But the difficulty here is that to the extent that there was an original worry about consciousness and its Page 13 of 23

Intentionalism explanation, this worry will carry over to the pure‐intentionalist account in terms of representational content. For example, if the worry was that zombies seem to be possible, then (given the manifest possibility of non‐conscious intentionality) this worry will arise even on a (pure‐ or impure‐) intentionalist approach. I doubt, then, whether intentionalism can really help a reductive account of mind. But, as I see it, its appeal for reductionists is not the main reason for believing in intentionalism. The line of thought developed earlier in this section is a defence of intentionalism as a phenomenological thesis: a thesis about what it is like to be a subject of experience. As a phenomenological thesis, intentionalism offers the prospect of a unitary account of states of mind; an account which explains the unity of our concept of mind. Our concept of mind, on this account, essentially involves the concept of a subject's point of view on the world. The essence of intentionality is having such a point of view. There are those who are sceptical about the unity of the concept of mind. But given the connections just drawn between phenomenal character and intentionality, the burden is now upon them to explain why intentionality is not the mark of the mental. In the final section of this chapter I will consider what some claim to be the strongest objections to this thesis.

28.5 Sensations and Moods The general thesis that intentionality is the mark of the mental has been denied on the grounds that there are clear cases of mental states which have no objects. The examples normally offered (e.g. by Searle 1983: 1) are bodily sensations and certain emotions or moods. Let us examine these supposed counter‐examples more closely, taking pain as our paradigm of a bodily sensation. A non‐intentionalist account of pain is one which says either that pain has no intentionality or that it is not exhausted by whatever intentionality it may have. On these views, the phenomenal character of pain is wholly or partly characterized by its non‐ intentional qualitative properties or qualia. Many non‐intentionalists have come to accept that in so far as they are felt to have a location, pains exhibit some (p. 488) intentionality.15 But they insist that there is more to these experiences than their intentionality: they also have their characteristic qualia. Pure and impure intentionalists resist this, normally on the grounds that the notion of qualia is obscure and ill‐defined. But it is not enough to say this; they also have to explain what it means for a pain or a mood to be an intentional state. Some pure intentionalists (Tye 1995; Bain 2003) have argued that the representational content of a pain in a part of one's body is that the part of the body is damaged or otherwise disturbed or disordered (the view derives from Armstrong 1968). The view has a number of advantages, not least of which is the way it connects the representational content of pain to its manifest function of alerting an organism to harm which has been Page 14 of 23

Intentionalism done to its body. But nonetheless it seems to me that the view cannot be correct. The main reason is that it is phenomenologically implausible, and the task we are engaged in here is a phenomenological one. Although there might well be cases where an experience of pain in a part of the body seems also to be an experience of damage to that part, there are also many cases where it does not. There is nothing in an experience of a headache which connotes damage to the subject, and it would be entirely irrational for the subject to conclude that his head was damaged purely on the basis of a headache. (To insist that nonetheless the headache is experienced as a disorder in the head may be true, but it hardly helps the thesis unless we know what kind of disorder it is, which is what the idea of ‘damage’ was meant to do for us. The mere idea of disorder is surely too unspecific to single out what is distinctive of the phenomenal character of pain.) To this kind of criticism Tye (1995) responds that the content of the pain experience is ‘non‐conceptual’ and this is why an experience of pain does not connote damage to the subject. But the non‐conceptual character of this experience does not seem to be relevant here. For suppose the experience does have a non‐conceptual content in the way that it has been claimed that visual experience has a non‐conceptual content. In the visual case the differences between colours which are supposed to be non‐conceptually represented are themselves phenomenologically salient (Evans 1982). But our criticism of the damage/ injury theory is that damage is often not phenomenologically salient at all, conceptually or not. Tye might respond that the ‘damage’ proposal is meant to be one about ‘subpersonal’ information processing below the level of consciousness. But this would then be changing the subject; he would not in this case be offering an account of the conscious character of the experience. We should, I think, reject the pure‐intentionalist idea that the content of pains must be characterized in terms of damage. And, as we saw above, the pure‐intentionalist view that phenomenal character is wholly determined by the content of an experience is independently implausible. So an intentionalist account of pain should rather explain the phenomenal character of pain in terms of three things: intentional mode, intentional content, and intentional object, where these do not involve a representation of damage to the body. (p. 489)

On the picture I recommend, the intentional object of a pain is the felt location of the pain, the part or region of the body which hurts. Treating the location or apparent location of a pain as its intentional object allows us to say, as in other cases of intentionality, that the intentional object of a pain transcends the experience itself, and might in certain cases not exist, or not be real. (For example, this is how we should treat the case of a phantom limb.) The intentional content of the pain is the representation of its felt location. This representation is always representation in a certain way or under a certain aspect. For example, if one feels that one has a pain in one's arm, the arm is the intentional object of the experience, and its content is the representation of one's arm as one's own. This is the Page 15 of 23

Intentionalism ‘aspect’ under which it is experienced. It might be possible in certain pathological cases for someone to feel a pain in their arm even when they did not recognize the pain as being in their own arm. This would not be to experience one's arm under the same aspect; it would not be an experience with the same content. (Notice that a view which said that pain is simply a representation of damage to one's arm might have difficulty in distinguishing these two experiences.) The intentional mode is the relation—or apparent relation, a form of representation—in which the body part or region stands to the subject of the experience. It is such a relation which we generically call ‘hurting’: it is my leg which hurts; that is, it hurts me. Of course, there are many different ways in which something can hurt. So the term ‘hurt’ can pick out different intentional modes in different cases; in any particular case the hurting will have a distinct intensity and phenomenal character. Hence, the intensity of a pain should not be thought of so much as a property of the pain, but rather as a determination of an intentional mode.16 According to impure intentionalism, the same is true of all bodily sensations, although much more needs to be said about the phenomenal character of these sensations to give a full defence of impure intentionalism. Turning now to the second supposed counter‐example to intentionalism—the cases of supposedly objectless feelings, moods, or emotions—we find a topic which is much less widely discussed than pain, and much less well understood, philosophically and empirically. Everyone should accept that there are emotions which have intentional objects. But some say that there are also feelings or moods which have no objects at all: one might feel generally gloomy, for example, without being gloomy about anything in particular (Dretske 1995: xv). What should a (pure or impure) intentionalist say about such phenomena? In some cases, although it might not be immediately obvious what the intentional object of a mood is, it may have an object which is revealed by further examination. So it is with those moods whose objects are their causes. For example, you might feel generally irritated and it not be clear to you what you are irritated about, but only on reflection do you realize that it is the presence of your aged relative who is both the cause and the object of the irritation. So it is, too, with another kind of case: those moods whose objects can only be characterized in the most generalized way. (p. 490) A mood of depression can have as its object ‘things in general’ or ‘everything’—a point underlined by the important commonplace that the depressed person and the non‐depressed person live in different worlds.17 Further reflection on this kind of case opens up the possibility of a slightly different approach. One way of spelling out what is meant by saying that the depressed and the non‐depressed ‘live in different worlds’ is to say that a mood like depression can be something which affects a subject's entire mental condition: not just every conscious episode of thought and experience, but the subject's motivation, imagination, and action are all permeated with the mood. In this kind of case, then, perhaps we should not think of the mood as an individual mental state in its own right, so to speak, but rather as a Page 16 of 23

Intentionalism commonality among all the mental states of someone experiencing such a mood. In general, it is plausible that every conscious episode of thought, perception, or desire has a certain affective ‘colouring’ to it. Objects are presented to us as meaningful in various ways, and part of this meaning is their affective significance: objects can seem lovable, valuable, in need of care, frightening, or nauseating. This can be, depending on the case in question, an aspect of their content or an aspect of their intentional mode. If this is so, then we can see how it might be that an aspect might be common across many different mental states, how such an aspect might give a thoroughly negative colouring to all one's experiences, and how we might generalize across this aspect by calling it a mood of depression. A mood like this might therefore be a general way in which experience might be modified, a way which can be common across many different kinds of mental episode. To what extent each recognizable mood fits into one of the intentionalist classifications discussed is something which will need further investigation. The category of the emotions (including moods) is a category in which it is crucial to pay attention to individual differences between the mental phenomena in question. It may be unlikely that one general theory will apply to all the things we recognize as emotions. But nonetheless we have found no good reason to think that there are emotions which lack intentional objects altogether.

28.6 Conclusion The general idea that intentionality is the ‘mark’ of the mental can be developed in a number of ways. Different developments will differ in what they say about intentionality, but also in what they say about consciousness since, as I argued above, the general idea only becomes controversial where consciousness is involved. In this chapter I have considered two such developments: the pure‐intentionalist thesis (p. 491) that the phenomenal character of a conscious state of mind is determined by its representational or intentional content, and the impure‐intentionalist thesis that the phenomenal character of a conscious state is determined by its intentional content and its intentional mode. I argued for the phenomenological superiority of impure intentionalism. In addition, there seems no good motivation for pure intentionalists to insist on their conclusion. The guiding idea behind pure intentionalism—captured in Dretske's slogan that ‘all facts about the mind are representational facts’—can be better developed by the impure intentionalist than by the pure intentionalist.18

References Armstrong, D. M. (1968), A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Bain, D. (2003), ‘Intentionalism and Pain’, Philosophical Quarterly, 53: 502–23. Page 17 of 23

Intentionalism Block, N. (1990), ‘Inverted Earth’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 53–79. —— (1996), ‘Mental Paint and Mental Latex’, Philosophical Issues, 7: 19–49. —— (2003), ‘Mental Paint’, in M. Hahn and B. Ramberg (eds.), Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 165–200. Brentano, F. (1874/1995), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. McAlister (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973); repr. with an introd. by Peter Simons (London: Routledge, 1995). Byrne, A. (2001), ‘Intentionalism Defended’, Philosophical Review, 110: 199–240. Chalmers, D. (2004), ‘The Representational Character of Experience’, in B. Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–81. Crane, T. (1998), ‘Intentionality as the Mark of the Mental’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 229–51. —— (2001), Elements of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2003), ‘The Intentional Structure of Consciousness’, in A. Jokic and Q. Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 33–56. —— (2006a), ‘Is There a Perceptual Relation?’, in T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 126–46. —— (2006b), ‘Brentano's Concept of Intentional Inexistence’, in M. Textor (ed.), Austrian Philosophy (London: Routledge), 20–35. Davidson, D. (1970), ‘Mental Events’, in L. Foster and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (Amherst, Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press), 79–101; repr. in Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 207–25. Dennett, D. C. (1969), Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). —— (1988), ‘Quining Qualia’, in A. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Contemporary Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 42–77. Dretske, F. I. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2000), ‘Reply to Lopes’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60: 455–9. (p. 492)

Page 18 of 23

Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

Intentionalism Farkas, K. (2006), ‘Semantic Internalism and Externalism’, in E. Lepore and B. C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 323–40. Goldie, P. (2000), The Emotions (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Grahek, N. (2001), Feeling Pain and Being in Pain (Oldenburg: Hanse Institute for Advanced Study). Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Hellie, B. (2002), ‘Consciousness and Representationalism’, in L. Nadel (ed.), Encylopedia of Cognitive Science (London: Macmillan). Horgan, T., and Tienson, J. (2002), ‘The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality’, in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 520–33. Husserl, E. (1901/2001), Logical Investigations, trans. J. N. Findlay, ed. D. Moran (London: Routledge, 2001). Jackson, F. (2004), ‘Representation and Experience’, in H. Clapin, P. Slezack, and P. Staines (eds.), Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation (Wesport Conn: Praeger), 107–24. Johnston, M. (2004), ‘The Obscure Object of Hallucination’, Philosophical Studies, 120: 113–83. Kind, A. (2003), ‘What's So Transparent about Transparency?’, Philosophical Studies, 115: 225–44. —— (forthcoming), ‘Restrictions on Representationalism’, Philosophical Studies. Lycan, W. G. (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). McCulloch, G. (2003), The Life of the Mind (London: Routledge). McLaughlin, B. (2003), ‘Color, Consciousness and Color Consciousness’, in A. Jokic and Q. Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 97–156. Martin, M. G. F. (1998), ‘Setting Things Before the Mind’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 157–79. —— (2002), ‘The Transparency of Experience’, Mind and Language, 17: 376–425. Montague, M. (forthcoming), ‘Against Propositionalism’. Noûs. Page 19 of 23

Intentionalism Moran, D. (1996), ‘Brentano's Thesis’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 70: 1–27. O'Dea, J. (forthcoming), ‘Representationalism, Supervenience and the Cross‐Modal Problem’, Philosophical Studies. Parsons, T. (1980), Non‐existent Objects (New Haven, Conn: Yale University Press). Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 215–71. Quine, W. V. O. (1948), ‘On What There Is’, Review of Metaphysics, 2: 21–8. Rosenthal, D. (1986), ‘Two Concepts of Consciousness’, Philosophical Studies, 49: 329–59. Salmon, N., and Soames, S. (1988) (eds.), Propositions and Attitudes (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Schiffer, S. (2003), The Things We Mean (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Siewert, C. (1998), The Significance of Consciousness (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). —— (2003), ‘Is Experience Transparent?’, Philosophical Studies, 117: 15–41. Stoljar, D. (2004), ‘The Argument from Diaphanousness’, in M. Ezcurdia, R. Stainton, and C. Viger (eds.), New Essays in the Philosophy of Language and Mind, Suppl. vol. of Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Calgary: University of Calgary Press), 341–90. (p. 493)

Strawson, P. F. (1979), ‘Perception and Its Objects’, in G. Macdonald (ed.), Perception and Identity: Essays Presented to A. J. Ayer with His Replies (London: Macmillan). repr. in A. Noë and E. Thompson (eds.), Vision and Mind: Selected Readings in the Philosophy of Perception (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 91–110. Thau, M. (2002), Consciousness and Cognition (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2000), Consciousness, Color and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Notes:

Page 20 of 23

Intentionalism (1) See Moran (1996) for a historical discussion of this thesis and Crane (1998) for further elaboration of the thesis; for Brentano's views see Brentano (1874/1995); for some discussions of their contemporary relevance see Crane (2006b). (2) Some philosophers think that certain non‐mental states and events exhibit a kind of intentionality: for example, the rings of a tree can represent or indicate their age (see Dretske 1981). (3) For recent discussions of representationalism or intentionalism see Block (1990), Dretske (1995), Tye (1995), Byrne (2001), Hellie (2002), Thau (2002), Bain (2003), Kind (2003), Siewert (2003), Chalmers (2004), Jackson (2004), Stoljar (2004), O'Dea (forthcoming). Note also that the contemporary use of ‘representationalism’ differs from an earlier usage; namely, from the view that our perceptual access to the world is ‘mediated’ by representations. This is a view which is obviously very different from representationalism as discussed here; to avoid confusion, Block prefers to use the term ‘representationism’. (4) In saying this I side with Husserl (1901/2001) as opposed to Brentano (1874/1995). Brentano originally thought that the objects of intentional acts were phenomena (i.e. appearances); Husserl rejected this and emphasized the transcendence of the object. (5) Here I follow John Searle (1983). Husserl (1901/2001) calls this difference a difference in intentional ‘quality’; David Chalmers (2004) uses the term ‘manner’. Those (like Davidson 1970) who think that all intentional states are propositional attitudes would call it a difference in ‘attitude’. (6) Hilary Putnam (1975) employs a similar principle (‘intension determines extension’) in his argument for the claim that ‘meanings ain't in the head’. See Farkas (2006) for discussion of such principles in connection with externalism and internalism. (7) Here I am indebted to discussions with Barry Hall. (8) Note: (i) mode is not Fregean mode of presentation, which is an element of the content of the state. Chalmers (2004) prefers his term ‘manner’ to my ‘mode’ because of the risk of confusion with ‘mode of presentation’. (ii) To make this claim about modes or manners is not to agree with Lycan's view (1996: 11) that the functional role of a state of mind contributes towards its phenomenal character. To get here one would have to add the further claim that differences in mode are explained by differences in functional role —a plausible thesis but not one which follows from intentionalism. Here I disagree with Block (2003); my sympathies are more with McLaughlin (2003), Jackson (2004) and O'Dea (forthcoming). (9) See Chalmers (2004) for an additional plausible argument against pure intentionalism. (10) Terminology has really started to grow wild here: Byrne (2001) calls this view ‘intermodal intentionalism’, while Block (2003) calls it ‘quasi‐representationism’.

Page 21 of 23

Intentionalism (11) For the qualia theory see Block (1990, 2003). In Crane (2003), written in 1998, I called this version of the qualia theory a version of intentionalism (‘weak’ intentionalism). Since this theory does not say that phenomenal character is determined by intentionality, it now seems to me misleading to call this a form of intentionalism at all. (12) Resistance might also come from a defender of a kind of ‘higher‐order thought’ (HOT) theory of consciousness, which holds that bodily sensations (for example) are neither essentially intentional nor essentially conscious—they only become conscious when they are the objects of higher‐order thoughts (see Rosenthal 1986). I find the view that sensations are not essentially conscious very implausible, and will not discuss it further here. (13) Disjunctivists such as Martin (2002) will disagree; for them, the objects and properties we experience are not represented but instantiated in veridical perception. In Crane (2006a) I discuss the difference between disjunctivism and intentionalism in terms of whether their proponents think experience is representational. Here I am not providing an argument against disjunctivism, but describing the options for someone tempted by intentionalism. (14) Hence it is very unnatural, as many recent philosophers have noted (Siewert 1998; Horgan and Tienson 2002; McCulloch 2003; Chalmers 2004) to think that the notion of ‘what it's like’ only has application to the qualia of mental states, conceived of as non‐ intentional intrinsic properties. (15) Even Searle (1992: 251) accepts this. For further criticism of the non‐intentionalist views of pain see Crane (1998: sect. 2) and Grahek (2001). (16) Here I am especially indebted to discussion with A. W. Price. (17) For more on the intentionality of moods see Crane (1998: sect. 3) and Goldie (2000: 143–51). (18) Thanks to Katalin Farkas, Hong Yu Wong and Dan Zahavi for discussion, and to Mario De Caro and Alfredo Paternoster for their helpful comments at the first meeting of the Italian Society for Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Sciences at the University of Calabria in June 2006. This chapter was written with the support of the EU Sixth Framework NEST (‘new and emerging science and technology’) project, REFCOM (‘the origins of referential communication’).

Tim Crane

Tim Crane is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University College London.

Page 22 of 23

The Content of Perceptual Experience

Oxford Handbooks Online The Content of Perceptual Experience   Michelle Montague The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0030

Abstract and Keywords Our waking life involves a constant stream of perceptual experience. But what is it, exactly? What is the content of perceptual experience? This is a very difficult question to answer satisfactorily, and it has been made a great deal more difficult by the fact that almost all the key terms in the debate have been used in different ways, and sometimes in mutually incompatible ways. This article begins by establishing some basic points and terms of discussion, and asking readers to pay careful attention to the use the article gives to terms, which may not be the same as their own preferred use. It treats the notion of perceptual experience as non-factive, unlike the notion of perception, and lacking the causal implication of the notion of perception. Keywords: perceptual experience, waking life, notion of perception, phenomenology, sensory experience, intentionality

29.1 Introduction OUR

waking life involves a constant stream of perceptual experience. But what is it,

exactly? What is the content of perceptual experience? This is a very difficult question to answer satisfactorily, and it has been made a great deal more difficult by the fact that almost all the key terms in the debate have been used in different ways, and sometimes in mutually incompatible ways. I will therefore begin this brief account by establishing some basic points and terms of discussion, and asking my readers to pay careful attention to the use I give to terms, which may not be the same as their own preferred use. I will have nothing to say directly about the rather technical debate that has recently arisen between those who hold that the content of perceptual experience is wholly conceptual, and those

Page 1 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience who reject this view (see e.g. McDowell 1994; Peacocke 2001), because I believe it construes the content of perceptual experience far too narrowly. The verb ‘perceive’ is what philosophers commonly call a ‘factive’ or ‘success’ verb, as are all the more specific verbs of perception, such as ‘see’, ‘smell’, ‘hear’, ‘taste’, and ‘touch’. Thus, if John perceives—sees—a cow, it follows that there is a cow that he sees, and if he sees that the cow is brown, then she is brown.1 It is also (p. 495) overwhelmingly plausible to say that for any verb of perception ϕ and object O, if John ϕs O then there is a causal relation between John and O of the kind specified by the verb.2 In this article, however, I am not going to work primarily with the notion of perception, but, rather, with the wider notion of perceptual experience. I am going to treat the notion of perceptual experience as (a) non‐factive, unlike the notion of perception, and (b) lacking the causal implication of the notion of perception. In my terms, then, one can have a perceptual experience of a cow—i.e. a perceptual experience as of a cow—without there actually being a cow to hand, let alone a cow with which one is in causal contact. Plainly all perceptions are perceptual experiences, on the present terms, but not all perceptual experiences are perceptions. A wholly realistic hallucination of a cow is a perceptual experience, on the present terms, but it is not of course an actual or ‘veridical’ perception of a cow, although it is by definition subjectively indistinguishable from an actual or veridical perception of a cow (for it is ‘wholly realistic’).3 Given these terms, one traditional approach to the problem of perception may be said to focus on the question of what makes a perceptual experience a (veridical) perception, and I will say something about this in due course. The philosophical discussion of perception has, however, been excessively entangled with attempts to deal with the problem of scepticism about the external world, and this has caused a great deal of conflation of issues that can be largely avoided by focusing on the question of how to characterize the content of perceptual experience, properly and broadly construed.4

29.2 Phenomenology The very first thing to say, perhaps, is that all perceptual experiences are experiences. They are conscious experiences that represent or present 5 things as being a certain way; and an experience is something that has, essentially, a certain phenomenology; that is, a certain phenomenological qualitative character, a character which is such that there is, in a familiar phrase, ‘something it is like’ for the subject of experience to have it. Some, it seems, define perceptual experience in such a way that it need involve no conscious experience at all, and allow that non‐conscious robots can (p. 496) perceive things, motivated by the fact that a creature can receive informational inputs that serve all the practical purposes of perception without having any experience. Some participants in the current rather narrow debate, in fact, want to define all perception merely functionally, in this way, and do not really admit that it involves any phenomenology at all, as just

Page 2 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience defined, even in our own case. In this chapter, however, I will take it to be true by definition that perceptual states have, necessarily and essentially, a phenomenological qualitative character. What more may be said about phenomenology? All perceptual experiences involve sensory experience, whether exteroceptive (visual, olfactory, auditory, gustatory, tactile) or interoceptive or somatosensory (e.g. experience of pain, hunger, nervousness, bodily movement, and so on), and many take it that the word ‘phenomenology’ only covers the qualitative character of sensory experience. It is, however, clear that there is more to perceptual experience, qualitatively or phenomenologically, i.e. experientially, than merely sensory phenomenology. It is clear that there is more to perceptual experience (as) of a cow lying beside a beach ball than there is to having merely sensory experience of the array of colours that would be recorded by a photograph taken from where one is. I will express this point by saying that in any perceptual experience there is non‐sensory phenomenology, which I will call cognitive phenomenology, as well as sensory phenomenology.6 Some philosophers seem to deny that there is any such thing as phenomenology as I understand it, i.e. experiential ‘what‐it's‐likeness’. There is an old programme in analytic philosophy of mind that seeks, in one way or another, to give a reductive analysis of the mental in non‐mental terms (‘to reduce the mental to the non‐mental’), and hence seeks to give a reductive analysis of phenomenology in non‐phenomenological terms (‘to reduce the phenomenological to the non‐phenomenological’). This inevitably leads to the denial of the existence of consciousness or phenomenology, as I understand it, because its nature cannot be fully specified in non‐phenomenological terms, any more than the nature of the physical can be fully specified in non‐physical terms. It is true that to reductively identify X with Y is not, on the face of it, to deny the existence of X; it is simply to say that although X exists, it is really nothing over and above Y. And it is this fact that gives those who seem to be denying the existence of (real) phenomenology a way of denying that that is what they are doing. ‘Phenomenology exists’, they say, ‘but it is just this’, giving some functional specification of it that involves no essential reference to qualitative character. In the case of phenomenology, however, to reductively identify it with something non‐phenomenological is to eliminate the existence of (real) phenomenology while denying that that is what one has done. This is obvious to some but it is of course disputed. The issue lies outside the scope of this chapter, however, and I am going to take it as read.

Page 3 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

(p. 497)

29.3 Intentionality and Content

All perceptual experiences purport to present some aspect of the way things are in reality, and in so doing, and in this way being about something, in having a subject matter, all perceptual experiences have intentionality. This is true of hallucinations as much as veridical perceptions. In the typical case, a perceptual experience presents an external world of mind‐independent objects, objects whose existence does not depend on our experiences of them. And these presentations seem to provide us with direct or immediate access to this external world: that is how it seems, phenomenologically. Perceptual experiences are also said to have content. The notion of content has, however, been understood in many different ways, so let me begin with the simple proposal that the content of a perceptual experience is whatever is given to one in having a particular perceptual experience. It is whatever is given to consciousness, however this is further characterized. Since I take the phenomenological character of the experience to be part of what is given in the experience, it is part of the content of the experience, on my view. One might call it the ‘phenomenological‐character content’ or ‘purely phenomenological content’, for it is the (sensory and cognitive) phenomenological character of a perceptual experience considered just as such, and hence considered entirely independently of anything in the world that the perceptual experience purports to be about. Plainly this is a fundamental part of the content of a perceptual experience. Some philosophers now use the word ‘content’ in a way that prevents them from recognizing the existence of purely phenomenological content as just defined; and since different people also understand the word ‘phenomenology’ in different ways, as remarked above, it will be useful to have a neutral term to refer to purely phenomenological content. I will call it ‘A‐content’. To say that A‐content is part of the content of an experience is not yet to say that it is part of the intentional content of the experience, although I will later claim that it is. What else, other than A‐content, should be included as part of the content of perceptual experience, or indeed experience in general? To answer this question, consider first what one might call the ‘content/attitude’ approach to the general notion of content. Suppose Jane is thinking (happy, disappointed) that the computer in front of her is square. According to the content/attitude approach, this phenomenon has the structure Rab, where a and b are names for things and R is the name of a relation. There is (1) the thinker, a, (2) the thing designated by the that‐clause, b, and (3) the thinking (etc.) relation in which a stands to b, which I will call the ‘intentional mode’ or ‘manner of representation’.7 On this view, the thinking (etc.) is a two‐place relation between the subject and whatever is designated by the that‐clause,8 which is (p. 498) taken to be a state of the world wholly distinct from the thinking (etc.) itself: that the computer in front of me is square, for example. Now many philosophers hold that the content of the

Page 4 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience thinking (etc.), by which they mean the intentional content, is simply whatever is designated by the that‐clause; that is, a state of the world wholly distinct from the thinking. I will call this ‘B‐content’: B‐content is defined as states of the world wholly distinct from the thinking (etc.) in question. When the content/attitude account is then carried over to the case of perceptual experience, we get the following: When Jane sees that the computer is square, the seeing is the ‘intentional mode’, the (visual) ‘manner of representation’, and that the computer in front of me is square is understood to be the intentional content of the perception. The question now is whether the intentional content of the perception (of perceptual intentional modes in general) is or is not more than B‐content as just defined. I said earlier that the content of a perceptual experience is what is presented or given to one in having a particular perceptual experience. Otherwise put, the idea is that the content of a perceptual experience is everything that you are aware of in having that perceptual experience, whether it is in the focus of awareness or at the periphery. I am now going to argue, with Brentano, that it follows from the fact that you are (by definition) aware of all the content of a perceptual experience (a) that all the content of a perceptual experience is intentional content and (therefore) (b) that all its A‐content is intentional content. Since many philosophers take it that all the intentional content of a perceptual experience is B‐content, they may read this as saying that all supposed A‐ content is really nothing but B‐content. But this is not at all what I am proposing. To put the point in other words: given the currently dominant understanding of the words ‘intentional’ and ‘content’, I may be thought to sound like a ‘representationalist’ about perception, or an advocate of the ‘transparency’ thesis, or a certain sort of extreme ‘externalist’ or extreme ‘direct realist’. But in fact I am none of these things. This is what I will try to explain.

29.4 What is Given We need to consider everything that a perceiver experiences in having a perceptual experience. I will consider my visual perception of the computer in front of me. What am I aware of in having this experience? Here is one very loose overlapping list. Most agree, I think, that there is (1) a representation of things being a certain way in reality that can be wholly conveyed in terms of B‐content. If we allow (1), as almost all philosophers do, I think we have no reason to object to picking out for philosophical purposes

(2) the purely sensory A‐content of the perception.

Page 5 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience (2) is often attacked as an illegitimate abstraction, and it is true that I cannot isolate (2) and hold it before my mind, in having the perception, in the way that it seems that I can hold (1) before my mind.9 The sensory A‐content of the perception is, however, fully real, and it is no less part of what I am aware of than the B‐content. (If there were no sensory‐phenomenological aspect to my experience, it would not be a perception at all.) And the present claim is that it is ipso facto part of the intentional content of a perceptual experience, simply because it is part of what I am aware of in having the perceptual experience, although it is not in the focus of attention (it is ‘non‐thematic’ or ‘non‐thetic’, in the phenomenologists' terminology). Plainly, then, the present conception of intentional content is broader—softer—than any conception of it that requires that anything that is to count as intentional content must in some sense be in the focus of attention, or must be ‘aimed at’. (p. 499)

We can put (1) and (2) back together again in (3) the thick, overall phenomenological way reality is represented, both sensory and cognitive. In the present case this is, on the sensory side, specifically visual, rather than say tactile, and it has, as visual, further specificity in its details, including those which stem from my spatial position in relation to the computer, the lighting, and so on. (3) may also be said to include

(4) spatial positional‐information content about how I am situated with respect to the computer, information that is intuitively not sensory at all, but which has also been argued to be non‐conceptual (see Evans 1982: ch. 6) and which may also be said to fall wholly under (1)

(4) may in turn be linked to (5) whatever innate or learned grasp of opportunities for action is essentially involved in my perceptual experience in such a way that it is part of the very content of the perceptual experience, something that I am in some sense aware of in having the experience I do,10 and (5) leads naturally to

(6) all temporal as opposed to spatial positional‐information content relevant for action, and, more generally, to the temporal quality of experience that Husserl aims to capture in his protention‐primal presentation‐retention scheme (see Husserl 1893– 1917/1991).11 This too is part of the content of the perception, part of what is given to awareness, and is therefore part of the intentional content, on the present view.

The crucial claim, from the present perspective, is that there is always also (7) some sort of awareness of the experience or experiencing (see Searle 1983; Siegel 2006).

Page 6 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience It follows from this claim, which is strongly endorsed by Aristotle as well as Brentano and many others more recently, and which I will shortly discuss further, that the A‐content of a perceptual experience is not just part of what is involved in the overall phenomenon of the occurrence of a perceptual experience, but is also and necessarily part of the intentional content of the experience. (p. 500)

29.5 Awareness of Awareness As I have said, this list is loose and overlapping and could be variously adjusted. What I want to focus on is the possibly controversial claim that the A‐content of the perception is part of its intentional content. I will concentrate almost exclusively on the sensory‐ phenomenological side rather than the cognitive‐phenomenological side (see Section 29.2 above), because it is more familiar and easier to grasp, and from now on I will use ‘phenomenological’ as short for ‘sensory‐phenomenological’ and consider only the sensory‐phenomenological aspect of A‐content. As remarked earlier, most philosophers take it to be definitional of intentional content that it has the property of aboutness. So whatever an experience is about must be included in its intentional content, and whatever is included in its intentional content must be something that it is about. Now most will agree that my seeing a square computer is about the computer and its shape. But many will not agree that it is also about its own visual phenomenological character. However, it seems clear that the visual (as opposed to, say, tactile) quality of one's seeing the computer is part of what one is aware of in having the experience.12 The properties of the computer are made available via vision, by the experience's having certain very specific phenomenological properties, and this is part of what is experienced by the experiencer in having the experience. (It is not something extra to the experience.) So if I am going to say that whatever is given in the experience is part of its intentional content, it seems that I will have to say that the experience is not just about the computer but about its own A‐content and that this is a fundamental fact about the content of perceptual experience.13 I am happy to say this. I am happy to say that a visual experience is about its visual character, among other things, simply because its visual content is, necessarily, part of what is given to one in having it. But many are closely attached to a narrower use of ‘about’, and I will therefore be sparing with ‘about’ in the remainder of this chapter, in which I want to clarify my position by briefly considering its relations (p. 501) to a number of closely connected and currently popular theses and terms already mentioned: ‘transparency’, ‘externalism’, ‘direct realism’, and ‘representationalism’. All of these have many forms, and I will have to be very selective in the features I pick out.

Page 7 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

29.6 Transparency According to G. E. Moore, writing in 1903, the moment we try to fix our attention upon consciousness and to see what, distinctly, it is, it seems to vanish. It seems as if we had before us a mere emptiness. When we try to introspect the sensation of blue, all we can see is the blue; the other element is as if it were diaphanous. (1903: 450) Here his suggestion seems to be that the A‐content of an experience is no part of what is given in the experience, and this is the sort of point stressed by the advocates of ‘transparency’ or ‘diaphanousness’. In ordinary life, they say, when we see a chair we are conscious only of the chair and not of any experience of the chair. Moore goes on to grant that the sensation ‘can be distinguished, if we look attentively enough, and know that there is something to look for’ (1903: 450). However, it is not as if it has to be extracted in this way to be part of what is given in awareness. That is, in my view Moore is wrong if he thinks that there is any sense in which the ‘sensation of blue’ is not already fully given, with the blue, in the experience of blue in which ‘all we can see is the blue’. So, too, advocates of transparency are wrong if they think that there is any sense in which the chairish visual phenomenological content is not fully given, with the chair, in ordinary perceptual experience of a chair in which all we see (and are thinking about) is the chair.14 Such A‐content is therefore not only part of the existence of the perceptual experience, it is also part of what is given in the perceptual experience. It is therefore part of what it is ‘about’, in my broad terms, and it is therefore part of the intentional content of the experience.

In saying this I endorse the view, which is well expounded and defended in the phenomenological tradition, that—roughly—awareness always involves some sort of awareness of awareness. I agree with Aristotle when he writes that ‘if we perceive, we perceive that we perceive, and if we think, that we think’ (Nicomachean Ethics, IX. 9. 1170a29–b1), although I don't think one should lay too much stress on his explicitly propositional formulation ‘perceive that we perceive’, since I take it that a creature can perceive without possessing the concept of perceiving.15 Aristotle notes what is true in the transparency position, remarking that ‘knowledge (p. 502) and perception and opinion and understanding have always something else as their object, and themselves only by the way’ (Metaphysics, X. 9. 1074b35–6; my emphasis). The awareness of the awareness is in the ordinary case ‘non‐thematic’, in the phenomenologists' terms: it is not explicitly in the focus of attention. Aristotle also noted the threat of infinite regress in the claim that conscious awareness always involves awareness of awareness (De Anima, III. 2). He rightly found it unthreatening, although the details of his solution are still debated.16 Here I can note only that one can either hold that this awareness of awareness involves no higher‐order

Page 8 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience operation at all, experience being in some way essentially ‘self‐intimating’, or that the regress stops at the second order.17 The no‐higher‐order view is well put by Gurwitsch: Consciousness … is consciousness of an object on the one hand and an inner awareness of itself on the other hand. Being confronted with an object, I am at once conscious of this object and aware of my being conscious of it. This awareness in no way means reflection: to know that I am dealing with the object which, for instance, I am just perceiving, I need not experience a second act bearing upon the perception and making it its object. In simply dealing with the object I am aware of this very dealing (1941/1966: 330)18 and Brentano follows Aristotle very closely:

in the same mental phenomenon in which the sound is present to our minds we simultaneously apprehend the mental phenomenon itself. What is more, we apprehend it in accordance with its dual nature in so far as it has the sound as content within it, and in so far as it has itself as content at the same time. We can say that the sound is the primary object of the act of hearing and that the act of hearing itself is the secondary object, so that it is intentional with respect to itself. (1874/1973: 127–8)19

Page 9 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

29.7 Representationalism Many today adopt a position called ‘representationalism’, but they disagree about what it amounts to. I will take the basic claim of representationalism to be that the phenomenological character of an experience is its representational content, or, more weakly, that the phenomenological character of an experience supervenes (p. 503) on its representational content. On this view, then, any difference in A‐content has to be reflected in a difference in intentional or ‘representational’ content, the A‐content of an experience being wholly fixed by or determined by its representational or intentional content. (From now on I will simply use ‘intentional’ and not ‘representational’.) In claiming with Brentano that all perceptual‐experience content is intentional content and that all phenomenological content is (therefore) intentional content I may sound, to present‐day ears, like a ‘representationalist’. Really, though, we are very far apart. Suppose I perceive a brown cow. The account of this given by ‘strong representationalism’, as I understand it, is that the cow itself and its brownness, and various other spatial aspects of the world, are what are represented by my visual perception, and that they themselves, the B‐content phenomena alone, are the whole intentional content of my experience. If we then turn to the question of the A‐content of my experience, we find that it is already fully answered, according to this version of representationalism, because the A‐content is said to be either identical to, or at least wholly determined by, the intentional content, which is just B‐content, namely the cow itself and its brownness, etc. There is nothing more to it: A‐content reduces to B‐ content.20 On the view I favour, the A‐content of a perception is itself an irreducible part of its intentional content, essentially over and above its B‐content.21 To attempt to provide any reductive account of it, functional or otherwise, is to wholly misconstrue what one is aware of, and so misconstrue part of the intentional content of the perception. This is where the issue of the understanding of the word ‘phenomenology’ discussed above becomes acute. In attempting a reduction of phenomenology, in particular A‐content, to B‐content these strong representationalists have really eliminated it so that it can no longer feature in the perceptual content, and hence in the intentional content, in the way it actually does. I don't know whether anyone endorses representationalism in such a strong form, and there are ‘weak’ forms that seem to genuinely acknowledge the existence of phenomenology. However, I also disagree with those weaker representationalists who, while seeming to acknowledge the existence of phenomenology, claim that it features in experience only as the ‘manner’ or ‘mode’ (e.g. visual, auditory, etc.) in which the intentional content is presented and is not itself part of the intentional content of the perception (see e.g. Chalmers 2004; Crane, Ch. 28 above).

Page 10 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience Reductive accounts of phenomenological properties often appeal to the ‘transparency’ of experience already mentioned: the idea that we are not in having an experience aware of what it is like to have the experience, but only of mind‐independent (p. 504) objects (see Harman 1990; Tye 1995, 2000). With Aristotle and Brentano, I reject this view. Part of what we are aware of when we see a physical object (and not just when we reflect on seeing a physical object) is the seeing itself; that is, the having of a visual experience. And one is aware of the having of the visual experience in virtue of the phenomenological character of visual experience. So, in fact, in having visual experiences we are aware of phenomenological properties, although in everyday activity, as Aristotle and Reid observed long ago, we are focused on the properties of objects, not on our particular perceptual access to them.

29.8 Externalism and Internalism, Direct and Indirect Realism Another important issue concerning the content of experience is whether one provides an ‘externalist’ or an ‘internalist’ account of it. This is connected to the question of whether one is a ‘direct’ or ‘indirect’ realist about perception. The view I favour is externalist and direct realist in the fundamental sense of the father of modern direct realism, Thomas Reid, and also I think in any sense in which externalism and direct realism are defensible, but it is also internalist in a fundamental respect, and many philosophers may want to classify it as indirect realist—even if they will then have to say the same about Reid, supposedly the archetypal direct realist. I do not think the names matter so much, so long as the view is clear, but clarification is required. Consider two subjects, X and Y, who are having veridical perceptual experiences of a boy playing a trumpet. They are, we may suppose, internally—molecule‐formolecule— identical, and they are therefore also identical in respect of any phenomenological properties. According to standard accounts of externalism, their experiences may, in spite of this, have completely different content, typically called ‘wide content’. X may see and hear Tom (Tom1), while Y, located, perhaps, on a perfect copy of earth, sees and hears a quite different but qualitatively indistinguishable boy, also called Tom (Tom2). Now what fixes the content of an experience, according to externalism, is wholly a matter of external relations (causal and functional) between the subject and the environment, and X and Y are in completely different environments (numerically speaking). So their experiences have completely different content.22 According to internalist accounts, by contrast, content is fixed, at least in part, by the internal features of experiencers, so that X and Y will have at least some content—typically called ‘narrow content’—in common, even if their environments differ.23

Page 11 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience Direct realism states that what we perceive, and directly (or ‘immediately’) perceive, when we have perceptual experience of a boy playing a trumpet that is (p. 505) appropriately caused in us by a real boy and a real trumpet, and is therefore a case of perception, is a boy and a trumpet, period. Indirect realism, by contrast, holds that what we directly or immediately perceive is only an internal phenomenologically propertied representation of a boy and a trumpet. To that extent we perceive an actual boy and an actual trumpet only indirectly or (‘mediately’). Indirect realists point out that a veridical perception of the boy and a completely realistic hallucination can be completely indistinguishable, and argue that this shows beyond doubt that what we immediately perceive—what is directly given to us—is only some sort of psychological entity, an inner representation, and not a boy.24 In both these debates the truth lies between the two opposed parties. The present account of perception is direct realist in so far as it holds that what we perceive, in this case, is a boy playing a trumpet, period. But it does not in any way deny the existence of the internal phenomenological state that makes this so. Being in the phenomenological state just is directly perceiving the boy, so long as the phenomenological state is appropriately caused by the boy: for nothing gets in the way, nothing at all. No realist, however direct, can plausibly deny that there is a causal process involved in seeing the boy, that perception is a causally mediated process. Nor can any sensible direct realist deny that there is indeed a phenomenological state involved in perception, at least in the case of creatures like ourselves. The existence of the phenomenological state can be made vivid precisely by the point that a realistic hallucination could in principle be completely indistinguishable from the veridical perception of the boy. We may say, then, that the perception of the boy is experientially direct, perceptually direct, judgementally direct; but it is also, of course, causally mediated, and the causal mediation involves, in addition to light waves, sound waves, and so on, a richly propertied, richly contentful, internal representation. The Brentanian proposal that the internal phenomenological aspect of the perception is part of its intentional content, in addition to the boy, does not interfere with the direct realism about the boy. The internal phenomenological aspect is obviously something of which one is directly aware, but it does not follow that the boy is not directly perceived. This is because being in the internal phenomenological state just is directly perceiving the boy (given that the external connections are right). The current proposal is also comfortably externalist in that it takes the boy and the trumpet to be part of the content of what is perceived, part of the content of the perception (just as it takes the boy and the trumpet to be part of the content of what is believed or thought about, if belief or thought is in question). It differs from extreme externalism in that it denies that everything about the content of a perception is determined by external relations. It simply sees no reason to deny that whatever the perceptual experiences of X and Y and the hallucinator have in common (p. 506) (and it is

Page 12 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience ex hypothesi the case that they have something fundamental in common) can be called part of the content of their perceptual experience.

29.9 ‘Disjunctivism’ Some of those who call themselves direct realists in the current debate deny that the veridical perception and the hallucination have any content in common. They do this by defining content in a wholly externalist way, with the result that the hallucination has no content at all (or has a very different kind of content from genuine perception). This line of thought prepares the way for a view sometimes known as disjunctivism. In John Foster's terms, disjunctivists define perceptual experiences that are veridical perceptions as essentially ‘physically perceptive’; that is, as psychological states whose identity depends essentially on the existence of the physical object that they are perceptions of (see Foster 2000). By contrast, perceptual experiences that are not veridical perceptions, like hallucinations, are not ‘physically perceptive’. This then allows these extreme direct realists to say that the types of psychological states involved in veridical perception and hallucination are (radically) different—they are fundamentally different psychological kinds. In the case of veridical perception we have a psychological state of the physically perceptive kind, whereas in hallucination we don't have a psychological state of that kind at all. This, however, seems an uneasy and wholly unnecessary move, because admitting the commonality between hallucination and veridical perceptions does not interfere in any way with the ‘direct access’ to objects sought by direct realism. The present position is thus anti‐disjunctivist. That is, it rejects the idea that a hallucination and a qualitatively indistinguishable veridical perception can be said to be psychological states of completely different kinds. Some have tried to identify anti‐ disjunctivism with indirect realism, but we have already seen that the first does not entail the second, and in considering some of the other terms in which these matters have been debated I will from now on use the expression ‘anti‐disjunctivist’.

Page 13 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

29.10 Modes of Presentation This issue can be re‐expressed in terms of modes of presentation, a notion first introduced by Frege in his discussion of the content of thoughts and beliefs and extended to the case of perceptual experience. In this terminology we may say that internal features of perceptual experiences, phenomenological modes of presentation (whether sensory or cognitive), are presentations of objects and properties, but that this does not involve any indirectness in the perception of objects and properties, even though the presentations are themselves part of what is given in experience. What these presentations do is directly present objects. So when the relevant physical object (p. 507) exists, in the right causal relations to oneself, one's perceptual experience provides one with direct access to that object (see e.g. McGinn 1989).25 I cannot here give a full account of perceptual modes of presentation, but, whatever the full account, they will be complex structures whose full specification will make essential reference to phenomenological content. For example, seeing that a chair is yellow will essentially involve a visual mode of presentation of the property yellowness. Some may now ask whether modes of presentation are to be understood as object‐ dependent or object‐independent.26 This is in effect just another way of expressing the difference between psychological states that are ‘physically perceptive’, in Foster's terms, and those that are not (although those who accept the terminology of physically perceptive states may reject the terminology of modes of presentation). According to the object‐dependent view, a mode of presentation of an object depends on the existence of the relevant object for its existence; it is essentially object‐involving. If the object in question does not exist, then neither does the relevant mode of presentation. This view of modes of presentation, then, goes hand in hand with externalism and disjunctivism. If in the case of genuine perception the mode of presentation depends on the existence of the particular object being perceived, then that same mode of presentation cannot occur in the absence of that object. Thus, the modes of presentation that feature in veridical perception, and that constitute its content, simply will not feature in hallucination.27 Object‐independent modes of presentation, by contrast, are essentially general in nature. They are ‘ways in which things can appear’ that are not tied to particular objects. Plainly the same chairish mode of presentation can feature in a hallucination and a particular veridical perception.28 Such a view, therefore, may be anti‐disjunctivist.

Page 14 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

29.11 The Particularity of Perception One motivation for object‐dependent modes of presentation is the particularity of perception, which has a phenomenological aspect. It is a phenomenological feature of perceptual experiences that they present us with particular objects such as cats, dogs, and chairs (see e.g. Campbell 2002: ch. 6; Martin 2002). The object‐dependent account has it that the particularity of perception is built into the mode of (p. 508) presentation, since the mode of presentation is itself object‐involving; the idea is then that object‐ independent modes of presentation, on their own, do not isolate a unique object, and that the particularity of perceptual experiences must therefore be explained by something else, presumably something outside of thought. McGinn (1989, 1997) accounts for the particularity of perception in terms of the causal relations that exist between perceptual experiences and the objects they are causally related to. Perceptual experiences are anchored in the world in virtue of being causally related to unique objects.29 But one consequence of McGinn's view, which he recognizes, is that the answer to the question of which particular object a perceptual experience is about depends only on whatever causes it in the relevant way, even if its internal components quite radically misrepresent the object in question. McDowell, following Evans, objects that McGinn's ‘two‐factor’ view does not really explain the particular‐object‐directedness of perceptual experiences, or indeed thought in general. On McGinn's view, it seems, perception is not in itself object‐directed. Modes of presentation are perfectly general and so cannot on their own isolate particular objects. How can we then characterize perception, or thought—in themselves—as object‐directed? McDowell concludes by embracing disjunctivism, with its essentially object‐dependent modes of presentation, on the grounds that it is a consequence of giving a satisfactory explanation of the object‐directedness of perceptual experiences. Disjunctivism also has severe troubles, however, as already noted, in insisting that there is no sense in which subjectively indistinguishable veridical perceptions and hallucinations can be said to be mental states of the same psychological kind. Some disjunctivists attempt to capture this commonality with the following description: a perception of a purple table and a hallucination of a purple table are both subjectively indistinguishable from a perception of a purple table (see McDowell 1986). What one wants, however, is some theoretical account of why this is the case, and of why and how it is that one cannot in a particular case know for sure (even if one is a disjunctivist) whether one is really perceiving a table or, under hypnosis, merely hallucinating a table. It is natural, at this point, to say the profound commonality of the two states is due to their both being of a single psychological kind.

Page 15 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience

29.12 The Matching View Another deep axis of disagreement now emerges: the difference between those theories that give internal components of perceptual experience a role in determining which particular object if any is being perceived, and those that do not. As remarked, two‐factor views such as McGinn's do not give internal components of perceptual (p. 509) experience any essential role in determining which particular object if any is being perceived.30 McDowell and Evans, by contrast, do give internal components of perceptual experiences an essential role by invoking object‐dependent modes of presentation, which are essentially object‐directed. To some this may seem like begging the question. But whether or not one accepts their idea, there are surely limits on what the (internal) phenomenological content of perceptual experience caused in me by the impacts of light waves reflected from a tree can be like if it is to be true that I am seeing a tree, and indeed seeing that tree. In conclusion I will briefly sketch a view that seeks to capture some of what is intuitively correct on both sides. The ‘matching view’, as I will call it, gives an essential role to internal components of perceptual experience in determining which object is being perceived, because it holds that in order for a perceptual experience to be about an object there must be a certain degree of matching between the properties an object has and the properties the experience represents the object as having. But it doesn't invoke object‐dependent modes of presentation, or risk disjunctivism. Suppose one is in causal, sensory, and indeed visual contact with a garden shed. However, due to a disorder in one's visual system, or perhaps a hypnotic command, when one looks at the shed one has an experience as of a pink elephant. Despite one's inaccurate conception one can locate and track the shed. But does one see the shed? It is arguable that one does not, because one's conception of it is simply too inaccurate. On this view, to stand in a causal, sensory, and indeed visual relation to an object is not enough to guarantee that one sees it, and this is so even if this relation allows one to locate and track the object: to truly see an object, one's experience (conception) of the object must not be wildly inaccurate. The general principle, then, is that if there is to be perception of the object then there must be a certain degree of match between the properties represented in the (internal) experience and the properties of the object, even if it is impossible to determine the lower bound on matching with any precision. The claim is that there can be a fatal failure of match even when the external conditions of perception are sufficiently met. If this is correct, internal components of perceptual experiences play an essential role in determining which object (if any) one sees. The matching view therefore meets McDowell's desideratum that internal components of perceptual experiences play a necessary role in determining the object of perception, and the internal component it appeals to is precisely the overall sensory‐cognitive Page 16 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience phenomenological state, considered now in all its fullness, the very thing in virtue of whose existence it is true to say that one directly perceives the object. It requires a sufficient degree of match, however exactly this is to be determined. (The same goes for thought.) There are, no doubt, many difficulties with this view. My present claim is only that it seeks to occupy a place that any satisfactory theory of perceptual experience—of perception—must occupy.31

References Anscombe, E. (1965), ‘The Intentionality of Sensation: A Grammatical Feature’, in Anscombe, Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: Collected Papers, ii (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press), 3–20. Bach, K. (1994), Thought and Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Brentano, F. (1874/1973), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. L. McAlister, trans. L. L. McAlister, A. Rancurello, and D. B. Terrell (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. —— (1991), ‘Vision and Intentional Content’, in E. Lepore and R. Van Gulick (eds.), John Searle and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell), 195–214. Campbell, J. (2002), Reference and Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Caston, V. (2002), ‘Aristotle on Consciousness’, Mind, 111: 751–815. Chalmers, D. (2004), ‘The Representational Character of Experience’, in B. Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–81. Crane, T. (2003), ‘The Intentional Structure of Consciousness’, in A. Jokic and Q. Smith (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press), 33–56. Dewey, J. (1896), ‘The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology’, Psychological Review, 3: 357– 70. Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Foster, J. (2000), The Nature of Perception (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Gibson, J. (1979), The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin).

Page 17 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience Gurwitsch, A. (1941/1966), ‘A Non‐egological Conception of Consciousness’, in Gurwitsch, Studies in Phenomenology and Psychology (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press), 287–300. Harman, G. (1990), ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives, 4: 31–52. Heidegger, M. (1927/1962), Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell). Horgan, T., and Tienson, J. (2002), ‘The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality’, in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 520–33. Husserl, E. (1893–1917/1991), On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time, trans. J. Barnett Brough (Dordrecht: Kluwer). Kriegel, U. (2003), ‘Consciousness as Intransitive Self‐consciousness: Two Views and an Argument’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33: 103–32. Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). McDowell, J. (1984), ‘De Re senses’, in C. Wright (ed.), Frege: Tradition and Influence (Oxford: Blackwell), 98–109. —— (1986), ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space’, in P. Pettit and J. McDowell (eds.), Subject, Thought, and Context (Oxford: Clarendon), 137–68. —— (1994), Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). McGinn, C. (1989), Mental Content (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1997), The Character of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Martin, M. G. F. (2002), ‘Particular Thoughts and Singular Thought’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Logic, Thought and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 173–214. —— (2004), ‘The Limits of Self‐awareness’, Philosophical Studies, 120: 37–89. Moore, G. E. (1903), ‘The Refutation of Idealism’, Mind, 12: 433–53. Noe, A. (2004), Action in Perception (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Peacocke, C. (2001), ‘Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?’, Journal of Philosophy, 98: 239–64. (p. 511)

Pitt, D. (2004), ‘The Phenomenology of Cognition, or What Is It Like to Think That P?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69: 1–36.

Page 18 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, ii (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 215–71. Reid, T. (1785/2002), Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press). Robinson, H. (1994), Perception (London: Routledge). Schiffer, S. (1995), ‘Descriptions, Indexicals, and Belief Reports: Some Dilemmas—But Not the Ones You Expect’, Mind, 104: 107–31. Segal, G. (1991), ‘Defense of a Reasonable Individualism’, Mind, 100: 485–94. Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Siegel, S. (2006), ‘Subject and Object in the Contents of Visual Experience’, Philosophical Review, 115: 355–88. Siewert, C. (1998), The Significance of Consciousness (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Smith, D. (1989), The Circle of Acquaintance (Dordrecht: Kluwer). —— (2005), ‘Consciousness and Reflexive Content’, in D. Smith and A. Thomasson (eds.), Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 93–114. Snowdon, P. (1980), ‘Perception, Vision, and Causation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81: 175–92. Strawson, G. (1994), Mental Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2008), Real Materialism and Other Essays (Oxford: Clarendon Press). Thomasson, A. (2000), ‘After Brentano: A One‐level Theory of Consciousness’, European Journal of Philosophy, 8: 190–209. Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2000), Consciousness, Color and Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Williamson, T. (1990), Identity and Discrimination (Oxford: Blackwell). Zahavi, D. (2006), Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First‐person Perspective (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Notes: Page 19 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience (1) Some philosophers argue that there are non‐factive uses of perceptual verbs (see e.g. Anscombe 1965). (2) The causal claim has been challenged, e.g. by Snowdon (1980). (3) The correct characterization of subjective (or phenomenal) indistinguishability is controversial. Some take it to involve objective phenomenological sameness. Others (e.g. Williamson 1990; Martin 2004) argue that taking phenomenal sameness to be anything more than an epistemic property of indistinguishability (from a subject's point of view) is a substantive claim. (4) The ‘problem’ of scepticism seems insoluble but also quite unimportant for the present discussion. (5) ‘Present’ is preferable to ‘represent’ in so far as the meaning of ‘represent’ has in recent discussion been changed. Its natural factive meaning (if anything—including a hallucination—represents a chair, then it does indeed represent a chair!) has been given a merely ‘externalist’ (see below) reading according to which a hallucination of a chair does not represent anything. This is a very unnatural use of ‘represent’, and although ‘present’ can be treated in the same way, I think it helps a little. (6) The nature of cognitive phenomenology is something that needs independent discussion. For some recent work see e.g. Smith (1989), Strawson (1994: ch. 1), Siewert (1998), Horgan and Tienson (2002), Pitt (2004), Strawson (2008). (7) Following Crane (2003) and Chalmers (2004). (It is generally called an ‘attitude’.) Chalmers distinguishes between manners of representation and (4) modes of presentation. (8) Some think that it is three‐place relation between (1), (3), and (4). For a good statement of this see Schiffer (1995). (9) In fact, though, it is not at all clear that I can really be said to continue to have the perception, rather than just a thought, if I am focusing just on the B‐content. (10) Here I have in mind everything that is true in the ‘enactive’ theory of perception found, for example, in Dewey (1896), Heidegger (1927/1962), Gibson (1979), Noë (2004), and others. (11) For a good recent account see Zahavi (2006). (12) Aristotle puts the point by saying that ‘we perceive that we perceive’ (see below). The former kind of perceiving is obviously different from the latter. In short, the claim is not that we see that we see. What the first occurrence of perception amounts to is a very controversial and big issue. See Caston (2002) for some discussion. The present claim is

Page 20 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience simply that whatever its full account, it will involve appeal to phenomenological properties. (13) In phenomenologists' terms, phenomenological properties are part of the ‘noema’, the content or object, of a ‘noesis’, in this case a particular experience. (14) Reid (1785/2002: essay II, ch. 16) gives a very good diagnosis of this error and notes how natural it is. (15) This is itself the topic of an interesting debate. (16) See in particular Caston (2002). Aristotle has a first‐order view. (17) For a (differently focused) higher‐order‐without‐regress strategy see Rosenthal (Ch. 13 above). (18) It is important that ‘aware of my being conscious of it’ is not read as involving any consciousness of self considered as such. Gurwitsch's central point in this paper is that ‘the subject in his dealing with the object, aware as he is of this dealing, is nevertheless in no way aware of his ego, much less of his ego's involvement in his dealing’ (1941/1966: 327). (19) Many who agree with Brentano's basic position reject his use of ‘object’ in the phrase ‘secondary object’, but the broad use of ‘object’ amounts to no more than ‘what is given to the subject’, and in that use I think it can be accepted. For other examples of non‐higher‐order views see Thomasson (2000), Kriegel (2003), Smith (2005), and Zahavi (2006). (20) Note that ‘representationalism’ is used to mean the opposite of what one would expect it to mean. It is natural to expect it to be used for a theory that distinguishes sharply between the object of perception and the representation of the object of perception, even if it is not used, as it might well be, as a name for a full‐blown representative theory of perception of a Lockean kind, according to which what we directly perceive, when we perceive a chair, is only a representation of a chair, by virtue of which we can be said to perceive (but only indirectly) the chair itself. (21) It could be said to be a variety of what Chalmers (2004) calls ‘nonreductive representationalism’. (22) See Putnam (1975), Burge (1979), Kripke (1980) for classic accounts of externalism. (23) How much content is internalist is controversial. See Segal (1991) for a wholly internalist view and Chalmers (2004) for a partial internalist view. (24) The debate between direct and indirect realism assumes realism about material objects, as its name suggests. For contemporary accounts of idealism—the view that

Page 21 of 22

The Content of Perceptual Experience material objects are not logically independent of the human mind—see Robinson (1994) and Foster (2000). (25) For present purposes I focus on modes of presentations of physical objects although the term has a wider use. (26) For the first see e.g. Evans (1982) and McDowell (1984); for the second see e.g. McGinn (1989, 1997). It is unfortunate that some use ‘mode of presentation’ and the Fregean term ‘sense’ almost interchangeably in this debate, and I will stick to ‘mode of presentation’. (27) In the absence of material objects, Evans (1982) seems to vacillate between saying the psychological state in question has no content and the content is different. (28) There is another alternative in the literature (see e.g. Burge 1991; Bach 1994), which I will not discuss here, according to which what can be common to a hallucination and a genuine perception is a gappy entity similar to an open sentence, e.g. x is a purple table. Only genuine perceptions have object values for the gap. (29) Of course there are well‐known problems for stating the appropriate causal link between a perception and the relevant object. (30) See Evans's criticisms of the ‘photograph model’ (1982: ch. 3). (31) Thanks to: George Bealer, Brian McLaughlin, Susanna Siegel, Dave Chalmers, Dan Zahavi, David Smith, and especially Galen Strawson.

Michelle Montague

Michelle Montague is Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, Oxford University, St John's College.

Page 22 of 22

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind

Oxford Handbooks Online Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind   George Graham, Terence Horgan, and John Tienson The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0031

Abstract and Keywords Phenomenology, the movement, has contributed and continues to contribute much to the study of phenomenal consciousness as well as to understanding the role of intentionality in our conscious lives. This article, however, is not about intellectual history or methodological movements. So it is not about such contributions. There is nothing in this article about the movement (Phenomenology) but much about the property (phenomenology). The word ‘intentionality’ is a technical word for the feature of a mental state in virtue of which it is directed at or is about or represents something other than itself. Keywords: phenomenology, intentionality, unity of the mind, mental state, phenomenal consciousness, conscious lives

30.1 Introduction: Are We of One or Two Minds? WE

persons are conscious as well as intentional beings. There is something it is like to be

us. We also represent things in the world, as well as ourselves. Partly for such reasons, the mental or our being minded is said to have two defining properties or features. The first is phenomenology or the conscious character of our form of mentality. The second is intentionality or its representational feature. ‘Phenomenology’? ‘Intentionality’? We have just deployed two technical words. These two words also occur in the chapter's title. So before taking a single step, or even stating our intentions in this chapter, something must be said about them. Page 1 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind In the professional literature ‘phenomenology’ is used in two different ways. First, it is used to refer to a method or movement in philosophy developed by (p. 513) Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) and some of his followers such as Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), Jean‐Paul Sartre (1905–80), and Maurice Merleau‐Ponty (1908–61). Phenomenology is not a method or movement that is easy to characterize. This is because it possesses no clearly delineated doctrines. However, it may be said, with pronounced oversimplification, that the method consists of an analysis of what it means to live as a human being in a ‘conscious world’ (a world both in and of which we are consciously aware). Second, the word ‘phenomenology’ is also used for the feature of conscious experience that makes conscious experience conscious: its phenomenology. Its phenomenology is the something it is like to have or undergo an experience. A mental state is phenomenological or phenomenally conscious just when there is something it is like to be in that state. There is something it is like to see a vivid red, to feel a sharp pain, to visualize the Empire State Building, and to entertain the thought that it is sunny in Arizona. Each of these mental states has a conscious character, with phenomenal or phenomenological properties (or qualities; see discussion below) characterizing what it is like to be in the state.1 Phenomenology, the movement, has contributed and continues to contribute much to the study of phenomenal consciousness as well as to understanding the role of intentionality in our conscious lives. This chapter, however, is not about intellectual history or methodological movements. So it is not about such contributions. There is nothing in this chapter about the movement (Phenomenology) but much about the property (phenomenology). The word ‘intentionality’ is a technical word for the feature of a mental state in virtue of which it is directed at or is about or represents something other than itself. We persons think about or represent all sorts of things: red sunsets, pains in the neck, the Empire State Building, and the sun in Arizona. There is no question that the conscious‐experience feature of mentality (phenomenology) is at least sometimes associated with the being‐about‐something feature (intentionality). Our most salient representational mental states are phenomenally conscious states: there typically is something it is like to be about the external world. Similarly, our most salient conscious states typically represent things other than themselves. In typical cases of experiencing red, for example, the overall phenomenal character of one's visual experience is that of experiencing a visually presented scene—including the property of redness occurring as if on the surfaces of external objects. However, in twentieth‐century Anglo‐American philosophy any association between phenomenology and intentionality has often been said to be not intimate, perhaps just coincidental. As the Anglo‐American tradition has tended to interpret the situation, a mental state can be intentional without being phenomenological and a mental state can be phenomenological without being intentional. Summarizing the tradition Jaegwon Kim (1998: 101) writes: ‘It has been customary to distinguish between two broad categories of mental phenomena, (p. 514) the intentional and the phenomenal’. Kim is among those sympathetic to the dissociation of phenomenology and intentionality. He writes: ‘If someone should ask us to create a Page 2 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind device with consciousness … I don't think we even know how to begin’ (1998: 102). However, Kim adds, if asked to design a structure with intentionality ‘it seems to me that we can go about designing’ such things (1998: 103). Is Kim right? Can the one (intentionality) occur or be created without the other (phenomenology)? If so, that would be one‐way independence or separateness of intentionality from phenomenology. Others say that the phenomenological is independent of the intentional. John Searle (1983: 2), for example, offers the examples of forms of elation, depression, or anxiety in which one is not ‘elated, depressed, or anxious about anything’. ‘Many conscious states’, he says, ‘are not intentional.’ If so, that would be independence in the other direction: of phenomenology from intentionality.2 With the possibility of two‐way or bilateral independence of intentionality and phenomenology, one may ask whether the mental with its two defining properties is a unified phenomenon. The problem of the unity of mind is, roughly, the problem of whether, and if so how, phenomenology and intentionality are related to each other. Separatism (or the thesis of bilateral independence), roughly, is the thesis that phenomenology and intentionality are mutually independent of one another. Either sort of property can occur without the other.3 The opposite view is inseparatism, the thesis that phenomenology and intentionality are inseparable. According to inseparatism we are of one mind—a structurally integrated what‐it's‐likeness of representing or being directed at the world or ourselves. In some sense: No phenomenology without intentionality, and no intentionality without phenomenology.4 Given theoretically different dimensions along which, or sorts of mental states in which, either the separability or inseparability of the phenomenological and intentional may be said to occur, various versions of separatism and inseparatism have been proposed or categorized in the literature (see Siewert 2003; Chalmers 2004).5 (p. 515) Our concern in this chapter is to spell out separatist and inseparatist theses as well as key terms used in their description. We say something about why one might hold, as we now do, that despite its relative unpopularity within Anglo‐American philosophy inseparatism is true. We mention some prominent objections to inseparatism and say something about how an inseparatist of the specific variety or type that we favour might reply to each. Our strategy here is not merely expository, but positive or positional. We aim to defend a position. Elements of the inseparatist position defended here are described and defended by us in a series of earlier papers.6 The present chapter is complementary to the papers in that series. Although entirely self‐contained, it develops the position beyond what is said there by further exploring ideas of unity of mind, determinacy of intentional content, and the phenomenal and conceptual components in our conscious intentional lives (see especially Graham et al. 2007; Horgan and Graham forthcoming). Other philosophers have developed inseparatist or virtually inseparatist positions similar to ours in various respects. We comment upon some of this work, but given space

Page 3 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind limitations we do not resolutely explore professional discussion of inseparatist theses or separatist counter‐arguments. Our immediate focus is on defending the specific version of inseparatism that we favour.

30.2 Terms of Disagreement First, let us introduce some additional conceptual or terminological preliminaries including further description of consciousness, intentionality, separatism, and inseparatism.

30.2.1 Conscious Experience What is conscious experience or phenomenal consciousness? There is no non‐contentious, non‐circular characterization that can be provided. The best that can be done is one or another type of pointing to the phenomenon, offering examples, and providing synonyms (like ‘subjective experience’). Examples include: the ways things look, taste, or smell; the way pain feels; what it is like to hear Swedish spoken (depending upon whether you understand or fail to comprehend the language); the facial appearance of one's mother; certain bodily pleasures; the sound of singing birds. (p. 516)

An essential feature of conscious experience is that the character of conscious experience presents itself immediately or directly to the conscious person or subject. The immediacy of conscious experience to the subject is sometimes said to be what it is like to have the experience (Nagel 1974). It is also referred to as its like‐thisness or phenomenal character. So, for example, when you taste sweet chocolate there is an immediate way in which the chocolate seems to you: it tastes sweet. There is an immediate experiential presentation of sweetness. This presentational immediacy of sweetness is the like‐ thisness or phenomenal character of the experience of tasting sweet chocolate. Phenomenal character is sometimes also spoken of as the qualitative character of experience or as its quale (plural qualia) (see Flanagan 1992: 65). Pain, for example, appears to have at least three different qualitative dimensions: intensity, aversiveness, and type (e.g. ‘stabbing’, ‘shooting’, ‘throbbing’, etc.). Each of these qualitative dimensions contributes to what Nicholas Georgalis (2003) speaks of as uniformly type‐ identifiable qualities that help to distinguish pain from, say, itchiness, which instantiates different qualities. Itches, for example, tend to be less negative or aversive than pains. Non‐sensory, non‐perceptual, and non‐emotional instances of conscious experience may have no distinctive or proprietary qualities of a feeling (as one has in the case of pain) or of an imagistic sort (as one has in the cases of sensory or perceptual images). No feelings or images may be proprietary or distinctive, for example, to immediately seeming to Page 4 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind understand the meaning of words spoken in your mother tongue. Compare, however, what it is like to listen to a conversation in your mother tongue (English, let us assume) with what it is like to listen to a conversation in a language you completely and utterly fail to comprehend (Swedish, let us assume). The English utterances will immediately sound different to you than the Swedish utterances, not just as sounds, but as comprehended in meaning in the first case, and as uncomprehended in the second. Meaning comprehension, writes Barry Dainton, can be ‘as much a phenomenal feature of what [you] hear as the timbre and pitch of [a] voice’ (2000: 12). Even though non‐sensory, non‐perceptual, and non‐emotional instances of conscious experience may lack feeling or images, we maintain that it still makes sense to speak of such experiences possessing a qualitative or phenomenal character. Whenever a proprietary and distinctive feeling or image is part of the phenomenology of a conscious state, we shall speak of its phenomenal qualities in a narrow sense (restricted to its defining feeling or image, whether sensory or otherwise). This is quite compatible with the claim that phenomenology as such has the quality or attribute of self‐presentational immediacy and that in a broad or more general sense phenomenally conscious states are states in which qualia are instantiated—in the form of such states' presentationally immediate qualities or properties (whether or not feelings or images are present). To illustrate: Consider consciously entertaining a thought. Suppose you are thinking of Arizona. ‘Thoughts often appear without any distinctive sensory garb’, says Dainton. ‘Yet [their] content could not be clearer’ (Dainton 2000: 13; see also Strawson 1994). Arizona thoughts immediately appear to you as thoughts of Arizona. (p. 517)

The immediate content of Arizona thoughts may or may not be accompanied by qualitative elements of a feeling or imagistic kind. But we should not mistake such accompaniments for a proprietary or distinctive phenomenology associated with thinking of Arizona. They are not essential to the immediate presentation (conscious experience) of an Arizona thought. Suppose I feel parched in thinking of Arizona. Or suppose I imagine the face of a Navajo Indian. No such feelings or images are constitutive or definitive of thinking of Arizona. I may think of Arizona with or without them. This is quite compatible with the claim that an Arizona thought has the quality of being presentationally immediate and that what it is like to think about Arizona is distinctively different than what it is like to think about, say, Alaska. That distinctive difference is its quale, but it is a kind of cognitive quale, rather than a sensory or imagistic one.7 On our view there is a difficulty philosophers get into (like Kim, for example) when they refer to conscious experience period as states with qualitative character but do not distinguish between qualia in the narrow and broad sense, all the while assuming that conscious experiences possess qualia in the narrow sense. The difficulty is that some states (such as consciously thinking of Arizona) typically do not possess anything narrowly qualitative. They are not endowed with constitutive narrow qualia. Meanwhile defences of separatism sometimes presuppose that phenomenal character just is narrow Page 5 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind qualitative character. Then, it is argued by separatists, intentionality is separable from consciousness because intentional states qua intentional lack distinctive and proprietary sensory or imagistic qualitative characters, whereas conscious experience instantiates them. Such a description of conscious experience defeats one form of inseparatism. However, it's an indefensible form of inseparatism that is defeated; namely, one that mistakenly requires narrow qualitative character of conscious thought, and thus mistakingly subsumes phenomenology in general under the rubric of sensory or imagistic phenomenology. A person can think in a manner that is utterly devoid of uniformly type‐identifiable qualia of the narrow sort. Of course, some intentional states actually do have immediately apparent qualities in the narrow (and not just broad) sense and not as mere accompaniments but as constitutive of the state. If I tell you that I am thirsty and desire a drink, it may make sense for you to ask, ‘How desirous do you feel?’; and it would not suffice for me to say, ‘Oh, I just have the desire without feeling anything’. When thirsty you may feel desirous of a drink and you may report how much you desire it. Desire for a drink is (as will be appreciated after the discussion of intentionality to follow) an intentional state. Felt intensity is an essential feature of some instances of desiring. For inseparatists such as the three of us, fortunately, talk of conscious experience does not commit one to the view that narrow as opposed to broad qualitative character is essential to conscious experience. The spectrum of conscious experience, as Galen Strawson remarks (1994: 4), ranges from ‘the most purely sensory (p. 518) experiences to the most abstractly cognitive experiences’. These last include ‘the experience of consciously entertained thought, of reading and understanding, of unplanned fantasy, and of directed imagining’. Some experiences, especially those on the sensory, mood, and emotion side of the spectrum, involve proprietary and distinctive feelings (or images), but others, including those on the cognitive side (such as the experience of consciously entertained thought), do not. Alvin Goldman writes as follows: A person can be immediately aware of ‘having a determinate thought‐content’. ‘Entertaining [such a] conceptual unit has a phenomenology, just not a sensory phenomenology’ (1993: 365). ‘Thoughts’, Owen Flanagan writes (1992: 65) referring to consciously entertained thought, ‘seem in a certain way’, though, he says, ‘they don't have the sort of robust qualitative feel that sensations have.’ They needn't, we hasten to add by way of clarification, have any feel proper to them, robust or not.

30.2.2 Self‐Presentational Immediacy We will call our conception of (phenomenally) conscious experience the self‐ presentational immediacy conception. It may be described as follows, using a case of conscious visual perception as an example. Consider the kinds of evidence to which I might appeal in establishing the truth of the following two statements. Page 6 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind (1) There is a tree over there [said when pointing] that's dying. (2) There is a tree over there [said when pointing] in front of me. The evidence that might support the truth of (1) might include the following: what a tree expert told me about the tree, time‐delayed photographs of the gradual decline of the tree, whether the tree fails to support bird‐life, and so on.

Let's call the evidence just cited for (1) ‘indirect’ or ‘inferential’ (treating these synonymously). We are calling the evidence ‘indirect’ (etc.) because we are supposing that in saying that a tree is dying, and indeed, by extension, in observing that a tree is dying I infer from the evidence to something about a tree: that it is dying. Given the indirectness there is inferential room for epistemic error. In such a case I might be misled. Experts, photographs, and the behaviour of wildlife can mislead in the sense that they might encourage or permit drawing incorrect conclusions. I might believe that a tree is dying when it is not. Let's call the fact or purported fact (in the hypothetical context of the example) that a tree is dying presentationally mediated (or indirectly evidenced). This fact or purported fact (a tree dying) is presented to me, as the perceiver, only indirectly, that is, through such evidence as the testimony of a tree expert, photographs, and so on. It is not, as it were, inherent in the perceptual experience. Let's compare the hypothetical evidence for (1) with that for (2). Suppose, in the full context of the example, that I am a normal perceiver with semantic competence with concepts like those of ‘tree’ and ‘being in front of’. If so, the evidence that supports the truth of (2) is, we might suppose, not indirect or inferential. Suppose (p. 519) that there being a tree in front of me is directly, self‐evidently, non‐inferentially, or immediately (we are treating these locutions as synonymous) evident or presented to me. After all, to see a tree as being in front of me I have merely to open my attentive eyes under normal viewing conditions. I don't have to talk to experts, examine photographs, or birdwatch. Having conscious content as of a tree in front of me is, as it were, inherent in the experience or intrinsic to its presented character. Indeed, to emphasize the immediacy or inherence of the content of the experience, note that I might have the very same conscious content without there actually being a presented objective scene of a tree in front of me. When I dream, for example, I might have the same sort of experience as of a tree being in front of me. There can be such an experience without there being some suitable kind of causal or evidential connection between what is going on in my head when I dream and the wider environment. So in the case of (2) (as described here) there apparently being a tree in front of me is manifest or presents itself to me without evidential mediation. Tree‐in‐front‐of‐me immediately appears to me. Four points about such presentational immediacy should be noted and are germane to the type of inseparatism we favour.

Page 7 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind (i) In general, to be immediately appeared to precludes being misled about the content of the experience, although it does not preclude being misled or mistaken about whether things truly are as they appear. It might immediately seem to me as if I am in front of a tree without it's being the case that I am, as it happens, in such a position. I might be dreaming or hallucinating. There‐seeming‐to‐be‐a‐tree‐in‐front‐of‐me might not be caused or environmentally associated in the right way (by my being facing the tree) to count as veridical or as a reliable indicator of the world independent of my experience.8 (ii) Immediate appearance or presentation has two dimensions: what it is of and whom it is to. Colin McGinn (1988/1997: 298) aptly refers to these components as ‘Janus‐faced’ features of conscious experience (see also Kriegel 2003). Thus, the perceptual experience of a tree is of something other than the subject (it is of a tree) but it also presents a subjective face to the subject. There apparently being a tree in front of oneself is like this to the subject having the experience. Because conscious experience possesses these two dimensions, we refer (above) to our concept of the content of conscious experience as the self‐presentational immediacy conception. Conscious content is not just immediate. It also presents itself to a self (subject) immediately or without evidential mediation. (iii) Conscious experience occurs to subjects possessed of varying degrees or types of conceptual or semantic competence. It is shaped by a subject's background competence. For example, in visually perceiving a tree it is perfectly possible and normal for one to be presented with a tree as a tree and not as an amorphous, jumbled, (p. 520) brownish‐ coloured shape. A young child may see it as such a shape; a normal adult may see a tree as a tree. To the child a tree‐appearance is not an appearance as of a tree. To the adult a tree‐appearance is as of a tree. To different degrees and in different aspects, in the words of William Seager, the entire realm of conscious experience is ‘ “parsed” by [our] conceptual apparatus and presented to … consciousness as a world of trees, cars, houses, people’, and so forth (1999: 188). (iv) One notion of consciousness that may seem close to that of conscious experience as immediate appearance or self‐presentational immediacy is what Ned Block (1995) calls ‘access consciousness’. A state of a subject is access conscious, says Block, just when it can be introspectively reported by the person and can govern her motor movements or behaviour. For example, I can report perceiving as if being in front of a tree and this perception may govern my behaviour of looking for Tabby the cat, who, I believe, has run up the tree in Professor Malcolm's garden. Block says that access consciousness is not one and the same as phenomenal consciousness but is a different sort of consciousness. We are sceptical. If conscious experience consists of self‐presentational immediacy, this fact helps to explain why phenomenal content—that which is immediately apparent—is reportable and can govern behaviour. Other things being equal, access to content is immediate given that content evidentially is immediate. Or, more precisely: so‐called access consciousness is not a different type of consciousness at all, but rather is a reportorial and behavioural competence afforded to a neurologically healthy subject

Page 8 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind under certain conditions when he or she is the subject of immediate appearance (conscious experience). We are not going to pause for extended discussion of each of the above four points. They are intended to clarify the notion of immediate self‐presentation. That notion is crucial for the brand of inseparatism we favour, that is intended to be free of allegiance to the proposition that conscious states qua conscious possess qualities in the narrow sense of sensory‐imagistic qualia. We make three general assumptions about conscious experience culled from the above discussion. (1) Conscious experiences are immediate appearances or direct presentations. (2) Some conscious experiences are narrowly qualitative in character; others are not. All conscious experiences, however, are qualitative in at least the broad sense of being constituted by distinctive and proprietary immediate appearances or presentations. (3) Conscious experiences are informed by a subject's semantic or conceptual competence. Now let us turn to the concept of intentionality.

Page 9 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind

30.2.3 Intentionality The concept of intentionality refers to that feature of a mental state or condition of a subject according to which the state or condition is about or represents something or has an object (Brentano 1874/1973). (p. 521)

‘Intentionality’ may be a misleading term for aboutness. It suggests intentional action, doing something intentionally, with a certain purpose or goal. However, many mental states or conditions are intentional without being a matter of a person's intending to do anything. Beliefs, for example, are intentional although believers, as such, don't intend to do anything. Intending to do something is just one type of intentionality among others. Here are some other examples (among dozens that may be mentioned) of types of states or conditions with intentionality: memory, fear, hope, love, hate, expectation, anger, shame, and disappointment. Intentional‐state types are sometimes called ‘attitudes’. Being intentional means that these states or attitudes are of or about something. I am angry that such‐and‐such, disappointed about so‐and‐so, etc. Being directed at something means that intentional states or attitudes have intentional objects and intentional content (sometimes also known as propositional or representational content). Suppose, for example, that you believe that a picture in your living room is hanging crooked. The intentional object is a photograph; the content is that the photograph is hanging crooked. The distinction between object and content can be characterized as follows. The ascription of an intentional state to a person typically involves the use of a that‐clause, as in ‘I believe that a picture in my living room is hanging crooked’. To the right of the that‐ clause is mentioned the content or proposition on which the intentional state is directed (‘that a picture in my living room is hanging crooked’). The so‐called (logically atomic) content includes the topic(s) of the that‐clause (‘the picture in the living room’) as well as the comment made about the topic (‘is hanging crooked’). Intentionality though relational is not an ordinary physical relation like that of touching or kissing. (Whether it is a non‐ordinary physical relation of a sort that physical science is committed to and can discover is discussed below.) I cannot touch something unless it exists, but I can think of something (a unicorn) even if it doesn't exist. The intentional object might not really exist. I can desire to ride a unicorn even though no unicorn exists. It is characteristic of intentional states or attitudes that there are two parts or components to them. One is the attitude type—believing, hoping, intending, etc.—and the other is the intentional content of the particular instance of the type. One and the same content can occur in different types of attitude. I can believe that a unicorn is in my

Page 10 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind backyard, I can desire that a unicorn be in my backyard, etc. One and the same type of attitude can harbour different contents. I can believe that a unicorn is in my backyard, I can believe that the picture is hanging crooked, etc. The object of an intentional attitude qua intentional object cannot be identified independently of the content. It can only be identified from inside, as it were, the content. Compare this fact with objects in ordinary physical relations. If Lois Lane kisses Clark Kent and Clark Kent is Superman, she kisses Superman. Contrast with the intentional domain: Lois Lane can believe that she kissed Clark Kent without believing that she kissed Superman. This fact of being ‘inside’ the intentional state (p. 522) contributes to the intentional inexistence of some intentional objects. I can think of unicorns, but, as it happens, there are no such creatures. A unicorn might ‘exist’ only in thought. Such an internal‐to‐content constraint on intentional‐object identification also contributes to what is known as the failure of substitution (‘intensionality’) in the idioms that are used to characterize the phenomena. Lois Lane believes that she kissed Clark Kent, but without believing that she kissed Superman, even though Clark Kent is Superman. So we cannot substitute ‘Superman’ for ‘Clark Kent’ without changing the truth‐value of the statement ‘Lois Lane believes that she kissed Clark Kent’.

Page 11 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind

30.2.4 Separatism and Inseparatism What is the disagreement between separatists and inseparatists about? At one level of description, as Charles Siewert notes (2003: 25), it's a disagreement about ‘how to conceive of the mind or domain of psychology as a whole’. It is about how to solve the problem of the unity of mind. Is there something that deserves to be called the unity of the mental? Inseparatism says yes. Separatism says no. Separatism says that the intentional mind and phenomenal mind are not intimately related. One exists on the intentional side of the intentionality/non‐intentionality divide. The other exists on the phenomenological side of the phenomenal‐character/non‐ phenomenal‐character divide. Meanwhile the phenomenological is non‐intentional and the intentional is non‐phenomenological. Inseparatism says that the intentional mind and phenomenal mind are intimately related. We are not of two distinct minds. Each is, in some sense, co‐present in the other. Intentionality is, in some sense, proper to phenomenology. Phenomenology is, in some sense, proper to intentionality. Together they unify the domain of the psychological and provide the concept of mentality with a univocal sense or meaning (at least in uncontroversial cases of mentality; see below). The above statements of separatism and inseparatism are fairly imprecise. A major reason for this imprecision is that attempts to define the core notions of intentionality and consciousness traverse essentially contested theoretical territory. So, for example, if it is assumed that intentionality is more scientifically tractable than consciousness, then one will believe that intentionality is independent of conscious experience. Or if one assumes, for another example, that consciousness necessarily is qualitative in the narrow sense and contains proprietary images or feelings, then, again, one may claim that this means that consciousness is independent of intentionality. Can such background assumptions be pruned from initial descriptions of consciousness and intentionality; that is to say, from descriptions offered before embrace or rejection of either separatism or inseparatism? It would be helpful and ecumenical to understand concepts like those of intentionality and phenomenology so as not to beg the question in favour of separatism or inseparatism. We have attempted to do just that in Sections 30.2.1–3.

(p. 523)

30.3 Conceiving Inseparability

We are inseparatists, though of a special sort. We advocate the following two theses about both phenomenology and intentionality: The intentionality of phenomenology (Thesis IP): Mental states that are uncontroversially (i.e. paradigmatically or incontestably) phenomenal (e.g. sensory‐

Page 12 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind perceptual states such as colour experiences, pains, and emotions) have intentional content that is inseparable from their phenomenal character. The phenomenology of intentionality (Thesis PI): Mental states that are uncontroversially intentional (e.g. cognitive states such as belief and conative states such as desire) have phenomenal character that is inseparable from their intentional content. In terms of these two theses we will now state the form of inseparatism that we favour and which we call moderate inseparatism: Mental states that uncontroversially have intentional content have phenomenal character (i.e. are conscious), and mental states that uncontroversially possess phenomenal character have intentional content directed at something (i.e. are possessed of intentionality). More or less equivalently: In uncontroversial (i.e. paradigmatic, exemplary, or incontestable) cases of mental intentionality, the fact that a mental state is intentional entails facts about the presence of phenomenal character; whereas in uncontroversial cases of phenomenal consciousness, the fact that a mental state is phenomenal entails facts about the presence of intentional content.

As we are putting things, to say that a mental state is uncontroversially X (mental‐ phenomenal, mental‐intentional) is to say that its being X is incontestable. It's a paradigm or exemplar of X. It is a state that competent speakers would not question or doubt as being of the X sort. Pains, for example, are mental states that are uncontroversially phenomenal; they are incontestable instances of the phenomenally conscious sort. The desire that a unicorn run across a lawn, for example, is a mental state that is uncontroversially intentional; it is an incontestable instance of the intentional sort. So understood, the distinction between uncontroversial/incontestable, on the one hand, and controversial/contestable, on the other, is a broadly epistemic distinction. It is a distinction between cases of robust (paradigmatic or exemplary) warrant for classifying a state as phenomenological or intentional, respectively, and cases in which the warrant falters or can reasonably be challenged by competent speakers. Moderate separatism is quite compatible with the claim that if a state can be shown to be phenomenological or intentional, even if not incontestably so, it, too, might also be intentional in content or phenomenological in character, respectively. Such a stronger or less moderate inseparatism, however, would require much more detailed discussion and examination than we have the space for in this chapter. On our view the inseparability of consciousness and intentionality, though framed by us as moderate, nonetheless is pervasive and estimable, raising deep questions not just about the scientific tractability of intentionality (to be considered later) but about (p. 524) a variety of different issues in the philosophy of mind including the issue (to be described momentarily) of whether intentional content is constitutively determined by something ‘inside the head’ or partially ‘outside the head’.

30.3.1 Defending Moderate Inseparatism

Page 13 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind The first thesis of moderate inseparatism, namely Thesis IP, has advocates—of a sort. So‐ called representationalist theories of phenomenal consciousness are a currently influential departure from separatism about phenomenology (see Dretske 1995; Tye 1995). According to representationalism, everything in the category of mental states paradigmatically cited as conscious is included in the category of states that are intentional or directed at something. Our perceptual experiences inform us about the local environment. Emotions have intentional objects (as when I feel ashamed for having committed a cowardly act). According to representationalism, even what John Searle calls (1983: 2) being ‘simply elated, depressed, or anxious without being elated, depressed or anxious about anything’, contrary to Searle, is intentional. Objectless depression is a kind of representation of everything (not of any one particular thing or circumstance) as negative. It's a way of being conscious of things in general: everything is perceived to be worthless or pointless. Or, as a depressed character in Ingmar Bergman's Scenes from a Marriage puts it: ‘Everything's getting meaner and grayer, with no dignity’ (see Church 2003: 175>). Sensations such as pain are experienced as having a (represented) location (as phantom‐limb pains demonstrate). (See Seager 1999: 132–77 for a generally sympathetic discussion of representationalism.) Most extant versions of representationalism, including those of Dretske and Tye, say that the intentional content of phenomenal states is constitutively determined by certain objective relations (e.g. certain kinds of correlational relations) between the occurrence of these states and the presence, in a cognitive agent's surrounding environment, of certain external properties or features, such as the red surfaces of external objects. This means, in effect, that phenomenal character ‘isn't in the head’. In some sense, phenomenal character is constitutively determined in part by what is in the outer world. Elsewhere we have defended a claim we call phenomenal intentionality according to which phenomenology is not constitutively dependent upon anything ‘outside the head’ of the experiencing subject and according to which there is a kind of intentionality (which we call ‘phenomenal intentionality’) that is entirely constituted by facts internal or intrinsic to the phenomenology that pervades our mental lives (see Horgan and Tienson 2002; Horgan et al. 2004). Among the different aspects of this ‘inside the head’ phenomenology, including the phenomenologies of sensory, emotional, and imagistic experience which are not mentioned below, are the following. The phenomenology of perceptual experience: the enormously rich and complex what‐it's‐ like of being perceptually immediately presented with a world of apparent objects, apparently instantiating a rich range of properties and relations—including (p. 525) one's own apparent body, apparently interacting with other apparent objects which apparently occupy various apparent spatial relations as apparently perceived from one's own apparent‐body‐centred point of view. The phenomenology of agency: the complex what‐it's‐like of apparently voluntarily controlling one's apparent body as it apparently moves around in, and apparently interacts with, apparent objects in its apparent environment. Page 14 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind The phenomenology of attitude content: this is illustrated by the immediately apparent or presented difference between thinking that Clark Kent is a newspaper reporter and thinking that Superman is a newspaper reporter—where the attitude type remains the same while the attitude content varies. The phenomenology of attitude type: this is illustrated by the immediately apparent difference between wondering if Clark Kent is late for work and fearing that Clark Kent is late for work—where content remains the same but attitude type varies. An important epistemological by‐product of the fact that these and other aspects are intrinsic or internal is that a person can just tell or subjectively discern what these aspects are—what her conscious attitude content is, for example. The reason for being able to ‘just tell’ is that conscious aspects qua conscious and qua mentally intrinsic immediately present themselves. (Remember, for us conscious content is self‐ presentationally non‐inferential or immediate.) Some aspects (say, pains) are like this. Others (say, thoughts of Paris) are like that. Moreover, being able to just tell is impervious or resistant to sceptical doubts about such things as, for example, whether one is, as Descartes envisioned in the First Meditation, the victim of an enormously powerful, enormously clever deceiver who ensures that conscious contents are radically non‐ veridical, and that one's conscious beliefs are massively false (see Horgan et al. 2006). Such radical scepticism gets no grip because self‐presentational phenomenology undergirds the experiencing subject's capacity to just tell what conscious state she is currently undergoing—although arguably such radical scepticism should get a grip if (as representationalists typically claim) the constitutive determinants of phenomenal character are partly ‘outside the head’. If the picture of conscious content that we prefer is on the right track, then most extant versions of representationalism are on the wrong track in misconstruing its intrinsicness as extrinsic. They also underestimate the richness and pervasiveness of the phenomenological in our mental lives, since most representationalists tend to think of the domain of the distinctively phenomenological as that of narrow qualia (feelings, images, etc.) rather than broadly self‐presented (including cognitive as well as narrow) qualia. We shall assume, however, that representationalism is on the right track at least in saying that paradigmatic or uncontroversial phenomenological mental states are intentional. What of the converse proposition that fully‐fledged intentional mental states are conscious? Has any theorist or philosopher advocated that proposition (Thesis PI)? Descartes said ‘[t]here can be nothing in the mind … of which it is not aware’ (1993: 171). On his view, the intentional (being mental) is conscious. Not many theorists agree with Descartes, though some come close. (p. 526)

Page 15 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind Alvin Goldman claims that ‘a plausible looking hypothesis is that mental states are states having a phenomenology, or an intimate connection with phenomenological events’ (1993: 24). The phrase ‘intimate connection’ is not clarified by Goldman. John Searle (1990, 1992) has advocated the connection principle (his expression) that ‘unconscious intentional states are in principle accessible to consciousness’ (1992: 156). Galen Strawson has said that ‘one cannot have intentionality unless one is an experiencing being’ (1994: 208). Both Searle and Strawson make the existence of phenomenology in a subject a precondition for its having intentional states. For Searle a mental state must be conscious or the person must be able to access the state consciously, although this is a notion of access about which Searle is none too clear. For Strawson, the person must be a conscious subject, a requirement that Strawson asserts but about which, again, at least on our reading, he is none too clear. Strawson writes: ‘[T]here is no … intentionality in a world in which there is no consciousness or experience’ (1994: 208). In the effort to defend Thesis PI we might press the texts for clarifying interpretations of Goldman, Searle, and Strawson. Searle's connection principle has already received a great deal of attention (see the peer commentary in Searle 1990). Perhaps such interpretations would uncover convincing arguments for the thesis that uncontroversial intentional mental states are conscious. We shall not explore these interpretative possibilities. We wish to follow another course. It consists in asking whether the intentionality of a conscious or phenomenal intentional state (i.e. of a state that is both phenomenological and intentional) is the same, qua intentional, as the intentionality of a non‐conscious intentional state. Or does it rather possess properties distinctive to its being conscious and therein perhaps also contributory to its status as intentional? In addressing this question we shall first focus on an example of the purported intentional content of a non‐ conscious perceptual belief, though examples of other sorts of non‐conscious intentional states could be chosen to make the same points that we make about non‐conscious intentionality.9 We want to know which facts if any settle or fix questions of the identity or determinacy of the intentional content of a non‐conscious perceptual belief. If facts about the individuation of non‐conscious intentional content are unsettled in a way that is sufficient to warrant saying (i) that non‐conscious perceptual beliefs are not uncontroversial or paradigmatic intentional states and (ii) that perceptual beliefs must be conscious to qualify as incontestably intentional, then this conclusion will help or begin to demonstrate that paradigmatic intentional states must be, in some sense, phenomenal or conscious. No uncontroversial intentionality without phenomenology.

(p. 527)

Page 16 of 30

30.3.2 Frogs, Flies, and Pellets

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind Consider the case of what the frog's eye tells the frog's brain (Lettvin et al. 1959/2000; see also Dennett 1987, esp. pp. 106–16, 302). Suppose that whatever the frog's eye tells the frog's brain is not consciously processed by the frog. It is not ‘like anything’ for the frog's brain to be told something by the frog's eye. Suppose, also, for the sake of hypothesis, that as a result of what the eye tells the brain, the frog comes to have a non‐ conscious perceptual belief that helps to govern the behaviour of catching and swallowing flies.10 Now suppose the frog is provoked into catching and swallowing a fly which darts in front of it. If we interpret the signal coming from the eye as ‘telling’ the frog that there is a fly coming towards it, then we might also interpret the frog's non‐ conscious perceptual belief as the belief that there is a fly coming towards it. However, now suppose that we provoke the frog into catching and swallowing a lead pellet we toss at it. If we interpret the signal as ‘telling’ the frog that there is a lead pellet coming towards it, then we might interpret the frog's perceptual belief as the belief that there is a lead pellet coming towards it. If we are robustly charitable in our belief attribution, when situations like those of the fly and the pellet arise we might interpret the frog as never making a mistake. Every darting object in the relevant pathway that the frog catches and swallows can always be interpreted by saying that the frog believes that such‐and‐such a particular sort of object is coming towards it: fly or pellet or moth or dark moving spot or insect or whatever. This would be excessively inflationary, of course, endowing the frog with concepts of fly, pellet, moth, and so on. It would also make it impossible for the frog to believe falsely that a fly is coming towards it, when, as it happens, a pellet is coming towards it, as it catches and swallows the pellet. For when a fly darts, the frog (we shall assume) believes that it is a fly. Whereas when a pellet comes, it believes (we shall assume) that it is a pellet. And so on. In principle, it would seem that the frog's behaviour can be described and explained with the invocation of any number of belief contents: that there is an insect flying off to the right, that there is some food now there, that something yummy is nearby, that there is a pellet, etc. We will not develop the narrative with other potentially relevant hypothetical details. What, as told, is the lesson we wish to extract from the story? The lesson is a worry about intentional content. We might worry not just about how to avoid over‐endowing the frog with conceptual competence, attributing a more conceptually specific or sophisticated meaning to the frog's perceptual system than the case warrants. We might also worry whether the frog ever misrepresents or misinterprets what is coming towards it. Whether it believes ‘thing of kind F (fly) or thing of kind P (pellet) or kind (etc.) is here now’, its belief (as we might interpret it given that we have nothing but its behaviour to go on) might always turn out to be true. And then we might have a related worry, one closely connected to the defence of Thesis PI. If the frog never misrepresents its environment, is its perceptual belief (p. 528) really possessed of intentional content? That is, is the state of the frog that we have called its believing really a state with content? Remember earlier we presupposed that a defining mark of intentionality is intensionality or the failure of substitution in the idioms deployed to characterize intentional content. If the frog believes that a fly is coming towards it, this must not be the same as believing that a pellet is coming towards it even if, as it happens, Page 17 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind a pellet is coming towards it and the trajectory of the pellet causes the frog to believe that a fly is coming towards it. (Recall: If Lois Lane believes that she kissed Clark Kent, this is not the same as believing that she kissed Superman, even if, as it happens, Clark is Superman and even if kissing Superman caused her to believe that she kissed Clark.) Intentional content must be sufficiently determinate or individual in its represented aspect so that there is a genuine difference between, for example, believing that a fly is approaching and believing that a pellet is approaching and thus between representing and misrepresenting the environment. It is one thing to represent the pellet as a pellet, another to (mis)represent it as a fly. Perhaps the content that the frog employs is indeterminate or non‐aspectual, lacking determinate identity. Perhaps there is no (specific) fact of the matter as to what the frog believes. So as long as the frog catches and swallows whatever visible and digestible object comes towards it, it makes no sense to say that the frog ‘misbelieves’ or ‘misperceives’ or ‘misrepresents’ something that it believes is kind F (say, a fly) but, as it happens, is kind P (say, a pellet). What explains the frog's catching and swallowing a pellet may well be the fact that the frog has the information that it does (whatever that is). But the information fails to constitute real‐honest‐to‐goodness intentional content because it is non‐aspectual or intractably indeterminate. Given that the frog's information lacks intentional content, the frog is not in an incontestable or paradigmatic (intentional) belief state. (More on whether such content even deserves to be called ‘information’ below.) Or more generally: The frog's ‘information’ is not intentional (or at least not incontestably intentional); not unless, as we shall argue, it is conscious. Not unless, to anticipate some remarks to follow, consciousness is essential to determinate content and thus to uncontroversial intentionality.

30.3.3 Phenomenal Intentional Content What is it about a thinking creature that individuates or fixes or settles the question of what it is thinking about? What determines intentional content? We assume, hypothetically, that there are three and only three theoretically possible ways of answering this question. First, something physical might individuate content—either something physical about a thinker considered in environmental isolation, or something physical about a thinker and its environmental context or environmental history. Second, something phenomenal might individuate the content of a thought. Descartes, for example, notoriously bemoaned being unable to tell which of his perceptual beliefs is veridical, but he claimed to be certain of what he believed (p. 529) (i.e. of the intentional content of his beliefs). This is because Descartes conceived of intentionality and consciousness as forming a single package, presupposing that a belief's intentional content is part of its cognitive phenomenology. Or third, one could rest with (what we might call) a nihilist dissolution of the problem of content individuation: nothing individuates or determines the intentional content of thought. There is no such content. Thought, strictly speaking, is thoughtless (i.e. contentless). (Of course this may also mean

Page 18 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind that there are no such things as thoughts, or events such as thinking, which is a prospect we shall not explore here, since we are not attracted to nihilism.) In short, we are faced with the following dialectical situation: Assuming that intentional states possess intentional content, and that intentional content is sufficiently determinate to distinguish representing from misrepresenting and to satisfy the constraint of intensionality in its description, then content is individuated either physically or phenomenally. So how might physical individuation work? Physical individuation would consist in physical patterns or relationships that determine the identity of the intentional object and content of thought. These might be the causal physical antecedents of the thought, systematic correlations between environmental activities (stimuli) and responses, configurations of brain states and environmental affairs, adaptive functions of neural states in ecological niches, features of an internal neurocomputational mechanism, millions of interactions among subatomic particles, activations of receptor cells, neurochemical or cell‐biological transfers, or whatever. A schematic attempt at physical individuation was at work in our brief discussion of the example of the frog and the fly. As suggested, however, by that discussion, physical individuation threatens to fail unless some principled means can be found to determine the intentional object qua intentional content of the frog's belief. We will not try to discuss candidate principles for physical‐content individuation here. In contemporary philosophy an active cottage industry has been trying to produce such principles for years; some philosophers believe that this work has been successful, others, like ourselves, are sceptical. (For some background discussion see Adams 2003.) Here, however, we will suppose that what Daniel Dennett (1987) says about all such attempts at physical individuation—which is a direct extension of Quine's thesis (1960) of the inscrutability of reference—is true. This is that when these physical principles, no matter what they are, ‘fall short of perfection, as they always must, there will be uninterpretable gaps … so that no further [physical] fact could settle what the [thinker] in question really [thinks]’ (Dennett 1987: 40; see also Dennett 1987: 106–16, 312). No physical fact about the frog, including its causal relation to the environment or its learning history, can individuate what the frog believes. What satisfactory grounds can we have for saying that the thinker is thinking about this? No definite answer, says Dennett, can be extracted from the physical manner of intentional‐content individuation. Dennett's Quinean nihilism about physical individuation is not accepted by those who hold one of the currently popular versions of ‘naturalistic’ theories of intentional content. These include some popular extant ‘outside the head’ versions (p. 530) (such as those of Dretske and Tye) of representationalism about phenomenal content which hold that conscious content is intentional and is itself ‘outside the head’. All sorts of worries have been raised for such theories, some for particular versions, and others for the whole externalist brand of theory. These worries include: (i) worries about names (as in beliefs about George Washington) and demonstratives (as in beliefs about this or that); (ii) worries about uninstantiated properties or individuals (as in beliefs about unicorns and Superman); (iii) worries about disjunctive content (as in whether the frog's content locks Page 19 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind to fly or pellet); (iv) worries about over‐endowment (too much conceptual sophistication); (v) worries about proximal projections (why a frog's thought might mean its distal cause [fly] rather than a more proximal cause such as a retinal projection of a fly); (vi) worries about instantiations of content in organisms without environmental histories (so‐called swampman worries) or without normally embodied embedment (brains in vats) or normal waking states (persons in protracted dreaming and hallucinatory conditions)—to name some of the many sorts of worries that have been raised about outside‐the‐head or causal/ historical/environmentally embedded accounts of content individuation. (See Adams 2003 for a helpful survey from the perspective of someone sympathetic to ‘outside the head’ theories of intentional content. For criticism specifically of Dennett see Keeley 1999.) Although we certainly cannot defend the assumption here, as noted above we share Dennett's nihilism about the prospects for the physical individuation of intentional content. So, too, does John Searle (1992: 163–4). However, whereas Dennett vigorously denies that intentional content can be phenomenally individuated—for Dennett is a nihilist about intentional‐content individuation period (whether physical or phenomenal) —Searle advocates a phenomenal mode of individuation. We do, too, although not in Searle's manner. Remember: we believe that there is a type of intentionality that is entirely constituted phenomenally, and it pervades our mental lives. This is phenomenal intentionality. Among the different aspects of phenomenal intentionality is the phenomenology of phenomenal intentional content. Phenomenal intentional content is individuated phenomenologically. To illustrate: Suppose that you are travelling in New Hampshire and you consciously wonder whether rabbits in New Hampshire have long tails. If you contrast consciously wondering whether New Hampshire rabbits have long tails with consciously believing that New Hampshire rabbits have long tails, you will notice, we claim, that there is something common phenomenologically that remains the same in consciousness as you pass from, say, wondering whether New Hampshire rabbits have long tails to believing that New Hampshire rabbits have long tails. It is the distinctive phenomenal content New Hampshire rabbits have long tails. It seems patently false—and false for reasons having to do with the like‐thisness or just‐tellness of conscious content—that there is indeterminacy as to whether you are thinking that New Hampshire rabbits have long tails or thinking that (p. 531) New Hampshire squirrels have long tails or thinking that Alabama rabbits have long tails or thinking that New Hampshire collections of undetached rabbit parts have long‐tail subsets. It is false because the immediately self‐ presenting phenomenal intentional content New Hampshire rabbits have long tails is just‐ tell (subjectively) distinguishable from those other contents. (See Horgan and Tienson 2002: 523 for additional discussion, as well as Horgan et al. 2006.)11 Of course, if we are wrong, and Dennett is right that the identity of intentional content cannot be settled by any means, then either (a) intentional content is not determinate or aspectual but also determinacy/aspectuality is not necessary for intentionality (and descriptions of intentionality fail to possess the property of failure of substitutivity or Page 20 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind ‘intensionality’) or (b) there is no such thing as intentionality period. In such a (b)‐case some version of nihilism about intentional content is in order, perhaps softened by advocacy of some form of quasi‐realism or projective realism or instrumentalism about intentionality. Assuming, contrary to Dennett, that some facts really do settle the matter of questions about the identity of intentional content and that there is one right answer as to whether I am thinking this, that, or some other thing entirely, but agreeing with his Quinean misgivings about the physical determination of content, then all that's left as a mode of individuation is phenomenological individuation. Subjects can ‘just tell’ what they are thinking (see also Horgan and Graham, forthcoming). We hasten to add that for us this does not mean that nothing physical or physically outside the head plays any role whatsoever in some individuating features of some intentional objects and contents. Important lessons about the relevance of things ‘outside the head’ to some questions of content have emerged from the work of ‘outside the head’ theorists. One of these lessons concerns so‐called wide truth conditions of thought contents that incorporate the actual physical‐worldly referents (if any) of the relevant thought contents. An adequate overall philosophical position about intentionality should accommodate various lessons of the externalists, we claim, though without abandoning the thesis of phenomenal intentionality. Just how this can be done is a complex exercise which we will not even attempt to outline here (see Horgan et al. 2004 for detailed discussion). Things are getting rapidly complicated, so let's bring the themes of the last several pages to a close. We have been trying to defend Thesis PI. Let's briefly sum up where we are in defending Thesis PI and moderate inseparatism. If some states of mind are intentional, incontestably so, there must be something that distinguishes their contents from each other. What counts as the same or different content can depend in theory upon something physical or upon something phenomenal. Physical individuation does not work (this is the Quine‐inspired Dennett nihilism). When intentional states, however, are consciously intentional, they (p. 532) are immediately self‐presenting in such a way that subjects can ‘just tell’ what their contents are. Their contents are therein determinate or distinguished one from the other. Then and only then, we claim, are they incontestably or uncontroversially intentional. So there is no incontestable intentionality without phenomenology. Perhaps this is what Galen Strawson means when he says: ‘I think that mere behavioral intentionality can never amount to true intentionality’ (1994: 208). He continues: ‘There is a clear and fundamental sense in which … intentionality exists only in the conscious moment’ (1994: 209). What about moderate inseparatism? There is no incontestable or ‘true’ (Strawson's word) intentionality without phenomenology (Thesis PI). There is also (as we assume) no incontestable phenomenology without intentionality (Thesis IP). So IP plus PI equals the thesis of moderate inseparatism: In the domain of mental states that are

Page 21 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind uncontroversially phenomenal or uncontroversially intentional, phenomenology and intentionality are inseparable.

30.4 Two Critical Questions for Further Consideration We must now confront some questions, each with a critical purport, about moderate inseparatism. We have space for two sets. First set of questions: What about unconscious mentality including tacit and implicit intentional states? Doesn't excluding them from the domain of the incontestably intentional impoverish our ability to predict and explain behaviour? The attempt to harness talk of intentional states to phenomenology puts an unfamiliar strain on a popular assumption of both folk psychology and cognitive science and prompts rejection of inseparatism by many philosophers. The assumption under strain is that intentional‐attitude states, indeed perhaps prima facie paradigmatic ones, can be unconscious. It is the assumption that some beliefs, desires, and so on are beneath the threshold of phenomenological or self‐presented scrutiny but play a causal role in producing behaviour or in interacting with conscious states such as conscious fears or emotions, even though we cannot ‘just tell’ whether they are present or what they represent. Our response? For starters, we do not deny that it is useful for various purposes to ascribe unconscious intentional states to a creature (including oneself). Instead, we deny that such attributions are of genuinely uncontroversial or paradigmatic intentional states. As long as we are careful to distinguish uncontroversial belief from useful belief‐ ascriptions, we may readily admit that we might have good grounds for employing ascriptions of non‐conscious beliefs even though it is contestable whether the states ascribed really are beliefs. Likewise, mutatis mutandis, for ascriptions of unconscious intentional states other than those of belief, such as unconscious desires, memories, and so on. (p. 533)

It is a separate question what actually is present in or true of an individual when an unconscious belief is said, on practically wise or expedient grounds, to be present. One possibility is that believing is a complex phenomenon, and that partly constitutive of this phenomenon are certain behavioural dispositions, and that much that is proper to those dispositions can be present when the belief is absent. (This might be what Strawson is referring to as behavioural intentionality and why he complains that it is insufficient for intentionality.) Consider the frog. Does the frog's catching and swallowing a fly mean that it unconsciously believes that a fly is present here and now? We would claim that we don't Page 22 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind (and shouldn't) need to credit the fly with unconscious beliefs, since similar dispositions to behaviour might be structurally implemented in non‐conscious information states which are indeterminate as between being locked onto flies, pellets, or whatever and therein fail to incontestably qualify as beliefs. Or, more precisely, since some theorists are apt to think that information, by its very nature, is determinate, and thus that the idea of ‘indeterminate information’ is an oxymoron, let's refer to the relevant non‐conscious states as quasi‐information states that are indeterminate between being locked onto flies, pellets, or whatever. What explains the frog's behaviour may well be the fact that the frog's brain state carries the indeterminate quasi‐information that it does, ‘information’ that never rises to the level of conscious attitude but functions similarly to a conscious belief. (It may move, as we have put it elsewhere (Graham and Horgan 2002), along the same causal grain as a conscious experience.) If so, similarly indeterminate ‘information’ might underlie the behavioural dispositions whose observation gives us good reason to attribute unconscious beliefs to creatures such as ourselves. After all, as Quine and Dennett would claim, the behaviour of the frog does not exhibit behavioural sensitivity to the difference between flies and pellets. So the same internal ‘information’ state can be assumed to explain the animal's responses to either sort of object. Meanwhile just as the frog has ‘information’ states which are explanatory of its behaviour, so, too, we may assume does the ‘unconsciously believing’ person. A person has no paradigmatic beliefs unless these are conscious beliefs, so says inseparatism of the moderate sort, but a person might have non‐conscious ‘information’‐processing states that undergird similar dispositions as those presumably unconscious beliefs that are attributed to them. They might behave as if they had beliefs without these being beliefs or intentional states of an incontestable sort.12 Much more may need to be said in response to the first set of questions, but let's turn to the second. (p. 534)

Second set of questions: Ask separatists why they prefer separatism, and what are they likely to say? Why favour separatism? We suspect that many would offer, among primary reasons, the following. Treating the mental as parsed or divided into the intentional and phenomenological provides a methodological basis for conceptual and empirical advances in the physical science of mind (see Wilson 2003). This is because (so the reasoning goes) while there aren't principled obstacles to the explanatory analysis of intentionality in physical‐science terms, there are principled obstacles to the explanatory analysis of consciousness in such terms. David Chalmers (1996: 203), for instance, calls the problems associated with the physical‐scientific analysis of the intentional ‘easy problems’ in the sense that we can picture how neurobiological science might offer the analysis. Understanding consciousness, he says, as a physical phenomenon is ‘the hard problem’ in the sense that we are unable to picture how brain or physical science might propose the analysis.

Page 23 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind Colin McGinn, no friend of the doctrine of separation, says the following: While there has been much optimism about the prospects of success in accounting for intentionality [in broadly physical terms], pessimism about explaining consciousness has deepened progressively. We can, it is felt, explain what makes a mental state have the [intentional] content it has; at least there is no huge barrier of principle in the way of our doing so. But, it is commonly conceded, we have no remotely plausible account of what makes a mental state have the phenomenological character it has; we do not even know where to start. (1988/1997: 295) We agree with Chalmers that what he calls the hard problem of consiousness is indeed a very difficult problem. Standard physical accounts of consciousness do not close the ‘explanatory gap’ (as it has been named by Joseph Levine 1983, 2001) between conscious states and whatever brain states supposedly subserve them; rather, physical analyses neglect a defining feature of the conscious content of mental states. This feature we have called their self‐presentational immediacy or like‐thisness. We believe, too, however, as card‐carrying inseparatists, that the scope of the hard problem is much broader or more extensive than it is often said to be, for the expanded or whole hard problem incorporates the fact that the intentional, in a sense, is pervasively conscious. The hard problem is not limited to conscious states, in some narrowly parsed, intentionality‐excluding way. The explanatory gap ramifies throughout the realm of the phenomenally intentional.

What about the physical science of mind? Doesn't inseparatism make that impossible? Much depends upon what is meant by the physical science of mind. An important task for a physical science of the mental, where the mental is assumed to possess moderately inseparable features, would be to provide a way of mapping phenomenal intentionality on to the types of entities or processes studied in neuroscience; that is to say, of correlating types of phenomenal intentional states including their contents with types of brain states and neural activities. This might be called the search for the neural correlates of phenomenal intentionality (NCPI). Arguably, though, the discovery of modes of physical correlation or NCPI will not tell (p. 535) us why certain brain states are about that or possess intentional content. If Dennett is warranted in his Quinean nihilism about physicalist individuation, as we assume that he is, we aren't going to get that question answered in physical‐scientific terms. Hopes for a cell‐biological alphabet of intentional content would appear stymied by the union of uncontroversial phenomenology and intentionality in our mental lives. The unity of mind, although moderate in its inseparable parts, may humble certain physicalistically immodest aspirations of its physical science.

References Adams, F. (2003), ‘Thoughts and Their Contents: Naturalized Semantics’, in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell), 143–71.

Page 24 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind Block, N. (1995), ‘On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18: 227–47. Brentano, F. (1874/1973), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint ed. O. Kraus, Eng edn. trans. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister ed. L. L. McAlister (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2004), ‘The Representational Character of Experience’, in B. Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–81. Church, J. (2003), ‘Depression, Depth, and the Imagination’, in J. Phillips and J. Morley (eds.), Imagination and Its Pathologies (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 175–86. Dainton, B. (2000), Stream of Consciousness: Unity and Continuity in Conscious Experience (London: Routledge). Dennett, D. C. (1987), The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2007), ‘What Robo Mary Knows’, in T. Alter and S. Walter (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 15–31. Descartes, R. (1993), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, i, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Flanagan, O. (1992), Consciousness Reconsidered (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Georgalis, N. (2003), ‘The Fiction of Phenomenal Intentionality’, Consciousness and Emotion, 4: 243–56. —— (2006), The Primacy of the Subjective: Foundations for a Unified Theory of Mind and Language (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Goldman, A. (1993), ‘The Psychology of Folk Psychology’, in A. Goldman (ed.), Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 347–80. Graham, G., and Horgan, T. (2000), ‘Mary Mary, Quite Contrary’, Philosophical Studies, 99: 59–87. —— (2002), ‘Sensations and Grain Processes’, in J. Fetzer (ed.), Consciousness Evolving (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 63–86. —— (2005), ‘Mary Mary Au Contraire’, Philosophical Studies, 122: 203–12.

Page 25 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind —— (2008), ‘Qualia Realism: Phenomenal Contents and Discontents’, in E. Wright (ed.), The Case for Qualia (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 89–107. Graham, G., Horgan, T., and Tienson, J. (2007), ‘Consciousness and Intentionality’, in S. Schneider and M. Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (Medford, Mass.: Blackwell), 468–84. (p. 536)

Horgan, T., and Graham, G. (forthcoming), ‘Phenomenal Intentionality and Content Determinacy’, in R. Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning (Berlin, New York: de Gruyter). Horgan, T., and Tienson, J. (2002), ‘The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality’, in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 520–33. Horgan, T., Tienson, J., and Graham, G. (2003), ‘The Phenomenology of First Person Agency’, in S. Walter and H.‐D. Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action (Exeter: Imprint Academic), 323–40. —— (2004), ‘Phenomenal Intentionality and the Brain in a Vat’, in R. Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge: New Studies in Cognition and Intentionality (Berlin, New York: de Gruyter), 297–318. —— (2006), ‘Internal‐world Skepticism and the Self‐presentational Nature of Phenomenology’, in U. Kriegel and K. Williford (eds.), Self‐Representational Approaches to Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 41–61. Keeley, B. (1999), ‘Fixing Content and Function in Neurobiological Systems: The Neuroethology of Electroreception’, Biology and Philosophy, 14: 395–430. Kim, J. (1998), Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind–Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Kriegel, U. (2003), ‘Is Intentionality Dependent upon Consciousness’, Philosophical Studies, 116: 271–307. Lettvin, J., et al. (1959/2000), ‘What the Frog's Eye Tells the Frog's Brain’, Proceedings of the Institute of Radio Engineers, 47: 1940–51; repr. in R. Cummins and D. Cummins (eds.), Minds, Brains, and Computers: The Foundations of Cognitive Science (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2000), 82–96. Levine, J. (1983), ‘Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 354–61. —— (2001), Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Conscious Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Page 26 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind McGinn, C. (1988/1997), ‘Consciousness and Content’, Proceedings of the British Acacdemy, 76: 219–39; repr. in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1997), 295–308. Nagel, T. (1974), ‘What is it Like to Be a Bat?’, Philosophical Review, 83: 435–50. Quine, W. V. O. (1960), Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Raffman, D. (2005), ‘Even Zombies Can Be Surprised’, Philosophical Studies, 122: 189– 202. Seager, W. (1999), Theories of Consciousness: An Introduction and Assessment (London: Routledge). Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1990), ‘Consciousness, Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive Science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13: 585–96. —— (1992), The Rediscovery of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Siewert, C. (2003), ‘Consiousness and Intentionality’, in E. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , accessed 2008. (p. 537)

Strawson, G. (1994), Mental Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Wilson, R. (2003), ‘Phenomenology and Intentionality’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 84: 413–31. (p. 538)

Notes: (*) This is a co‐authored paper. The order of authorship is alphabetical. Correspondence may be addressed to any of the authors. We are grateful to several people for their help and assistance. (1) Phenomenological properties can also be taken to be properties of individuals (e.g. human persons) rather than of mental states of individuals, characterizing what it is like to be that individual during a given period of time; this use of phenomenological‐property talk is not germane to the present chapter.

Page 27 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind (2) So‐called representationalist theories of phenomenology are a currently widely discussed departure from the claim that the phenomenological is independent of the intentional. Some representationalists, such as Fred Dretske (1995) and Michael Tye (1995), sometimes express their view by claiming that phenomenal properties are identical to certain represented or directly perceived external properties of objects such as the redness of a visually presented object, understood perhaps as a certain surface spectral reflectance. (3) Advocates of separatism do typically acknowledge a distinction between intentional mental states that are conscious and those that are not. But they typically claim that the pertinent concept of consciousness is not phenomenal consciousness but rather what Block (1995) calls access consciousness. To be access conscious, says such a separatist, is (roughly) to be introspectively accessible. (4) From the perspective of inseparatism, the introspective accessibility of intentional mental states is not another form of consciousness distinct from phenomenal consciousness (namely the so‐called access consciousness mentioned in n. 3). On the contrary, intentional states are accessible by virtue of being conscious; that is, by virtue of their phenomenal character. (5) Among philosophers who have recently been working on the topics of consciousness and intentionality with, in occasionally quite particular respects, inseparatist sensitivities are Barry Dainton, Owen Flanagan, Nicholas Georgalis, Alvin Goldman, Uriah Kriegel, Brian Loar, Colin McGinn, David Pitt, and Galen Strawson, as well as Siewert and Chalmers (among others). Some of this work is cited or discussed in the rest of the chapter as well as in the papers mentioned in n. 6. (6) The general position defended here was first introduced in general terms in Horgan and Tienson (2002), extended in Horgan et al. (2003), and refined in Horgan et al. (2004) and (2006). It was distinguished from representationalism in Graham and Horgan (2000). It has elicited criticism in one or another respect from Georgalis (2003), Wilson (2003), Raffman (2005), and Dennett (2007), with a reply to Raffman in Graham and Horgan (2005) and a reply to Dennett in Graham and Horgan (2008). (7) Compare with Georgalis (2006), a friend of the first‐personal or subjective but not of the language of the broadly phenomenal or qualitative. (8) What's said in the text is also intended to leave open the possibility of being mistaken in applying certain linguistic labels to one's experiences, by virtue of lacking a full grasp of the meanings of certain words in a natural language. (9) Thus, nothing essential will turn on the fact that we will describe the kind of state we are focusing on—a non‐conscious, putatively intentional state—as a putative belief. We will use belief talk mainly for vividness. The real issue concerns the purported intentional content of such a non‐conscious state.

Page 28 of 30

Phenomenology, Intentionality, and the Unity of the Mind (10) Again, it does not really matter whether or not one calls this internal state a belief. See the preceding note. (11) Conceptually infused phenomenal content of the sort involved in thinking that New Hampshire rabbits have long tails shares in whatever vagueness attaches to its associated concepts. But vagueness as such is one thing. Indeterminacy of intentional‐ content identity is another. Just what counts as a rabbit may be debated (a vagueness issue) without debating whether I can just tell that I am thinking of rabbits (an issue of determinate content). (12) If non‐intentional ‘information’ states help to control behaviour in a manner that is indistinguishable from phenomenally intentional states, doesn't this lead to epiphenomenalism about consciousness? This is a complex and difficult question which cannot be addressed here (for discussion see Graham and Horgan 2002), but the short answer goes something like this. No; conscious states or dispositions might run along the same causal grain as non‐conscious ones without therein failing to contribute causally to behaviour. They may play a de facto causal role qua conscious even if non‐conscious ‘information’ states would otherwise be sufficient and could help to produce similar behaviour. For additional complexities and variations in an inseparatist response to the first set of questions see Graham et al. (2007).

George Graham

George Graham is a Professor Philosophy and Neuroscience at Georgia State University in Atlanta, Georgia. Terence Horgan

Terry Horgan is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Arizona. His publications include ‘Mental Quausation’ in Philosophical Perspectives 3 (1989); ‘Kim on Mental Causation and Causal Exclusion’ in Philosophical Perspectives 11 (1998); ‘Causal Compatibilism and the Exclusion Problem’ in Theoria 16 (2001); and ‘Mental Causation and the Agent-Exclusion Problem’ in Erkenntnis 67 (2007). John Tienson

John Tienson is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis.

Page 29 of 30

The Self

Oxford Handbooks Online The Self   Galen Strawson The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0032

Abstract and Keywords This article aims to give some sense of the conceptual geography of the notion of the self, and the article can do this without requiring the reader to accept any of its assumptions or conclusions. It talks about historical figures, but only because they provide by far the best, most direct, most vivid, and most searching discussions of the problem of the self. Keywords: notion of the self, historical figures, problem of the self, subject of experience, semantic intention, existence of self

31.1 Introduction ‘I know that I exist; the question is, what is this “I” that I know?’ (Descartes 1641/1984: 18). I am, I answer, a human being, a product of evolution by natural selection, a living organism, a physical object—a wholly physical object. I will take all this for granted. I should admit, though, that I don't fully know the nature of the physical. No one does. Nearly all of us take it that the physical is essentially spatio‐temporal, for example, but no one expert in these matters claims to know for certain what space and time are, or whether they are really fundamental features of reality as we standardly conceive them. Many are sure that they are not, and speak instead of ‘space–time’, but the same doubts arise about the unified space–time of relativity theory, and even if our best theories are right about the nature of space–time, the overall nature of the physical remains in many respects profoundly obscure to us, especially given that consciousness itself is something physical. So even if I know—take it for granted—that I am a wholly physical thing, much remains unknown.1

Page 1 of 28

The Self I am, nevertheless, an animal, a human being, a physical thing. What else am I? I am a conscious subject of experience and I know I am. This is part of what I know with certainty in knowing I exist. There is, furthermore, a fundamental sense in which I know what sort of thing a subject of experience is just in being one and in being self‐conscious. This is so even though there may be philosophical and scientific truths about what it is to be a subject of experience that I do not know. (p. 542)

I am a subject of experience, then. Am I also a self? Only if selves exist. Do they exist? It depends what one means by the word ‘self’. In what follows I will take the word ‘self’ in a certain specific way, make a number of assumptions, and answer Yes to the question: selves do indeed exist. Many, however, will think my Yes amounts to a No, because they will not be prepared to take the word ‘self’ in the way I do. And perhaps I would do better to answer No. In many ways my position is closer to the No‐sayers than the Yes‐sayers, and in saying Yes I am likely to lose the sympathy of both sides, each objecting that I concede too much to the other. The pro‐self party will object that the selves I claim to exist don't really deserve the name, and that by using ‘self’ in this way I am obscuring the fact that there are other things that do deserve the name. The anti‐self party will agree with the pro‐self party that the selves I claim to exist don't deserve the name, and object that by using ‘self’ in this way I am obscuring the fact that nothing deserves the name. This will, I hope, be helpful. My present aim is to give some sense of the conceptual geography of the notion of the self, and I can do this without requiring the reader to accept any of my assumptions or conclusions. I will talk about historical figures, but only because they provide by far the best, most direct, most vivid, and most searching discussions of the problem of the self.

31.2 I and ‘I’ If I am a human being, say human being H, and if the ‘am’ I have just used is the ‘am’ of identity, as it certainly seems to be,2 then I=H. And if I am a self, say self S, and if this ‘am’ is again the ‘am’ of identity, as it certainly seems to be, then I=S. It follows, by the logic of the identity relation, that H=S—that the self that I am is just (just is) the human being that I am; that selves are just human beings; that they are not items distinct from, in the sense of non‐identical with, human beings considered as a whole. Some analytic philosophers think that this conclusion is inevitable, if one is going to talk of selves at all (see, paradigmatically, Kenny 1988, 1999). They infer that it is much better not to. It is enough, they say, to talk of human beings. Talk of selves is superfluous and intensely misleading.

Page 2 of 28

The Self I disagree. I agree that I am a human being, and I think that I am a self, but I don't think that the self that I am is the human being that I am. I don't reject the logic of the identity relation. That would be silly. I reject the assumption that the word ‘I’ is univocal—the assumption that it has only one possible meaning or reference in thought or speech. The reference of ‘I’—both its actual reference and its explicitly or implicitly intended or presupposed reference—standardly shifts between two different things in my thought and speech and in the thought and speech of others. Sometimes ‘I’ is used to refer to a human being considered as a whole, sometimes it is used (p. 543) to refer to a self. These are two things that have quite different identity‐conditions, if indeed selves exist, and that stand— I will argue—in some sort of straightforward part–whole relation.3 To say this is not to assume that selves exist. It is only to report a fact about how the word ‘I’ is used. If it turns out that the best thing to say about selves is that there are no such things, then the best thing to say about ‘I’ may well be that it is univocal after all, and that the apparent doubleness of reference of ‘I’ is just the echo in language of a metaphysical illusion. If this is right, then ‘I’ is not in fact used to refer to selves as distinct from human beings even when its users intend to be making some such reference and believe that they are doing so.4 On this view, the semantic intentions of ‘I’‐users sometimes incorporate a mistake about how things are. I disagree. I think that we do at different times successfully use ‘I’ to refer to different things: to human beings considered as a whole and to selves. In this respect the word ‘I’ is like the word ‘castle’. Sometimes ‘castle’ is used to refer to the castle proper, sometimes it used to refer to the ensemble of the castle and the grounds and associated buildings located within the perimeter wall, sometimes it can be taken either way. The same goes for ‘I’, but ‘I’ is perhaps even more flexible, for it can sometimes be taken to refer both to the self and to the whole human being, indifferently.5 Our thought (our semantic intention) is often unspecific as between the two; it's all pretty relaxed.6 My claim, then, is that there is a fully correct use of ‘I’ in which it is true to say that I am not a human being, i.e. a human being considered as a whole.7 That's fine, you may say, so far as the word ‘I’ is concerned. But wouldn't it be better, even so, just to stop using the word ‘self’ altogether, in philosophy? It really doesn't do any good, and it causes a great deal of confusion. Shouldn't we try to get everyone to stop using it? The notion of a self is so hopelessly unclear (see e.g. Olson 1998; Kenny 1999). The notion of a self is extremely unclear, but this proposal is unrealistic. People will always talk of the self, both in and out of theoretical contexts, and there are good reasons why this is so. The idea of the self is very compelling. James Trefil speaks for common sense when he writes ‘No matter how my brain works … one (p. 544) single fact remains … I am aware of a self that looks out at the world from somewhere inside my skull … this is … the central datum with which every theory of consciousness has to grapple’ (1997: 181).8 More importantly, I believe we get something right in thinking and talking in terms of the self, although I also think we get something wrong. I think that there really are things that are subjects of experience and that are not the same things as whole human Page 3 of 28

The Self beings and that are good candidates for being called ‘selves’. It's true that the use of the definite article ‘the’ in the phrase ‘the self’ is very misleading in some contexts, and directly question‐begging in others, and for this reason I will often speak of selves, or a self, rather than of the self. But the self will often be the most convenient expression, and when it is I will use it freely.

31.3 Conditions on being a Self (1) I take it, to begin, that anything that is to count as a self must be something that is (1) not the same thing as a whole human being—a human being considered as a whole. Otherwise there would be no point in introducing the term ‘self’. I also take it that anything properly called a self must be

(2) a subject of experience. I take this to be true by definition, and no one, I think, will wish to disagree.

(2) does, however, raise a problem. For we standardly say that human beings considered as a whole are subjects of experience, and it follows from (1) that a subject of experience that is a self cannot be the same thing as a subject of experience that is a whole human being. So what can it be? I take it, in answer, and wholly conventionally, that a self is (3) an inner subject of experience, an inner presence or locus of consciousness that is (therefore) not the same thing as the whole human being. I assume that the inner subject of experience is wholly located in the brain, but this is not essential, and ‘inner’ can also be taken more loosely to cover the possibility that the existence of the subject essentially involves the existence of a non‐physical or ‘immaterial’ soul.9

(3) implies (2) and (1), but now we face a question about the relation between the self that one is—for one must surely count as a self if there are such things as selves at all— and the human being that one is. (p. 545)

I take it to be thoroughly amicable. Consider Louis, a representative human being, and consider the L‐reality, the part of reality that consists of Louis. If there is an inner subject of experience in the L‐reality, then that is why Louis considered as a whole human being is rightly said to be a subject of experience. It is not as if there are two subjects of experience doubled up in the L‐reality, the self subject and the human‐being subject. And the relation between Louis considered as an inner subject‐of‐experience self and Louis considered as a whole human being, in virtue of which we speak of the whole human being as a subject of experience just as easily as we speak of the inner locus of Page 4 of 28

The Self consciousness as a subject of experience, is not only completely amicable; it is also, I take it, a completely straightforward, spatio‐temporal part–whole relation. (We can imagine that a human subject of experience might survive even when all that is left of a human being is an uncompromised brain.) My next condition is that any candidate for being a self must count as a single thing or object or substance of some sort. Or, rather, since the notions of object and substance are surprisingly unclear,10 and may be thought metaphysically dubious, it is that a self must be (4) at least as good a candidate for being a substance or object as anything else. The idea that the self is a thing or substance of some sort is wholly conventional in the long recorded history of discussion of the self, from the early Hindu texts onwards, and it is obviously accepted by those who think that selves are immaterial soul‐substances, as these are traditionally conceived, although it equally obviously does not require any belief in any such entities. Condition (4), then, ensures that we are addressing the traditional metaphysical issue directly, and it will be valuable in structuring the discussion even if it comes under considerable pressure. For my own part I think there is a sense in which it must be correct, given only (2): the fact that a self must be a subject of experience.11

Condition (4) imposes a clear and highly substantive constraint on any attempt to answer the question whether selves exist. It rules out, for one thing, common present‐day uses of ‘self’ to refer merely to the personality or character of a human being, where the personality of a human being is seen as just a set of properties of that human being.12 It also brackets whatever it is that people have in mind when they talk of the ‘social’ self, or the ‘ecological’ self, or the ‘narrative’ self (see e.g. Mead 1913; Gibson 1993; Phillips 2003), for these phrases are typically used to denote modes or styles or aspects of human behaviour and experience, properties or characteristics of human beings that can be fully characterized without supposing that there is such a thing as a self distinct from a human being considered as a whole. The present concern (at least so far) is with the good old‐ fashioned metaphysical question ‘Do selves (p. 546) exist?’ and this question is taken to be equivalent to the question ‘Are there objects or substances that are correctly called “selves” ’? I don't, however, have a good old‐fashioned view of what an object or substance is, so far as most of the western philosophical tradition is concerned. My sympathies lie rather with the philosophers like Nagarjuna, Nietzsche, Whitehead, and others. I think, for example, that the hugely natural distinctions between objects and processes, on the one hand, and between objects and their propertiedness, on the other hand, are hopelessly superficial when one gets metaphysically serious (see Section 31.6 below). I also take it that Berkeley's description of the self as a ‘thinking active principle’ passes the ‘object’ test comfortably, and I see no reason to think it will exclude Fichte's conception of the self as a Tathandlung, a ‘deed‐activity’ (Berkeley 1713/1975: 116; Fichte 1794–1802/1982: 96).13

Page 5 of 28

The Self

31.4 Assumptions To raise doubts about the standard understanding of what objects and substances are is not to say that they don't exist, and I am going to assume for argument that they do, that (i) there are such things as objects or substances i.e. that we can acceptably talk in terms of a plurality of objects or substances, when we do metaphysics, and also that

(ii) a human being is an object or substance if anything is. Let me also make explicit my assumption that

(iii) physicalism (or materialism) is true, physicalism (materialism) being, unsurprisingly, the view that every real, concrete phenomenon in the universe is … physical.14

I don't, however, mean what most philosophers today mean by ‘physical’ or ‘physicalism’. I mean real physicalism, serious physicalism, i.e. physicalism that is fully realist about conscious experience, i.e. fully realist about the existence of the subjective qualitative character or ‘what‐it's‐likeness’ of experience, where this is conceived of in the most ordinary everyday way. Such conscious experience (from now on I'll simply call it ‘experience’) is in fact the only thing we know for certain to be physical, on the assumption that physicalism is true, because it is the only concrete phenomenon we know for certain to exist. (p. 547)

Experience, then, is the fundamental given natural fact. It is what any remotely serious version of physicalism or naturalism must start from. (Here I make the common assumption that physicalism and naturalism are the same thing.) Some self‐styled physicalists and naturalists use ‘physicalism’ and ‘naturalism’ to denote a view that involves the denial of the existence of the most certainly existing natural thing there is— experience, or what‐it's‐likeness—but they are unreal physicalists, unnatural naturalists, defenders of the silliest view ever espoused in the history of humanity.15 Real physicalism or naturalism, by contrast, is defined by the fact that it fully acknowledges the existence of the most certainly existing thing there is, experience, and takes it—considered as such —to be a wholly physical phenomenon. Real physicalism can't treat ‘physical’ and ‘mental’ as terms that are in any way opposed (it must rather distinguish between mental and non‐mental aspects of the physical), because it holds that everything mental, including everything experiential, is wholly physical. Nor can it have anything to do with physicsalism, the view that the fundamental nature of everything concrete can be accounted for in the terms of physics, for if physicalism is true then nothing is more certain than that there is more to the physical than what is or can be described or

Page 6 of 28

The Self accounted for by the discipline of physics, which has no terms for the phenomena of experience considered just as such. It follows from assumptions (i)–(iii) that (iv) human beings are physical objects, wholly physical objects or substances and, given (4), that

(v) if human selves exist, they too are wholly physical objects or substances.

31.5 Conditions on being a Self (2) This may seem a strange claim. I hope it will seem less strange when I say more about ‘physical’ and ‘object’ in the next section. First, though, I want to ask whether anything else, in addition to (1)–(4), is essential to being a self. Many, I think, would want to add that a self is necessarily (5) something that standardly persists for life, or at least over a reasonably long period of time, and is also necessarily

(6) an agent, something capable of action, intentional action and

(7) something that has a certain character or personality and is not a mere locus of consciousness and cognition (p. 548)

and

(8) a self‐conscious being.16 I think, in fact, that all of (5)–(8) can be cogently challenged, when one tries to work out the absolutely minimal case in which one may reasonably speak in terms of a self—an ‘inner’ subject of experience or locus of consciousness, an inner someone, an inner mental presence.17 In this chapter however, I am only going to challenge (5).

31.6 Objects — You say you want to show that there is such a thing as the self, and that you use the word ‘thing’ to mean object or substance, but you've been fooled by the word ‘self’—by the fact that it is grammatically substantival, a noun. There is no such thing as ‘the self’.

Page 7 of 28

The Self The objection is ancient, but it misunderstands my aim, which is precisely to defend the self's claim to be an object or substance of some sort, if only as a way of articulating the general structure of the notion of the self.

Suppose I can't show that there are things that are worthy candidates for the title ‘self’ on these terms. Suppose I can't even show that a view that takes the self to be a thing or substance of some sort is better than a view according to which it is best seen as a property of some other thing like a brain or a human being. Suppose I find it ‘quite impossible’, in Kant's words, to determine the manner in which I [i.e. the self or soul] exist, whether it be as substance [or thing, or object] or as accident [or property]. (1781–7/1933: B420)18 In that case I may have to conclude that the self is guilty as charged: non‐existent. I may have to conclude that all the undoubtedly real self‐phenomena—all the phenomena that lead us to talk in terms of the self, whether or not there is such a thing—just do not provide adequate grounds for the claim that selves actually exist. For the moment, though, my aim is to argue that selves exist, and that they are objects or substances of some sort, and hence, given physicalism, physical objects.

This last suggestion strikes many as absurd. The reaction stems, I believe, from a failure to think through what it is to be physical, on any realistic physicalist view, and, equally, from a failure to think through what it is to be a thing or object. It is (p. 549) as if one has to solve for three inadequately conceived quantities—self, object, physical— simultaneously, using each to get leverage on the others. This is a large task, but the claim that selves are physical objects may start to look a little less strange once one begins to acquire a proper understanding of what it is to say that something is an object, or physical. One simple point, already touched on, is that even the most cursory consideration of what we ordinarily think of as physical objects, from stones to brains, shows them to be fabulously unlike our everyday conception of them. The most basic lay acquaintance with science shows physical objects to be inconceivably insubstantial by common‐sense standards. They are patterns of energy, diaphanous process‐entities, entities whose being involves a constant interchange with the quantum vacuum given which it is literally correct to say that they are partly constituted by the vacuum. The first thing to do, I think, in order to see things more accurately, is to think of physical objects as, literally, processes—where this requires, at the least, abandoning the standard metaphysic according to which a process requires an object or substance distinct from itself in which to occur. If this is to commit a ‘category mistake’, don't blame me. Blame the collision of ordinary thought and language with the world. The same collision occurs in the case of the routine but ultimately wholly untenable ontological distinction between an object, considered at any given time, and its properties or qualitative characteristics, at that time, where by its properties, its propertiedness, I mean whatever it is about it concretely that makes it true to say that it is the particular way it is. One can't, when one gets metaphysically serious, suppose that one has, at any Page 8 of 28

The Self given time, on the one concrete ontological hand, the object, and, on the other concrete ontological hand, its propertiedness, the totality of its qualities or accidents, in any way that allows that they can be said to be ultimately ontologically distinct, in concrete reality. When it comes to the ancient problem of particular and universal, the trick is not to say too much: to say no more than Kant when he remarks that ‘in their relation to substance, accidents [or properties] are not really subordinated to it, but are the mode of existing of the substance itself’ (1781–7/1933: A414/B441).19 There is no ontological subordination of the total qualitative being of the object to the object considered just as such, no ontological subordination of its nature to its existence. The whole object/process/ property/state/event cluster of distinctions, unexceptionable in everyday life, is fatally superficial from the point of view of science and metaphysics. Our most fundamental thought categories simply do not get the world right, and when we think hard we can see a priori that this is so.20

(p. 550)

31.7 The Transience View

Talk of objects and substances, then, is not what it is often taken to be (as Descartes would agree—see below). A full treatment of these issues would take a long time, but I will now return to the current proposal that selves, as characterized by (1)–(4), and perhaps also by (6)–(8), do indeed exist. They are parts of human beings considered as a whole, and deserve to be treated as fully metaphysically respectable objects or substances, whether or not one has acquired a properly processual view of what an object or substance is, or a proper grasp of the relation between what we speak of in speaking of an object and what we speak of in speaking of the properties of that object. So far, perhaps, so good. But if, now, you ask me how long I think human selves exist, I will answer ‘No more than a second, if that’—flatly rejecting (5), the view that anything that can count as a self must be something that persists for life or at least over a reasonably long period of time. It seems plain that if a being qualitatively identical to an ordinary adult human being sprang suddenly into existence, enjoyed two seconds of experience just like two ordinary seconds of your or my experience, and then ceased to exist, a self would most certainly exist in that two‐second period; if, that is, selves exist at all. But one could fully accept this while rejecting as absurd the claim that selves (assumed now to exist) last only a second or two—or less—in our case. Many, in fact, will take such a claim to be equivalent to the claim that there are no such things as selves, because they take it to be true by definition that selves persist for a long period of time, a lifetime for example, if they exist at all. The inclination to think of the inner subject or self as a persisting thing lies deep in most ordinary (non‐pathological) thought.

Page 9 of 28

The Self And yet I do not think we do well to conceive the self as some sort of persisting—sleeping, waking—inner inhabitant of a human being. If we must have something that endures in this way, I think we do best to stick to the whole human being, as many analytic philosophers have wished to do. — Each normal human being contains some complex persisting brain structure Q which is (obviously) not the same thing as the whole human being and which can be roughly characterized as follows: Q is that which supports the consciousness and personality of a human being. Imagine a human being losing limbs, body, reduced by surgical miracle to a head or just a brain or even something less than a brain, without any fundamental disruption of Q or of psychological life or character. In this case a subject of experience plainly persists, and what this shows is that talk of a persisting inner self doesn't involve any bad inner inhabitant's picture. It's just that Q, the self‐organ, as it were, is wholly located in the brain. It's simply part of the brain, a brain structure, as you say, and there can be no objection to thinking of it as a persisting thing, like a hand or eye, although it is not a single part of the brain physiologically speaking. One might call this the ‘self‐system view’ (see Flanagan 2003: ch. 6). Granted. I certainly can't show that such a use of the word ‘self’ would be wrong, and this is one simple way to give an unqualified Yes in answer to the question whether the self exists. It is a view that is fully available to physicalists, and most will think it obvious that selves exist, so understood, for they exist as surely as hearts do.21 Why do I hesitate? Because I doubt that selves can satisfy condition (4) in an adequate fashion, when they are understood in this way. I lack space to justify this view here, however (see Strawson 2009), and propose instead to give some further substance to the idea that human selves are transient. I think this is a good way to articulate thought about the notion of the self even if it is not in the end the best thing to say about selves. (p. 551)

31.8 Thin Subjects My starting proposal is that we need to add a relatively unfamiliar conception of what a self or subject of experience is to the two existing common conceptions. The first of these, already discussed, is (a) the thick conception according to which it is human beings and other animals considered as a whole that are subjects of experience. I'll call the second

(b) the traditional conception, the traditional inner conception of the subject according to which the subject properly or strictly speaking is some sort of persisting, inner, mentally propertied entity or presence.

Page 10 of 28

The Self I take it that (a) and (b) both build in the assumption that a subject may and standardly does continue to exist even when it is not having any experience: whether you think that human subjects are whole human beings or whether you think they are inner loci of consciousness you are likely to allow that they can continue to exist during periods of complete experiencelessness —in periods of dreamless sleep, say.

It is this that creates the need for a third conception of the subject, (c) the thin conception according to which a subject of experience, a true subject of experience, does not and cannot exist without experience also existing, experience which it is having itself.22 The thin conception stands opposed to both (a) and (b) precisely because they both contain the natural assumption that a subject of experience can be said to exist in the absence of any experience, but it doesn't by itself offer any support to the idea that selves are transient entities. The claim that human selves or thin subjects are short‐lived, given (c), is an independent, empirical claim. (p. 552)

There is a problem of exposition here, because most are so accustomed to (a) and/or (b), and to the idea that they exhaust the options, that they cannot take (c) seriously. And yet (c) simply makes a place for a natural use of the term ‘subject’ according to which it is a necessary truth, no less, that there cannot be a subject of experience, at any given time, unless some experience exists for it to be a subject of, at that time. On this view, there can no more be a subject of experience without an experience than there can be a dent without a surface. (c) requires that the subject be ‘live’, so to say, in order to exist at all. I believe it is crucial to have (c) in play when taking on the metaphysics of the self.

31.9 Hume, Descartes, and Others The thin conception of the subject is hardly new in philosophy. We find it in Hume when he is characterizing the notion of the subject of experience that is philosophically legitimate given his strict empiricist principles (i.e. when he is expounding the ‘bundle’ theory of the self). ‘[W]hen my perceptions [experiences] are remov'd for any time, as by sound sleep’, he writes, ‘so long am I insensible of myself, and may truly be said not to exist’ (1739–40/2000: 165). Note that Hume never claims that there is no subject or self at all when there is experience, contrary to widespread belief. The point is sufficiently established by the quotation, but it would be no less certain without it. It is after all a necessary truth that there can't be experience without a subject of experience, an experiencer, simply in so far as experience is essentially experience‐for‐someone‐or something; and Hume doesn't go in for denying necessary truths. What he denies is something much more specific: the idea that we have any good evidence for the existence of a persisting self or subject, let alone an invariable, unchanging self or subject of the Page 11 of 28

The Self sort whose existence is taken for granted by almost all philosophers in his time.23 So far as the empirical data are concerned, he observes, we find only transient selves: ‘our thought is fluctuating, uncertain, fleeting’; it is ‘in a perpetual flux’, in which different thoughts and experiences ‘succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity’ (Hume 1779/1947: 194; 1739–40/2000: 165; 1739–40/1978: 252).24 Descartes also endorses the thin conception of the subject, as far as I understand him, although his thin subjects, being possibly immortal,25 are far from transient. (p. 553) His most fundamental claim is that the soul or self or subject does not and cannot exist at all in the absence of conscious experiencing (‘thinking’, in his terminology). A subject without conscious experiencing for it to be the subject of is as impossible, for Descartes, as a physical object without extension, and his root—radical—idea about the nature of the subject of experience or soul is that it is wholly and literally constituted of conscious experiencing. That, it seems, is what a res cogitans—a soul—is. It is nothing like an immaterial soul as traditionally conceived. Its being is, rather, a matter of occurrent experiencing—so that it certainly can't exist when there isn't any. At one point Descartes talks of ‘our soul or our thinking’ as if the two terms were strictly interchangeable (Descartes 1644/1984: 184). At another he writes, seemingly unequivocally, that in being the essential attribute of thinking substance ‘thinking … must be considered as nothing else than thinking substance itself …, that is, as mind’ (Descartes 1644/1984: 215). The standard, comfortable view of the immaterial soul or self, then, is nothing like Descartes's. According to the standard picture, [P1], there is (i) some sort of soul‐substance or soul‐ stuff that is (ii) the ground Click to view larger or bearer of conscious Fig.31.1 Three pictures of the immaterial self experiencing and that (iii) can continue to exist even when there isn't any going on, and that therefore (iv) has some nature other than conscious experiencing. Everyone agrees that Descartes rejects (iii), in holding that a subject of experience must always be experiencing, but his claim that ‘each substance has one principal property which constitutes its nature or essence … and thinking constitutes the nature of thinking substance’ (1644/1984: 210; my emphasis) is often read as allowing, as in [P2], that (iv) the soul has some other manner of being that is not conscious experiencing. In fact, though, this reading is hopelessly problematic, because to claim that something constitutes the nature of something is to claim that nothing else does. Descartes, (p. 554) then, rejects all of (ii) to (iv) and accepts (i) only in so far as there is no real distinction between a substance and its attributes. His picture is more like [P3].

Page 12 of 28

The Self Impossible. Replying to Arnauld, Descartes agrees that episodes of thinking like ‘understanding, willing, doubting etc. are … attributes which must inhere in something if they are to exist; and we call the thing in which they inhere a substance’ (1641/1984: 156). Replying to Hobbes he notes that ‘a thought cannot exist without a thinking thing’, and that if confusion has arisen in the interpretation of his position it is because ‘ “thought” is sometimes taken to refer to the act, sometimes to the faculty of thought, and sometimes to the thing which possesses the faculty’. The implication of this last quotation seems clear: all these three references are references to distinct things, so that there is a thing or substance (res) which possesses certain faculties and accordingly performs certain sorts of acts; and Descartes further insists that he does not ‘deny that I, who am thinking, am distinct from my thought, in the way in which a thing is distinct from a mode’ (1641/1984: 123–5). These are good quotations, but they do not undermine the attribution of (P3) to Descartes, who for reasons of caution makes a particular point of continuing to use accepted terminology even though it no longer plays any active role in his view.26 It must be stressed again that (P3) cannot be understood to incorporate any standard substance–property distinction, for while Descartes grants, as just noted, that ‘we call the thing in which [mental attributes] inhere a substance’, he does not think that the notion of substance has any meaning or intelligible reference or explanatory force, in so far as it is supposed to be something that is in any way distinct from its (‘its’) attributes or properties.27 Speaking of the fundamental attributes of thought and extension, he says that ‘the distinction between these notions and the notion of substance itself is a merely conceptual distinction’, and by this he means that although it is a distinction that can indeed be made in thought it is not a ‘real’ distinction, where to say that there is a real distinction between two things is simply to say that each can exist in reality without the other existing, that each can exist ‘separately’, in complete ontological separation from the other (Descartes 1644/1984: 215).28 In his conversations with Burman he confirms this view: ‘[T]he attributes [of a substance], when considered collectively, are indeed identical with the substance’ (1648/1976: 23). It is only in so far as we agree to employ the language of ‘inherence’ and ‘substance’, and agree to speak of thought and extension as ‘inhering in a substance’, that we must—given the way in which the properties of thought and (p. 555) extension are on his official theory essentially mutually repellent—say that there are two substances. The word ‘substance,’ however, is doing no work at all, and towards the end of his life Descartes the indefatigable dissector of brains, in every other pore of his philosophy a materialist, admits in effect that he does not know enough of matter to be sure of this repulsion.29

There is still a serious difficulty in the radical position as so far characterized: the difficulty of finding a ground or ‘place of residence’ for mental faculties like will and understanding and ‘intellectual memory’30 (not to mention innate ideas), given that the thinker is, metaphysically, simply a process of conscious experiencing. Nor is this difficulty diminished by Descartes's view that these faculties are ‘potentialities’;31 for potentialities, it seems, also need a place of residence beyond what can be supplied by an occurrent process of conscious experiencing if the whole being of such a process, considered at any particular moment, is only the entertaining of whatever content is then occurring. It seems plain that Descartes conceives of the process of conscious experiencing as something that is somehow inherently active. This, however, is a matter for another time. It raises wider issues not only in Descartes's wildly misrepresented Page 13 of 28

The Self philosophy but in metaphysics generally (see e.g. Strawson 1994: ch. 5; 2006: sect. 8).32 For now the point is that (c), the thin‐subject view, is not a particularly eccentric view. Leibniz also accepts it, taking thin subjects to be long‐lived. Kant writes that ‘the thinking or the existence of the thought and the existence of my own self are one and the same’ (1772/1967: 75). Fichte and Nozick (following Fichte) can also be read as accepting it, taking thin subjects to be short‐lived.33 Buddhists also accept short‐lived thin subjects of experience, in spite of the fact that they are often supposed to deny the existence of subjects of experience altogether. So also does William James, the greatest modern philosopher of mind.

31.10 James James takes over Descartes's standard use of the word ‘thought’ to cover all types of conscious episodes,34 and explicitly appoints ‘Thought … with a capital T’ as a name (p. 556) for ‘the present mental state’ (James 1890/1950: i. 186–7, 338). He then argues that ‘the I’ or self ‘is a Thought’. ‘The thoughts themselves are the thinkers’, he says; each ‘ “perishing” … pulse of thought’ or ‘ “section” of consciousness’ is a (short‐lived) thinker or self or subject of consciousness (James 1890/1950: i.400–1, 371, 337).35 As a materialist, he takes it that these pulses are occurrences in the brain. ‘The thoughts themselves are the thinkers’ sounds hopelessly odd at first. One can recast it as ‘the conscious episodes themselves are the subjects of consciousness’, for the best translation of Descartes's ‘cogito, ergo sum’ is ‘I am conscious, therefore I am’, but this hardly improves matters. Slightly less indigestible, perhaps, is: ‘the existence of each conscious episode or experience consists in the existence of a subject of consciousness entertaining a certain mental content’, this being, once again, a wholly physical event. There is a way of reading this in which it doesn't obviously dilute James's claim, and it may sound just a little less unpalatable to some: it may have a slightly better chance of delivering the odd mental shock that comes from grasping (even if only briefly) truths that have no non‐counter‐intuitive expression. One can only go so far with such rephrasings, however. The idea remains very difficult on first acquaintance, given the ordinary background of thought. It is I believe correct, given that one is operating with (c), the thin conception of the subject, but it has to grow on one. A little more fully, James claims that the self or subject or I … is a Thought [present mental state], at each moment different from that of the last moment, but appropriative of the latter, together with all that the latter called its own. All the experiential facts find their place in this description,

Page 14 of 28

The Self unencumbered with any hypothesis save that of the existence of passing thoughts or states of mind. (1890/1950: i. 400–1; also 1892/1984: 191 [1892/2001: 83])36 There are many subjects, on this view, in the life of a human being like Louis. Each one, each ‘pulse of thought’, is an ‘indecomposable unity’ (James 1890/1950: i. 371) in every sense in which it needs to be for distinct thought‐elements like grass, green, and wet to be able to be genuinely bound together (in the sense of the ‘binding problem’) in whatever way they must be if a thought‐unity like the thought the grass is green and wet is genuinely to occur, or if a single pulse of experience is to be, simultaneously, experience of swimming, thinking about Vienna, and hearing Australian magpies carolling.

What is the metaphysical status of these subjects relative to each other? James seems quite clear on the point. They are numerically distinct—albeit short‐lived — substances. A brain, no doubt, is a single continuing thing, but ‘the same brain may subserve many conscious selves, either alternate or coexisting’, that have ‘no substantial identity’ (James 1890/1950: i. 401). (p. 557)

At one point James puts the point by saying that the self or subject consists in ‘a remembering and appropriating Thought incessantly renewed’ (1890/1950: i. 338, 362– 3),37 and some may take this as evidence that he thinks selves do have some sort of long‐ term continuity. However, his more careful statement of his view cancels any such suggestion: Successive thinkers, numerically distinct, but all aware of the past in the same way, form an adequate vehicle for all the experience of personal unity and sameness which we actually have. (1892/1984: 181) My present Thought stands … in the plenitude of ownership of the train of my past selves, is owner not only de facto, but de jure, the most real owner there can be. … (1890/1950: i. 360)

Page 15 of 28

The Self How does this fit with James's doctrine of the ‘stream of consciousness’, the apparent continuity of conscious experience that occurs in the case of an individual human being like Louis, and leads him (i.e. one short‐lived Louis subject or another) to think of himself, in so far as he is a self, as a single, persisting—continuously existing—entity? The first thing to note is that James rightly doesn't claim to know that the stream of consciousness is continuous.38 Second, he has a ready explanation of the appearance of continuity, for on his view each subject ‘appropriates’— makes its own, takes to itself, inherits, has access to—the content of the experiences of its numerically and substantially distinct predecessors. The notion of appropriation is loose but it is clear enough what James has in mind and it supplies all the apparent (phenomenological) continuity and developmental coherence of experience.39 A further reason why the appearance of continuity is unsurprising, on his view as on mine, is that the subjects (subjects‐or‐ experiences) in question arise successively, in a single person's brain, from brain conditions that have considerable similarity from moment to moment even as they change.40 (p. 558)

— James doesn't really believe in numerically distinct short‐lived metaphysical subjects. His ‘pulses of thought’ are really just convenient theoretical abstractions from the fundamental given fact, a metaphysically single flow. At one point he writes that ‘as the brain‐changes are continuous, so all these consciousnesses melt into each other like dissolving views. Properly they are but one protracted consciousness, one unbroken stream’ (1890/1950: i. 2478)41 This quotation doesn't I think conflict with James's endorsement of short‐lived, numerically distinct subjects, if only because numerically distinct pulses of thought, riding on continuous brain‐changes, can succeed each other in a seamlessly joined and indeed partly temporally overlapping (‘coexisting’) way to form an unbroken stream. James has already denied that we can know there to be an unbroken stream of consciousness, even if we assume there to be an unbroken stream of brain‐changes, and this passage gives no reason to doubt that he takes it that the subject‐constituting pulses of thought are genuinely metaphysically distinct entities rather than theoretical abstractions from a single flow that is single in some way that goes beyond the singleness or uninterruptedness of (possibly overlapping) seamlessness. He thinks that there are many Is or selves or subjects, ‘indecomposable unities’ that are not mere theoretical abstractions.42

These selves, these thoughts, are of course physical unities, on his view, and they have the seemingly unique distinction of being physical unities that we can know for certain to exist (given the assumption that physicalism is true) and to be true unities. For we know (1) that particular thoughts, for example, occur: thoughts in the narrower sense, particular events of proposition‐comprehension. And we know (2) that thoughts must have distinguishable parts or elements, in order to be genuine thoughts. And we know (3) that these distinguishable parts must be held or bound together in the unity that is the comprehension of the proposition by a subject, if there is to be a genuine thought at all. So we know (4) that there are actually existing physical entities that concretely realize a certain sort of unsurpassable unity, a ‘logical’ unity, in Kant's terms, the ‘absolute … logical unity of the subject’, the ‘logical unity of any thought’ (Kant 1781–7/1933: A356, A398).43 In knowing, then, that thoughts exist, and in knowing that any thought must have a certain sort of absolute unity, i.e. the unity that makes it truly the thought that (e.g.) grass is green, we know, to put it in terms that will seem provocative to some

Page 16 of 28

The Self Kantians, although not I believe to Kant, when I have sufficiently explained myself, that there exist entities that are genuine, concrete metaphysical unities of an unsurpassable sort. (p. 559)

The existence of one of these fundamental metaphysical unities may well involve a large number of neurons acting in concert, as we ordinarily suppose; it may well essentially involve a plurality of ‘different substances acting together’, to use Kant's formulation in his discussion of the Second Paralogism (1781–7/1933: A353). And we can't ground any claims about the non‐materiality and hence possible simplicity and hence incorruptibility and hence immortality of the soul on the knowable existence of these ‘absolute’ concrete unities. This, after all, is the line of thought Kant demolishes in his Paralogisms, in which he takes it as common ground that ‘the assertion of the simple nature of the soul is of value only in so far as I can thereby distinguish this subject [i.e. the soul] from all matter, and so can exempt it from the dissolution to which matter is always liable’ (1781–7/1933: A356; my emphasis).44 This demolition is, however, wholly compatible with, and indeed derives part of its force from, the fact that we can know that these fundamental and unsurpassable unities exist even though they are no help in establishing the existence of a persisting immaterial soul.45 Kant allows that thoughts (experiences) really, concretely exist, and it is he himself who makes it most vivid that the fact that ‘the I in every act of thought is one, and cannot be resolved into a plurality of subjects … lies already in the [very] concept of thought’ (1781–7/1933: B407). So when I propose that these real concrete unities are or essentially involve selves, and propose to dignify these selves with the title ‘object’ or ‘substance’, I am not in fundamental conflict with Kant, because I am not trying to lay down a path to immortality via incorruptibility via simplicity via non‐materiality.46 I am, though, proposing that there are in the universe no better candidates for being physical objects or substances than subjects of experience. For what is a physical object? This question receives many different answers in metaphysics (see e.g. Dorr 2005: 234–6), but a physical object is, at least, and most basically, a certain kind of physical unity. The primordial criterion for something's counting as an object, in fact, is its having a certain sort of unity; and it now appears that there is no more certain or absolute unity in nature than the unity of the subject of an experience in having a thought,47 the unity of subjectivity which is necessary to the thought's genuinely occurring at all. The fundamental particles of physics are perhaps the best rival candidates for being unsurpassable physical unities, but photons and electrons as described by physics cannot rival selves or subjects so far as the certainty of their ontological unity is concerned, if indeed they exist at all as irreducibly separate unities, as now seems extremely doubtful. (p. 560) — Won't there be two subjects in the L‐reality if temporal ‘overlap’ of the sort you describe does actually occur in the L‐reality? And isn't this consequence of your view completely unacceptable?

Page 17 of 28

The Self Yes to the first question—if there can be such overlapping then there will for a time be two experiences‐with‐subjects in the L‐reality, one rapidly waning and the other rapidly waxing—No to the second. The idea of two selves or loci of consciousness coexisting in a single brain at a single time is another idea that may offend our ordinary intuitions and emotions, but there is no theoretical difficulty in it, and there is reason to believe that it sometimes happens, and may indeed be routine. If there is such temporal overlapping, neither of the two neuronal‐ recruitment‐constituted thin subjects that will then be numerically distinguishable at a given time t will be aware of there being two subjects at t, any more than Louis the whole human being considered as a (thick) subject of experience will be. However we count subjects in this case, we may take it that the experience of each one of them will have, for that subject, the character of being part of a continuous process of experience on the part of a single subject.48

31.11 The Persistence Belief This, I propose, is what the subjective life of a human being consists of, as a matter of empirical fact. This is what human selves are, in so far as there are such things. With William James and many others, including Buddhists, I think that the idea of the long‐ term persisting self—the persistence belief, for short—is an illusion.49 ‘The state of self is continuously and consistently reconstructed … from the ground up’, as Damasio (1994: 240) says. It's like a word running in lights along a news ticker in Times Square. We naturally think of the word as a single persisting thing, but really it is a rapid series of numerically distinct illuminated things each of which is made up of numerically distinct parts, and would be seen as such by a creature with a higher flicker‐fusion rate than our own. If we now imagine that the word is conscious, and feels that ‘it’ has a continuous existence, although there is no continuing ‘it’ at all, only a rapid series of numerically distinct illuminated words each of which individually has the feeling that it has continuous existence, we have a passable model of the ordinary human experience of a continuing self, such as it is.50 It bears comparison with the experienced constancy and steadiness of vision across constant saccades. (p. 561)

The persistence belief is at the heart of the ordinary conception of the self, and it is not hard to see how it arises. It is supported, directly or indirectly, by many things; most fundamentally, our deep, innate, often thoroughly sensible and extremely general tendency, so ingeniously analysed by Hume, to posit the existence of continuing single things, long‐term continuants, when confronted by certain sorts of diachronically sustained patterns of resemblance between phenomena—experiences, or in his terminology ‘perceptions’—that are in fact numerically distinct. This tendency leads us, as Hume observed, to assume or posit (‘suppose’) a continuously existing table or chair as the cause—and thus explanation—of certain sorts of resemblances among our successive

Page 18 of 28

The Self experiences just as surely as it leads us to posit a continuing self as the common locus of these experiences and part of the cause (and thus explanation) of their resemblances, which are resemblances of content.51 Fundamental among these resemblances of content from one experience to the next are deep, regularly repeated—constantly revived—similarities of interoceptive, proprioceptive, somatosensory bodily awareness, sustained both from moment to moment and from day to day,52 and equally deep similarities of mental feeling‐tone that are in fact, although we may not know it, part of this overall bodily awareness (see e.g. Damasio 1999). To this we may add all the similarities and flow coherencies of development of perceptual and cognitive content from experience to experience, as we move around in the world and think our thoughts. Further support comes in from our exteroceptive and cognitive awareness of our evident singleness and continuity as whole human beings. To this we may add the fact that our thought about ourselves moves very freely between our apprehension of ourselves as persisting human beings and our apprehension of ourselves as mental subjects, in such a way that our awareness of ourselves as persisting whole human beings feeds the persistence belief about the self even though conceiving of oneself as a self is precisely conceiving of oneself as something that is not the same thing as the whole human being. Tied in with all this is the powerful support the persistence belief receives from one's natural apprehension of others as single continuing persons, and one's vivid awareness of others' apprehension of oneself as a continuing single person. All this feeds through to fix the idea of a specifically inner persisting self, (p. 562) and further support comes from specific forms of persistence‐presupposing moral emotion (guilt among them); from the instinct of self‐preservation; from the natural ‘narrativity’ of much human thought (see e.g. Dennett 1991: ch. 11; Strawson 2005); from fear of death; from religious commitments; from the sense that the process of consciousness is stream‐like; from practical planning purposes: from experience of memory (backward‐looking) and intention (forward‐looking); and from the intrinsic continuities of action sequences. If you believe in an inner self at all, then, you are likely to believe in a persisting inner self and feel yourself to be one, in so far as you experience yourself as a self; and I have as remarked on page 551 no decisive argument against a physicalist version of this view according to which the self is whatever anterior‐insula/precuneus/medial‐prefrontal‐ cortex/reticular‐activating‐system/etc.‐involving thing it is in the brain that supports the consciousness and personality of a human being and is still there when the human being is in dreamless sleep. Of the four conditions laid down in 31.3 as crucial to being a self, a persisting self conceived of in this way can fulfil the first three, and can also be argued to fulfil the fourth. It is not as if I can show it to be a mistake to say that such a thing is a subject of experience, a respectable candidate for being called an object or substance, and not the same thing as the whole human being. I have no such experience of being a persisting inner self, although my sense of being an inner mental presence is as strong as anyone's, and this, no doubt, is one reason why I prefer my way of putting things—although I agree with William James that such features Page 19 of 28

The Self of the phenomenology of the self have, in themselves, no consequences for its metaphysics.53 Most will want to reject this way of putting things, and that is fine. My aim here has been to articulate the question of the self in a certain way. I take it that the non‐ continuous‐pulse theory of experiences is the factual truth about the human process of consciousness however anyone wants to use the words ‘self’, ‘subject’, ‘substance’, and so on.

References Berkeley, G. (1713/1975), ‘Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous’, in Philosophical Works, ed. M. R. Ayers (London: Dent). Bradley, F. (1893–7), Appearance and Reality, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Clarke, D. (2003), Descartes's Theory of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2006), Descartes (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Damasio, A. (1994), Descartes's Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (New York: Avon). —— (1999), The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (New York: Harcourt Brace). Dawkins, R. (1998). Unweaving the Rainbow (London: Penguin). Dennett, D. (1988), ‘Why Everyone is a Novelist’, Times Literary Supplement, 16–22 September. (p. 563)

—— (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston, Mass.: Little, Brown).

Descartes, R. (1619–50/1991), ‘Letters’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, iii, trans. and ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–384. —— (1641/1984), ‘Meditations’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ii, trans. and ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–398. —— (1644/1984), ‘Principles of Philosophy’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, i. trans. and ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 177–292. —— (1648/1984), ‘Comments on a Certain Broadsheet’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, i, trans. and ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 293–312.

Page 20 of 28

The Self —— (1648/1976), Conversations with Burman, trans. and ed. J. Cottingham (Oxford: Clarendon). Dorr, C. (2005), What We Disagree About When We Disagree About Ontology’, in M. Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon), 234–86. Fichte, J. G. (1794–1802/1982), The Science of Knowledge, trans. and ed. P. Heath and J. Lachs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Flanagan, O. (2003), The Problem of the Soul (New York: Basic). Gibson, E. (1993), ‘Ontogenesis of the Perceived Self’, in U. Neisser (ed.), The Perceived Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 25–42. Greene, B. (2004), The Fabric of the Cosmos (New York: Knopf). Hume, D. (1739–40/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby‐Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1739–40/2000), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. D. F. Norton and M. Norton (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1779/1947), Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. N. Kemp Smith (Edinburgh: Nelson). James, W. (1890/1950), The Principles of Psychology, i. (New York: Dover). —— (1892/1984), ‘The Self’, in Psychology: The Briefer Course (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 159–91. —— (1892/2001), ‘The Self’, Psychology: The Briefer Course (New York: Dover), 43–83. Kant, I. (1772/1967), Letter to Marcus Herz, 21 Feb. 1772, in Kant: Philosophical Correspondence 1759–99, trans. and ed. A Zweig (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). —— (1781–7/1933), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan). —— (1781–7/1996), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. W. S. Pluhar (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett). —— (1783/1953), Prolegomena, trans. P. G. Lucas (Manchester: Manchester University Press). Kenny, A. (1988), The Self (Marquette, Wisc.: Marquette University Press). —— (1999), ‘Body, Soul, and Intellect in Aquinas’, in M. James and C. Crabbe (eds.), From Soul to Self (London: Routledge), 33–48.

Page 21 of 28

The Self McLaughlin, B., and McGee, V. (2000), ‘Lessons of the Many’, Philosophical Topics, 28: 129–51. Mead, G. H. (1913), ‘The Social Self’, Journal of Philosophy, 10: 374–80. Nozick, R. (1981), Philosophical Explanations (Oxford: Clarendon). Olson, E. (1998), ‘There Is No Problem of the Self’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5: 645–57. Phillips, J. (2003), ‘Schizophrenia and the Narrative Self’, in T. Kircher and A. David (eds.), The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 319–35. (p. 564)

Sider, T. (2001), Four‐Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Spelke, E. (1994), ‘Initial Knowledge: Six Suggestions’, Cognition, 50: 431–45. Strawson, G. (1994), Mental Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1997), ‘The Self’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4: 405–28. —— (1999), ‘The Self and the SESMET’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6: 99–135. —— (2001), ‘Hume on Himself’, in D. Egonsson et al. (eds.), Exploring Practical Philosophy: From Action to Values (Aldershot: Ashgate), 69–94. —— (2002), ‘Postscript to “The Self”’ in R. Martin and J. Barresi (eds), Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell), 363–70. —— (2003/2008), ‘What is the Relation between an Experience, the Subject of the Experience, and the Content of the Experience?’, revised version, in Strawson 2008a: 151–87. —— (2005), ‘Against Narrativity’, in Strawson, The Self? (Oxford: Blackwell), 63–86. —— (2006), Consciousness and its Place in Nature (Thoverton: Imprint). —— (2008a), Real Materialism and Other Essays (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (2008b), ‘The identity of the categorical and the dispositional’, Analysis, 68/4. —— (2009), Selves (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (in preparation), The Evident Connexion: Self, Mind and David Hume (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Trefil, J. (1997), Are We Unique?: A Scientist Explores the Unparalleled Intelligence of the Human Mind (New York: Wiley). Page 22 of 28

The Self van Inwagen, P. (1990), Material Beings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press). Wundt, W. (1874/1911), Principles of Physiological Psychology, trans. E. B. Titchener (New York: Macmillan).

Notes: (1) Greene (2004: 471–93) lists some striking reasons for thinking that reality is not ultimately spatiotemporal—spacetimelike—in nature. (2) The ‘am’ in ‘I am undone’, ‘I am English’, or ‘I am here’ is not the ‘am’ of identity. (3) I defend this view against Wittgensteinian and other philosophical‐logical objections in Strawson (2009: sect. 2.2). (4) Such intentions and beliefs are common even though they may not be explicit. (5) ‘Whole human being’ is short for ‘human being considered as a whole’. It doesn't rule out amputees. (6) The reference of ‘I’ doesn't expand outwards in a continuous fashion, like the reference of ‘now’ and ‘here’, with which it is often compared. Instead it moves between two fixed positions. (7) Objection. Suppose I say [P] ‘I am conscious and I was conscious yesterday too’, using ‘I’ in both instances to refer to a self (rather than to the human being that I am). We want [P] to turn out to be true, but it's false, on your view. Reply. I do think [P] is false—it is quite plain to me that the ‘I’ who is conscious now was just not there yesterday. Still, someone sympathetic to my view who nonetheless wanted [P] to be true could embrace a ‘counterpart semantics’ for past and future sentences: the second ‘I’ would be evaluated in terms of there being a counterpart of me that existed yesterday and was conscious (see Sider 2001; thanks to Brian McLaughlin). (8) Compare Dawkins (1998: 283–4): ‘each of us humans knows that the illusion of a single agent sitting somewhere in the middle of the brain is a powerful one’. (9) In this case the subject is no longer ‘inner’, strictly speaking, but it is still not the same thing as the human being, and this is the crucial idea. Note that ‘immaterial’ is a merely negative word—it has no positive meaning at all—and simply means ‘non‐ physical’. (10) I use the two words interchangeably, aware that the word ‘object’, with its chair‐like feel, causes greater resistance when applied to the self. (11) Kant himself makes the relevant point as he attacks the metaphysics of the self popular in his time (1781/1996: A350), see p. 549 below.

Page 23 of 28

The Self (12) If that is what a self is then we know there are such things and there is no philosophical issue. (13) ‘Principle’ is useful inasmuch as a principle manages to sound like a thing of some sort, in this old use of the word, without sounding anything like a chair or a dog. Plainly selves, so conceived, are not things that can exist only as a ‘predicate of something else’, to put it in Aristotelian/Kantian terms. (14) If immaterial souls existed they would of course be concrete phenomena, for ‘x is a concrete entity’ simply means ‘x is not an abstract entity’, where an abstract entity is something like a number, or a proposition. (15) All religious claims are by comparison only a little less sensible than the claim that grass is green. (16) Note that (1)–(8) are just as likely to be accepted by those who think that selves are immaterial souls as by anybody else. (17) ‘Mental’ does not imply ‘non‐physical’, and here means only ‘mentally propertied’. (18) A strong distinction between substances and their properties is not metaphysically tenable, as Kant knows (see e.g. Kant 1783/1953: sect. 46), but it serves here to make a point. (19) ‘Mode of existing’ cannot here mean the particular way a substance is, where the substance is thought to be somehow independently existent relative to its mode of existing; for that would be to take accidents or properties to be somehow ‘subordinate’ after all. (20) See further Strawson (2008a). Note that our natural counterfactual talk has the classical object–property metaphysic essentially built into it—it is in fact just an expression of this metaphysic—and may very easily mislead us. (21) Van Inwagen holds that selves so understood cannot be said to exist any more than hearts can, even when it is assumed that human beings are wholly material entities (van Inwagen 1990: sect. 15; his reasons for saying this are of great interest). Note that those who identify selves with whole human beings can agree that the brain or self‐system alone is the self in the case in which the brain or self‐system is all that is left of a human being, because it is in that case the whole human being; but not otherwise. (22) In Strawson (2009) I call this entity a ‘sesmet’. (23) ‘Some philosophers … imagine we are … intimately conscious of what we call our SELF: that we feel its existence and its continuance in existence; and are certain both of its perfect identity and simplicity.’ But we do not ‘have … any idea of self, after the manner it is here explain'd’ (Hume 1739–40/2000: 164; my emphasis).

Page 24 of 28

The Self (24) For a discussion of Hume's widely misunderstood position on personal identity and the self, see Strawson (2001, in preparation). (25) Descartes does not think one can prove immortality, and when the second edition of the Meditations appeared he took care to delete the words ‘in which the immortality of the soul is demonstrated’ from the subtitle. (They had been added in the first edition without his knowledge or consent; see Clarke 2006: 202–3.) (26) In January 1642 he writes to Regius: ‘I wish above all that you would never propose any new opinions but, while retaining all the old ones in name, only offer new arguments. No one could object to that, and anyone who understands your new arguments properly will conclude immediately from them what you mean. Thus, why did you need to reject substantial forms and real qualities explicitly?’ (quoted by Clarke 2006: 224; see Descartes 1619–50/1991: 205). (27) He thereby rejects a fundamental assumption of his time (and ours?). See e.g. Clarke (2003: chs. 1, 8, 9). (28) See also Clarke (2003: 215): there is ‘no real distinction, in the Cartesian sense, between a thing and its properties’. (29) I discuss this further in Strawson (2006, 2009: sect. 7.3). (30) Memory that cannot on Descartes's official theory be stored in the brain. (31) ‘The term “faculty” denotes nothing but a potentiality’ (Descartes 1648/1984: 305). (32) One issue concerns Descartes's understanding of what it is to continue to exist in time. (33) ‘The I exists only in so far as it is conscious of itself … The self posits itself, and by virtue of this mere self‐assertion it exists; and conversely, the self exists and posits its own existence by virtue of merely existing. It is at once the agent and the product of action’ (Fichte 1794–1802/1982; 98, 97). ‘There is no preexisting I; rather the I is delineated, is synthesized around the reflexive act. An entity is synthesized around the reflexive act and it is the “I” of that act’; ‘the self which is reflexively referred to is synthesized in that very act of reflexive self‐reference’, ‘an entity coagulates’ (Nozick 1981: 87, 91, 88). (34) ‘Thought. I use this term to include everything that is within us in such a way that we are immediately aware of it. Thus all the operations of the will, the intellect, the imagination, and the sense are thoughts’ (Descartes 1641/1984: 113). (35) A common and spectacular misreading of James has him taking the self to ‘consist mainly of [muscular] motions in the head or between the head and throat’ (James 1890/1950: 301).

Page 25 of 28

The Self (36) He makes the same point in other terms in James (1890/1950: i. 338–42). (37) Compare Damasio (1994: 240): ‘[A]t each moment the state of self is constructed, from the ground up. It is an evanescent reference state, so continuously and consistently reconstructed that the owner never knows that it is being remade unless something goes wrong with the remaking’. (38) ‘Is consciousness really discontinuous, incessantly interrupted and recommencing (from the psychologist's point of view)? And does it only seem continuous to itself by an illusion analogous to that of the zoetrope? Or is it at most times as continuous outwardly as it inwardly seems? It must be confessed that we can give no rigorous answer to this question’ (James 1890/1950: i. 200; see also i. 199). (39) Kant makes the same point in his famous footnote in the Third Paralogism (1781– 7/1933: A363–4). The notion of appropriation would of course be much too strong if it suggested that no content is ever lost. (40) Given short‐term or ‘working’ memory, the content of the immediately preceding experience standardly forms part of the overall experiential context in which the new experience arises in every sense in which features of the external environment do. This is true both of content in the focus of attention and background content, somatosensory content, mood‐tone content, and so on (somatosensory and mood‐tone contents are continually refreshed from sources that usually undergo only slow change—from pulse to pulse, subject to subject—even as salient contents may turn over rapidly). It may be added that the features of the brain that constitute a human being's character, beliefs, general epistemic and cognitive outlook, general conative and emotional outlook, and so on generally remain highly stable from moment to moment. (41) I owe this objection to Mark Sacks. Note that when James uses the phrase ‘melt into each other like dissolving views’ a second time (1890/1950: i. 279) he is talking about transitions within a single pulse of thought. (42) The claim that they are unities is wholly compatible with the view that they involve many neurons and many parts of neurons. Note that a ‘temporal slice’ of the subject of experience cannot be said to be itself a subject having that experience, or a part of that experience, or any experience. (43) ‘That … the I of … thought … designates a logically simple subject—this lies already in the very concept of thought’ (Kant 1781–7/1933: B407). (44) This qualification of his attack on the idea that we can know that the soul is a simple substance—that we can't know it to be a simple substance in such a way as to support the hopes and ends of religion—is crucial but little noticed. Kant goes on to say that ‘this is indeed, strictly speaking, the only use for which the above proposition is intended’ (1781–

Page 26 of 28

The Self 7/1933: A356), ‘the only case in which this concept can be of service’ (1781–7/1933: A360). (45) Even if we do not know them as they are in themselves, given that they have for us an irreducibly temporal character. (46) I expand on this claim, which may be doubted, in Strawson (2009: sects. 2.9, 4.3, 8.5). (47) Or in having sensory experience in more than one sensory modality. (48) Some people naturally experience consciousness as if it were somehow continually restarting—as essentially non‐stream‐like (see e.g. Strawson 1997: sect. 9). There is a lot more to say on the question of the identity conditions of selves; for one useful line of thought see McLaughlin and McGee (2000). (49) Compare Dennett's compelling account of the persisting self as an illusion, a ‘center of narrative gravity’ (1991: 418). See also Dennett (1988). (50) A substantial minority of human beings have no particular experience of there being a persisting, continuing self. (51) For Hume's general discussion of this process see his (1739–40/2000: 133–5, 165–9 [1739–40/1978: 200–4, 253–9]). For his discussion of it with specific regard to the self see Hume (1739–40/2000; 169–71 [1739–40/1978: 259–62]). There is reason to think that the process in the case of the self might be more different from the process in the case of chairs than Hume allows, even on the terms of his own scheme. For important recent improvements on the general point, which can be put by saying that the concept of objects as continuants is innate, see e.g. Spelke (1994). (52) Wundt: ‘the most speculative of philosophers is incapable of disjoining his ego from those bodily feelings and images which form the incessant background of his awareness of himself’ (1874/1911, quoted in James 1890/1950: i. 303 n.). Bradley: ‘there seems … no doubt that the inner core of feeling, resting mainly on what is called Coenaesthesia, is the foundation of the [sense of the] self’ (1893–7: p. 68). James: ‘we feel the whole cubic mass of our body all the while, it gives us an unceasing sense of personal existence’; ‘the nucleus of the “me” is always the bodily existence felt to be present at the time’ (1890/1950: i. 333, 400). The idea is old but has recently been treated as new. (53) This view has been cogently questioned.

Page 27 of 28

The Self

Galen Strawson

Galen Strawson is President’s Chair in Philosophy at University of Texas at Austin. He is the author of seven books, Freedom and Belief (1986), The Secret Connexion: Realism, Causation and David Hume (1989), Mental Reality (1994), Real Materialism and Other Essays (2008), Selves: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics (2009), Locke on personal identity: Consciousness and Concernment (2011), and The Evident Connexion: Hume on personal identity (2011). He is the keynote author in Models of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher and J. Shear (1999), and Consciousness and its Place in Nature, ed A. Freeman, 2006.

Page 28 of 28

Unity of Consciousness

Oxford Handbooks Online Unity of Consciousness   Paul Raymont and Andrew Brook The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0033

Abstract and Keywords When one focuses on words on a monitor and, say, feels a twinge of pain, one is not conscious of the words and, separately, of the pain. One is conscious of the words and the pain together, as aspects of a single experience. At least since Kant, this phenomenon has been called the unity of consciousness. A variety of approaches to characterizing unified consciousness have been tried by different theorists. Some start from the idea that a unified conscious experience is a composite of other experiences. Others assert or assume that, while a unified conscious experience will have a complex object or content, it has no experiential parts. This article returns to this disagreement. The first two ways of characterizing the unity of consciousness that are examined here are within the experiential-parts approach. Keywords: unity of consciousness, conscious experience, experiential-parts approach, co-consciousness, joint consciousness

WHEN one focuses on words on a monitor and, say, feels a twinge of pain, one is not conscious of the words and, separately, of the pain. One is conscious of the words and the pain together, as aspects of a single experience. At least since Kant, this phenomenon has been called the unity of consciousness.

32.1 Approaches

Page 1 of 16

Unity of Consciousness What characterizes the unity of consciousness? Note that this question can be asked and answered whether there actually is any such thing as unified consciousness or not. Indeed, we need to know what we are talking about even to address the question about existence. That said, it should also be noted that it is difficult to say much about the unity of consciousness that is both non‐question‐begging and more than a thinly disguised synonym, a point that Dainton (2000) emphasizes. Even as great a theorist of the subject as Immanuel Kant threw up his hands. He observed that this unity is ‘not the category of unity’ (1781–87/1998: B13)—and said no more. A variety of approaches to characterizing unified consciousness have been tried by different theorists. Some start from the idea that a unified conscious experience is a composite of other experiences. Others assert or assume that, while a unified conscious experience will have a complex object or content, it has no experiential parts. We will return to this disagreement below. For now it is enough to note that it underlies many of the differences in approach, to which we now turn. (p. 566)

The first two ways of characterizing the unity of consciousness that we will examine are within the experiential‐parts approach.

32.1.1 Subsumption One attempt to characterize the unity of consciousness holds that in unified consciousness particular experiences are subsumed in a more complex experience. For example, Bayne and Chalmers (2003) say that when particular experiences are unified, they are ‘aspects of a single encompassing state of consciousness’. More precisely, two experiences are what they call ‘subsumptively unified’ ‘when they are both subsumed by a single state of consciousness’ (2003: 27). This yields a distinctive phenomenology. Two subsumptively unified states will have what they call a ‘conjoint phenomenology’—a phenomenology of having both states at once that subsumes the phenomenology of the individual states: ‘[T]here is something it is like for the subject to be in [two conscious] states simultaneously’ (2003: 32). Clearly, this approach would require that there be experiential parts.

32.1.2 Co‐consciousness A second attempt to characterize unified consciousness claims that a co‐consciousness relation among local conscious states is the crucial element. James originated the term. As he put it, in synchronic unified consciousness we are co‐conscious of A, B, and C (1909/1967: 221). Others who centre their analysis on the notion include Parfit (1984) and Hurley (1998). Theorists generally do not try to define the term, content to let it function as a primitive in their analysis.

Page 2 of 16

Unity of Consciousness Some theorists combine the two approaches. In fact, many of the people who use the term ‘co‐consciousness’ seem to have subsumption in mind as the underlying notion. Dainton, for example, embraces the language of co‐consciousness, but cashes the notion in terms such as ‘being experienced together’ (2000: 236). Lockwood (1989: 88) describes co‐consciousness as ‘the relation in which two experiences stand, when there is an experience of which they are both parts’. Similarly Shoemaker: ‘The experiences are co‐conscious … by virtue of the fact that they are components of a single state of consciousness’ (2003: 65). Like subsumption, co‐consciousness would also require that there be experiential parts. At any rate that is true of co‐consciousness as a relationship among experiences. James held that it is a relationship among objects of a single experience, which is compatible with unified conscious experiences not having parts—a view to which he in fact adhered, as we will see.

32.1.3 Joint Consciousness At least two approaches to unified consciousness are compatible with the no‐experiential‐ parts view. One we find in Tye (2003). In unified conscious states, (p. 567) the things that we experience are ‘experienced together’, ‘enter into the same phenomenal content’ (2003: 36)—which phenomenal content could be the content of a single non‐ composite experience. Another approach has been advanced by Brook and Raymont (Brook 1994: 38; 2000; Brook and Raymont 2006, forthcoming). The key idea here is joint consciousness: If an experience that one is having provides consciousness of any item, then it provides consciousness of other items and of at least some of the items as a group. Likewise for consciousness of acts of experiencing. This notion is related to the phenomenal side of the Bayne and Chalmers notion of subsumption—there being something it is like to be in two conscious states simultaneously (Bayne and Chalmers 2003: 32)—but in a way that does not require subsumption.

32.2 Taxonomies Most writers agree that unified consciousness comes in a number of forms. There agreement stops. There are almost as many ways of dividing it up into sub‐kinds as there are theorists. Tye (2003: 11–15), for example, distinguishes object unity, neurophysiological unity, spatial unity, subject unity, introspective unity, and, finally, phenomenal unity. Bayne and Chalmers (2003: 24–7) distinguish ‘objectual’ unity (a matter of two conscious experiences of one object, so different from Tye's object unity), spatial unity, subject unity, and subsumptive unity—the last a matter of two or more conscious states becoming aspects of a single conscious state. Then within subsumptive unity they distinguish between access unity and phenomenal unity. Their definition of the

Page 3 of 16

Unity of Consciousness latter, as with Tye their main interest, we just examined: two conscious states are phenomenally unified ‘if there is something it is like for the subject to be in both conscious states simultaneously’. And so on. Interestingly, Kant and philosophers in his tradition break phenomenal unity itself down into sub‐kinds, usually starting with the division of the mind into subject, representation, and object or content and assigning to each a special form of unified consciousness. Few contemporary theorists break phenomenal unity down at all, so this division is of some interest. Kant's division results in at least four sub‐kinds. The first three can be expressed in terms of the notion of joint consciousness just introduced. There is unified consciousness of individual objects, Tye's object unity; Bayne and Chalmers's objectual unity. The most common name for the process at work here is binding (Hardcastle 1998; Revonsuo 1999). Binding is the process of tying various features of a visual scene such as colour, shape, edges, and contours, features detected in various places in the visual cortex, together into an experience of a unified, three‐ dimensional object. Binding may be necessary for consciousness of individual objects but it does not seem to be sufficient. We must, it seems, also be jointly conscious of the various elements to have unified consciousness of an object. Next, there is unified consciousness of contents: If an experience that one is having provides consciousness of any object or content, then it provides consciousness (p. 568) of other objects or contents and of at least some of the items as a group.1 Unified consciousness of contents appears to be central to our kind of consciousness. For example, suppose that I am conscious of the computer screen in front of me and also of the car sitting in my driveway. I could not even ask if the car is the same colour as some item on my monitor if I were not conscious of the two in a single act of consciousness. As we will see, there are disorders of consciousness in which this ability to compare seems to be lost. Such people are seriously cognitively impaired. Unified consciousness of contents goes with a third sub‐kind of unified consciousness, unified consciousness of acts of experiencing. The latter is present when, for acts of experiencing that one is engaged in, consciousness of one act of experiencing (consciousness of how one is experiencing something, for example seeing it, imagining it, …) provides consciousness of other acts of experiencing. Not all philosophers accept that there is this form of unified consciousness. Those who promote the so‐called transparency thesis, the claim that we are not directly conscious of our own experiencings, do not accept this (Dretske 1995; Tye 2003). Tye, for example, says that when we hear something, we cannot be conscious of the auditory experience, just what it represents. If one tries to be conscious of the experience, at best one is aware only of ‘the auditory qualities that the experience represents’ (2003: 33). Kant and many Kantians have also spoken of a fourth sub‐kind of the unity of consciousness; namely, unified consciousness of oneself. Here one is or certainly seems to be (Rosenthal 2003 says merely seems to be) conscious of oneself not just as subject but, in Kant's words (1781–7/1998: A350), as the ‘single common subject’ of the many aspects Page 4 of 16

Unity of Consciousness of the unified experience that one is now having and of a number of similar experiences past and, in anticipation, still to come. Such consciousness of self is a sub‐kind of unified consciousness. Hume (1739–40/1962: 252) and Rosenthal (2003) deny that we have such unified consciousness of self and Dennett (1991, 1992) says at minimum that we have much less of it than we think. We will return to this issue. Some theorists hold that there is also a fifth form of unified consciousness. We might call it unity of focal attention. It consists in our ability to pay unified, focused attention to things. It differs from the last three sub‐kinds of unified consciousness. In them, consciousness ranges over either many represented items, or complex representings, or oneself as subject of the representings. Unity of focus picks out something within these unified ‘fields’. Wilhelm Wundt (1874/1893: ii. 67) captured what we have in mind in his distinction between the field of consciousness (Blickfeld) and the focus of consciousness (Blickpunkt). Unity of focal consciousness is more like unified consciousness of a single item than it is like any of the other three.2 The first four sub‐kinds are clearly Kantian. Kant did speak of attention, too—not very often but he did speak of it (e.g. Kant 1781–7/1998: B156 n.).

Page 5 of 16

Unity of Consciousness

(p. 569)

32.3 A Long History

The notion of the unity of consciousness has figured centrally in some of the most influential arguments about the mind from the time of Descartes to the twentieth century. It is central to the work of Descartes, Leibniz, Hume, Reid, Kant, Brentano, James— indeed, to most major precursors of contemporary philosophy of mind and cognitive psychology. It played a particularly important role in Kant's work. As an example, consider a classical argument for mind–body dualism. It starts like this: When I consider the mind, that is to say, myself inasmuch as I am only a thinking thing, I cannot distinguish in myself any parts, but apprehend myself to be clearly one and entire (Descartes 1641/1970: 196) Descartes then asserts that if the mind is not made of parts, it cannot be made of matter, because anything material has parts. He adds that this by itself would be enough to prove dualism, had he not proved it already. Notice where it is that I cannot distinguish any parts. It is in the unified consciousness that I have of myself. The central claim is then that unified consciousness could never be achieved by a system of components.

Arguments of this sort were familiar to Kant (chiefly from similar reasoning in Leibniz and Mendelssohn). However, Kant held that unity tells us nothing about what sorts of entity minds are, including whether or not they are made out of matter (1781–7/1998: chapter on the paralogisms of pure reason). His argument is that the achievement of unified consciousness by a system of components acting together would be no less mysterious than its being achieved by something simple—that is, that has no components (Kant 1781–7/1998: A352). The notion that consciousness is unified was also central to one of Kant's own arguments: his transcendental deduction of the categories. There Kant claims that in order to tie various objects of experience together into a single unified conscious representation of the world, we must be able to apply certain concepts to the items in question. In particular, we have to apply concepts from each of four fundamental categories of concept: quantitative, qualitative, relational, and what he called ‘modal’ concepts. We cannot explore this argument, but it does illustrate how central the unity of consciousness was in Kant's thought.3 As we saw earlier, unified consciousness played a major role in James's work, too, under the label ‘co‐consciousness’ (James 1909/1967: 221).4 Early in the twentieth century the notion disappeared from the work on the mind of all but a few philosophers. Logical atomism in philosophy and behaviourism in psychology had little (p. 570) need for such a notion. A partial exception is Carnap's choice (1928) to avoid any commitment to atoms of experience as the elements of his system, opting instead for ‘total experiences’. His notion of irreducible experiential wholes can, as we will see, be usefully developed. Page 6 of 16

Unity of Consciousness Carnap's actual motivation seems to have been a desire to make his system compatible with gestalt psychology (Smith 1994: 23). However, while gestalt unity does indeed appear in some structures of which one is conscious, it is different from the unity that characterizes one's consciousness of various objects, objects that need not include unified gestalt structures. There has been a resurgence of interest in unified consciousness among analytic philosophers in the past few decades, beginning with some influential commentaries on Kant in the 1960s (Bennett 1966, 1974; Strawson 1966) and works by Nagel (1971, 1974) and Parfit (1971, 1984). More recently, a large number of philosophers and a few psychologists have written on the subject, including Marks (1981), Trevarthen (1984), Lockwood (1989, 1994), White (1990), Hill (1991), Hurley (1994, 1998), Marcel (1994), Dainton (2000), Bayne and Chalmers (2003), Blackmore (2004), and Bayne (forthcoming).

32.4 Pathologies of Unified Consciousness One of the most interesting ways to study a psychological phenomenon is to see what happens when it breaks down or takes an abnormal form. Phenomena that look simple and seamless when functioning smoothly often turn out to have all sorts of structure when they begin to malfunction. This is certainly true of unified consciousness. Abnormalities of unified consciousness take two forms. There are (1) situations in which it is retained in an unusual form, situations where, for example, we seem to have two instances of unified consciousness when we'd expect one; and (2) situations in which the unity itself has been severely compromised. The first kind of situation first.

32.4.1 Unusual Forms of Unity of Consciousness Brain‐Bisection Operations Commissurotomies are the best‐known situations in which unified consciousness seems to split but otherwise remains intact. Often referred to as brain‐bisection operations, the abnormality is that the person seems to have been split into two unified centres of consciousness within one body. In a commissurotomy, the corpus callosum, a large strand of about 200,000,000 neurons running from one hemisphere to the other, is cut. When present, it is the chief channel of communication between the hemispheres. (These operations are a last‐ditch effort to control certain kinds of severe epilepsy by stopping the spread of seizures.) (p. 571)

In special laboratory conditions it is natural to hold that the original single instance of unified consciousness has been fissioned into two such instances. Here are a couple of examples of the kinds of behaviour that prompt this assessment. The human retina is split Page 7 of 16

Unity of Consciousness vertically in such a way that the left half of each retina is primarily hooked up to the left hemisphere of the brain and the right half of each retina is hooked up to the right hemisphere of the brain. Now suppose that we flash the word TAXABLE on a screen in front of a brain‐bisected patient in such a way that the letters TAX hit the left side of the retina, the letters ABLE the right side and we put measures in place to ensure that the information hitting each half of the retina goes only to one lobe and is not fed to the other. If such a patient is asked what word is being shown, the mouth, controlled usually by the left hemisphere, will say TAX while the hand controlled by the hemisphere that does not control the mouth (usually the left hand and the right hemisphere) will write ABLE. Or, if the hemisphere that controls a hand (usually the left hand) but not speech is asked to do arithmetic in a way that does not penetrate to the hemisphere that controls speech and the hands are shielded from the eyes, the mouth will insist that it is not doing arithmetic, has not even thought of arithmetic today, etc.—while the appropriate hand is busily doing arithmetic! Note that in none of these situations do we have much inclination to say that the unity has been destroyed or even much damaged. It is just ‘parcelled out’ differently. The same may be true of the next condition that we will examine.

Dissociative Identity Disorder In what used to be called ‘multiple personality disorder’, now, more neutrally, ‘dissociative identity disorder’ (DID), some have found a similar split into two (or more, sometimes many more) instances of unified consciousness. Since everything about this phenomenon is controversial, including whether there is any multiplicity of consciousness at all, we will not say more about it.

32.4.2 Compromised Unity of Consciousness In contrast to the cases that we just considered, there are phenomena in which unified consciousness seems more to shatter than to split.

Schizophrenia In some particularly severe forms of schizophrenia the victim seems to lose the ability to form an integrated, interrelated representation of his or her world and self altogether. The person speaks in ‘word salads’ that never get anywhere, indeed sometimes never become complete sentences. The person is unable to put together or act on plans even at the level necessary to obtain sustenance, tend to bodily needs, or escape painful irritants. Here it seems more correct to say that the unity of consciousness has shattered rather than split. The behaviour of sufferers seems to express what (p. 572) we might call mere experience fragments, the contents of which are so narrow and unintegrated that the subject is unable to cope and interact with others in the ways that even split‐brain subjects can.

Dysexecutive Syndrome Page 8 of 16

Unity of Consciousness In schizophrenia of the severe sort just described the shattering of consciousness is part of a general breakdown or deformation of mental functioning: affect, desire, belief, even memory all suffer massive distortions. In another kind of case the normal unity of consciousness seems to be just as absent but there does not seem to be general cognitive or affective disturbance. This is what some researchers call dysexecutive syndrome (Dawson 1998: 215). What indicates breakdown in the unity of consciousness is that these subjects are unable to consider two things together, even things directly related to one another. For example, such people cannot figure out whether a piece of a puzzle fits into a certain place even when the piece and the puzzle are both clearly visible and the piece obviously fits. They cannot crack an egg into a pan. And so on.5

Simultagnosia A disorder presenting similar symptoms is simultagnosia, or Balint's syndrome. In this disorder patients see only one object located at one ‘place’ in the visual field at a time. Outside a few ‘degrees of arc’ in the visual field, patients say they see nothing but an ‘undifferentiated mess’ and seem to be receiving no information about objects (Hardcastle 1998: 562). What is common to dysexecutive disorder and simultagnosia is that subjects appear not to be conscious of two items in a single conscious state. They cannot, for example, compare the objects. If the person has any representation of the second item at all, it is not unified with consciousness of the first one. Unlike the split‐brain case, the second representation is not just missing from one conscious state. It is not unified with any other conscious states, too. Rather than consciousness being split into two unified parcels, there is little unity or none at all.

32.5 Is There a Common Thread to the Pathological Cases? What, precisely, is missing in these cases where consciousness is seriously compromised? Let us call back the distinction between unified consciousness of individual objects and unified consciousness of a number of objects in a single act of consciousness. (p. 573) The first kind continues to be available to dysexecutive and simultagnosia patients: they continue to be conscious of individual objects, events, etc. The damage seems to be to the second stage: it is the tying of objects together in unified conscious representation that is impaired or missing. The distinction can be made in this way. Sufferers can achieve some measure of unified focus with respect to individual objects, but unified consciousness of groups of objects and of experiences of them is abnormally restricted or missing altogether. By contrast, it appears that even the first stage is not available in the severe schizophrenias just discussed.

Page 9 of 16

Unity of Consciousness Brain‐bisection cases are a contrast in the other direction. The ability to tie objects together is intact, especially in the left lobe. What opens the way to the idea of a split in consciousness is that in some situations whatever is conscious of some items being represented in the body in question is not conscious of other items being represented in that same body at the same time. (See the examples of the word TAXABLE and of doing arithmetic.) Nonetheless, commisurotomy, severe schizophrenia, dysexecutive disorder, and simultagnosia all appear to display a common pattern. In all cases consciousness of some items goes with a lack of consciousness of others contained in the same brain.

32.6 Four Theses The literature about unified consciousness, especially the philosophical literature, contains some striking claims about the phenomena. So far we have always had a clear number of instances of unified consciousness in each case. Some philosophers reject this result. Nagel (1971), for example, claims that there is no whole number of ‘centres of consciousness’ in brain‐bisection patients: there is too much unity to say ‘two’, yet too much splitting to say ‘one’. Then there are two claims about what characterizes unified consciousness. One urges that some kind of relationship among contents is generally required, logical coherence for example (Hurley 1994, 1998).6 Unified conscious states cannot be inconsistent with one another. But that cannot be right. Suppose that one sees a stick immersed in water as being bent but knows that this is an illusion. Here one's conscious perception conflicts with one's conscious belief that it is not bent. Yet one's consciousness of them is unified. The other we will call the strong unity thesis. This is the thesis that all the conscious states of a subject are unified; every conscious state is unified with every other conscious state. Thus Bayne and Chalmers (2003: 24): ‘Necessarily, any set of conscious states of a subject at a time is unified’. Against this thesis, cases of dissociation may be adduced, particularly split‐brain cases, where it looks as if a subject has parallel streams of consciousness between which there is no unified consciousness. (p. 574)

Even though there is reason to question these requirements on unity, the idea that unified consciousness goes with such exotic properties may be behind some of the recent scepticism about whether there is any such thing. This is the fourth claim. Davidson (1982) and Dennett (1991) have both urged that the mind's unity has been overstated, citing the everyday incoherence of our beliefs, perceptions, etc. From the fact that not all of one's conscious contents are unified it does not follow, of course, that none are.

Page 10 of 16

Unity of Consciousness

32.7 Two Models What does unified consciousness consist in? As we have already said, there are two broad approaches. On one view, the experience whereby I have unified consciousness of a number of things includes simpler experiences of those contents. For example, my experience of the pain and the noise includes an experience of just the pain, and an experience of just the noise. These simpler experiences are the relata of co‐ consciousness, and are joined as parts of the unified experience of the pain and noise together: experiences a and b are united in a third experience, c, which is their joint occurrence. Call this the doctrine of experiential parts (EP). On the rival account, the conscious mental act through which diverse contents are presented does not have other conscious states as parts. Call this the doctrine of no experiential parts (NEP). We will close with a further look at this disagreement. Proponents of EP include Lockwood (1989: 88), who introduces the notion of co‐ consciousness as ‘the relation in which two experiences stand, when there is an experience of which they are both parts’, and Dainton (2000: 88), who says: ‘The relata of co‐consciousness are experiences’ and speaks of co‐conscious experiences as ‘component parts’ of the ‘total experience’ that results from their linkage (2000: 214). Similarly, Shoemaker (2003: 65) says: ‘The experiences are co‐conscious … by virtue of the fact that they are components of a single state of consciousness’.7 James was the first to champion NEP in an unmistakable way. He endorsed it in the course of repudiating the ‘mind‐stuff theory’, according to which ‘our mental states are composite in structure, made up of smaller states conjoined’ (1890: 145). Against this James says that while our experience is complex, this complexity is not a matter of there being several experiences (or ‘feelings’) present in an encompassing experience. This is because ‘we cannot mix feelings as such, though we may mix the objects we feel, and from their mixture get new feelings’ (1890: 157). If one's (p. 575) experience appears to become more complex, that is a matter of a single experience's content being more complex, and is not the addition of more experiences (of the diversity of content). In the tradition of James, NEP is now advocated by Searle and Tye among others. Searle ventures the hypothesis that ‘it is wrong to think of consciousness as made up of parts at all’. For I have a ‘single, unified, conscious field containing visual, auditory, and other aspects’, but ‘there is no such thing as a separate visual consciousness’ (2002: 56). Do ‘visual experiences stand to the whole field of consciousness in the part/whole relation?’. No, says Searle (2002: 54). Tye offers a similar view, which he dubs the ‘one‐experience view’ (2003: ch. 1). Considering the polymodal nature of our experience, he says: ‘There are not five different … experiences somehow combined together to produce a new unified experience’. Instead, ‘there is just one experience here’ (2003: 27).

Page 11 of 16

Unity of Consciousness As James saw it, EP faces a difficulty that does not confront NEP. His well‐known example of the twelve‐word sentence is designed to expose it. Suppose each word in the sentence is known by one and only one of twelve people. It is hard to see, James says, how these twelve thoughts could be combined to yield a unified consciousness of the sentence. As he says: Take a sentence of a dozen words, take twelve men, and to each one word. Then stand the men in a row or jam them in a bunch, and let each think of his word as intently as he will; nowhere will there be a consciousness of the whole sentence. (1890: 160) What EP needs is a way of combining experiences that yields more than just an experiential aggregate, for a mere combination of experiences is not the experience of a combination. EP needs, then, a way of putting together experiences that also puts together their contents. Without any specification of how this combining of contents is to be achieved, we are left with a mere aggregate of experiences, each member of which is oblivious to the contents of the other states in the aggregate. As James says: ‘Idea of a+idea of b is not identical with idea of (a+b)’ (1890: 161).

Tye links NEP to the idea that conscious states are transparent. ‘Transparent’ here means that while I am conscious via conscious states, I am not conscious of them. I ‘see through’ them; hence ‘transparency’. What might seem to be qualities of conscious states are really qualities that things are represented as having. ‘Phenomenal unity is a relation between qualities represented in experience, not between qualities of experiences’ (Tye 2003: 36). However, proponents of NEP need not affirm transparency. One alternative is the idea that conscious states are self‐representing states, states of which one becomes conscious just by having them. On this approach, some of the qualities of which one becomes conscious in having an experience belong to the experience itself. This idea seems to be entirely consistent with NEP. If it is, NEP carries no commitment to the transparency thesis. To conclude, the unity of consciousness is a pervasive, cognitively important feature of our kind of mind. It comes in a number of related but distinguishable forms. (p. 576) The ways in which it breaks down are revealing and informative. And, finally, the claims that philosophers make about it are a very mixed bag.8

References Bayne, T. (forthcoming), The Unity of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Bayne, T., and Chalmers, D. (2003), ‘What Is the Unity of Consciousness?’, in A. Cleeremans in (ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration, and Dissociation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 23–58.

Page 12 of 16

Unity of Consciousness Bennett, J. (1966), Kant's Analytic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1974), Kant's Dialectic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Blackmore, S. (2004), Consciousness: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Brook, A. (1994), Kant and the Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2000), ‘Unity of Consciousness: What It Is and Where It is Found’, Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (New York: LEA), 102–8. —— (2005), ‘Kant, Cognitive Science, and Contemporary Neo‐Kantianism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11: 1–25. Brook, A., and Raymont, P. (2006), ‘The Unity of Consciousness’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, , accessed 2008. —— (forthcoming), A Unified Theory of Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Carnap, R. (1928/1967), Logical System of the World, trans. R. George (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press). Cassam, Q. (1996), Self and World (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Dainton, B. (2000), Stream of Consciousness: Unity and Continuity in Conscious Experience (London: Routledge). Davidson, D. (1982), ‘Paradoxes of Irrationality’, in R. Wollheim and J. Hopkins (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 289–305. Dawson, M. (1998), Understanding Cognitive Science (Oxford: Blackwell). Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained (New York: Little, Brown). —— (1992), ‘The Self as the Center of Narrative Gravity’, in F. Kessel, P. Cole, and D. Johnson (eds.), Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 101–15. Descartes, R. (1641/1970), ‘Meditations on First Philosophy’, in The Philosophical Works of Descartes, i, trans. E. S. Haldane and G. R. Z. Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 131–200. Dretske, F. (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Hardcastle, V. (1998), ‘The Binding Problem’, in W. Bechtel and G. Graham (eds.), A Companion to Cognitive Science (Oxford: Blackwell), 555–64.

Page 13 of 16

Unity of Consciousness —— (1997), ‘Attention Versus Consciousness: A Distinction with a Difference’, Cognitive Studies: Bulletin of the Japanese Cognitive Science Society, 4/3: 56–66; repr. in N. Osaka (ed.), Neural Basis of Consciousness (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2003), 105–20. Hill, C. (1991), Sensations: A Defense of Type Materialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Hume, D. (1739–40/1962). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby‐Bigge (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Hurley, S. (1994), ‘Unity and Objectivity’, in C. Peacocke (ed.), Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 49–78. (p. 577)

—— (1998), Consciousness in Action (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). James, W. (1890), Principles of Psychology, i (London: Macmillan). —— (1909/1967), ‘A Pluralistic Universe’, in James, Essays in Radical Empiricism and A Pluralistic Universe (Gloucester, Mass.: Smith), 1–233. Kant, I. (1781–7/1998), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. P. Guyer and A. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Lockwood, M. (1989), Mind, Brain and the Quantum (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1994), ‘Issues of Unity and Objectivity’, in C. Peacocke (ed.), Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 89–98. Marcel, A. (1994), ‘What is Relevant to the Unity of Consciousness?’ in C. Peacocke (ed.), Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 79–88. Marks, C. (1981), Commissurotomy, Consciousness and Unity of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Nagel, T. (1971), ‘Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness’, Synthese, 22: 396–413. —— (1974), ‘What is it Like to Be a Bat?’, Philosophical Review, 83: 435–50. Parfit, D. (1971), ‘Personal Identity’, Philosophical Review, 80: 3–27. —— (1984), Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Revonsuo, A. (1999), ‘Binding and the Phenomenal Unity of Consciousness’, Consciousness and Cognition, 8: 173–85.

Page 14 of 16

Unity of Consciousness Rosenthal, D. (2003), ‘Unity of Consciousness and the Self’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103: 325–52. Searle, J. (2000/2002), ‘Consciousness’, Annual Review of Neuroscience, 23: 557–78, repr. in Searle, Consciousness and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 36–60. Shoemaker, S. (1968), ‘Self‐reference and Self‐awareness’, Journal of Philosophy, 65: 555– 67. —— (2003), ‘Consciousness and Co‐consciousness’, in A. Cleeremans (ed.), The Unity of Consciousness: Binding, Integration and Dissociation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 59–71. Smith, B. (1994), Austrian Philosophy: The Legacy of Franz Brentano (Chicago, Ill.: Open Court). Strawson, P. F. (1966), The Bounds of Sense (London: Methuen). Trevarthen, C. (1984), ‘Biodynamic Structures: Cognitive Correlates of Motive Sets and the Development of Motives in Infants’, in W. Prinz and A. F. Sanders (eds.), Cognition and Motor Processes (Berlin: Springer‐Verlag), 327–50. Tye, M. (2003), Consciousness and Persons: Unity and Identity (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). White, S. (1990), The Unity of the Self (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Wundt, W. M. (1874/1893), Principles of Physiological Psychology, trans. E. B. Titchener (London: Allen).

Notes: (1) Kant was the first to articulate this distinction between unified consciousness of individual objects and of multiples of objects (Kant 1781–7/1998: first division, bk. 1, ch. 2; see Brook 1994: 123). (2) If focus is closely related to attention, as we suggested, attention need not be part of at least some forms of consciousness (Hardcastle 1997). (3) One aspect of Kant's strategy continues to capture the imaginations of philosophers: his attempt to connect the unity of consciousness to the structure of knowledge. Arguments of this form can be found in P. F. Strawson (1966), Hurley (1994, 1998), and Cassam (1996). For a critical analysis of moves of this kind see Brook (2005). (4) Parfit reintroduced the term into contemporary literature (1984: 250). (5) Trevarthen (1984) reports a related syndrome.

Page 15 of 16

Unity of Consciousness (6) Hurley stops short of applying this constraint universally, but says that it applies ‘in many cases’ (1998: 115). (7) Tye (2003: 21) numbers Bayne and Chalmers among the adherents of EP (without using that label). However, while Bayne and Chalmers do indeed speak of the encompassing conscious state as involving ‘at least a conjunction of each of many more specific conscious states’ (2003: 27), and of a ‘complex phenomenal state and a simpler state that is intuitively one of its components’ (2003: 40), they also caution that thinking here in terms of ‘a mereological part/whole relation among phenomenal states’ should be regarded only as an ‘aid to intuition rather than as a serious ontological proposal’ (2003: 40). So it is not clear how their view should be classified. (8) An earlier version of some portions of this chapter appeared in Brook and Raymont (2006). Material carried over to this chapter has been extensively rewritten.

Paul Raymont

Paul Raymont is Assistant Professor, Ryerson University. Andrew Brook

Andrew Brook is Chancellor's Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Institute of Cognitive Science, Department of Philosophy, Carleton University.

Page 16 of 16

Personal Identity and Metaphysics

Oxford Handbooks Online Personal Identity and Metaphysics   Tamar Szabó Gendler The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0034

Abstract and Keywords This article tries to situate the recent discussions of personal identity in their historical context. It begins with a brief discussion of Locke's account of identity as such, turning then to a more detailed account of his views on personal identity in particular. It then discusses a pair of problems that arise for any sort of neo-Lockean account, and surveys the sorts of responses that have been offered to them. Finally the article briefly presents three recent accounts, each of which can be seen as relying on a subtle recharacterization of the traditional problem of personal identity. Keywords: personal identity, metaphysics, neo-Lockean concept, judgements, living things, imaginary cases

THE

traditional philosophical problems surrounding the issue of personal identity arise

from trying to answer the following series of questions in a systematic way. Given a person X, we want to know: (1) With which past and future entities is X (numerically) identical? (2) Which facts determine the answer to (1)? (3) On what bases do we ordinarily make judgements about (1), and on what bases could we do so in principle? (4) What sorts of practical and emotional significance should the answer to (1) have?

Page 1 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics The questions themselves appear to be straightforward. But it has proved challenging to answer them in a philosophically satisfying way. It is surprisingly difficult to come up with an account of personal identity that simultaneously respects plausible commitments about the metaphysics of identity while preserving the platitudes about personhood that seem to characterize our intuitive grasp of the concept. As a result, most sophisticated contemporary accounts are both subtle and complicated. Indeed, there is little agreement even about what sort of concept person is—a substance concept or a phase sortal? a natural‐kind concept or a conventional one? an ethical concept or a metaphysical one?—and hence little agreement about what sort of analysis we should aim to provide for it. Without some sense of how the debate came to have the form it does, recent discussions of personal identity are likely to seem bewildering. (p. 579)

In the remainder of this chapter I will try to situate these recent discussions in their historical context. I will begin (Section 33.1) with a brief discussion of Locke's account of identity as such, turning then to a more detailed account of his views on personal identity in particular. I will then (Section 33.2) discuss a pair of problems that arise for any sort of neo‐Lockean account, and survey the sorts of responses that have been offered to them. Finally (Section 33.3), I will briefly present three recent accounts, each of which can be seen as relying on a subtle re‐characterization of the traditional problem of personal identity.

33.1 The Lockean Background 33.1.1 Locke on Identity Contemporary discussions of personal identity take their cue from John Locke's discussion ‘Of Identity and Diversity’ in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Locke presents his analysis in the context of defending the view that identity is ‘suited to the Idea’ (1690; II. xxvii, sect. 7); that is, that criteria for identity (over time) are criteria for identity as an X (over time).1 These criteria, he suggests, can be grouped into three categories:2 one for material substances (atoms and masses of matter); one for living entities (plants and animals); and one for self‐conscious beings (persons).3

33.1.1.1 Atoms and Masses of Matter On Locke's picture, atoms (or particles of matter) are the primitive bearers of bodily identity; they are the fundamental simples from which all physical complexes are composed. They are individuated by their time and place of coming into being, and their identity over time is a brute matter of their continued simple existence. Though we are unable to distinguish one such particle from another simpliciter, virtually (p. 580) all of our practical judgements about the continued existence of material objects presuppose that we are able to track them across space and time, and that an atom at one time is

Page 2 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics identical to an atom at another if they are connected by a continuous path in space and time. (Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sect. 2).4 Masses of matter are objects where ‘two or more atoms [are] joined together into the same mass’ (Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sect. 26); that is, collections of contiguous atoms with some sort of force connecting them.5 A given mass of matter consisting of some set of contiguous atoms is identical to any future (or past) mass of matter consisting of those same contiguous atoms so long as those and only those atoms remain properly united throughout. As with atoms, our evidential basis for such judgements rests on our ability to track objects that trace continuous paths through space–time (though we are presumably insensitive to minor changes in constitution, and hence to the identity of stuff over time); few particular practical judgements seem to rest on (re)identifying such complexes, though again our general practices presuppose the absence of massive error (Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sect. 3). In sum, atoms and masses of matter are individuated on the basis of their constitution properties and nothing else—an atom or mass at one time is not (identical to) an atom or mass at another unless they have exactly the same contiguous matter; facts about how that contiguous matter is organized, or about properties that emerge as a result of that organization, are irrelevant. By contrast, objects that fall under the sortals that Locke discusses next are individuated not by the matter that composes them but by the various properties that their organized matter manifests.

33.1.1.2 Living Things A living thing, such as a plant, animal, or ‘man’ (human animal), is an entity whose material parts are organized so as to be parts of a self‐sustaining organic whole. A living thing at one time is identical to a living thing at another if and only if they participate in the same continuous self‐organizing organic process, regardless of changes in form and matter. We are cognizant of the sorts of changes that living organisms of various categories are wont to undergo, and of the features that they are wont to exhibit; hence, we are generally (though not infallibly) able to (re)identify living beings by observing their manifest properties. Because they suffer predictable causal histories—both individually and generically—being able to reidentify particular complex organisms allows us to navigate and control the world around us; and because they display considerable variation in their features, we may come to especially value our interactions with one or another of them. As a result, the answers (p. 581) to such identity questions often have considerable practical significance (Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sects. 4–8).

Page 3 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics 33.1.1.3 Persons The final category that Locke discusses is that of person: ‘a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places’. A person at one time is identical to a person at another time if they are the same ‘rational being’: ‘as far as this consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person’.6 In ordinary cases we make judgements about personal identity both on the basis of physical properties (as sameness of human animal is generally indicative of sameness of person) and on the basis of manifest psychological characteristics (evidenced through speech and non‐verbal behaviour).7 And these judgements are of great practical significance; for ‘person’ is ‘a forensic term’ (Locke) and legitimate attributions of praise and blame require that the individual who is punished or rewarded be the same person as the individual who performed the commendable or condemnable deed. Moreover, it is identity of personhood that matters to us subjectively, ‘happiness and misery being that for which every one is concerned for himself, and not mattering what becomes of any substance, not joined to, or affected with that consciousness’ (Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sects. 9–26). In short, Locke insists, it is ‘one thing to be the same substance,8 another the same man, and a third the same person’ (1690: II. xxvii. sect. 7): the first is a question about sameness of matter; the second is a question about sameness of living being; the third is a question about sameness of consciousness. And, he insists, it is the third of these questions that is of primary importance to our daily practices, both with regard to ourselves and with regard to others: our judgements of praise and blame and our basis of self‐concern track personal rather than animal or substantial identity.

33.1.2 Locke's Proposal 33.1.2.1 Our Tendency Towards Confusion Given the practical importance of personhood, we might expect that when we use names such as ‘Socrates’ to refer to some entity, it is with the intention of referring (p. 582) to some person, and that when we use the term to refer to some other sort of entity, we will be sensitive to our deviant practice. After all, ‘Socrates could survive the loss of (the material composing) his left hand’ is false of Socrates the mass of matter9 but true of Socrates the man and Socrates the person; ‘Socrates could survive a complete change of body’ is false of Socrates the man and Socrates the mass of matter but true of Socrates the person; and ‘Socrates could survive a complete loss of memory’ is false of Socrates the person but true of Socrates the mass of matter and Socrates the man.10 But, Locke suggests, we are in fact quite careless in this regard: when we use the term ‘Socrates’, we are often indifferent as to whether we mean something with the persistence conditions of a person, something with the persistence conditions of a man, or something with the persistence conditions of a mass of matter (1690: II. xxvii. sect. 15). The result has been ‘a great deal of … confusion’ (1690: II. xxvii. sect. 7). And this confusion means

Page 4 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics that developing an adequate theory of personal identity will require careful sorting out of our intuitions, which may well be coloured by our tendency to conflate distinct notions.

33.1.2.2 Locke's Imaginary Cases It is with this in mind that Locke goes on to present a series of real and imaginary cases designed to reveal our tacit commitment to the distinctions he has just made. His aim is to show that all along we have had at least two relevant concepts in our repertoire (human animal and person); that all along we have been committed to the idea that the persistence conditions for the two classes differ; and that all along we have had the capacity to recognize how these conditions apply to particular cases.11 It is in this context that he introduces the now famous example of the prince and the cobbler, as follows: ‘Should the soul of a prince, carrying with it the consciousness of the prince's past life, enter and inform the body of a cobbler, as soon as deserted by his own soul, every one sees he would be the same person with the prince, (p. 583) accountable only for the prince's actions: but who would say it was the same man?’ (1690: II. xxvii. sect. 15).12 That is, if the psychology that we associate with the prince came to be united with the body that we associate with the cobbler, we would say (speaking loosely) that the resulting being was the same person as the prince, but that he was the same man as the cobbler.13 Moreover, the ‘every one’ who ‘sees [that] he would be the same person with the prince’ includes the prince himself; for on the basis of his subjective experiences it would seem quite apparent to him that what has happened is simply that he has changed bodies.

33.1.2.3 Locke's Proposal Locke's proposal, then, is basically the following. There are at least two sorts of connection that we recognize as significant in our ordinary practice: sameness of consciousness and sameness of life. These determine two sorts of identity: personal identity and animal identity. And while the two coincide in most normal cases, we have the conceptual repertoire available for keeping things straight when they diverge. Moreover, for most of the questions we are interested in it is personal not animal identity that matters: in so far as we are concerned with issues involving our own happiness and misery, or the praise and blame of others, we care about sameness of person, not sameness of animal. And an individual at one time is the same person as an individual at another time if and only if they share the same consciousness.

33.2 Coincidence, Identity, and What Matters Locke's view faces two categories of problems, the finessing of which has shaped contemporary discussions of personal identity. The first arises from a cluster of issues in ontology and the philosophy of language; the second from trying to find an otherwise

Page 5 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics satisfactory criterion for identity over time for persons that is reflexive, symmetric, transitive, and intrinsically determined, and that obeys the law of indiscernability of identicals.14 (p. 584)

33.2.1 Coincidence The first cluster of problems includes the following. On one natural reading, Locke is committed to a sortal‐relative view of individuation according to which there are at least three things sitting where you are right now—a mass of matter, a human animal, and a person—each a material object, each composed of many (or all) of the same parts, and each occupying the same space.15 Moreover, if the human animal is capable of thinking (and it is hard to see why it would not be), then there are at least two thinking things sitting where you are now, a person and a human animal, each contemplating whatever you are contemplating.16 And the problems do not end here. For each of these entities is a distinct and viable candidate for reference by your name: when I spoke of something ‘sitting where you are right now’ or ‘contemplating whatever you are contemplating’, what exactly did ‘you’ refer to—the person, or the animal, or the mass of matter, or perhaps all three at once—or was it instead ambiguous? Among those who take this cluster of worries seriously in the specific context of personal identity, three sorts of responses have been offered. Some think the problems so severe that they should cause us to reconsider the adequacy of any sort of materialist account of personhood. (For discussion see Zimmerman 2003; see also Swinburne 1984; Merricks 1998.) Others insist that for these and other reasons we should accept an ontology that is four‐dimensionalist; that is, an ontology according to which the material world is composed of temporal as well as spatial parts (see Sider 2001). The final group responds by limiting the number of contenders, for example by denying that one or the other of the candidate objects exists,17 or by insisting that our referential practices allow us to latch on properly to the correct entity (see, for example, Noonan 1998).

33.2.2 Identity and What Matters Even if we set aside these issues, difficulties remain. For the appealing feature of the Lockean analysis is that it seems to capture why we care about tracking persons over (p. 585) time; namely, that we care about tracking the clusters of psychological properties that they manifest. But in so far as these property clusters are qualitatively specified, they could not serve as criteria for identity, since there is no guarantee that a property specifed qualitatively will be uniquely instantiated;18 and in so far as they are specified in some other way, the initial appeal of the psychological account is lost.

33.2.2.1 Teletransportation

Page 6 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics Two families of descendents of Locke's prince and cobbler reveal these difficulties. The first family of cases exploits the assumption that two structurally identical individuals composed of qualitatively identical matter will manifest the same characteristics, both physically and (assuming materialism) psychologically. If so, there is no in‐principle barrier to teletransportation—in which information about the microstructural properties of an entity provides a blueprint for producing one or more duplicates. Whereas certain psychological‐continuity criteria would credit each duplicate with being identical to the original, their (presumed) non‐identity with one another renders this interpretation untenable: if personal identity is an equivalence relation, then mere causal continuity of consciousness is not sufficient for personal identity. So Locke cannot be right that an individual at one time is the same person as an individual at another time if they share the same consciousness.

33.2.2.2 Fission Suppose, then, that we retreat from a pure neo‐Lockean view, and insist that personal identity requires not only psychological continuity but also sameness of sustaining substance. Will this psychology‐plus‐substrate view do the trick? No: unless we require that that sustaining substance be indivisible (in the sense that no two disjoint proper parts of it could each be sufficient for sustaining the requisite consciousness), parallel problems will arise. We can see this by considering a slightly modified version of Locke's prince and cobbler case. Assume for the sake of discussion that it is the prince's brain that plays the role of sustaining the prince's consciousness. Assume further (idealizing somewhat) that the features required for sustaining consciousness are distributed redundantly, so that if either half of the brain were transplanted into an appropriate environment (such as the recently decerebrated body of the cobbler) we would be inclined to follow Locke in saying that ‘the resulting being was the same person as the prince’.19 But now suppose that, instead of a single transfer taking place, fission occurs: the brain is divided and each of the lobes is suitably resituated in one of two decerebrated cobbler bodies. (p. 586)

Now there are two individuals—each with the prince's psychology, each with enough of the prince's brain such that were it not for the presence of his competitor we would say that he was the same person as the prince.20 But even if we would say that each resulting being is the same person as the prince, we surely cannot say it of both (since they are not identical to one another, and hence cannot both be identical to the same thing). Nor do we wish to say it of one of the resulting beings as opposed to the other (since by hypothesis each on its own would be an equally good identity candidate, so there are no non‐arbitrary grounds for choosing between them). So unless we assume that there were two persons there all along (see Lewis 1976), the only remaining possibility is that neither is the same person as the prince. But if we maintain our initial assessment of the half‐lobe prince and cobbler case, then this means that a process (say, the transfer of the left lobe) that is entity‐preserving under one set of circumstances (the single transplant case) is Page 7 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics entity‐creating under another set of circumstances (the double‐transplant case)—even though the intrinsic relations between the prince and his (non‐)successor are the same in both cases.21 So long as we accept a standard materialist picture, there seems to be no way of articulating a psychological criterion of personal identity that is reflexive, symmetric, transitive, and intrinsically determined.

33.2.2.3 Responses Since reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity are non‐negotiable, two sorts of retreat seem possible. The first involves maintaining a commitment to intrinsic determination and holding that person is a phase sortal (something that can apply to a given entity at some but not other times) rather than a substance concept (something that applies to an entity at every moment of its existence) (see Wiggins 2001: 30).22 The cost of such a view is that persons turn out to be much less fundamental than we might have thought: a person is not something that a given individual could fundamentally be; instead, person is a status that a given individual (who belongs fundamentally to some other kind) could have.23 A second retreat involves abandoning the commitment to the view that identity is intrinsically determined.24 This move is problematic for two reasons. First, (p. 587) there are intuitive grounds for thinking that the facts that determine whether an entity persists over time should be facts about the entity itself, not facts about (the existence or non‐ existence of) some other entity. So unless one thinks that there are no interesting criteria of identity over time that depend only on intrinsic relations between the candidate entities (along with the obtaining of certain background facts), the extrinsic determination of same person raises the spectre that personal identity is identity manqué. The second reason for worrying about the abandonment of intrinsic determination is that, if one accepts a series of individually quite plausible assumptions, it implies that ‘personal identity is not what matters’.25 The argument goes as follows. Suppose the prince's left lobe is transferred according to the procedure described above, and that one accepts the psychology‐plus‐substrate view. Regardless of whether the right lobe is also transferred (in which case he will go out of existence and be replaced by another individual), or destroyed (in which case he will continue to exist as the new occupant of the cobbler's body), all of the things that matter to the prince about his relation to some future being (for instance, that it be psychologically continuous with him for the right sorts of reasons) will be present: they depend only on the intrinsic relations between him and his continuer(s), and not on facts about any of their relations to anything else. So, in contrast to personal identity, which is extrinsically determined, the thing we care about when we worry about our future is something that is intrinsically determined—so personal identity cannot be the thing we care about.26

33.2.2.4 The Quandary Together, these arguments seem to put us in something of a quandary. They suggest that to the extent that we are interested in fundamental metaphysical questions about identity we are interested in something other than persons, and to the extent that we are

Page 8 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics interested in things that matter to us we are interested in something other than identity. It looks as if we can talk about strict identity; or we can talk about persons; or we can talk about something that matters—but we can't talk about them at the same time. The problem, of course, is that we would like to do all three at once. The reason Locke's analysis is so appealing is that it seems to allow us to pick out a class of entities that we care deeply about, whose identity‐conditions are a matter of their psychological features, and which persist over time in a ‘strict and philosophical’ sense. The reason the debate about personal identity is so complicated is that—even setting aside the larger metaphysical issues about coincident identity and reference—it looks as if we just can't have everything we want.

(p. 588)

33.3 Some Contemporary Discussions

It is against this background that contemporary discussions of personal identity take place. In this final section I will briefly present three sophisticated and influential recent accounts.27 Each relies on a subtle reconceptualization of the notion of personhood in a way that then makes the resulting question of diachronic personal identity tractable. That is, each answers our first question—given a person X, with which past and future entities is X (numerically) identical?—with something of a ‘twist’. The lesson of Locke's legacy, I take it, is the need for such a twist.

33.3.1 Olson In a series of papers culminating in his 1997 The Human Animal Eric Olson considers arguments akin to those in Section 33.2, leading him to conclude that what each of us is, strictly speaking, is a human animal whose persistence conditions are independent of facts about our psychology: ‘no sort of psychological continuity, with or without further physical qualifications, is either necessary or sufficient for us to persist through time’ (1997: 4). This might seem like a wholesale rejection of the Lockean account. And in some sense it is. But by reconceptualizing what sort of thing persons are, Olson's framework leaves room for Locke's insights. Olson suggests that even if our persistence conditions are those of animals, the animals that we are may also be persons, where ‘being a particular person’ is ‘a sort of role or office that a human organism (or any other appropriate object) might fill at a particular time’ (1997: 66). This allows for the possibility that ‘being the same person is a practical or moral relation’—characterized by just the sorts of psychological‐continuity relations that neo‐Lockeans have identified. And it likewise allows that our legal and emotional practices be predicated on personhood, just as Locke maintained.

Page 9 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics But if diachronic personal identity is a matter of psychological continuity, then (as we learned in Section 33.2). ‘there is no reason to expect it to have the same formal features as identity so‐called’; the relevant relation might, for example, violate transitivity. As a result, Olson contends, ‘being the same person, as we might say, is not a metaphysical relation’ (1997: 68–9).

33.3.2 Rovane A similar subtle rejection of the demand to provide strict diachronic identity‐conditions for persons is found in Carol Rovane's The Bounds of Agency (1998). (p. 589) At first appearance Rovane's view seems maximally distant from Olson's: Olson considers himself a minority critic of the ‘notorious’ Lockean tradition; Rovane presents herself as its valiant defender. But once one recognizes that, like Olson's, Rovane's account of diachronic personal identity does not seek to provide strict identity‐conditions over time, the differences may seem less striking. According to Rovane, the core notion of personhood is the notion of agency: on her view, persons are beings who are capable of acting and bringing others to act on the basis of reasons (as opposed to non‐rational causes); they are all and only those beings who are ‘commit[ted] to achieving overall rational unity’ (1998: 8; italics omitted). As a result, Rovane's view allows that persons may be something radically distinct from individual human animals: groups of human animals might together form a single person (‘group persons’), or numerous persons (such as the ‘alters’ of multiple personality disorder) might together exist within a single human being (‘multiple persons’). Moreover, since ‘persons are nothing but certain sorts of episodes standing in certain sorts of relations’, relations which may obtain to a greater or lesser degree, ‘the boundaries between persons can be vague … [both] over time and at a particular time’ (1998: 134). So on Rovane's view as well we might say (using Olson's terminology) that being the same person is not a metaphysical relation.

33.3.3 Sider A slightly different reconceptualization of the demand to provide diachronic identity‐ conditions for persons can be found in Ted Sider's Four‐Dimensionalism (2001). Sider makes appeal to a four‐dimensionalist metaphysics (one with temporal as well as spatial parts), accompanied by a commitment to unrestricted composition (that any combination of things composes an object), to provide a world replete with object‐stages to which we are free to attend as our interests demand (since any combination of object‐stages composes an object which can serve as the target of our attention). On such a view it is a matter of our concerns and conventions which stage‐sequences we choose to single out and treat as persisting entities. Lockean persons, on such a picture, are no more or less real, no more or less problematic, than any other sort of purported entity. But purported entities themselves are very different than we might pre‐reflectively have thought. So Page 10 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics while, on such a view, being the same person might be, in so far as anything is, a metaphysical relation, being a metaphysical relation is, to put the point slightly tendentiously, not one (see Sider 2001). In short, though they disagree about much else, each of our contemporary authors holds that the question of personal identity (as traditionally understood) is not a metaphysical question (as traditionally understood)28—though the question of whether it is such a question is a metaphysical question par excellence. Though there (p. 590) are ways of resisting this picture, it is nonetheless striking how readily the Lockean legacy pushes us down one of the many paths towards it.29

References Alston, W. P., and Bennett, J. (1988), ‘Locke on People and Substances’, Philosophical Review, 97: 25–46. Baker, L. R. (2000), Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Butler, J. (1736), The Analogy of Religion; excerpt repr. in J. Perry (ed.), Personal Identity (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1975), 99–105. Deutsch, H. (2002), ‘Relative Identity’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, summer 2002 edition, . Garrett, B. (1998), Personal Identity and Self‐Consciousness (London: Routledge). Geach, P. T. (1967), ‘Identity’, Review of Metaphysics, 21: 3–12; repr. in Geach, Logic Matters (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972), 238–47. —— (1980), Reference and Generality. 3rd edn. (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press). Gendler, T. S. (2002), ‘Personal Identity and Thought Experiments’, Philosophical Quarterly, 52: 34–54. Hawthorne, J. (2003), ‘Identity’, in M. Loux and D. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 99–130. Hudson, H. (2001), A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person (Ithaca, NY: Cornell). Johnston, M. (1987), ‘Human Beings’, Journal of Philosophy, 84: 59–83. —— (1992), ‘Constitution Is Not Identity’, Mind, 101: 89–105.

Page 11 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics Lewis, D. (1976), ‘Survival and Identity’, in A. Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 17–41; repr. in Lewis, Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), 55–72. Locke, J. (1690), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon); excerpt repr. in J. Perry (ed.), Personal Identity (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1975), 33–52. Lowe, E. J. (1996), Subjects of Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Martin, R. (1998), Self‐concern. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Merricks, T. (1998), ‘There Are No Criteria of Identity Over Time’, Noûs, 32: 106–24. —— (2001), Objects and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Noonan, H. (1998), Animalism Versus Lockeanism: A Current Controversy, Philosophical Quarterly, 48: 302–18. Olson, E. T. (1997), The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2002a), ‘An Argument for Animalism’, in J. Barresi and R. Martin (eds.), Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell), 318–34. —— (2002b), ‘Personal Identity’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, fall 2002 edition, , accessed 2008. —— (2002c), ‘Personal Identity’, in S. Stich and T. Warfield (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 352–68. (p. 591)

Parfit, D. (1984), Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Rea, M. (1997) (ed.), Material Constitution: A Reader (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield). Reid, T. (1785), On the Intellectual Powers of Man; excerpt repr. in J. Perry (ed.), Personal Identity (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1975), 107–18. Rovane, C. (1998), The Bounds of Agency (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Shoemaker, S. (1963), Self‐Knowledge and Self‐Identity (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).

Page 12 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics —— (1984), ‘Personal Identity: A Materialist's Account’, in S. Shoemaker and R. Swinburne (eds.), Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell), 67–132. —— (1999), ‘Self, body, and coincidence’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 73: 287–306. Sider, T. (2001), Four‐Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Sosa, E. (1990), ‘Surviving Matters’, Noûs, 24: 305–30. Swinburne, R. (1984), ‘Personal Identity: The Dualist Theory’, in S. Shoemaker and R. Swinburne (eds.), Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell), 1–66. Unger, P. (1980), ‘The Problem of the Many’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5: 411–67. —— (1990), Identity, Consciousness, and Value (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Van Inwagen, P. (1990), Material Beings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press). Wiggins, D. (2001), Sameness and Substance Renewed (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Zimmerman, D. (2003), ‘Material People’, in M. Loux and D. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 491–526. (p. 592)

Notes: (1) Note that this sort of commitment to sortal‐relative individuation need not bring with it a commitment to (Geachean) relative identity (the view that (objects) x and y both could be the same (kind) F without being the same (kind) G, while both being F and G). (See Geach 1967; for discussion see Wiggins 2001; Deutsch 2002; Hawthorne 2003.) Avoiding it, however, requires either accepting some type of dominant sortal view (that each object belongs fundamentally to one particular sort), or adopting some sort of temporal‐parts view (that entities have temporal as well as spatial parts), or embracing coincidence (that more than one entity (of the same kind) might be at the same place at the same time). These issues are discussed briefly in Section 33.2 below. (2) The taxonomy is not exhaustive; for example, Locke does not discuss identity criteria for non‐living natural objects (such as rocks and mountains), though he does discuss (as I will not) identity‐conditions for God and for finite intelligences (which he holds to be akin to those for simple substances), and offers a few brief remarks concerning identity‐ conditions for artefacts (which he holds to be akin to those for living entities). (3) Each of the main paragraphs in the next three subsections is organized around answering analogues of (1)–(4) for the sortal in question. That is, for each of Locke's categories I present synchronic and diachronic identity‐conditions for Cs, articulate the

Page 13 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics basis on which we do and could make judgements about C‐identity, and say something about the practical and emotional significance of C‐hood. (4) Indeed, these matters seem so fundamental that the prospect of massive error (say, that atoms indiscernibly swap locations every few seconds) seems best met by re‐ characterizing our referential intentions. (5) Locke does not say whether such objects are ‘nested’, so that a (suitably configured) four‐atom clump would contain four three‐atom clumps each containing three two‐atom clumps, or whether only maximal discontinuous clumps count. (6) Locke's text seems to suggest that he is committed to a ‘memory’ criterion for personal identity: P2 is identical to P1 if and only if P2 remembers P1’s experiences. This account faces a number of well‐known problems, including the problem of non‐ transitivity: that identity over time is transitive, but memory is not (an objection generally credited to Reid 1785), and the problem of circularity: that the concept of memory presupposes the concept of personal identity and hence cannot be used to explicate it (an objection generally credited to Butler 1736). In order to finesse these and other objections, contemporary accounts appeal instead to some broader requirement, such as psychological continuity, according to which P2 is identical to P1 only if P2’s psychological states are connected to P1’s psychological states by the right sort of causal chain. Such views are generally referred to as neo‐Lockean views. (7) Locke explicitly notes our fallibility in this regard (see Locke 1690: II. xxvii. sect. 22). (8) For discussion of Locke's use of the term ‘substance’ see Alston and Bennett (1988). (9) The locution ‘Socrates the mass of matter’ may be taken as shorthand for ‘the entity with mass‐of‐matter persistence conditions that (is one of the things) we refer to by “Socrates” ’. For discussion of some of the problems associated with such a notion see Section 33.2. Strictly speaking, it is unlikely that we ever use the term ‘Socrates’ to refer to some mass of matter; its exacting identity‐conditions render its practical interest minimal. We do, however, sometimes seem to use personal names to refer to something like ‘stuff’, as when we say ‘Socrates is buried outside Athens’ or ‘Poor Socrates: he's all over the universe by now’. Whether this is a literal use of the term—some might contend that ‘Socrates’ here is used as shorthand for ‘the matter that once composed Socrates' body’—and whether the ‘stuff’ in question is a suitable candidate for reference are matters for consideration elsewhere. (10) Again, we need to be a bit careful here. The memories of Socrates the person are things of which he is conscious; the memories of Socrates the human animal may be things of which the person with which he coincides is conscious. For discussion of some of these issues see Noonan (1998) and Olson (1997, 2002a).

Page 14 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics (11) Cf. Unger: ‘[W]hy not stick only to actual cases? … The reason is that this extremely conservative methodology is apt to incur great costs … In attempting to ascribe beliefs to ourselves on the basis of quite limited data, we might wrongly describe our own attitudes’ (1990: 11). Similarly Shoemaker: ‘What Mackie and Perry have done is to indicate how personal identity (or co‐personality, or psychological unity) are realized in us, i.e. in members of our own species. And this does not answer the question ‘What does personal identity consist in?’ at the level of abstractness at which we want it answered’ (1984: 127). (12) Twentieth‐century renderings of this story generally cast brain in the role of soul. In Sydney Shoemaker's version (1963), for example, the brain of one Brown is transferred to the body of one Robinson, carrying with it all of Brown's psychological characteristics. The resulting character, whom Shoemaker dubs Brownson, ‘display[s] all the personality traits, mannerisms, interests, likes and dislikes, and so on that had previously characterized Brown, and … talk[s] and act[s] in ways completely alien to the old Robinson’. ‘What would we say if such a thing happened?’, asks Shoemaker. ‘There is little question that many of us would be inclined, and strongly inclined, to say that while Brownson has Robinson's body, he is actually Brown’ (1963: 23–4). The substitution introduces a number of subtle differences whose significance is exploited in the contemporary literature: unlike the soul, the brain is part of the body; and unlike (presumably) the soul, the brain could be divided without loss of function. (For an additional difference between Shoemaker and Locke n. 14) (13) ‘Speaking loosely’ because this way of putting things suggests a commitment to relative identity, which presumably we wish to avoid (see Sect. 33.1.1). One might handle this problem by privileging one of the sortals (as Shoemaker does), by explicitly acknowledging a commitment to coincident identity, or by re‐characterizing the ontological situation so as to allow such relativity. For further discussion of these issues see Section 33.2. (14) The law of indiscernibility of identicals says that if x is identical to y, then x has all and only the properties that y has. (15) Indeed, the problems do not end here. Since each of the entities is (presumably) a material object, each itself confronts the gauntlet of puzzles that have shaped contemporary discussions of material constitution, including the problem of undetached parts (Tib/Tibbles) (see Geach 1980) and the problem of the many (see Unger 1980). (For recent discussion of these and related issues see the essays collected in Rea 1997.) Ironically, the generality of the conundrum may make the particular problem of sortal‐ relative identity seem less pressing. (16) Olson (1997, 2002a, 2000b) makes much of this problem; for one response see Shoemaker (1999).

Page 15 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics (17) For various versions of this approach see van Inwagen (1990), Olson (1997); Merricks (2001), and Wiggins (2001). (18) One might insist that clusters of psychological properties are necessarily uniquely instantiated. But justifying this insistence would require either denying the possibility that two sufficiently complex sets of qualitatively identical microparticles could be configured in identical ways, or rejecting the supervenience of the mental on the physical. (19) Some have denied this, insisting that the required physical substrate involve at least 51 per cent of the original matter; most consider this move to be ad hoc (see Unger 1990; Wiggins 2001). (20) For discussion of some of the subtleties involved in presenting this case in a non‐ question‐begging way see Unger (1990: 259–60). (21) For one version of such a view see Shoemaker (1984). (22) Olson (1997: 27–31) emphasizes this implication. (23) On the view in question, substance concepts are constrained by a requirement that— in so far as we are concerned with constitutive (question 3) criteria, as opposed to evidential (question 4) criteria—the facts that determine identity over time are facts about a and b and the relations between them, and not facts about anything else (the ‘only‐a‐and‐b rule’) (see Wiggins 2001: 96 ff., 231 ff., 237 ff.). It is a subtle question whether there is really sense to be made of the only‐a‐and‐b rule as a metaphysical (as opposed to an epistemic) principle; discussing this issue would take us beyond the scope of this chapter. (24) Sydney Shoemaker considers and endorses such a move in his (1984). (25) The main advocate of such a view has been Derek Parfit. For one widely discussed formulation of this argument see Parfit (1984). (26) For one way of resisting this line of reasoning see Gendler (2002); one might also contend that ‘what matters’ is itself extrinsically determined (see Johnston 1987, 1992; Sosa 1990). (27) In so doing I am neglecting a number of other important and interesting discussions. Recent book‐length treatments of personal identity include Lowe (1996), Garrett (1998), Martin (1998), Baker (2000), Hudson (2001), Merricks (2001). (Note that this entry was written in 2003.) (28) Did Locke take himself to be asking a metaphysical question when he set discussion on its current course? Answering this seems a tricky exegetical issue. But regardless of what Locke thought he was asking, it is clear that many of his followers set out to answer such a question.

Page 16 of 17

Personal Identity and Metaphysics (29) For comments and suggestions I am grateful to Ansgar Beckermann, Tim Crane, Brian McLaughlin, Ted Sider, and Zoltán Gendler Szabó.

Tamar Szabó Gendler

Tamar Szabó Gendler is Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Department of Philosophy, Yale University.

Page 17 of 17

Imagination

Oxford Handbooks Online Imagination   Colin McGinn The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0035

Abstract and Keywords The topic of imagination is broad and multifarious: we are dealing with an extended family of interrelated concepts and capacities. Imagining covers everything from the simple mental image, to the philosophical counter-example, to the most sublime act of creation. It takes in both dreaming and logical thinking, reverie and hypothesis formation. To bring order to this range of mental phenomena it helps to make an initial distinction between what the article calls sensory and cognitive imagination — roughly, between forming a mental image and entertaining a possibility in the conceptual style. Keywords: imagination, mental image, logical thinking, hypothesis formation, cognitive imagination, sensory imagination

THE topic of imagination is broad and multifarious: we are dealing with an extended family of interrelated concepts and capacities.1 Imagining covers everything from the simple mental image, to the philosophical counter‐example, to the most sublime act of creation. It takes in both dreaming and logical thinking, reverie and hypothesis formation. To bring order to this range of mental phenomena it helps to make an initial distinction between what I shall call sensory and cognitive imagination—roughly, between forming a mental image and entertaining a possibility in the conceptual style. Thus, I may form a visual image of the colour blue or of a friend's face, on the one hand, and I may consider the possibility that a skyscraper might at some future time be built on this very spot, on the other. The ascription of the former type of imaginative act has the form ‘x forms an image of y’, the latter takes the form of a that‐clause: ‘x imagines that p’. Sensory imagination, as the label suggests, partakes of the phenomenology of the sense modalities in some way (in which way we shall have to examine)—we ‘see’ with the mind's eye as well as with the ordinary eye—while cognitive imagination is a conceptually based propositional attitude, in the same general family as belief. What we might call ‘the

Page 1 of 13

Imagination imaginative faculty’ includes both sensory and cognitive imagination, and of course these may interact with each other. I shall accordingly divide my discussion into two parts.

(p. 596)

34.1 Sensory Imagination

Look at some object in front of you; now close your eyes and form a mental image of that object—you will notice a marked similarity, or affinity, between these episodes of seeing and visualizing. You may form an image of the seen object that corresponds closely to the way it just looked to you; say, a table of such‐and‐such a shape and colour, presented at such‐and‐such an angle. Indeed, in some clear sense your image will be derived from your initial percept. Both the intentional content and phenomenology of the percept and the image overlap in an obvious way, and differ from the relevant properties of other percepts and images; the image and the percept belong together, forming a natural pair. Yet you are clearly able to distinguish them introspectively; there is no chance of confusing the percept with the image or vice versa. The affinity is evident, and so is the diversity. How shall we characterize these points of similarity and difference? Two extreme views have been advanced. One view, associated with Hume, maintains that the image is really just a faded percept:2 the senses present the mind with a sensory impression of some specific type, and this impression undergoes a process of degradation as it lingers in memory, becoming fainter as time passes. Even an invented image—as, say, of a fire‐breathing dragon—is just the bleached‐out version of a possible percept. Images and percepts differ purely quantitatively, in their degree of ‘force and liveliness’. And this, it is supposed, is why we intuitively judge that images and percepts have something in common—the image just is a percept, though one that has lost a lot of its initial sparkle. On this view the percept is the basic item of the pair, with the image being just a special case of it: there can be percepts without images, but not vice versa. The relation between percept and image is that of an original to an indistinct copy. According to the second extreme view, associated perhaps with Kant, it is the other way about:3 it is imagination that is the basic item of the pair, with percepts being derivative from imaginative acts. Thus, it is held that all perception is a kind of imaginative construction, in which stimuli from the world are processed and interpreted by the imaginative faculty. The mind must contribute to the bare input of the senses, it is held, in order for anything like a conscious percept to occur, and this active ingredient in perception is the work of the imagination—a constructive, creative faculty. Perception is really just the imagination tied down to an impinging perceptual stimulus. Accordingly, there is no genuine perception without imagination—imagination suffuses perception. The reason for the similarity between image (p. 597) and percept is therefore quite simple; in effect, the percept is an image, though one that is anchored to a sensory input.

Page 2 of 13

Imagination The first step in getting clear about imagination is to see that both of these assimilationist positions are incorrect. Neither percept nor image is a special case of the other, despite the manifest similarity between them. Each is sui generis, though they are intimately related. I shall now enumerate some of the salient points of difference, which preclude both assimilations. When you perceive something, you are passive before your sensory experiences. The course of your visual experience, say, is outside the direct control of your will; it is dictated by the barrage of stimuli that assail the sense organs. You cannot simply decide to see something and conjure up the appropriate visual experience. This is as true of hallucinating as it is of veridical perceiving: you cannot, at will, cause yourself to hallucinate pink rats, say. Suppose you are seeing a swelling ocean and would rather be seeing a tropical jungle; this wish cannot be converted into the desired experience, save by taking an appropriate trip. But it is quite otherwise with images: they are ‘subject to the will’ (to use Wittgenstein's term (1981: 621, see also 627, 632)).4 If I don't like what I am seeing I can indeed conjure up an image of something more to my liking—in fact, I do this all the time. I can also order you to form an image of your father, and you can voluntarily comply. Even when an image comes to you unbidden, you can control its course and termination; at least, it makes perfect sense to try to do these things. Forming images is something that belongs on the side of action, not passion: it can be motivated, exhibit weakness of will, satisfy desire, and be morally evaluated. Here, then, is a marked difference between the perceptual faculty and the imaginative faculty: the latter is subject to executive control, being part of our active nature, while the former operates outside the domain of the will. This point already shows that both assimilations have to be mistaken: images cannot be a type of percept, pace Hume, or else they would be as passively received as percepts; and percepts cannot be externally elicited images, or else they would be in principle subject to the will. Thus, the passivity of perception and the activity of imagination show that neither is a special case of the other. Second, percepts and images relate differently to attention.5 I can attend to what I am seeing or I can fail to do so (and similarly with the other senses). But it is not that I am blind with respect to what I am not attending to—there are unattended sightings of things. My sensory experiences proceed in unattended form as I focus my attention on other matters. Shifts of attention away from a percept do not obliterate it. However, the same does not seem to be true of images: they do not persist in unattended form as I focus my attention on other matters. I cannot form an image of the colour blue, say, and then leave that image in suspension in my consciousness as I turn my attention to lunch. My images do not subsist as a background to my (p. 598) conscious life over which my attention selectively plays, as my percepts do; rather, they are products of my attentive acts. When I form an image of something I thereby attend to it in the mode of imagination, and I cannot keep it in my imaginative sights while I switch attention elsewhere. In this respect images are like thoughts: I also cannot keep thinking of something as I turn my attention to other matters. It would be nice if I could, because then I could think of many things at the same time, but, unfortunately, thinking intrinsically takes up attentional space. Images are likewise hungry for attention, and wilt Page 3 of 13

Imagination away from its spotlight. But, then, images must differ fundamentally from percepts: if images were a type of percept, they should be attention‐independent; and if all perception were an exercise of imagination, then percepts would not enjoy their freedom from the limits of attention. Imagining is something we do by means of our attentive faculty, but perceiving is something that befalls us whether we wish to focus on it or not. Third, perception and imagination relate very differently to our knowledge‐acquiring capacities. When I perceive the world I am constantly learning about it, picking up information about my environment, and I adopt an attitude of observation—I am receptive to what is coming in. The world may surprise me with what it contains, as it updates my store of knowledge. Perception is essentially an ongoing link between the world and our knowledge of it. But when I form an image I am not in this way registering what is going on around me; indeed, my attention becomes detached from my surroundings. If I form an image of my mother, I am not in any sense observing my mother, and she cannot surprise me qua imaged object.6 Here it is not that the object of my intentional act is feeding new information to me by means of appropriate causal channels, in such a way that the image constantly changes as the object and my causal relationship to it change. The object is having no such causal impact on me (beyond what might be needed to have an image of that object to begin with).7 The image is informationally insulated from the object, in the sense that it is not responsive to alterations in the real properties of the object. (It may be hidden thousands of miles away.) Accordingly, I do not have an attitude of observation with respect to my image: I do not eagerly await the news it is about to bring me of the latest doings of the object I am imagining. Perception is all about informational input, but imagination is all about informational output—what my memory and cognitive resources can put into my image. The image is a product of the resources already contained within the mind, not the vehicle of fresh data from outside.8 It (p. 599) would be bizarre for me to create an image of an elk, say, and then wait with baited breath to see what my imagined elk will do next (unless this reflected an interest in my own imaginative tendencies, and not the behaviour of actual elks). Again, this difference is lost if we try to assimilate images and percepts, in either direction. Fourth, percepts come with a corresponding sensory field, but images do not. Thus, we have the visual field, with its periphery and centre, its fixed perimeter, its sense of a spatially proximate world; but there is nothing comparable in the case of visual images. To be sure, visual images display spatial extent in some way, but they don't have a centre/ periphery distinction, have no anatomically fixed scope, and do not present the imaged object as within the surrounding space. When I see something I see it as here/there, in the vicinity of me, as looming or receding, as in the centre of view or off to the side, as about to vanish from my visual field or stay put. But when I visualize something none of this applies: the object is given in a spatially neutral way, not located in my own egocentric space, and it does not occupy more or less of the fixed field of my inner eye, or threaten to disappear behind me. Imagined objects appear in a kind of limbo, in a space all their own, not as located beside other objects and in spatial relation to me and my body.9 Phenomenologically, imagining is not felt as a kind of orienting to the environment, an immersion within it; instead, it reaches beyond the impinging world, bringing absent Page 4 of 13

Imagination objects within its scope. So perception and imagination do not occur within the same kind of matrix of intentionality, despite the frequent identity of their intentional objects, and hence cannot be reduced one to the other. Fifth, and finally, it is easy to see that images and percepts do not compete with each other for mental space: while seeing one thing, I can imagine another.10 There are two sensory streams of consciousness here, and neither usurps the other: the stream of percepts and the stream of images. On a typical day both streams will be found happily flowing together, in choreographed simultaneity, as you shift your attention from what is being currently perceived to the image that momentarily seizes your fancy; in particular, the exercise of imagination in no sense blinds you to what is going on, nor even dulls your sensory acuity. And it is fortunate that this is so, or else sensory breakdown would accompany every act of imagination—no reveries while driving! But notice how hard it is to square this obvious fact with the assimilationist theories: if an image were merely a faint percept, rather like an after‐image, then it would interfere with (p. 600) ordinary perception, since I cannot have different percepts occupying the same region of my visual field; and if perception were merely externally stimulated imagination, then percepts would not interfere with other percepts, since a mere image does not prevent the occurrence of a simultaneous percept with a different content.11 But it is of the essence of the imaginative faculty that it can operate concurrently with the perceptual faculties, while the perceptual faculties themselves exclude competing elements—as when that hovering after‐image momentarily blinds me to what is before my eyes. None of this is to deny that images and percepts are in some important way similar; it is just to say that they are not merely versions of each other, differing only in degree. Nor is it to deny that perception is a constructive process, in which prior knowledge is brought to bear upon a fragmentary stimulus—so long as this is not exaggerated into the claim that the very same faculty of imagination that is involved in paradigm cases of imagining is employed to generate percepts. Perceiving is not a form or mode of imagining, and imagining is not a form or mode of perceiving. The right thing to say here is rather that the two are analogous, or even homologous. Ordinary seeing and visualizing are variations on the theme of visual experience, with neither of them primary or paradigmatic. It is not that visualizing can only count as visual because of its reduction to ordinary seeing, nor that ordinary seeing is unified with visualizing by being an instance of it. It is rather that the concept of visual experience is more abstract than either of these two species of it, so that it is inherently neutral between them. That neutral concept of the visual then gets specialized into these two very different exemplifications of it, marked by the deep contrasts we have enumerated. Visual experience—the genus—comes in these two very different modes; the mistake is to think that conceptual unification here requires conceptual assimilation.12 So: some types of visual experience are subject to the will, attention‐dependent, non‐observational, devoid of visual field, and tolerant of other types of visual experience. These are the distinctive characteristics of what we aptly call the mind's eye, and that eye has just as much of a title to the name ‘vision’ as the other

Page 5 of 13

Imagination kind—once we resist those assimilationist urges. But the broader lesson here is to acknowledge the affinities between perception and sensory imagination while not neglecting the deep differences between them. In particular, the autonomy of the imagination, with respect to perception, needs to be respected. Having said all that, we must enter an important caveat: it is not that perception and imagination can never interact, join together, and even interpenetrate. That occurs in the phenomenon usually labelled seeing as, though this phenomenon might better be called imaginative seeing.13 This is itself a large subject, but some brief remarks may be in order. When I see an ambiguous figure, such as the duck/rabbit drawing, in a particular way, say as a picture of a duck, this is aptly described as imagination (p. 601) making contact with perception. It is as if the perceptual stimulus evokes an image, in this case of a duck, which then becomes attached to the percept, thus combining to form an episode of imaginative seeing. Normally, images float free of the impinging perceptual world, but on occasion they may be ‘hooked’ by a stimulus—attracted to the stimulus as to a magnet. Then we see the world under an imagined aspect, which is contributed by the faculty of imagination, rather than being contained in the stimulus itself. And this imaginative aspect has all the marks of an image that we have just listed, notably subjection to the will. This might well encourage the idea that all perception is imaginative, but this is really just a conflation of disparate phenomena. When I see an object as square in the ordinary way, there is no sense in which I have imposed an imagined aspect upon it: the object really is square and this information has forced itself on my senses—even though much processing of the stimulus must occur for the percept to result. But when at night I imaginatively interpret a tree as a monster, say, this is a very different matter, since the tree is not in fact a monster and my seeing it that way really is an exercise of imagination: I may stop seeing it as a monster once my fear retreats, while nothing like that will stop me seeing an object as square. Seeing as is a joining or mingling of perception and imagination, in which the two elements can always be distinguished, and this phenomenon does not in any way compromise the distinctions drawn above.

34.1.1 Dreams Dreaming poses a challenge to what we have said so far. If we agree that dreaming is a form of imagining, then it is not clear that the mental images that compose dreams obey the conditions that characterize daytime images; specifically, there is the question of their subjection to the will. Normally, when I dream I seem to myself to be passive before the onslaught: I cannot manipulate the course and content of the dream, but occupy the role of helpless (and hapless) recipient. How then can dreaming be a form of imagining, if imagining is essentially active and willed? Two ways out suggest themselves. The first is to deny that dreaming is imagining—why not say that it is hallucinatory in character? That is, we might try suggesting that dreams consist not of images but of objectless percepts, like the hallucinations of the dipsomaniac or the brain in a vat. Then, of course, they will not be subject to the will, Page 6 of 13

Imagination since percepts in general are not. But there are a number of objections to this suggestion. In the first place, dreams regularly have a narrative structure that is hard to square with the percept theory of their contents. Daydream images are suited for manipulation into narrative sequences precisely because of their subjection to authorial (hence intentional) control, but if nocturnal dreams consist of percepts they will not be suitable resources for narrative manipulation. How can percepts be formed, deformed, strung together, made coherent (or incoherent), according to affective and narrative demands? How can the mind work on them if they are outside the control of narrative agency? Second, if dreams consist of percepts, shouldn't it be possible to combine them with simultaneous, and disparate, images? If I am a brain in a vat hallucinating a (p. 602) world, this will not prevent me from forming disparate images, since the perceptual and imaginative faculties do not compete with each other; so shouldn't I be able to do the same during my dreams, if they consist in the operation merely of my perceptual faculties? Yet surely this cannot happen: my dream consciousness is one‐dimensional, fixated on the content of the dream, not capable of wandering to other, more flavoursome, topics. That is, the dreaming mind cannot shift attention from the dream to some other subject, in the way the waking mind can stray from the field of current perceptions. This must seem anomalous under the percept theory of the dream. If the imagination is not in fact activated during dreaming, as the percept theory maintains, then it must in principle be possible for it to go about its business contemporaneously with the dream; but this is signally not the case. So it appears that dreaming must involve the prior deployment of imagination. Third, it is actually not true that all dreaming is resistant to the will: so‐called lucid dreaming, in particular, offers examples of dreams that are wholly under the dreamer's voluntary control—which is not feasible if all dreams consist of passively received percepts. In a lucid dream the subject can determine the course of the dream, and is well aware that it is a dream, just as in daydreaming; but if the dream experiences are held to be percepts, which are passive in nature, then lucid dreaming ought to be impossible. And there are lesser examples of dream control, as when you terminate a particularly appalling nightmare and wake up. The second way out abandons the criterion of subjection to the will as definitive of the imagination: dreams are simply a counter‐example to this, it maintains, so we should modify our account of what marks images off from percepts. This is certainly an option, but it is an unattractive one. It introduces an ugly division within the class of images, with nothing to recommend it except its ability to retain the imagistic account of dreams. Moreover, we start to lose our grip on the distinction between percepts and images once we relax the conditions that characterize them. How many distinctive conditions could we disavow and still retain a viable distinction between images and percepts? Could we also say that dream experiences carry a visual field, are attention‐independent, are observational, and still maintain they are images. Surely it would be much more

Page 7 of 13

Imagination satisfactory to stick to our original list of differentia and try to account for the felt passivity of dreams in some other way. That is what I propose we do. The key move is simple: shift agency to an unconscious author. Here I can only sketch the way this can solve our problem, without going into independent reasons for favouring the idea.14 If we suppose that the dreaming mind factors into two components, one active and one passive, where the passive component is unaware of the actions of the active component, then we can see how the felt passivity of the dreamer is only a partial account of the matter—for the unconscious component can be as active as you like compatibly with the felt passivity of the receiving component. That is, we need to distinguish the author of the dream, a submerged narrative agency, from the audience of the dream—you, as you experience the dream. Then we can (p. 603) insist that all images are subject to the will of some agency, but make room for the passivity of the audience of the dream. There is, in the dreaming mind, a kind of ‘psychic split’, wherein the agency behind the dream image is sealed off from the recipient of the dream, thus engendering an illusion of total passivity, which mimics (but is not a case of) the passivity of the perceptual state. Of course, this is a substantial theoretical move, and would need to be independently motivated, but my limited point here is that it solves our conceptual problem, as well as being not entirely ad hoc or unprecedented. It enables us to include dreams within the domain of the imagination while retaining our earlier conception of how imagination distinguishes itself from perception. It also provides a neat account of lucid dreaming, which now emerges as simply a reunification of the psychic split that normally accompanies dreaming: the author and audience of the dream are one in the lucid dream, and the susceptibility of the dream to voluntary control is fully evident to the dreamer.

34.2 Cognitive Imagination Imagining‐that is a propositional attitude, like belief: an exercise of the conceptual faculty. But it is not itself a type of belief, as a visual image is not a type of percept. Nor, conversely, is belief a type of imagining‐that, any more than perceiving is a type of imagining. To suppose otherwise is to commit the same kind of assimilationist errors we diagnosed earlier. Imagining‐that belongs with supposing, considering, hypothesizing, entertaining—it is the mere apprehension of a possibility, not a commitment to something's being actually so. It would be quite wrong to think of imagining‐that as a kind of weak or faint or degraded belief, since it is entirely possible to entertain a proposition and have no degree of belief in it whatsoever—indeed, strongly to disbelieve it. I know very well that I am not a king, but I can imagine that I am, and this does not involve me in any kind of commitment to the truth of ‘I am a king’. Both imagining and believing are species of conceptual deployment, but they are not special cases of each

Page 8 of 13

Imagination other. What we have here are two kinds of ‘thinking’, irreducible to each other, analogous to the two kinds of sensory experience we explored earlier. We can readily find analogues of the differentia we encountered while considering sensory imagination. Imagining‐that is subject to the will, but you cannot, notoriously, decide to believe. Imagining, like thinking, requires attention, but beliefs can persist in the absence of attention (‘dispositionally’). Beliefs are susceptible to evidence, but imagining is under no constraint to respect the evidence—imagining does not purport to be knowledge of the world. It is quite possible to imagine what one does not believe, so there is no competition between believing something and imagining its opposite (as distinct from believing its opposite). In general, imagining‐that is a voluntary activity, generated from the subject's own resources, not even in the business of aiming to fit the world, and capable of coexisting with disparate beliefs. It therefore has much in common with sensory imagination—the difference (p. 604) being that it is conceptual rather than sensory, propositional rather than ‘qualitative’. Both are combinatorial faculties that transcend the recorded facts of experience, inventing new entities and situations. They liberate the mind to apprehend what is not actually the case. Imagining‐that, therefore, has everything to do with possibility. Suppose I observe that grass is green, and form the corresponding belief. It is imagination that steps in to contemplate the possibility that grass is not green. Thus, negating what is known to be the case is a distinctive exercise of the cognitive imagination: when I say ‘not’ I step beyond actuality and consider the merely possible. Without imagination the realm of modality would be a closed book to us—as we may suppose it is for many (or most) animals. Not that imagination infallibly informs us of what is really possible; there are illusions of imagination as there are illusions of perception. But imagination is our cognitive route to knowledge of possibility, the faculty that brings possible worlds within our mental scope. Thus, we are not mere recorders of actual fact, but capable of contemplating alternatives. This capacity is what makes possible fiction, science, morality, politics, philosophy, and civilization itself.15 I think this connection between imagination and possibility leads naturally to a certain conception of what knowledge of linguistic meaning is; namely, it is the sentence‐directed imaginative apprehension of possibility. Suppose someone says ‘snow is green’ and I understand his utterance to mean that snow is green. What has happened is that his utterance has caused me to construct, from the structure and composition of the uttered sentence, a certain possibility, which I then associate with the processed utterance: I envisage the possibility that snow is green by means of my imaginative faculty, and this envisaging is what my understanding of the utterance consists in. I work out which possible state of affairs would make the sentence true—its truth‐condition—and the result of this process is understanding the sentence to represent that very possibility. None of this would be possible unless I had a faculty that put me into contact with the realm of possibility—and the name of this faculty is ‘imagination’. Sentences represent possibilities, and understanding them is imaginatively grasping which possibility is in

Page 9 of 13

Imagination question (and how this is determined by the structure of the sentence). Knowing a sentence's truth condition rests upon an imaginative act.16 This conception nicely fits the fact that meaning is essentially freedom from the actual: a sentence can mean something that has no counterpart in the real world. More precisely, the falsity of a proposition is no impediment to its being meant by a sentence. Meaning is a matter of alternatives—regions of logical space. If a sentence is meaningful, its negation always is. But this kind of freedom from the actual is exactly what imagination trades in: the contemplation of what is not the case. Also, and connectedly, meaning and imagination share a combinatorial passion: meanings (p. 605) can separate and join, recombining with other meanings, and imagination is itself expressly designed to arrange concepts into new combinations, novel and unheard of. The productivity of meaning is thus aligned with the productivity of imagination. Just as language can join together words whose referents are not found together in the world (as with ‘snow is green’), so imagination can associate elements that are pure fancy. Both are combinatorially unbounded (within the limits of sense). Thus it is—to put it grandly—that language and the mind break free of the tyranny of the actual. This is not to say that meanings are sensory images in the style of old empiricist theories of understanding—cognitive imagination is not sensory imagination. But it is to draw a connection of sorts between meaning and images; for images, too, are massively combinatorial, fluently productive, novel, and stimulus‐free. So although it would be wrong to identify meanings with mental images, the idea that there is an important affinity here is not as wide of the mark as much recent philosophy has maintained. The affinity, however, has more to do with the structure of the image‐generating faculty than with its products. It is not implausible to conjecture that the imagery faculty pre‐dates the capacity for imagining‐that, providing it with a foundation of cognitive operations—in which case, the roots of meaning lie with imagery, if not meaning itself. The old image theorists were not as wildly in error as we have come to suppose. The general point I would make is that the imagination is a basic faculty of mind, distinctive, irreducible to other faculties, which runs through a number of different mental capabilities, from simple images, to dreams, to language itself. In its furthest reaches, which we have not discussed—I mean, the creativity of the arts and sciences—it must take its rise from these more basic imaginative modes. Indeed, in my view, the creativity of even the humblest modes of imagination far exceeds what we tend to suppose, especially when we fully acknowledge the deep divisions between perception and imagination. When a percept is transformed into a memory image, undergoing a genuine metamorphosis—let alone when radically novel images are generated—the mind is already operating at a high level of creativity, as measured by the distance between the percept as input and the image as output. The image is no more a faint copy of an original percept, its pale simulacrum, than a butterfly is a faint copy of a caterpillar. Images are things with creativity built right into them.

Page 10 of 13

Imagination

References Brann, E. (1991), The World of the Imagination (Boston, Mass.: Rowan & Littlefield). Budd, M. (1989), Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Psychology (London: Routledge). Casey, E. (2000), Imagining: A Phenomenological Study (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press). Hume, D. (1739–40/1985), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. E. C. Mossner (New York: Penguin). Kant, I. (1950), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. K. Smith (New York: Humanities). Kosslyn, S. (1996), Image and Brain (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). (p. 606)

McGinn, C. (2004), Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.:

Harvard University Press). O'Shaughnessy, B. (2000), Consciousness and the World (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Sartre, J. (1966), The Psychology of Imagination (New York: Washington Square). Scruton, R. (1974), Art and Imagination. (London: Methuen). Strawson, P. F. (1970), ‘Imagination and Perception’, in L. Foster and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (London: Duckworth), 31–54. Wittgenstein, L. (1981), Zettel (Oxford: Blackwell). Wollheim, R. (1980), Art and Its Objects (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Notes: (1) Strawson writes: ‘The uses, and applications, of the terms “image”, “imagine”, “imagination”, “imaginative”, and so forth make up a very diverse and scattered family. Even this image [!] of a family seems too definite. It would be a matter of more than difficulty exactly to identify and list the family's members, let alone establish their relationships of parenthood and cousinhood’ (1970: 31). A useful historical and contemporary survey is provided by Brann (1991). I discuss imagination from several different angles in McGinn (2004). This chapter is basically a précis of that book, and states theses more than defends them. (2) Thus Hume: ‘Those perceptions, which enter with most force and violence, we may name impressions … by ideas I mean the faint images of these in thinking and

Page 11 of 13

Imagination reasoning’ (1739–40/1985: 49); and later: ‘That idea of red, which we form in the dark, and that impression, which strikes our eyes in sunshine, differ only in degree, not in nature’ (1739–40/1985: 51). (3) Thus Kant (1950): ‘Psychologists have hitherto failed to realize that imagination is a necessary ingredient of perception itself’. I take this quotation from Strawson (1970), who discusses the way Kant brings imagination into perception; in fact, the view became quite common among psychologists and is regarded by many as a virtual truism. (4) These remarks are discussed by Budd (1989: ch. 5); see also O'Shaughnessy (2000: ch. 11) and McGinn (2004: ch. 1). The point needs further elaboration and qualification than I have supplied in the text. (5) I discuss this neglected point at length in McGinn (2004: ch. 1). (6) This feature of imagination is stressed by both Wittgenstein and Sartre, whose treatments of imagination are remarkably similar. Wittgenstein (1981: 621) writes: ‘Images tell us nothing, either right or wrong, about the external world’. Sartre (1966: 25) writes: ‘[T]he image teaches nothing, never produces an impression of novelty, and never reveals any new aspect of the object’. (7) Nothing I say in the text is incompatible with a ‘causal theory’ of the image, to the effect that it is at least a necessary condition of an image being of an object that that object should be the cause of the image. Even if we accept that claim, it does not follow that the object continually updates the image. Compare reference: maybe an object needs to be at the origin of a causal chain leading to the use of a name for it to be a name of that object, but it doesn't follow that users of the name are continually receiving causally mediated information from the object. (8) Here it might be thought that recent empirical findings cast doubt on this claim, since one can use an image to answer questions about an object, as when I ‘consult’ an image of my living room to say how many windows it has. (See Kosslyn 1996 for a survey of these findings.) However, the point to stress is that such images issue from information that is already stored in memory, instead of acting as conduits for new information from the environment. I discuss this question in McGinn (2004: chs. 1, 5). (9) See Casey (2000: pt. 3) for a discussion of this and other germane matters. I also discuss the point in McGinn (2004: ch. 4), in which the notion of a distinctive imagistic space is explored. (10) Wittgenstein (1981: 621) makes the point that I cannot form an image of an object while I am looking at that object, though there is in general no problem about forming images of objects distinct from those one perceives. I discuss this also in McGinn (2004: ch. 1), entering various qualifications.

Page 12 of 13

Imagination (11) Of course, if all percepts were images, then forming one image might interfere with forming another image, given the limits of attention, and this will exclude simultaneous percepts with incompatible contents. But I take it that it is obvious that this is not the same phenomenon as perceptual exclusivity, in which it is impossible to have incompatible perceptual contents in the same region of the visual field. For one thing, this is a not a phenomenon of attention at all; and the interference between two images is not a matter of how one's sensory field can present objects; that is, how things can perceptually seem. (12) Again, I discuss this in McGinn (2004: ch. 2). (13) There is a large literature on seeing as; for example, Scruton (1974: ch. 8); Wollheim (1980: sects. 11–14); Budd (1989: ch. 4). (14) I discuss the matter at length in McGinn (2004: chs. 6–7). (15) The idea that people are distinguished from the brutes primarily through their imaginative capacities is an attractive one, as such ideas go: homo imaginans is not such a bad label. Certainly, we owe much of our distinctive pattern of life to our imaginations— even our linguistic life (see below). (16) This is the subject of McGinn (2004: ch. 12).

Colin McGinn

Colin McGinn is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Miami.

Page 13 of 13

Thinking

Oxford Handbooks Online Thinking   Louise Antony The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0036

Abstract and Keywords Human language is not the only naturally occurring symbol system. There are many animals other than human beings that communicate by means of signs or signals; vervet monkeys, for example, have specialized warning cries for different kinds of predators. And some animal-communication systems even have a rudimentary syntax: the dances performed by certain honey bees have structural elements that tell other bees the direction and distance from the hive of a nectar source. But what's distinctive of human language — and the feature that Descartes was highlighting — is that the syntax of human language permits us to take parts of signs and recombine them with parts of other signs. Keywords: symbol system, human language, animal-communication systems, reflex behaviour, human syntax

Preliminary Thoughts about Thinking COGITO, ergo sum, Descartes reasoned, and then immediately asked, ‘What is this “I” that thinks?’. This essay asks the different question, ‘What is this thinking that I do?’. Perhaps the first thing to be said about thinking is that it is a mental activity. But what does that mean? Most people, in speaking of the ‘mental’, have in mind some kind of contrast with the physical. Physical activities all involve our bodies, or parts of them, in some conspicuous way. Physical actions that we perform—walking, writing, playing a musical instrument—all involve the voluntary movement of our limbs. Physical processes like perception and respiration are clearly dependent upon the well functioning of our bodily organs. Thinking seems different from both those things. I can think without

Page 1 of 27

Thinking moving any part of my body; I can think with my eyes closed, and my ears plugged. The only thing that seems to be necessary in order for me to think is that I be conscious. Could it be that thinking doesn't require a body at all? René Descartes, notoriously, came to precisely this conclusion. In Meditations on a First Philosophy he argued that because mind and body were conceptually distinct it was possible for the one to exist without the other. Hence, mind and body were actually distinct, even when they were co‐instantiated (Descartes 1641/1901). This is an argument for dualism that many philosophers still find compelling today.1 But there's a second, less‐ well‐known argument of Descartes's for the same conclusion. In this argument, from his earlier work the Discourse on Method, Descartes appeals to some very specific—and plausible—assumptions about the nature of thought. Even (p. 608) if (as I believe) the argument fails to establish the immateriality of thought, it makes a good starting point for our investigation. The argument comes as Descartes is extolling the marvels of animal anatomy. He acknowledges that the complex structure and finely tuned operations of biological organs make it seem as if living beings might be machines of a sort. While he thinks that this suggestion is perfectly apt in the case of non‐human animals, he insists that it is completely wrong when it comes to human beings. A machine, he says, designed with the internal workings and external appearance of an animal, would be indistinguishable from the real thing. But no mechanical simulacrum of a human being, no matter how perfectly crafted to resemble us outwardly, could pass for a real person. There would be, he says, ‘two most certain tests whereby to know that [such machines] were not therefore really men’. The argument for dualism comes in the second of these two tests: [A]lthough these machines might do several things as well or perhaps better than we do, they are inevitably lacking in some other, through which we discover that they act, not by knowledge, but only by the arrangement [disposition] of their organs. For, whereas reason is a universal instrument which can serve in all sorts of encounters, these organs need some particular arrangement for each particular action. As a result of that, it is morally impossible that there is in a machine's organs sufficient variety to act in all the events of our lives in the same way that our reason empowers us to act (Descartes 1637: pt. v, para. 35)

Page 2 of 27

Thinking To understand the argument, we must first appreciate the distinction that Descartes is drawing between two ways in which seemingly intelligent behaviour might be produced: it might be simply necessitated by the machine's antecedent physical state—by the ‘disposition of its organs’—or it might be produced ‘by knowledge’. Only in the second case, Descartes says, is there genuine intelligence at work, for it is only in this case that the appropriateness of the behaviour to its circumstances is due to an understanding of the situation. In the first case the appearance of intelligence behind the behaviour can be explained by the fact that the physical structure that produces it happens to be (or, in the case of a machine, was designed to be) specialized to produce precisely that kind of behaviour, in precisely those circumstances. We can be confident that this is the explanation, Descartes argues, because the apparently skilled behaviour displayed by animals or machines is always limited to one or a few domains. In contrast, Descartes says, our faculty of reason, which enables us to act from knowledge, is ‘a universal instrument which can serve in all sorts of encounters’.

Let's suppose for the moment that Descartes has established a categorical difference between two types of behaviour production. (Let's call the first type ‘brute causation’ and the second type ‘rational causation’.) How does he get from this premise to the conclusion that rational causation cannot transpire within a material medium? He says of brutes' ‘souls’ as compared with human beings’ that ‘once one knows how different they are, one understands much better the reasons which prove that the nature of our souls is totally independent of the body’. How does the rest of (p. 609) the argument go? We need to understand better what Descartes takes to be involved when behaviour is ‘due to knowledge’. In order for us even to suspect that a piece of behaviour is genuinely intelligent, the behaviour has to be appropriate to the circumstances in which it is displayed. Contrast, for example, the following two cases: in the first, my doctor strikes my knee with her little mallet and my foot kicks out; in the second, I kick my foot and hit an assailant who has just struck me with a mallet (and seems about to do so again). In the first case there is nothing that makes my kicking appropriate to the circumstance of having been struck by a mallet; it is simply what my foot does when my knee has been struck in that way. In the second case, however, it makes sense for me to kick, because doing so may well drive away my assailant. The first case is a clear example of reflex action—hardly an ‘action’ at all—and the second a clear example of rational action. What's the difference? In the second case, as we know, Descartes would say that my behavioural response to the circumstances I face is mediated by knowledge. That means that one of the antecedents of my behaviour is a representation of the situation I face. In fact, there are several representations involved. I need to represent not only my circumstances, but the goal I wish to achieve, and the means by which I might achieve it. These representations stand in rational relations to each other. Because I want to drive away my assailant, and because I believe that kicking her is apt to drive her away, I conclude that kicking her would be a good thing to do. If these representations are all accurate—if they correctly represent my situation, my goals, and my options—then the behaviour that results from this process will be appropriate to the situation: it will further my goal.

Page 3 of 27

Thinking Here, then, are two surpassingly important features of thoughts: First of all, they represent—they display what the Austrian philosopher Franz Brentano called ‘intentionality’: the feature of standing for, or being about, something else (Brentano 1874/1973). Second, they possess some kind of rational structure in virtue of which they can stand in logical or rational relations to each other. It is likely that Descartes had both these features well in mind when he spoke of actions being due to knowledge. Returning to the first of my two illustrative cases, the case of reflex ‘action’, we can now see that the arbitrariness of the kicking response relative to the circumstance of being struck by the hammer is due to the fact that the kicking response is not in any way sensitive to my representation of my situation. We can better appreciate the difference by considering counterfactuals in the two cases. In the second case, if I had not represented the situation as one in which I was being assaulted then I would not have kicked. But in the first case the ‘disposition of my organs’ would have determined me to kick regardless of how I viewed the situation. It is this feature of rationally caused behaviour that makes for flexibility. In so far as my thoughts accurately represent my situation, goals, etc., and in so far as my behaviour is counterfactually dependent on my thoughts, my behaviour will tend to be appropriate to my circumstances whatever they are. (p. 610)

This, then, is the categorical distinction Descartes needs: between beings that can and beings that cannot condition their behaviour to representations of their circumstances, goals, and options. But why think that non‐human animals and machines fall into the second category rather than the first? Reflex behaviour, of course, need not be inappropriate to circumstances; it may mimic intelligent behaviour. This is the case, Descartes believes, with the behaviour of animals and machines. The instinctive behaviour of animals or the operation of well‐designed machines may even be more efficacious than human efforts—a person who tried to build a nest, for example, would be no competition for a bird, and our intuitive sense of the time is no match for a clock's marking of the minutes—but the true aetiology of such behaviour would be betrayed once we placed the animal or the machine in a novel circumstance. Because the brute or the mechanism does not know what is going on—because it lacks the capacity for representation—it cannot tailor its behaviour to suit its circumstances. Indeed, Descartes argues, it is the fact that animals’ and machines’ performance is so uneven—better than human behaviour in some circumstances, but worse in most others— that assures us that they are not acting through reason. If the better performances were due to thinking, then we would expect the performer to be uniformly better than us, able to produce more appropriate behaviour across the board: Thus, the fact that they do better than we do does not prove that they have a mind, for, if that were the case, they would have more of it than any of us and would do better in all other things; it rather shows that they have no reason at all,

Page 4 of 27

Thinking and that it's nature which has activated them according to the arrangement of their organs—just as one sees that a clock, which is composed only of wheels and springs, can keep track of the hours and measure time more accurately than we can, for all our care. (Descartes 1637: pt. v, para. 38) So the argument for dualism proceeds: since beings that lack reason can only produce appropriate behaviour through the operation of specialized organs, they would need a separate specialized organ for every distinct task they face. It would be impossible—morally impossible, Descartes says, and this is important—to outfit a purely material being with enough of these organs to enable the being to respond appropriately to any circumstance whatsoever. Since we human beings do possess this kind of general flexibility, the faculty that enables it—‘reason’, in Descartes's terms—must inhere in an immaterial substance.

But there's still a piece missing: why is Descartes so confident that we possess the degree of flexibility that would require an impossibly large inventory of specialized organs in a purely material being? What makes him think that reason is truly a ‘universal instrument’? The answer comes in the first test he gives for telling whether one is dealing with a person or a mechanical simulacrum, and has to do with language. Machines, Descartes says, would never be able to use words or other signs … as we do to declare our thoughts to others. For one can easily imagine a machine made in such a way that it expresses words, even that it expresses some words relevant to some physical actions which bring about some change in (p. 611) its organs … but one cannot imagine a machine that arranges words in various ways to reply to the sense of everything said in its presence, as the most stupid human beings are capable of doing. (1637: pt. v, para. 34) Notice that when Descartes asserts that no machine could use language, he is very specific about the limitation he has in mind. He does not doubt that one could build a machine that would produce what sound like meaningful utterances, and produce them in circumstances for which they appear appropriate—a machine, for example, that produces the sound ‘Please don't do that’ if we strike it. The thing Descartes thinks a machine could not do is to ‘arrange words in various ways to reply to the sense of everything said in its presence’. That is, no machine can recombine the parts of its ‘utterance’ so as to compose new utterances that make sense relative to new circumstances.

Descartes is here pointing to a strikingly distinctive feature of the human communication system: its compositionality. We've already remarked that thought is representational, that it has intentional content, or meaning. Language does, too: it is composed of symbols that stand for other things. The set of relations between symbols and the things they represent is called the semantics of the symbol system. While all symbol systems have semantics, only some have syntax—rules that govern the ways in which primitive signs can be combined so as to produce more complex signs.

Page 5 of 27

Thinking Human language is not the only naturally occurring symbol system. There are many animals other than human beings that communicate by means of signs or signals; vervet monkeys, for example, have specialized warning cries for different kinds of predators. And some animal‐communication systems even have a rudimentary syntax: the dances performed by certain honey bees have structural elements that tell other bees the direction and distance from the hive of a nectar source. But what's distinctive of human language—and the feature that Descartes was highlighting—is that the syntax of human language permits us to take parts of signs and recombine them with parts of other signs. The vervet monkey can utter a shriek that tells its troupe that an eagle is approaching overhead, and a different kind of shriek that tells them that there's a snake nearby in the grass. But each of these signs is an indissoluble unit—the monkey cannot recombine parts of the two shrieks to express, for example, the thought that there's an eagle in the grass (Cheney and Seyfarth 1990). In contrast, any human being who can say both that there's an eagle overhead and that there's a snake in the grass can also say that there's a snake overhead or that there's an eagle in the grass—this is guaranteed by the way sentences of human languages are composed. Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn call this property systematicity: your communication code is systematic if in possessing the ability to express one thought you are automatically equipped to express many (Fodor and Pylyshyn 1988). But there's another important property of human syntax: it is recursive. This means that we can take the expression that results from the application of some rule of combination and reapply that same rule to the new expression. For example, I can form a complex noun phrase by conjoining two nouns: ‘Bob’ and ‘Carol’ → ‘Bob and Carol’. But I can also reapply that rule to the noun phrase I just constructed: ‘Bob and (p. 612) Carol’ and ‘Ted’ → ‘Bob and Carol and Ted’. Compositionality plus recursion give us a guarantee that language has the resources to generate an unlimited number of distinct, meaningful signs. This property is called by Chomsky creativity (1975) and by Fodor and Pylyshyn productivity (1988). Descartes clearly took the compositionality of language to be evidence that human thought was itself systematic and productive. Because language is compositional and recursive, we know that we are not like the vervet monkeys, stuck with a fixed repertoire of signs. But if we have an unlimited number of distinct linguistic signs available to us, related in a systematic way, then we must also have available to us an elastic repertoire of distinct thoughts, corresponding to each of these signs. Hence, our observed ability to utilize a compositional (and recursive) language is ipso facto evidence of our ability to think and express an unlimited number of distinct thoughts. And that's the premise that Descartes needed in order to complete his empirical argument for the immateriality of thought. But here lies the great irony. In highlighting the systematicity of thought, Descartes inadvertently laid the groundwork for a materialist theory of mind. If it is the mind's systematicity—rather than, say, its subjectivity—that is the sticking point for a materialist

Page 6 of 27

Thinking account of mentality, then the Discourse argument for dualism could be neutralized if someone could show how systematicity could be mechanized. And this, it turns out, is exactly what Alan Turing did, more on this soon. As we've seen, Descartes presumed that the structure of language mirrored the structure of thought—that language was, indeed, merely the outward expression of thought. The most important aspect of this isomorphism was rational structure, secured by compositionality. This emphasis on rational structure was one of the things that distinguished philosophical rationalism from the empiricism that emerged in Great Britain about half a century after the publication of Descartes's Discourse (Locke 1690/1975). So let's be more explicit about what compositionality involves. We'll necessarily go beyond Descartes's brief remarks in the Discourse. Language is compositional: its primitive parts are words, which can be combined to create phrases and sentences. Does thought, similarly, have parts? It appears that it does. Consider the thought that HERSHEY'S KISSES ARE MADE OF CHOCOLATE.2 This thought seems to contain, as components, several elements: one that is about Hershey's kisses, one that is about chocolate, and one that is about being made of something. In this respect, thought contrasts interestingly with another kind of mental state, a ‘qualitative’ state like the one I would experience were I to taste a Hershey's kiss. The experience of tasting the candy doesn't seem at all to be segmented in the way the thought is—I would be hard pressed to distinguish a HERSHEY'S KISS part of a candy‐eating experience from a CHOCOLATE part.3 We have a name for thought parts: we call them ‘concepts’, and we individuate thoughts according to the concepts that compose them. The thought that lobster is (p. 613) high in cholesterol is a different thought from the thought that the most expensive thing on the menu is high in cholesterol, because the concept LOBSTER is different from the concept THE MOST EXPENSIVE THING ON THE MENU even if, in a given circumstance, the most expensive thing on the menu happens to be lobster. In other words, it's one thing to think about lobster as lobster, and another thing to think about it as the most expensive thing on the menu. Thoughts enable us to do this, and they do so by permitting us to pick out the same thing under different concepts. This feature of thought is called ‘intensionality’ (and sometimes called ‘intensionality‐ with‐an‐s’ to distinguish it from ‘intentionality’—‘intentionality‐with‐a‐t’).4 The intensionality of thought explains some otherwise puzzling phenomena. Lois Lane, as any well‐educated person knows, believes that Superman is strong and brave. She does not believe that Clark Kent is strong and brave—quite the contrary. She believes that Clark Kent is weak and cowardly. But it turns out that Superman is Clark Kent—he disguises himself with glasses and hairstyling! What, then, should we say about Lois's state of mind? We might insist that Lois does believe that Clark Kent is strong and brave. But this is something Lois would vehemently deny. Maybe we should say that Lois believes contradictory things. But that would indict her of logical confusion, and there's no reason to think she has that problem. Rather, what seems clear is that Lois thinks of, or conceives Page 7 of 27

Thinking of Superman in two different ways: as SUPERMAN, and also as CLARK KENT. Because she has two distinct concepts of the same individual, her SUPERMAN thoughts are distinct thoughts from her CLARK KENT thoughts. Brentano held that intentionality was the ‘hallmark of the mental’—that what made a state a mental state was its being representational. It is currently a hot topic in philosophy whether this claim is true. It is clear that sensations and emotions are part of our psychologies, but not so clear that they have representational content; some philosophers say they do, and some say they do not.5 But if such states do represent, they do it in a different way than thoughts do. I do not have available to me different ways of experiencing the taste of the candy, one a ‘Hershey's kiss’ way and one a ‘chocolate’ way. There is one distinctive way that a Hershey's kiss tastes, and that one way defines the qualitative character of the experience. Relatedly, my experience of the taste of a Hershey's kiss does not depend on my having any knowledge or understanding of ‘Hershey‐ness’. I need the concept HERSHEY'S KISS in order to think the thought ‘A Hershey's kiss is made of chocolate’, but I don't need it to experience its chocolate‐y goodness. We can capture these differences by saying that thoughts are conceptual while qualitative mental states are non‐conceptual. Not all concepts are the same. The concepts HERSHEY'S KISS and CHOCOLATE are different in a crucial way from the concept IS MADE OF. Roughly, the first (p. 614) two concepts are about things, while the third is about a property of, or a relation among, things. These different kinds of concept combine in specific ways, giving thought its structure.6 We noted above that concepts can combine and recombine in lots of different ways, provided they are of the right type to work together. To a first approximation, we can say that any concept of the ‘thing’ type can combine with any concept of the ‘property’ type. (In language, the mirror distinction is between subject terms and predicate terms.) This is, obviously, not all there is to conceptual structure, but it may be the fundamental feature of conceptually structured representation (Evans 1982; Fodor 2007). The version of computationalism that I'll present below is Cartesian or rationalist, in that it takes for granted that thought is structured compositionally. I'll have a few words to say at the end about the empiricist alternative, and the kind of computational model consonant with it.

Page 8 of 27

Thinking

The Computer Model of Mind: Thinking as Information Processing At first glance it would seem that no two things could be more deeply at odds than creativity and mechanism. As we just saw, Descartes relied precisely on the intuition that deterministic processes could not give rise to novelty to frame his second argument for dualism. But important work in logic in the 1930s by logicians Kurt Gödel, Alonso Church, and Alan Turing posed a deep challenge to this intuition. In particular, Turing proved that a deterministic ‘machine’—really a mathematical object, rather than a physical device— could embody recursive procedures (1937). In its essentials, the machine was conceived as consisting of a tape, on which is written some pattern of distinguishable symbols (1s and 0s, for example), and a writer/scanner that can move right or left along the tape, registering and reacting to the symbol it finds. The operation of the machine is specified by a list of ‘instructions’ (the reason for the scare‐quotes will come later) laid out in its ‘machine table’. Each instruction specifies what the machine will do, depending on what state the machine is currently in, and on what input the machine receives. The instruction could tell the writer/scanner to move left or right or to stop, and to erase, erase and replace, or ignore a symbol appearing on the tape. The table also specifies a starting state and an ending state for the machine. The configuration of symbols on the tape at the start represents the input to the machine, and the configuration at the end represents the output. What Turing showed was that for any step‐by‐step procedure that could be used to calculate the value of a function for a given argument, that procedure (or algorithm) could be captured by some Turing‐machine table. Hence, if a function is computable (p. 615) at all—that is, if there is an algorithm guaranteed to produce a value for any argument— there will be a Turing machine that can compute it. Thus, for example, there is at least one Turing machine that embodies an algorithm for addition function, and at least one for subtraction, and so on. Showing this much is an achievement dazzling enough, but Turing also went on to show something utterly breathtaking. He proved that one single machine —a ‘universal Turing machine’—could do anything and everything that could be done by any simple Turing machine. The trick was to show that one could effectively code and then list all the different special‐purpose (or ‘simple’) Turing machines; one could then build a Turing machine that took the list positions and coded instructions as part of its input. In this way, a single machine could, in effect, look up the simple machine that embodied the function to be computed, and then just follow the instructions associated with that machine. The universal Turing machine's ability to simulate the activity of any simple Turing machine affords it precisely the kind of flexibility that Descartes thought was beyond the capacities of ordinary matter: the flexibility to make apposite responses to an unlimited number of distinct problems. Moreover, the machine's flexibility is the result of the systematicity of the symbol system that encodes its inputs, outputs, and instructions. The Page 9 of 27

Thinking same two symbols—‘1’ and ‘0’—are combined and recombined in rule‐governed ways to represent a potential infinitude of meanings. Yet the machine's behaviour—no matter how complex—is always decomposable into small step‐by‐step reactions to primitive elements of the complex symbols. Turing's mathematical results were quickly applied to physical reality, resulting in the construction of concrete ‘thinking machines’: digital computers. These were not literally Turing machines—they incorporated some architectural innovations due to John von Neumann, for example data stores, or ‘memory’—but still realized the essential feature of Turing's model: computation performed on structured symbols. The philosophical import of these developments was also rapidly exploited.7 Hilary Putnam noted that the relation between the machine table of a computer and the ‘hardware’ that implemented it offered a useful model for representing the relation of mind to body (Putnam 1960, 1967a, 1967b). Mental states, on this model, would be abstractly characterized states of a human brain, just as machine states were abstractly characterized states of an electronic mechanism. Because the defining features of these abstract states were the functional relationships among individual states, inputs and outputs, this general view of mentality became known as functionalism.8 If we take the machine analogy completely at face value, we get the view of thinking known as the computational model: thinking is computation. That is, a thought process consists in a series of transitions from brain state to brain state, in a way that mirrors an explicit inference or computation, just as the electronic states of a digital (p. 616) computer each embody steps in an inference or computation. Jerry Fodor pressed the analogy a step further. He argued that if thinking was computation, then there needed to be a medium of computation—a symbolic language over which the computational processes that constituted thought were defined. Thoughts, then, would be tokenings of sentences in an internal language. This ‘language of thought’, he argued, was analogous to a computer's ‘machine language’, the system of symbols to which the machine's most basic computational operations are sensitive. Electronic computers can translate machine language strings back and forth into more ‘user‐friendly’ programming languages by means of special translation programs (compilers). Analogously, we can regard the acquisition of human natural languages as the building of a translation program that allows us to move back and forth between ‘Mentalese’ and ordinary public language (Fodor 1975). We'll return to the idea of a mental ‘machine language’ below. Before leaving this point, however, let me just note that Fodor's view raises a possibility that Descartes would not have allowed; namely, that ‘dumb brutes’ might be thinkers. Descartes, as we saw, presumed that the ability to use language tracked the ability to think—that all and only language users possessed the faculty of reason. (This is so even though his argument requires only that language use be evidentially sufficient for the attribution of reason to a creature.) But if Fodor is correct, the possession of an internal language of thought—a biologically specified ‘machine language’—is independent of the capacity for speech. We can thus make sense of attributions of genuine thought to non‐ linguistic creatures—infrahuman animals, as well as pre‐linguistic human children; to say Page 10 of 27

Thinking that such creatures think is to say that their behaviour is mediated by an internal compositional system of representation. This is indeed the position taken by contemporary ethologists and developmental psychologists, who have evidence of behavioural flexibility and creativity in animals and infants that might have changed Descartes's assessments (Gallistel 1990; Carey and Spelke 1994). Although Turing did not develop a computational theory of human thought, he did commit himself explicitly to the proposition that a machine could—at least in principle—think. Ironically (again), Turing endorsed the very same criterion of thinking that Descartes appealed to in his argument for dualism (Turing 1950). Turing, like Descartes, thought that the sustained ability to respond appropriately to a variety of circumstances was sufficient for being a genuine thinker. And like Descartes he saw verbal interaction as providing the crucial test. It's just that, unlike Descartes, Turing thought that this ability could be embodied in a machine.9 Turing envisioned an experimental set‐up like the following.10 Position a human ‘interrogator’ at two keyboards, one of which feeds inputs to another human being, and the other of which feeds inputs to a computing machine. Both human being (p. 617) and machine can respond to the inputs, and their responses are displayed as lines of type on a display screen visible to the interrogator. The interrogator does not know which keyboard is connected to which responder, and so does not know (at least initially) which responses are coming from which responder. The interrogator types questions or instructions, like ‘Please write me a sonnet on the subject of the Forth Bridge’ (or, if in the present day, something more like: ‘Who do you think should have custody of Britney's kids?’) and would receive answers like: ‘Count me out on this one; I never could write poetry’ (‘Don't ask me; I don't watch television’). If after a sufficient amount of time (Turing leaves this unspecified) the interrogator still cannot tell which of the responders is the machine and which is the human being, then the machine is deemed to be a genuine thinker. It's noteworthy that Turing's test of intelligence imposes no conditions on the means by which the machine is allowed to accomplish its deception. Most philosophers have taken this to mean that Turing was proposing a behaviourist definition of ‘thinking’: that he was essentially saying that thinking is whatever might turn out to be responsible for intelligent‐appearing behaviour. If this is what Turing had in mind, it's clear that his ‘definition’ is inadequate, for it's easy enough to describe a hypothetical case in which an obviously dumb device manages to pass the Turing test. To see how this might work, let's consider a hypothetical machine devised by Ned Block (1995). The machine runs a simple program, constructed in the following way. First a giant list is made of all possible strings of symbols that could be typed by a human interrogator within some particular period of time—say an hour. The list will include a vast number of what we might call ‘conversations’: strings that look like transcripts of some sensible conversation between two human beings. The next step, therefore, is for a team of programmers to comb through the list of strings, pulling out every conversation, and throwing away all the other strings, the ones that do not resemble actual human Page 11 of 27

Thinking exchanges. The programmers then ‘punctuate’ each conversation on the list by separating with commas or some other delimiters the lines that would belong to one ‘conversant’ from those belonging to the other. Call the delimited parts of the strings ‘remarks’. Now the instructions to the machine are trivial. All it has to do is to match strings of remarks with conversations on the list. It can do this step by step. When it receives its first remark as input, it finds some conversation that begins with that remark, and then copies the second remark in that conversation as its output. (Remember that every remark that is intelligible and that can be typed in the space of an hour will appear as part of some—indeed many—conversations on the grand list.) The human interrogator will, of course, make some reasonable response to the machine's remark. The machine now finds a conversation containing the string consisting of the first remark, the machine's own remark, and the interrogator's next remark, and outputs the fourth remark in that conversation. (Again, every possible three‐remark conversation will be on the grand list.) This process is repeated until the hour is up.11 (p. 618)

Will this work? Many actual working programs operate on essentially these principles. Think of (the now ubiquitous) phone menus. Suppose you want to renew a pharmaceutical prescription. You dial the number of the pharmacy, and a pleasant voice answers, welcoming you to the wonderful world of Acme Drugs, and requests that you ‘please listen carefully to your options’, adding that ‘you may enter the number of your choice at any time’. When the voice finally gets to the option you're interested in—‘to refill a prescription, press “4” now’—you follow the instruction: you press ‘4’. The voice then says, ‘please enter your prescription number’, and so on and so forth. What is actually going on, of course, is that the computer running the menu is simply using a look‐up table like the one described above. The computer takes your typed signals as input, and activates a particular taped message in response. When all goes well, the whole experience is not unlike a conversation with a real person. A naive user might even think that she actually is having a conversation with a real person. But if you are an experienced user of such technology you know that things often do not go well. Sometimes the menu of options is too limited, and doesn't include one that covers your needs. In that case, the voice may just stupidly—but pleasantly!—keep repeating the inadequate list over and over until you give up. Slightly more user‐friendly systems will, after a round or two, have the pleasant voice announce that ‘your call is being forwarded to an operator’ (i.e. a real person). Another problem that can arise is when your inputs don't meet the ‘expectations’ of the program—you enter too many digits, or too few, or you pause too long in between entering. If there is voice‐recognition software involved, the machine may find your accent or pronunciation pattern too unlike its stored exemplars to be able to find a match. In such cases, the machine may generate (in a pleasant, pleasant voice!) the message ‘I'm sorry—I didn't understand. Could you re‐

Page 12 of 27

Thinking enter/repeat your information?’. Even if one of these expedients works—and sometimes none does—you are left with the sour knowledge that the call could have been handled in seconds if you had only been allowed to speak with someone who could think. Returning to our master machine, we can now ask what would happen if the interrogator typed a question that was completely off the wall, or badly mistyped? Block points out that the basic programming strategy outlined above can be both simplified and improved (for purposes of passing the Turing test) if the programmers of our master machine keep a real person in mind as they craft the machine's responses. Block suggests his Aunt Bubbles: someone who apparently took a slightly dim view of academic exercises, and who thus would be prone to respond to strange or ill‐formed questions with a throwaway remark like, ‘My nephew told me you might try to confuse me’. The programmers could take a few remarks such as this, and have the machine cycle through them at random whenever it received an input that did not match any of the anticipated intelligible remarks. This expedient not only allows the programmers to give the machine a plausible and coherent ‘personality’, but provides them with a way of coping with inputs that might otherwise expose the program and expose the deception (lock 1995). Here, too, there have been working programs that run on such principles. A program written by Joseph Weizenbaum, called ELIZA, was designed to mimic the (p. 619) behaviour of a Rogerian psychotherapist (Weizenbaum 1976). Therapists in this tradition are ‘non‐directive’—they do not offer their patients analysis or advice; instead they try to facilitate their patients' self‐discovery by asking open‐ended questions prompted by themes in the patients' own comments. This fact about Rogerian therapeutic practice makes it ideal for mimicry by Aunt Bubbles‐type programs. After a brief opening question, ‘Why have you come to see me?’ or ‘How are you feeling today?’ the machine can let the ‘patient’ take the lead, responding with highly stereotypical responses, sometimes picking up on words in specified grammatical positions. Here's a typical example: ELIZA: WHY HAVE YOU COME TO SEE ME? Patient: I have been feeling depressed. ELIZA: CAN YOU ELABORATE ON THAT? Patient: Everything I do is wrong. ELIZA: CAN YOU BE MORE SPECIFIC? Patient: Well, my boss is very unhappy with my work. ELIZA: TELL ME MORE ABOUT YOUR BOSS.

Page 13 of 27

Thinking Although literature and lore are full of anecdotes about people who stumbled on to ELIZA unawares (and this is easier to do now in the age of email and the internet than it was back in the 1970s) and were fooled into thinking they were communicating with a real person, the program was pretty easy to unmask.12 But with Block's Aunt Bubbles machine we have the guarantee of a much more effective deception. As long as the interrogation lasts no longer than an hour, the machine will pass the Turing test. And of course, following Block's principles, we could design a machine that would last even longer by expanding the size of the original list. But while this machine would readily fool a human interrogator, no one who knows how it is accomplishing the deception would say that the machine is thinking. What Block's example shows is that we are not willing to identify thinking with whatever happens to be responsible for apparently intelligent behaviour. We want more than just intelligent‐looking behavioural responses—we want the responses to be caused in a certain way.

But this, of course, is just the point that Descartes emphasized in his Discourse argument. Behaviour can appear to be the result of thinking, without there really being thinking behind it. Notice that Block's machine is a version of the kind of physical device Descartes thought was ‘morally’ impossible. That is, the Aunt Bubbles machine essentially has a special‐purpose ‘organ’—in this case, a specialized subroutine—available for every envisioned circumstance. What's important to notice is that such a machine is not literally impossible; it is only practically impossible.13 Merely writing down the program we've been talking about would take more time (p. 620) and material than is available to any human being in the space of a lifetime. The amount of time it would take a physical device to search the relevant lists would also be prohibitively large. What all this means is that the look‐up table is not a plausible explanation of the intelligent behaviour we observe in other human beings. While Descartes may have been wrong about the capacities of matter in general, he was absolutely right in thinking that no human head—indeed, no physically possible being, period—could produce the range and amount of intelligent behaviour that we do by relying on a bag of special‐purpose tricks. We have, then, a happy convergence between an intuitively appealing condition on intelligence—that it must involve a systematic capacity—and an empirical argument that systematicity is the most likely explanation for the intelligent behaviour we actually observe. But is systematicity all there is to intelligence? It seems that the answer to this question is clearly no. After all, ordinary computers are systematic in their operation, but few people would say that these devices genuinely think. What's missing? To see what's missing in our account of thinking, let's look back at the Aunt Bubbles machine. Imagine that in place of a machine that's programmed to match remarks we instead achieve our effect by employing a human being to sit in a room and follow the instructions that constitute the machine's program. So our Aunt Bubbles operator will go through the procedure we imagined the machine doing automatically: she will look up the input strings, match them to conversations, and output the next appropriate strings. This is, of course, a rather silly procedure for a human being to go through, given that she could just read the input remarks and then think of appropriate replies. But now let's change the case a bit. Imagine that the conversations, inputs, and outputs are all in Chinese. If our operator is a monolingual speaker of English then she will not be able to understand any of the remarks she is dealing with, but—and this is the significant thing— Page 14 of 27

Thinking she will still be able to manipulate the strings of Chinese characters in accordance with the instructions, so as to simulate just as effectively as before the behaviour of an intelligent person. The set‐up I've just described is—except for one wrinkle that we'll add in a minute— identical to the set‐up devised by John Searle in his landmark essay, ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’ (1980). His thought‐experiment, now known as the ‘Chinese Room’, was devised to show that the limitations of machines go beyond those identified in the Aunt Bubbles example. According to the line of thought we were pursuing, the problem with the machine, the thing that kept it from being a genuine thinker, was the fact that it relied on the wrong kind of program: it used a ‘stupid’ look‐up algorithm instead of a program that exploited the compositional structure of the remarks it was manipulating. But according to Searle, the problem is the fact that the machine is running a program, period. A program is a set of instructions for the manipulation of symbols. Crucially, the instructions treat the symbols as mere formal objects, things that can be identified purely by their shapes. As far as the instructions go, the symbols may mean anything, or nothing. Consequently, the instructions can be followed by someone—or something—who has no idea whatsoever what the symbols mean. (p. 621)

Much earlier we noted that thoughts have contents, that they represent or are about things, that they possess the property philosophers call intentionality. But of course thoughts are not the only things that can represent. Ordinary objects can stand for things, as a red light stands for the command ‘stop’, and gestures can too, as a thumbs‐up gesture is a symbol of approval. And, of course, words stand for things. But there's a difference. Objects, gestures, and words, it appears, derive their intentional contents, their meanings, from the thoughts they function to express. Because we are thinkers, we can impose meaning on things—light fixtures, gestures, vocalizations, and squiggles on paper—that are otherwise completely insignificant. Because of conventions adopted by our ancestors, the word ‘horse’ is used by some of us to refer to horses; other people, because of different conventions adopted by different ancestors, use the word ‘cheval’ for the same purpose. The intentionality of words and other public symbols is thus a derived intentionality. The source from which this intentionality derives is the original intentionality of thought. Now of course we can impose derived intentionality on anything we like, including the symbols processed by computers. And we do. We speak of computer data as ‘code’, in recognition of the fact that we can construe the strings of ones and zeros that we type into the machines as representations of any information we want to store or utilize. And we can write programs—instructions for the manipulation of code—that mirror in form the thought processes that we want to apply to that information. That's what Turing showed us we could do, remember: devise a mechanical device the operation of which mirrors any thought process that can be carried out in a step‐by‐step way. But to say that the mirroring is formal is to say that the operations are sensitive only to the formal Page 15 of 27

Thinking properties of the symbols, that they would work the same way no matter what the symbols mean. Indeed, as far as the operation of the machine is concerned, the symbols mean nothing at all, just as the Chinese symbols manipulated by our Aunt Bubbles operator mean nothing at all to her. Do these considerations show, as Searle contends, that thinking cannot be computation? Defenders of the computational account have many criticisms of the Chinese Room example. To begin with, consider the program the Aunt Bubbles operator is following. Lack of systematicity was enough to rule out the original Aunt Bubbles machine as a genuine thinker; mightn't that defect be the problem in the new case as well? Moreover, we know that no actual speaker of Chinese could be following the program that the original machine follows, because there is not enough space in a human head to store the needed data, nor enough time in a human life to effect the required searches. If speaking Chinese involves, as the computationalist assumes, running a program, that program is very different from the one run by the Aunt Bubbles machine. What happens if we give that very program to our friend in the Chinese Room? This is the wrinkle that I referred to above. Go ahead, says Searle, give the person in the Chinese Room whatever set of instructions you like, including whatever program it is you think characterizes the competence of a Chinese speaker. The result, he contends, will be the same. The instructions will still always treat the words of Chinese as meaningless squiggles; the operator will always be able to follow them successfully (p. 622) without understanding a thing. Indeed, Searle adds, we can even imagine that the operator memorizes the program, so that her instructions are completely internalized, as is, presumably, the program ‘running’ in the head of a Chinese speaker. The intuition persists: our operator does not understand Chinese. Another response made by defenders of the computational model concerns the way in which the operator in the Chinese room interacts with the outside world—or, rather, the way in which she does not interact with the outside world. Actual thinkers can gather information about the external world by means of their various sense organs, and can affect that world by moving their limbs. It's this causal interaction with the external world that enables a thinker to attach meaning to the symbols it manipulates in thought. But once again Searle is happy to modify the set‐up to remedy the claimed deficiencies. Give the operator a camera, through which she can see the inputs being delivered, and let the symbols she outputs be wired up so as to cause movements in artificial limbs. This is analogous to attaching a computer to a robot, says Searle, and makes no difference at all to the crucial intuition. We would have, in this case, a monolingual English speaker causing the movements of a robot in ways that are appropriate (we may assume) to sentences in Chinese, but not via an understanding of the Chinese characters. But if Searle is right, that nothing we can add to the operator's situation will make the manipulated symbols come alive with meaning, where does intentionality come from? What makes it the case that thoughts represent things outside themselves? Searle's answer to this question is notoriously obscure. Intentionality, he says, is a biological Page 16 of 27

Thinking product of the human brain. In saying this, he insists that he is not ruling out the possibility of an artificial brain; that is, one made of non‐biological materials. Such a ‘brain’, he says, could even be made out of electronics, provided only that it possesses the same causal powers as a human brain (1980, 1992). But it's difficult to understand what Searle has in mind. The brain has many causal dispositions; an artificial brain would presumably need to possess only some of these. Which causal powers would be the ones essential to the ‘production’ of intentionality, and which ones could the designer of an artificial brain neglect? In the case of artificial hearts, it is the causal powers that have to do with the heart's function that we want preserved. Those that have to do with its reaction to, say, serum cholesterol are not properties that we want preserved; indeed, they're ones we'll take care to avoid duplicating. So it's presumably those properties of the brain relevant to the function of thinking that are the important ones. But if we use functional criteria to single out those ‘causal powers’ of the brain that are crucial for intentionality, then it's not clear how Searle's view differs from the functionalist's after all.14 But in any case there is a point about the Chinese Room thought‐experiment that we are neglecting, one that's key to understanding how thinking might be computation after all. Consider the fact that while the Chinese Room operator does not understand the Chinese symbols she is manipulating, she does understand something; namely, the English instructions. This suggests that the Chinese Room paradigm (p. 623) may not provide a fair test of the computationalist's hypothesis. Since the operator's relation to the English instructions she understands is obviously functionally different from her relationship to the Chinese symbols she does not understand, it's open to the computationalist to say that the thought‐experiment does not capture the relevant relationships between operator and language—that whatever program the operator is running, it is not the ‘program’ that human beings ‘run’ in the course of understanding language. While we're at it, let's look back at the Aunt Bubbles machine. Here again, on a second look, we have some reason to revise our original assessment of the situation. For the machine to carry out the ‘stupid’ operations associated with the look‐up table, operations, that is, that require no understanding whatsoever of the English strings it is receiving as input or producing as output, it must be running some program that enables it to respond appropriately—non‐stupidly—to the symbols in which the program is written. We have already encountered the concept of a ‘machine language’. This is the code in which the most basic computer commands are written; it's the symbol system that directly triggers changes of states in the computer. Perhaps if we could get clearer on what it is for the machine to figuratively understand its own machine language, we could get an idea what it is, in computational terms, for the Chinese Room operator to really understand her instructions. When we figure that out, perhaps we'll be able to characterize the difference, in computational terms, between the operator's relationship to the English instructions and her relationship to the Chinese characters that she does not understand.

Page 17 of 27

Thinking Let's pretend that the Aunt Bubbles machine not only stores an enormous list of conversations expressed in English, but that its machine language is a simplified form of English.15 In that case, we could give the machine the following instruction: ‘If FIND “FIND” THEN SAY “OK” ’. There are two occurrences of the English word ‘FIND’ in this command, but they differ importantly in the effects they will produce in the computer. The first ‘FIND’ will cause the machine to initiate a sequence of state changes that constitute—because of the programmer's cleverness—a search routine. The second ‘FIND’, however, because it is enclosed in quotation marks, will not instigate such a sequence. The computer's program will treat this occurrence of the symbol as a mere object, and not as the expression of a command. That's the effect of the quotation marks: they cordon off the symbol and present it to the computer as a meaningless, inert shape. The fact that the shape is the same as the shape of the symbol that, when unquoted, prompts the computer to begin a search is invisible to the computer, and irrelevant to its operation. The machine's program uses the symbol in one case, and merely mentions it in the second. Functionally speaking, we can mark this distinction by saying that the unquoted symbol possesses, for the machine, a conceptual role, a distinctive pattern of causal relations to the computer's internal states, to its other potential inputs and outputs, and, in particular, to the other symbols that constitute the machine's machine (p. 624) language. The quoted symbol, on the other hand, has no such distinctive causal profile (although the quotation marks themselves do). This, then, is the difference between the Aunt Bubbles machine's relation to the symbols that compose its instructions and its relation to the symbols that it is instructed to manipulate: the former, but not the latter, have a conceptual role in the machine's functional architecture. It can use the symbols that compose its instructions, but it cannot use the symbols that are merely mentioned in those instructions. The same distinction can be drawn, arguably, in the case of the Chinese Room. The symbols that compose the operator's instructions (whether written down or vocalized to her) must be integrated into the operator's overall psychology in much the same way that the ‘FIND’ symbol is integrated into our machine's internal functioning in order for her to understand them. The fact that the Chinese symbols are merely mentioned, and thus the fact that they have no conceptual role within the operator's psychology, is sufficient to explain why she does not understand them. But is conceptual role all there is to meaningfulness? To put the question another way, must we now say that the Aunt Bubbles machine really understands its instructions? We do not. For there is a difference between the kind of conceptual role possessed by symbols in a machine's machine language and the kind possessed by mental representations in the minds of real thinkers. The difference has to do with the way in which the symbols are connected—or not connected—to states of affairs in the external world. In the ‘conceptual economy’ of a mere computer the internal relations among the internal states of the machine are independent of events occurring in the external world. All of these states are interconnected with the inputs and outputs the machine receives,

Page 18 of 27

Thinking but which inputs the machine receives, and the effects of the outputs the machine produces, are unrelated to anything but the intentions and interests of the person using the machine. In contrast, the inputs that a genuine thinker receives are information‐bearing: they co‐ vary reliably with specific external states of affairs. Similarly, the outputs produced by a genuine thinker—typically, actions of one sort or another—have consequences in the external world. These patterns exist independently of the will or intentions of any thinker; they are matters of natural law. Because the conceptual roles of symbols in the internal representational system of a genuine thinker necessarily involve a coordination of these ‘naturally’ meaningful inputs and these consequential outputs, the ‘interpretation’ of the symbols will be naturally constrained. I can impose whatever interpretation I want on the symbols on which a computer is operating, treating the one and the same configurational state, perhaps, as a position in a chess game on one day and a depiction of erosion in Iceland the next. In so far as such a state has a meaning at all, it is a meaning that derives from my intentions to use it in a certain way. I am not similarly at liberty with respect to the meanings of my mental symbols. DOG will mean ‘dogs’ in my psychological economy just in case the occurrence of that symbol is connected in lawful ways, via its connections with information‐bearing input states and consequential output states, to environmental (p. 625) circumstances involving dogs.16 The intentionality, or meaningfulness, of my mental symbols thus originates in the non‐intentional, natural world. To say that the mental symbols deployed by real thinkers possess original intentionality is not to say that the intentional contents of the symbols affect the operations of the computational device that realizes the thinker's mind. Fodor has argued that computationalism is committed to a principle he calls methodological solipsism: the principle that computational mechanisms are sensitive only to intrinsic, formal features of the symbols they manipulate, and a fortiori not to the relational properties that determine their meanings.17 But methodological solipsism, Fodor insists, does not entail that the manipulated symbols have no meanings. He charges that Searle makes exactly this erroneous inference, conflating formal operations on symbols with operations on formal symbols. To say that the operations that a computer (or, as computationalism would have it, a brain) performs are formal is to say that the causally relevant features of the representations over which the operations are defined are formal features. This is just the doctrine of methodological solipsism, and is indeed something to which computationalism is committed. But it is no part of computationalism to say that the symbols on which the mental operations work are formal symbols; that is, symbols devoid of meaning (Fodor 1991). Here then, finally, is a characterization of thinking: thinking is the operation of structure‐ sensitive processes defined over the compositional structures of symbols possessing original intentionality. It falls out from this characterization that thinking is something that a purely physical entity can do, but not something that only a biological brain can do.

Page 19 of 27

Thinking I will leave matters here. In doing so, I acknowledge that I leave many objections unanswered, and many questions unaddressed. In particular, I have said nothing about the relationship between thinking and consciousness, a lacuna many philosophers— including both Descartes and Searle!—will find unforgivable. Let me just assert—without argument, and in the face of many contemporary defences of his view—that Descartes's fundamental mistakes about the capacities of matter carry over, and call into question his arguments for the connection between thinking and consciousness. I do not mean to cast stones at Descartes, however. My own characterization of thinking was developed on the basis of philosophical argument (p. 626) and low‐level empirical observation—the very kind of armchair theorizing that Descartes undertook in his own Meditations. Still, I believe that my account comports nicely with our emerging scientific understanding of the mind, with work in cognitive psychology, linguistics, ethology, information sciences, and neuroscience. Just as Descartes would have expected.

APPENDIX: Empiricism and Connectionism

Page 20 of 27

Thinking As I remarked earlier, the conception of thought I've been presuming is the Cartesian, rationalist conception, which treats inference as the paradigm mental process. But it must be acknowledged that much of our mental life does not fit this conception. In particular, a good portion of our thinking involves non‐rational trains of thought. For example, I hear news on the radio of the Iowa caucuses. Thinking of Iowa makes me think of my favourite musical, The Music Man, which is set in Iowa. The phrase ‘music man’ makes me think of the phrase ‘confidence man’, which reminds me of a magazine article I read about confidence men in the mid‐nineteenth century, which makes me think of the bill sitting next to the magazine that I need to pay, which reminds me that paying the bill will trigger an overdraft. In such cases as this the thoughts composing the train of thought are not bound by logical relations among the thought contents, but rather by loose relations of some kind of similarity. They are bound by association. Against Descartes and other rationalist theorists, the British empiricists—John Locke, George Berkeley, David Hume in the eighteenth century and John Stuart Mill in the nineteenth—held that all thinking, fundamentally, had this character. In their theories they sought to characterize the principles that explained why certain ideas would be associated with others, principles like resemblance (Iowa caucuses and the Iowa setting, ‘music man’ and ‘confidence man’), contiguity (the magazine and the bill), and causation (bill paying and overdrafts). Not only did the empiricists think that associations bound thoughts together in the mind, they held that association bound thoughts to their contents. According to these philosophers, individual ideas got their contents through association with things in the outside world. My idea of a dog was a dog‐idea, an idea that meant ‘dog’, because it was an idea of the type that was regularly occasioned in my mind by perceptions of dogs. (This view about the origin of semantic content represents an unusual point of convergence between empiricists and contemporary rationalists like Fodor.) Because of this idea–world connection, relations like similarity and contiguity among objects in the world would be tracked by the ideas thinkers associated with them. In this way, they thought, we get an account not only of thinking, but of knowledge. Properties that are frequently co‐instantiated, and event types that are (p. 627) ‘constantly conjoined’ (Hume's phrase) in our experience, and hence in nature, will be mirrored by strongly associated ideas in our minds. Associative processes do seem to be part of our mental life. Memory, for example, appears to be organized in accordance with the sorts of principles posited by the empiricists. And it's clear that the content of our stereotypes—mental templates that we rely on for ‘quick and dirty’ conclusions—are built out of experience in much the way the empiricists held that we constructed general ideas from particular experiences. But empiricism fails as a general account of thinking in offering no account at all of the kinds of thought processes the rationalists focused on; that is, rational processes. From the thoughts ‘Clinton accepts money from big insurance companies’ and ‘No one who accepts money from big insurance companies will implement real health‐care reform’ we Page 21 of 27

Thinking might infer ‘Clinton will not implement real health‐care reform’. Trains of thought such as these cannot be explained just by association. The last thought certainly is similar enough to each of the preceding thoughts for it to have been triggered by association with them— that's not the problem. The problem is that there are any number of different thoughts that could be equally strongly associated with the previous two, including the negation of the last thought: ‘Clinton will implement real health‐care reform’. The relation of association simply places no constraints on the kinds of thoughts that can be associated with each other. (Since contiguity is one of the relations that gives rise to association, we can easily forge an association between any two thoughts whatsoever, just by juxtaposition.) Logic, however, does impose constraints; not just any thought follows—in the logical sense—from any other. The inability of empiricist models to account for logical inference is connected with the empiricists' failure to recognize the existence, or at least the importance, of the compositional structure of thought. Most importantly, they failed to apprehend what Frege noticed—that the component parts of thought differ in character from each other. This meant that they had no materials with which to build conceptual structure other than appending and abstracting, and those are not enough. Just as the von Neumann machine provides a natural model for the rationalistic conception of thought, a different kind of computer, called a connectionist network, offers a way of realizing the empiricist conception. A connectionist network consists in layers of interconnected nodes. Each node can send signals to any node in the upper layer to which it is connected. Every node has a firing threshold, which means that the node will fire when the total strength of the signal reaching it (got by adding the strengths of all the signals) reaches that threshold. Connection strengths can change over time, partly as a function of the frequency with which a connected node fires. The first layer of nodes is called the ‘input layer’, and the last is called the ‘output layer’. Connection strengths between nodes can change in response to the frequency and patterns of firings from the nodes at the level below. If and when a network reaches the point at which new inputs fail to produce any change in connection strengths, the network is said to ‘settle’. (p. 628)

Connectionist networks are good at integrating and propagating information, and at extracting patterns—at performing, in other words, exactly the kinds of mental operations empiricists took to be constitutive of mental life. The following example, though unrealistically simple, should give an idea how this might work. Imagine a network with an input layer in which each node is selectively sensitive to the instantiation of some sensory quality. The network can gain ‘experience’ through activation of its input nodes by signals sent from the relevant sense receptors. As the network's experience accrues, it will begin to become sensitive to patterns of co‐occurring sensory qualities, and will eventually begin to produce a distinctive output whenever such a pattern occurs. These

Page 22 of 27

Thinking outputs can then be thought of as concepts, constructed by the association of and abstraction from primitive sensory ideas. Connectionist networks are proving to be valuable as models of those aspects of thought that conform to empiricist principles: memory, some kinds of perceptual processing, and some kinds of associative learning. Many philosophers and cognitive scientists, especially those who are opposed to the computational/representational model of mind promoted in this chapter, contend that connectionism can offer a comprehensive account of thought (see Rumelhart and McClelland 1986; Smolensky 1988; Ramsey, Stich, and Garon 1991). But some philosophers contend that these networks are inherently unable to model those kinds of thought that depend upon the exploitation of compositional structure (Fodor and Pylyshyn 1988; Fodor and McLaughlin 1990; McLaughlin 1993).

References Antony, L. (1997), ‘Feeling Fine About the Mind’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57: 1–8. Block, N. (1978), ‘Troubles With Functionalism’, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9: 261–325. —— (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 615–78. —— (1995), ‘The Computer Model of Mind’, in D. N. Osherson and E. E. Smith (eds.), An Invitation to Cognitive Science, iii: Thinking (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 247–89. Brentano, F. (1874/1973), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. L. McAlister, trans. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Burge, T. (1986), ‘Individualism and Psychology’, Philosophical Review, 95: 3–45. Carey, S., and Spelke, E. (1994), ‘Knowledge Acquisition: Enrichment or Conceptual Change?’, in S. Carey and R. Gelman (eds.), The Epigenesis of Mind: Essays in Biology and Cognition (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 257–91. Cheney, D. L., and Seyfarth, R. M. (1990), How Monkeys See the World: Inside the Mind of Another Species (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). Chomsky, N. (1975), Reflections on Language (New York: Pantheon). Crane, T. (2001), Elements of Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Descartes, R. (1637), Discourse on Method, trans. I. Johnston, , accessed 2008. (p. 629)

Page 23 of 27

Thinking —— (1641/1901), Meditation VI, sect. 9, in Meditations on First Philosophy, trans. John Veitch , accessed 2008. Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Egan, F. (1991), ‘Must Psychology Be Individualistic?’, Philosophical Review, 100: 179– 203. Evans, G. (1982), Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1991), ‘Yin and Yang in the Chinese Room’, in D. Rosenthal (ed.), The Nature of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 524–5. —— (2007), ‘The Revenge of the Given’, in B. P. McLaughlin and J. D. Cohen (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 105–16. Fodor, J., and McLaughlin, B. (1990), ‘Connectionism and the Problem of Systematicity: Why Smolensky's Solution Doesn't Work’, Cognition, 35: 183–205. Fodor, J., and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988), ‘Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critique’, Cognition, 28: 3–71. Frege, G. (1892/1970), ‘Concept and Object’, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. and trans. P. Geach and M. Black (Oxford: Blackwell), 42– 55. Gallistel, C. R. (1990), The Organization of Learning (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Harman, G. (1982), ‘Conceptual Role Semantics’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 28: 242–56. Harnish, R. M. (2002), Minds, Brains, Computers: An Historical Introduction to the Foundations of Cognitive Science (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Heil, J., and Mele, A. R. (1993) (eds.), Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Locke, J. (1690/1975), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). McLaughlin, B. (1993), ‘The Connectionism/Classicism Battle to Win Souls’, Philosophical Studies, 71: 163–90.

Page 24 of 27

Thinking Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Putnam, H. (1960), ‘Minds and Machines’, in S. Hook (ed.), Dimensions of Mind (New York: New York University Press), 148–79. —— (1967a), ‘The Mental Life of Some Machines’, in H. N. Castaneda (ed.), Intentionality, Minds and Perception (Detroit, Mich.: Wayne State University Press), 177–200. —— (1967b), ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merrill (eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Pittsburgh University Press), 37–48. Ramsey, W., Stich, S., and Garon, J. (1991), ‘Connectionism, Eliminativism and the Future of Folk Psychology’, in W. Ramsey, D. Rumelhart, and S. Stich (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 199–228. Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., and the PDP Research Group (1986), Parallel Distributed Processing, i–ii (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Searle, J. (1980), ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’, Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 3: 417– 24. —— (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Smolensky, P. (1988), ‘On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism’, Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 11: 1–23. (p. 630)

Turing, A. M. (1937), ‘Computability and λ‐definability’, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 2: 153–64. —— (1950), ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’, Mind, 59: 433–60. Weizenbaum, J. (1976), Computer Power and Human Reason (San Francisco, Calif.: Freeman).

Notes: (1) See Ch. 3 above for a discussion of substance dualism. (2) I'll use capitals when I'm indicating thoughts or concepts. (3) Which is, of course, not to say that I cannot distinguish Hershey's‐kiss‐chocolate from other kinds of chocolate, like for instance Ghirardelli‐chocolate. I'm no philistine. (4) It's an unfortunate fact, and the source of much confusion, that this term is homophonic with Brentano's term ‘intentionality’, especially since there's almost complete overlap between the things that are intentional, and the things that are

Page 25 of 27

Thinking intensional. For a comprehensive discussion of the meanings of these terms, and the connections between them, see Crane (2001). (5) Several of the chapters in this volume address the issue of whether qualitative mental states such as sensations have intentional contents, so I will not consider it here. (6) Frege may have been the first philosopher to recognize this fact, or at least the first to understand its crucial contribution to the compositionality of thought (1892/1970). (7) For a detailed history of the development of computation and its implications for the study of the mind see Harnish (2002). (8) There are different varieties of functionalism; one variety, called ‘analytical functionalism’ makes no appeal to a machine analogy. For discussion see Block (1978). (9) Turing's one doubt about this came, bizarrely, from his reading of the evidence for extra‐sensory perception, which he found, ‘at least for telepathy’ to be ‘overwhelming’ (see Turing 1950: 453–4). (10) Turing's actual set‐up is more complicated, but in ways that add nothing to the structure of the experiment (see Turing 1950: 433–4). (11) For a complete description of the machine, with some helpful illustrations of its operation, see Block (1995: esp. 381–4). (12) To visit ELIZA yourself, just google ‘Eliza computer therapist’ and go to any of the dozens of sites that come up. (13) Depending on the amount of time we want to allow the interrogation to run, it might become physically impossible—we could quickly get to the point where the number of characters needed to write the program would be larger than the number of electrons in the universe. (14) For fuller development of this criticism of Searle's account of intentionality see Antony (1997). (15) Actual machine languages are cumbersome and unperspicuous. Since simple commands written in English can be readily translated into machine languages, though, our pretence does no harm. (16) I should point out that while many philosophers of mind agree that original intentionality involves ‘natural meaning’ in some way or other, they disagree violently about precisely what way this is. Fodor thinks that a distinctive pattern of covariance between symbol and world is sufficient, and views the symbol's conceptual role as simply one way that the covariance can be causally sustained (1987). Harman (1982) and Block (1986) contend that it's the conceptual role itself that constitutes a symbol's meaning. Both Millikan and Dretske think a symbol's meaning is determined by its function, but

Page 26 of 27

Thinking differ in their accounts of what determines a symbol's function (Millikan 1984; Dretske 1988). (17) Many philosophers disagree that the considerations Fodor cites really count in favour of methodological solipsism, and contend that relational properties, like semantic properties, can be causally efficacious. For discussion see the papers in Heil and Mele (1993). Other philosophers, like Tyler Burge, disagree that mental states can be individuated without reference to their intentional contents (Burge 1986; for discussion see Egan 1991).

Louise Antony

Louise Antony is Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

Page 27 of 27

Language and Thought

Oxford Handbooks Online Language and Thought   John Heil The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0037

Abstract and Keywords This article aims to explore a pattern of reasoning about language and thought that seems to virtually guarantee a distortion of what precisely constitutes thinking. The guiding idea is a simple one, an idea officially embraced by many philosophers, but an idea the implications of which are too easily neglected. The article states a belief in the thesis that something functions as a representation only in so far as it is given a use by a representing agent. This thesis — that representation requires a representing agent — applies in equal measure to non-linguistic ‘pictorial’ and to linguistic representations. Keywords: language and thought, representation, representing agent, linguistic representations, conscious thinking, non-linguistic thoughts

A dog believes his master is at the door. But can he also believe his master will come the day after tomorrow? (Wittgenstein 1953/1968: sect. 174; see also sect. 650)

36.1 Introduction FOR human beings thought and language go hand in hand. But must they? This is most often put as a question concerning the relation of language to thought. Could thought (or ‘genuine thought’) occur in the absence of language (or ‘genuine language’)? Could a creature who lacked a language (a ‘genuine language’) entertain thoughts (‘genuine thoughts’)? Even if thought of a rudimentary sort is possible without language, are there kinds of thought that are thinkable only linguistically, thinkable only in language?

Page 1 of 20

Language and Thought Before venturing into deeper waters, a word on terminology. I take the question whether thought requires language to boil down to the question whether conscious thinking, or some conscious thinking, is inevitably linguistic. And I take ‘linguistic’ thinking to involve thoughts ‘in’ some natural language: English, Portuguese, Urdu. I do not mean to exclude the possibility that some thinking is unconscious or ‘subpersonal’. This is a topic to which I shall return in Section 36.8. Meanwhile, the focus will be on conscious thought and reflection. What of the language of honey bees, computer languages, Ockham's sermo interior, Fodor's ‘language of thought’ (1975)? These raise interesting questions, but I shall set (p. 632) them aside here. The plan is to concentrate on the clear case of natural language and see where this leads. It might then be possible to make sense of honey bees, computing machines, and the language of thought. My broader aim is to explore a pattern of reasoning about language and thought that seems to me virtually to guarantee a distortion of what precisely constitutes thinking. The guiding idea is a simple one, an idea officially embraced by many philosophers, but an idea the implications of which are too easily neglected. What I have in mind is the thesis that something functions as a representation only in so far as it is given a use by a representing agent. Let me hasten to add that I shall employ ‘agent’ in a broad sense that encompasses not merely intelligent human beings but intelligent systems generally. In this sense a digestive system—the ‘brain in the gut’—could constitute an intelligent system. This thesis—that representation requires a representing agent—applies in equal measure to non‐linguistic ‘pictorial’ and to linguistic representations. What I would like to call attention to is a tendency among philosophers to conflate thinking and materials used in thinking. We sometimes think ‘in language’, soliloquizing privately, and sometimes non‐ linguistically. Both sorts of thinking are imagistic: we deploy visual, auditory, olfactory, tactile, and kinaesthetic images. Some of these images are verbal. Verbal imagery can be auditory (as when you ‘hear’ utterances in your head), kinaesthetic (you ‘feel’ yourself uttering sentences), or a combination of these. We can visualize inscriptions, mentally ‘sign’, and ‘feel’ embossed letters or Braille sequences. The point to appreciate is that verbal imagery is no less ‘imagistic’ than imagery of other sorts. It is easy to lose sight of the imagistic character of conscious thought when we start philosophizing about language and thought. We suppose that although there is no problem at all as to how interior utterances could mean what they do, there is a special problem as to how pictorial images could have determinate meanings. Philosophers on all sides agree that meanings are not built into representations. Representations acquire significance by being put to use by representing agents. The apparent fact that pictorial representations lack ‘intrinsic meaning’ is simply a reflection of a wholly unsurprising fact about representations generally. Interior utterances—verbal images—are no less bereft of intrinsic meaning than images of sugarplums.

Page 2 of 20

Language and Thought Regarded in this light, discussions of language and thought take on a new colouring. Thinking—conscious thinking—is not the having or entertaining of images, verbal or otherwise. Thinking is a matter of an agent's using such images, putting them to work. And whatever it is to put images to work, it is not solely a matter of entertaining further images. Nor is thinking something occurring behind the scenes when you deploy representations: it is the deployment of those representations—in your head or otherwise. Your thinking the cat is on the mat might be a matter of your saying to yourself ‘the cat is on the mat’ or it might involve your conjuring a visual image of a cat on a mat. In either case, however, you do not do two things: (1) entertain an image; (2) think. Thinking occurs in your deploying the image. This point about use was made forcefully by Wittgenstein, but it has been endorsed by philosophers as (p. 633) different as Locke and Andy Clark. Although philosophers routinely pay lip service to the idea, its implications have not been widely appreciated. Or so it seems.

36.2 Davidson on Higher‐order Thought Philosophers have sometimes argued that higher‐order thoughts—thoughts about thoughts—are thinkable only by creatures capable of language. Donald Davidson goes further, contending that a capacity for thought per se requires a capacity for higher‐order thought (see Davidson 1975, 1982; Heil 1992: ch. 6). This thesis, coupled with the contention that higher‐order thought requires a capacity for language, implies that only creatures possessing a language harbour genuine thoughts. Davidson puts it this way: only a creature capable of interpreting (and so ascribing thoughts to) another creature is capable of any thoughts at all. Interpretation—which includes the mapping of sentences onto sentences—is impossible in the absence of language, however; so a creature lacking a language—a mute creature—is perforce incapable of thought. This is not an argument but the statement of a theory for which Davidson supplies elaborate support. I think it best to read Davidson not as denying that mute creatures are capable of representing their surroundings mentally and acting on those representations, but as contending that there is a stark discontinuity between representations deployed by such creatures and the kinds of representation found in agents equipped for higher‐order representation (see Bennett 1964). This is why, according to Davidson, ascriptions of beliefs, desires, and intentions to mute creatures are at best figurative and at worst flatly misleading. You can see what Davidson is driving at by noting that ascriptions of propositional attitudes to mute creatures are ‘semantically transparent’. Spot barks at an intruder lurking beneath the window. Which of the following is true: (1) Spot believes there is an intruder lurking beneath the window.

Page 3 of 20

Language and Thought (2) Spot believes there is someone beneath the window. (3) Spot believes there is a noise beneath the window. (4) Spot believes there is a noise there. Such questions seem puzzling, according to Davidson, not because we lack ready access to Spot's inner life but because, so long as Spot remains incapable of expressing his inner state linguistically, there is no fact of the matter as to which of these characterizations is correct. Genuine belief ascription is ‘semantically opaque’. Substitution of co‐referring terms in such ascriptions can alter their truth‐value. The belief that there is an intruder beneath the window differs from the belief that there is someone beneath the window. Thoughts about particular objects or states of affairs are thoughts about objects or states of affairs under some description. Attributions of states of mind to Spot, in contrast, identify those states of mind wholly by reference (p. 634) to objects on which they are directed. Because Spot lacks a language, there is no question of his representing a given object, the intruder, say, under one description rather than another.1

Davidson encapsulates all this in a slogan: only a creature possessing the concept of belief could have beliefs. A creature could be furry without possessing the concept of being furry; a creature could fly without possessing the concept of flight. Why should the mere possession of beliefs require possession of the belief concept? Davidson is thinking about it this way. Beliefs can be true or false. Possession of the concept of belief includes possession of a conception of something—a representation— that purports to fit the facts but could fail to do so. This is the concept of a truth bearer. Such a concept could be deployed only by a creature in a position to ascribe beliefs. Why? Consider your place in the world. As you move through the world, you come to represent your surroundings in various ways. In so far as you are observant, changes in your surroundings will be mirrored by changes in your representations of those surroundings. You represent the water in a pond as deep. You subsequently step into the pond and discover it is shallow. You now represent the pond as shallow. None of this requires you to distinguish what you believe to be the case from what is the case. A slightly more tendentious way to put this point is to note that a concept of truth comes into play only when you are in a position to distinguish truth bearers—representational states with definite, truth‐evaluable contents—from truth makers.2 This amounts to the idea that your possession of a truth concept requires possession of a capacity to represent representations and their contents—requires, that is, that you be capable of higher‐order representation. What is striking about Davidson's argument is his contention that your deploying representations with definite contents requires your possessing a truth concept, hence (if the reasoning above is sound) your being in a position to comprehend higher‐order representations. This is something you do when you ascribe beliefs to others. You invoke higher‐order representations in reflecting on your own beliefs, but Davidson's idea seems to be that in the absence of an opportunity to ascribe representational states of mind to others agents are in no position to ascribe such states of mind to themselves.3

Page 4 of 20

Language and Thought Given just the world and your experiences of it, you have no use for a concept of representation, no grounds for a distinction between the world as it is and the world as you represent it as being. These are deep waters, but pretend for the moment that something like this is right: the concept of representation finds purchase only when you are in a (p. 635) position to ascribe representational states to others. Once the concept takes hold, you are in a position to extend it to your own case. Indeed, first‐ and third‐person recognition go hand in hand.4 What has any of this to do with our having beliefs, ordinary first‐order representations of states of affairs? Here the argument becomes, if anything, even denser. Imagine a solitary creature who represents the world in particular ways. The creature's representations are dynamic: they ‘update’, reflecting changes in what the creature encounters. What are we to say about the contents of such a creature's representational states of mind? Return to Spot's belief about an intruder outside the window. We saw that there are many ways to characterize the content of this belief. Davidson would say that there is no reason to prefer any of these characterizations to any other: there is no fact of the matter as to how the creature represents its world. We can grant that the creature is in a state that changes in ways that reflect changes in the world, and we can grant that the creature's behaviour is guided by this state, without supposing that the state has any definite content. It's ‘content’, such as it is, can be described indifferently so long as it includes the pertinent object. Because the creature has no use for distinctions of the sort appearing in (1)–(4), the distinctions play no role in the creature's mental life. Matters look different when higher‐order representations appear on the scene. In representing a representation, we represent it, of necessity, as a representation possessing a definite content. What we have is a package deal: a creature capable of representing representations is a creature capable of ascribing representations—to other creatures and to itself—with definite contents, contents that could vary without the objects on which they are directed varying. And just as self‐reflection is born of reflection on others, so contents—definite contents—of first‐order representational states of mind are born of higher‐order representations of those states of mind. Suppose this were right, or at least that it is not obviously wrong. The final move is to tie a capacity for language to the capacity for higher‐order representation. Let us grant that an agent's entertaining higher‐order representations requires that the agent be in a position to ascribe representations with definite contents to other agents who are themselves ascribers. How is this to be brought off, Davidson asks, without the kind of definiteness we find in language? Sentences (1)–(4) differ, and so are apt for the ascription of distinct representational states, states possessing determinate contents. The idea is that only a linguistic representation could be a representation of a representational state with a determinate content.

Page 5 of 20

Language and Thought There you have it. The possession of representational states with determinate contents requires a capacity for higher‐order representation. Higher‐order representation requires possession of a language. So the possession of states with definite contents requires possession of a language. You are likely to remain unmoved by all this, but the aim is not to convince you of Davidson's view, only to convince you that the view is not entirely mad. Many (p. 636) philosophers have been attracted to the idea that there is something special about the capacity for higher‐order representation and to the thesis that a capacity for higher‐order representation requires a capacity for language. Philosophers have been attracted to such views for reasons that appear to have nothing to do with Davidson's arguments. What is important here is that Davidson does make explicit one line of reasoning to a popular, but unevenly defended, conclusion. I shall argue that all this is off the mark, but before going on the offensive it will be useful to look at another, independent line of argument that appeals to higher‐order thoughts en route to the conclusion that certain prominent species of thought must be linguistic in character.

36.3 Bermúdez's Argument The line of argument I have in mind is advanced by José Bermúdez (2003) in the course of an illuminating examination of ‘thinking without words’. Bermúdez, unlike Davidson, accepts the idea that mute creatures are capable of entertaining a variety of interesting and sophisticated thoughts about actual and even non‐actual, merely possible, states of affairs. He draws the line, however, at second‐ (or, more generally, higher‐) order thoughts. Bermúdez's contention is that thoughts on which higher‐order thoughts are directed must themselves be linguistic. If only creatures who deploy a language are capable of linguistic thoughts, only linguistically endowed creatures are capable of higher‐order thought. To see how Bermúdez's argument works, consider our capacity for what Andy Clark calls ‘second‐order cognitive dynamics’: Perhaps it is public language which is responsible for a complex of rather distinctive features of human thought viz, our ability to display second order cognitive dynamics. By second order cognitive dynamics I mean a cluster of powerful capacities involving self‐evaluation, self‐criticism and finely honed remedial responses. Examples would include: recognizing a flaw in our own plan or argument, and dedicating further cognitive efforts to fixing it; reflecting on the unreliability of our own initial judgements in certain types of situations and proceeding with special caution as a result; coming to see why we reached a particular conclusion by appreciating the logical transitions in our own thought; Page 6 of 20

Language and Thought thinking about the conditions under which we think best and trying to bring them about. The list could be continued, but the pattern should be clear. In all these cases, we are effectively thinking about our own cognitive profiles or about specific thoughts. (Clark 1998: 177) The characteristically human capacity for complex thoughts about thoughts could thus be tied to our capacity for language. This, according to Clark, is due not to the distinctiveness of the contents of linguistic thoughts but to the way they are embodied: as mental utterances or inscriptions of sentences. Imagine a particular state of affairs, the cat's being on the mat. This state of affairs might be represented pictorially or sententially. Your thought about the cat's being on the mat could take the form of (p. 637) an image of a cat on a mat or an interior utterance of a sentence ‘The cat is on the mat’. In either case, I have suggested, you make use of imagery: the ‘vehicle’ of your thought might be a visual image of a cat on a mat or a verbal image—what Bermúdez calls an ‘imaged sentence’ (2003: 160).

Against this background you can see Bermúdez's argument proceeding in two stages. First, he notes that thoughts on which second‐order thoughts are directed (‘target thoughts’) ‘must be at the personal level’ (2003: 159); they must be kinds of thought concerning which we could be conscious. This apparently uncontroversial proviso is meant to set to one side Fodor's language of thought, sentences of which are not consciously available, hence evidently unsuitable as ‘targets’ for higher‐order thoughts. The language of thought aside, might there be kinds of thought possible only for creatures possessing a natural language? Trivially, thoughts about linguistic representations (that include a grasp of the significance of those representations) are possible only for creatures possessing a language.5 The interesting question is whether there might be other kinds of thought that would require linguistic competence. Bermúdez's contention is that there are. Clark's ‘second‐order cognitive dynamics’ would be possible only for creatures linguistically endowed. This is stronger than the thesis defended by Clark. Clark argues that it is a contingent fact about human beings that much of our reasoning involves consideration of thoughts expressed sententially. Bermúdez, in contrast, holds that certain kinds of thought are flatly impossible in the absence of language: There are certain types of problem that we solve by manipulating mental images and exercising the visual imagination. And we are, of course, conscious of bodily sensations, emotional feelings, and other such qualitative states (although these are not properly described as types of thinking at all). But we are not, I think, ever conscious of propositional thoughts that do not have linguistic vehicles. (2003: 160)

Page 7 of 20

Language and Thought Next Bermúdez advances an ‘argument by elimination’ to the conclusion that in the case of such thoughts ‘the only available vehicles at the personal level are public language sentences’ (2003: 159). Representational ‘vehicles’ can be of two sorts. On the one hand, ‘representation might be secured symbolically through the complex symbols of a natural language’. In this case ‘a thought would be represented … through its linguistic expression and would appear as an object of thought qua linguistic entity’. On the other hand, ‘representation might be secured in an analogue manner, through some kind of pictorial model’ in which ‘the vehicle of thought is a pictorial representation of the state of affairs being thought about’ (2003: 160).

Although first‐order thoughts can be ‘vehicled’ pictorially, such thoughts, Bermúdez contends, cannot serve as objects of second‐order thoughts. This is a surprising claim, given that this is exactly what anyone does who reads Bermúdez's (p. 638) colourful accounts of non‐linguistic thoughts.6 Consider your own case. In the right circumstances you can entertain a ‘pictorial’ thought of the cat's being on the mat and you can reflect— as you are now reflecting—on that thought. Bermúdez is after bigger game, however. Representation, he contends, evidently requires the holding of a ‘structural isomorphism’ between representation and represented state of affairs. There are, however, at least two senses in which a representation could be said to share a structure with what it represents. In the weak sense there is structure whenever a structural isomorphism can be identified between the vehicle and what it represents. In the strong sense … structure requires the existence of basic representational units combined according to independently identifiable combinatorial rules. Natural‐language sentences … are clearly structured in the strong sense, whereas mental maps/ models possess structure only in the weak sense. (Bermúdez 2003: 161) Non‐sentential representations—‘mental maps and models’—represent what they represent by virtue of ‘some combination of isomorphic resemblance and exemplification holding between the model/map as a whole and the represented state of affairs as a whole’ (Bermúdez 2003: 161). Bermúdez notes that it is easy to doubt that isomorphism could suffice for representation, but the real problem, he thinks, is in seeing how ‘analogue’ representations could serve as targets for particular kinds of higher‐order thought:

Second‐order cognitive dynamics involves a sensitivity to inferential relations between thoughts, and we do not yet have an understanding of how images can be inferentially connected to each other. The problem … derives from the intimate relation between inference and structure … There is a sense in which mental models and maps are structured, since they contain elements that can feature in further mental models/maps. Nevertheless, they do not seem to be structured in the right sort of way to permit the reflexive type of second‐order cognitive dynamics under discussion. (Bermúdez 2003: 161)

Page 8 of 20

Language and Thought Consider cognitive ‘maps’ of the sort discussed by David Braddon‐Mitchell and Frank Jackson (1996) and consider a ‘canonical example of second‐order cognitive dynamics’: recognizing ‘the evidential basis for a particular belief and then evaluating the inferential transition made on that basis’ (Bermúdez 2003: 161).

It is perfectly easy to see how there could be some very basic forms of inferential transition between maps. Such transitions might be modeled on broadly associationist lines, and it is the possibility of such transitions that enables maps to serve as guides to action. What is not possible, however, is for such transitions to be understood and evaluated in terms of either deductive validity or probabilistic support. (Bermúdez 2003: 162) Such evaluations require the interpretation of the maps ‘in broadly propositional terms’. Thus, ‘we must interpret one map as expressing one proposition and the second as representing a further proposition, and then evaluate the inferential relations … between these two propositions’. The problem is that ‘our only understanding of how to do this rests on the two propositions being linguistically formulated’ (Bermúdez 2003: 162). (p. 639)

What of ‘mental models’ (see e.g. Craik 1967; Johnson‐Laird 1983, 1999; Rips 1994)? Mental models have been proposed as alternatives to ‘syntactic’ models in accounts of reasoning. The idea is that given an argument from premises to conclusion we ‘construct’ models of the premises and judge that the conclusion is implied when the conclusion is true in each of these models. Mental models, Bermúdez argues, are constructed on the basis of ‘sententially encoded propositions’. The theory construes … transactions between sententially encoded propositions as taking place in virtue of relations between analogue representations of the states of affairs portrayed in those sententially encoded propositions (as opposed to formal relations holding between the syntactic structures of the relevant sentences). (Bermúdez 2003: 163) In this regard,

mental models theory offers a particular way of developing the sentential conception, not of supplanting it. Mental models are not the vehicles of inference but rather, as their name suggests, models of those inferences. (Bermúdez 2003: 163) Bermúdez's contention is not that agents do not use mental maps and models, nor that agents cannot think about such things.

Page 9 of 20

Language and Thought The point is that we cannot use mental maps or mental models for thinking about thoughts in the manner demanded by second‐order cognitive dynamics. Natural language sentences are the only proxies that will permit thoughts to function as the objects of thought in this manner. (Bermúdez 2003: 164) This makes it clear that, despite suggestions to the contrary, Bermúdez's argument applies only to certain kinds of higher‐order thought: thoughts pertaining to evidential and inferential relations among representations. Thus construed, the thesis is that we can make sense of evidential and inferential reasoning only when the relata are sentential in form.

In summarizing his conclusion, however, Bermúdez endorses a stronger thesis: ‘[T]here can be no intentional ascent without semantic ascent. We think about thoughts through thinking about the sentences through which those thoughts might be expressed’ (2003: 164). This makes it sound as though higher‐order thought, quite generally, requires a capacity for linguistic thought. In what follows I shall offer a challenge to those sympathetic to either a weak or a strong reading of Bermúdez's (p. 640) contention. The message is simple: where cognition is concerned, there is nothing special about language.7

36.4 Thoughts and their Expression Consider Spot who, upon hearing the key in the lock, might naturally be said to believe his master is at the door. Why does Wittgenstein's rhetorical question—Could Spot believe his master will arrive the day after tomorrow?—give us pause? If Spot can have thoughts about his master today, why should we be reluctant to ascribe to Spot ‘tensed’ thoughts: thoughts about temporally distal occurrences? Or, to turn the question around, if we are reluctant to ascribe to Spot beliefs about occurrences the day after tomorrow, might our confidence that Spot could harbour beliefs about the here and now be misplaced? It is hard not to imagine that an answer to this question presumes an answer to the question whether thought is inevitably linguistic. Here are two reasons you might think that thought requires language. First, persuaded by Fodor, you might imagine that thoughts must themselves be linguistic. To think is to engage in something like inner speech: the medium of thought is linguistic.8 Non‐verbal imagery lacks the kind of determinate content required for genuine thought. Second, you might want to connect the having or entertaining of thoughts with actual or possible manifestations of those thoughts. You might have verificationist motives here: ‘an “inner process” stands in need of outward criteria’ (Wittgenstein 1953/1968: sect. 580). Or you might simply take it to be part of the nature of a thought that it manifest itself in particular ways in particular circumstances. An unmanifestable thought would be one the possession of which made no difference to what its possessor does or might do. This,

Page 10 of 20

Language and Thought coupled with the idea that the only unambiguous manifestation of thoughts—or some thoughts—is linguistic, implies that only linguistically endowed creatures could have thoughts—or thoughts of certain kinds. Consider this second reason more closely as it applies to Spot. The idea is that thoughts require manifestations (actual or possible), and only linguistic utterances could count as unequivocal manifestations of tensed thoughts. Spot could, the day after tomorrow, look expectantly at the door. This, however, would be most naturally taken to be a manifestation of Spot's belief that his master is at the door, not a manifestation of a tensed belief. Perhaps, however, the problem is not that Spot lacks a capacity for the linguistic manifestation of tensed beliefs, but that Spot lacks a use for tensed representations. (p. 641) One sort of use of such representations would be the conveying of tensed information to others. This is the kind of use manifested in utterances of tensed sentences. The suggestion on the table is that the idea that Spot is linguistically challenged hence unable to entertain thoughts about temporally remote states of affairs is a red herring. To be sure, Spot lacks a language. But it is not this that makes it unlikely that Spot could entertain tensed thoughts. Spot lacks a use for tensed representations, hence a capacity for tensed thinking.9 One prominent sort of use might be communicative—a fact that points to language. What is doing the work here, however, is not language, but use. You might be sceptical that there could be anything like a tensed representation in the absence of language. If you thought that, you could accept what I have said about use, but note that in many cases, including Spot's, only linguistic use is available. Maybe. But maybe not.

36.5 Thought Suppose we take seriously the venerable idea that language is a tool. Intelligent agents employ language in the way you might employ a screwdriver to achieve various ends. If language is a tool, it is a multi‐purpose tool, a Swiss Army knife. (To be sure, even a ‘single‐purpose’ tool—a screwdriver, for instance—can have multiple uses.) If this is right, it is a mistake to regard thoughts as being in language. Thinking is linguistic when we think with language. If a linguistic episode—an inner utterance, for instance—is analogous to a screwdriver, thinking is analogous to driving a screw with a screwdriver. Regarded in this light, the question whether thought, or some thought, requires language reduces to the question whether language might be the only tool that could be used for certain tasks. And just as it seems unlikely that any tool is irreplaceable, so it seems unlikely that language is, for any particular task, irreplaceable.

Page 11 of 20

Language and Thought What exactly is it to deploy language as a tool? And what other intellectual tools might be available to intelligent agents? Just as you make use of utterances—written or spoken—to articulate ideas to others, you can use inner utterances in the articulation of ideas to yourself. You can talk through a problem, recall some earlier event, or plan a course of action by listing steps to its completion in your head. In these cases inner utterances are not manifestations or copies of thoughts; you are thinking with language just as you might open a can with a can opener. There is no mystery here any more than there is mystery in your spontaneously engaging in intelligent conversation. You need not first think—rehearse—then speak. This is so whether speech is overt or covert. Inner utterances (I say, siding with Bermúdez) are a species of mental imagery, where the images are images of what their audible, visual, or tactile counterparts (p. 642) sound, look, or feel like. There is no logical or conceptual gulf between linguistic (‘propositional’) imagery and imagery of other sorts. Conscious thought in general is imagistic.10 Not all thoughts incorporate linguistic imagery, however. Much of our thought involves non‐linguistic visual, auditory, tactile, or olfactory imagery. Indeed, your thought about a particular person might include verbal imagery (an inner utterance of a name, for instance) accompanied by a visual image of the person and perhaps other imagery as well. The association of imagery with thought is not a matter of reducing thoughts to images. Thinking is a matter of using imagery. Bare images, what C. B. Martin (1987) calls the materials of thought, are devoid of significance. You can grant this, grant that images themselves lack intrinsic intentionality, without thereby giving up on the idea that conscious thinking is a matter of deploying images. There is nothing special about verbal imagery—what you might conceive of as linguistic thought. Interior utterances are no different in this regard than any other imagery. Intentionality arises when images (or signs, or representations generally) are put to work by intelligent agents. Without use, images or signs are empty; severed from use, representations fail to represent. It is easy to lose sight of this simple idea so long as we persist in the illusion that interior utterances are not themselves images altogether on a par with images of sunsets and romantic Greek isles. Debates over whether imagery is ‘pictorial’ or ‘propositional’ are beside the point (see Kosslyn and Pomerantz 1977; Pylyshyn 1981, 1984; Rollins 1989; Tye 1991). Linguistic thoughts are as ‘pictorial’ as any others in the sense that they include the use of imagery: verbal imagery.

36.6 Images, Sentential and Otherwise Suppose this is so: conscious thinking is inevitably imagistic; to entertain a thought consciously is to deploy images of one sort or another. Imagery can be ‘pictorial’ or ‘sentential’. You can imagine how something looks (did look, will look, or might look), Page 12 of 20

Language and Thought feels (did feel, will feel, or might feel), tastes (did, will, or might taste), sounds (did, will, or might sound), or smells (did, will, or might smell). One species of such imagining is verbal: you imaginatively utter, or hear yourself utter, words. In considering such cases we philosophers are apt to be misled in at least two ways. First, we are likely to regard verbal imagery as privileged. On the one hand, there is ordinary ‘pictorial’ imagery; on the other hand, there is the entertaining of ‘sentential’ thoughts. This is the kind of distinction Peter Carruthers (1996) appears to have in mind in distinguishing ‘imagism’ and ‘sententialism’. An ‘imagist’ regards (p. 643) thoughts as invariably pictorial. ‘Imagists’ hold that ‘thoughts inherit their representational properties from the representative powers of the images that constitute them’ (Carruthers 1996: 32). Carruthers mentions Locke, Hume, and Russell as proponents of imagism. ‘Imagists’ hold that thinking consists of a succession of picture‐like ideas parading across the mind. Carruthers contrasts ‘imagism’ with ‘sententialism’: the view that thoughts, or some thoughts, are linguistic in character. ‘Tokens’ of such thoughts are mental sentences, which are to be distinguished sharply from ‘pictorial’ images. But what are mental sentences if not images—verbal images? The contrast here, if there is one, is not between images and non‐images, but between two species of image: one non‐sentential, one sentential. There is no sense in which verbal images—mental ‘sentence tokens’, interior utterances or inscriptions—are less imagistic than nightmares or the remembered taste of a madeleine. A second way in which we philosophers are likely to be misled in thinking about verbal and non‐verbal imagery is more pernicious. Consider a passage from Carruthers: An image will always carry with it excess content beyond mere entailment relations. The sentence, ‘A cat is on a mat’ carries no more, and no less, content than the proposition [that a cat is on a mat]. So it will contain the content, [that a mammal is on a mat], since this is entailed, but it will not contain the content, [that a tabby cat is on a mat], nor the content, [that a cat is sitting on a mat]. Not so with an image. Although an image can be in various respects indeterminate or vague, it must always be more determinate than a proposition. My image of a cat on a mat must always be an image of some particular kind of cat (fluffy or short‐ haired, tabby or black) in some particular position (sitting or standing, facing or turned away) on some particular sort of mat. (Carruthers 1996: 38; brackets are in the original) Carruthers's comment echoes Berkeley's criticism of Locke's doctrine of ‘abstract general ideas’ (see Locke 1690/1978: III. iii. 6; Berkeley 1710/1998: introd., sect. 9). Locke's doctrine of abstract ideas is not a thesis about kinds of idea, however. Abstraction is, for Locke, ‘partial consideration’ (see e.g. Locke 1690/1978: II. viii. 13). An abstract idea is not a generic idea, but an idea used generically. In just the same way you can use a particular red paint chip to represent redness‐in‐general by considering it ‘partially’—just in so far as it is red. Page 13 of 20

Language and Thought Berkeley's own account of general ideas begins with the observation that images inevitably exhibit a kind of definiteness (Carruthers's ‘excess content’) lacked by linguistic representations. A pictorial representation of a cat on a mat will be a representation of a cat sitting or lying on a mat, for instance. This, Carruthers thinks, makes it ill suited as a vehicle for the thought that the cat is on the mat. But Berkeley— and Locke—note what Carruthers does not: generality is a product of our deployment of images. An image of a reclining tabby could be used to represent a cat's being on a mat. Think of road signs depicting a car skidding on a wet road. The image is of a particular kind of car, but sign‐makers count on our grasping the image as representing vehicles generally. (p. 644)

The point applies across the board: the key to understanding the nature of thought is the recognition that thinking is something we do when we use imagery. Thinking is not the having or entertaining of images, sentential or otherwise. Thinking is something we do imagistically.

36.7 Proto‐language Philosophizing is a largely verbal enterprise. It is scarcely surprising, then, that when we engage in philosophical reflection—when we think about philosophical topics—we do so in a thoroughly verbal idiom. There is nothing special about words, however, nothing magical about utterances and inscriptions. Words take on significance when they are put to use by intelligent agents or intelligent systems. If it is doubtful that Spot could entertain the thought that his master will arrive home the day after tomorrow, this is not because Spot lacks words to express this thought. It is because it is hard to see how Spot could have a use for a representation with this content. Here it might be useful to consider what C. B. Martin (1987) calls ‘proto‐language’: Non‐linguistic activity at its more sophisticated and structured levels has a remarkable pattern of parallels to that of linguistic activity. It is a matter of degree, but when an agent shows enough of this pattern of parallels, this structured network of procedures can be called ‘proto‐language’. (1987: 277)

Page 14 of 20

Language and Thought ‘Proto‐language’ is not ‘a kind of language as sign language is a kind of language’. Rather, it is ‘a structured rule‐governed network of semantic, procedural activity prior to and basic to linguistic activity, having an almost totally unnoticed and surprising pattern of parallels to language itself’ (Martin 1987: 278). Martin's idea is that semantic features of natural languages can have non‐linguistic, ‘procedural’ analogues in assorted non‐linguistic activities—overt and covert—of intelligent agents. It would follow that reference, quantification, modality, tense, and the like are language‐independent. The trick is to find roles for such things in the activities of creatures lacking a means of expressing them linguistically.

You can see what Martin is driving at by considering an example. Counterfactual and subjunctive conditionals might be taken to depend on a distinctively linguistic medium. The challenge is to find a non‐linguistic procedure aimed at discovering some counterfactual or subjunctive truth. Imagine an early hominid who has learned that what fish eat can be found in their stomachs. He has also noticed that they eat different things at different times. When he catches a fish, he opens its stomach to see what it has been feeding on, so that he can use it as bait. On one unsuccessful day's fishing he notices an approaching storm that looks like spoiling the fishing for a long time. Frustrated, he intends not to return to the fishing hole until the weather changes. He picks up his fishing gear and starts for the cave. He happens to frighten a mink eating a fish. His curiosity overtaking him, he opens the stomach to see what the (p. 645) fish had eaten and takes out some grasshoppers. This is a procedural action whose projected outcome is information about the past. It also has the point of finding out what would have helped him to catch fish if he had used it as bait. (Martin 1987: 287) Here we have a procedure aimed at establishing a particular outcome, an outcome we could express linguistically by means of a tensed counterfactual conditional. If it is hard to imagine Spot entertaining thoughts with tensed or subjunctive conditional contents, this is not because Spot lacks a capacity to express such thoughts linguistically, but because it is hard to credit Spot with a capacity to engage in any sort of procedure the aim of which is to establish a tensed or subjunctive conditional truth. Spot's deficit is cognitive not linguistic.

This is not to deny that cognitive and linguistic capacities might be importantly related in terrestrial species (see Clark 1998). The point, rather, is that a capacity for the production of utterances or inscriptions cannot, by itself, amount to a capacity for sophisticated thought. We knew this already: mynah birds and parrots can be taught to produce utterances.11 What they lack is a capacity to put those utterances to intelligent use, in a way that depends on their significance.

36.8 Non‐conscious Thought Page 15 of 20

Language and Thought I have suggested that ordinary conscious thought is to be understood as the manipulation of images. But not all thought is conscious thought. Thinking apparently occurs behind the scenes outside our awareness. Can the imagistic conception I am suggesting be extended to cases of non‐conscious or ‘subpersonal’ thought? The idea that non‐conscious thought might be imagistic is not something I want to pursue here. I do not want to pursue it because I believe there is a better way of understanding the nature of at least some non‐conscious thought. Let me begin with an example. If you are like me, you can sometimes resolve nagging intellectual problems by sleeping on them. You go to bed puzzled, wake up enlightened. Something similar can happen when you are trying to remember a forgotten name: you put it out of your mind and discover that it subsequently comes to you. How should we understand such cases? One possibility is that something is going on backstage altogether analogous to what goes on when we consciously reflect. Call this the shoemaker‐and‐elf model: when the shoemaker retires for the night, elves materialize, performing just as the shoemaker would, but secretly. Another possibility is that our unconscious mental life differs structurally and qualitatively from its conscious counterpart. Think of the brain as a complex, dynamic dispositional system. The system manifests itself in myriad ways: in bodily (p. 646) behaviour, in speech, and, often enough, in conscious thought. The system manifests itself as well in the regulation of various bodily functions, thermal regulation, the maintenance of equilibrium, and the like. The finely tuned, focused dispositions constituting the nervous system are not static but dynamic: they evolve continuously over time. The system that, a few minutes ago, was unable to produce the name of an acquaintance has resettled itself and can now, in concert with other, reciprocal, systems, yield the name. In many cases—in cases of ‘unconscious inference’, for instance—this could be what is going on. Were that so, non‐conscious thinking would not be a matter of something like conscious thought going on backstage. Rather, a different kind of process is occurring, a process that produces an alteration of the dispositional basis of thought.

36.9 Conclusion What is the upshot? First, thinking—ordinary conscious thinking—is imagistic. This is so for ‘linguistic’, or ‘sentential’, thoughts as well as for patently non‐linguistic thoughts. Second, thinking does not consist in merely having or entertaining images, but in putting those images to work. Third, verbal and non‐verbal imagery are representationally on a par. The significance of any sort of representation lies in the use to which it is put by intelligent representers. Finally, what we regard as non‐conscious thought need not resemble conscious thought occurring out of sight. Non‐conscious thought could turn out

Page 16 of 20

Language and Thought to be the dynamic unfolding of a dispositional base, one manifestation of which is conscious thinking. Creatures lacking a capacity for language could well be unable to entertain thoughts of various kinds. But this might be so, if it is so, not because thoughts or some kinds of thought are necessarily linguistic. An inability to use language and an inability to think certain thoughts could have a common cause. A creature could lack the kind of make‐up required for the pursuit of projects the satisfaction of which would afford opportunities for the deployment of representations of particular sorts. This, I think, puts language in its place.12

References Angell, J. R. (1897), ‘Thought and Imagery’, Philosophical Review, 6: 646–51. Bennett, J. F. (1964), Rationality: An Essay Towards an Analysis (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Berkeley, G. (1710/1998), A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, ed. J. Dancy (Oxford: Clarendon Press). (p. 647)

Bermúdez, J. L. (2003), Thinking Without Words (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Braddon‐Mitchell, D., and Jackson, F. C. (1996), Philosophy of Mind and Cognition (Oxford: Blackwell). Carruthers, P. (1996) Language, Thought, and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Clark, A. (1998), ‘Magic Words: How Language Augments Human Computation’, in P. Carruthers and J. Boucher (eds.), Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 162–83. Craik, K. (1967), The Nature of Explanation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Danzinger, K. (1980), ‘The History of Introspectionism Reconsidered’, Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16: 241–62. Davidson, D. (1975), ‘Thought and Talk’, in S. Guttenplan (ed.), Mind and Language (Oxford: Clarendon), 7–23; repr. in Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984), 155– 70. —— (1982), ‘Rational Animals’, Dialectica, 36: 317–27;

Page 17 of 20

Language and Thought repr. in E. Lepore and B. P. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985), 473–80. Fodor, J. A. (1975), The Language of Thought (New York: Crowell). Heil, J. (1992), The Nature of True Minds (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Johnson‐Laird, P. N. (1983), Mental Models (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1999), ‘Mental Models’, in R. A. Wilson and F. C. Keil (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 525–7. Kosslyn, S. M., and Pomerantz, J. R. (1977), ‘Imagery, Propositions, and the Form of Internal Representations’, Cognitive Psychology, 9: 52–76. Locke, J. (1690/1978), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). Martin, C. B. (1987), ‘Proto‐language’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65: 277–89. —— (2008), The Mind in Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press). Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981), ‘The Imagery Debate: Analogue Media Versus Tacit Knowledge’, Psychological Review, 88: 16–45. —— (1984), Computation and Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Rips, L. (1994), The Psychology of Proof (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Rollins, M. (1989), Mental Imagery: On the Limits of Cognitive Science (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press). Thomas, N. J. T. (1999), ‘Are Theories of Imagery Theories of Imagination?’, Cognitive Science, 23: 207–45. —— (2001), ‘Mental Imagery’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL , accessed 2008. Tye, M. (1991), The Imagery Debate (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Vonnegut, K. (1973), Breakfast of Champions (New York: Dell). Wittgenstein, L. (1921/1961), Tractatus Logico‐Philosophicus, trans. D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). —— (1953/1968), Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell).

Page 18 of 20

Language and Thought Woodworth, R. S. (1906), ‘Imageless Thought’, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, 3: 701–8.

Notes: (1) This is not to say that there might not be more‐ or less‐perspicuous ways of describing Spot's states of mind, only that pertinent factors fall well short of those constraining belief ascription to creatures endowed with a language. (2) The concept of a truth maker and the concept of a truth bearer are correlative concepts: grasp of one requires grasp of the other. (3) A parallel argument can be found in Wittgenstein (1921/1961: sects. 5.632–5.6331). (4) So it would be misleading to imagine that you reason from the third‐ to the first‐ person case. The relation is, rather, reciprocal. (5) The parenthetical rider is important. A cat might entertain thoughts about your utterances without having any idea what they meant or even that they have meaning. Your thoughts about sentences in an unfamiliar tongue might be no better in this regard than the cat's. (6) Perhaps what Bermúdez has in mind is that in reading about them we do not represent non‐linguistic representations but merely linguistic descriptions of non‐ linguistic representations. His discussion of non‐linguistic representations purports to be a discussion of the representations themselves, however, and not merely descriptions of them. In discussing such representations Bermúdez's own thoughts must be directed on them. (7) I do not deny that, as a matter of contingent empirical fact, human beings lean heavily on language. My interest is in the question whether what we accomplish by means of language could only be accomplished through the use of language. (8) Although the discussion focuses on spoken language, I intend for it to encompass other forms of linguistic expression—signing, for instance. Vonnegut (1973: 58–9) imagines an interesting possibility. (9) This is an empirical claim that could turn out to be false. (10) This, perhaps, is what lies behind the old debate about the possibility of ‘imageless thought’. See, for instance, Angell (1897), Woodworth (1906), Danzinger (1980), Thomas (1999, 2001). (11) Perhaps such creatures produce, as well, silent imagistic counterparts of these utterances!

Page 19 of 20

Language and Thought (12) The central thesis developed here was impressed upon me twenty years ago by C. B. Martin; see Martin (1987, 2008). Since then I have learned much about imagery from Nigel Thomas (see his 1999, 2001) and Mark Rollins (see his 1989). I am grateful to José Bermúdez, and to audiences at the University of Otago and the University of Geneva who suffered through preliminary versions of this chapter.

John Heil

John Heil: Professor of Philosophy, School of Philosophy and Bioethics, Building 11, Monash University VIC 3800. AUSTRALIA. And: Professor of Philosophy, Washington University in St Louis, Department of Philosophy, Wilson Hall, One Brookings Dr., Campus Box 1073, St. Louis, MO 63130–4899. USA. Email: [email protected]; [email protected]

Page 20 of 20

Consciousness and Reference

Oxford Handbooks Online Consciousness and Reference   John Campbell The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0038

Abstract and Keywords Russell was the first to articulate the connection between consciousness and a recognizably modern conception of reference, using his notion of acquaintance. The idea of ‘acquaintance’ is the idea of a kind of epistemic contact with a thing or property. Many theorists would agree that reference to something requires a particular kind of epistemic contact with it. Yet you might agree that the notion of ‘epistemic contact with a particular’ is needed to characterize reference, while arguing that epistemic contact is to be explained as possession of a body of propositional knowledge. Keywords: notion of acquaintance, consciousness, reference, epistemic contact, propositional knowledge, knowledge of truth

37.1 Acquaintance versus Knowledge of Truths SUPPOSE your conscious life were surgically excised, but everything else left intact, what would you miss? In this situation you would not have the slightest idea what was going on. You would have no idea what there is in the world around you, what the grounds are of the potentialities and threats that you are negotiating. Experience of your surroundings provides you with knowledge of what is there: with your initial base of knowledge of what the things are that you are thinking and talking about. But this connection between consciousness of the objects and properties around you and knowledge of the references of the basic terms you use has proven difficult to articulate. The connection cannot be recognized so long as you think of consciousness as a kind of glow with which representations are accompanied or enlivened. It is, though, also possible to think of perceptual experience as fundamentally a relation between the

Page 1 of 17

Consciousness and Reference subject and the things experienced; and given such a conception, we can make visible the link between consciousness and reference. Russell was the first to articulate the connection between consciousness and a recognizably modern conception of reference, using his notion of acquaintance. The idea of ‘acquaintance’ is the idea of a kind of epistemic contact with a thing or property. Many theorists would agree that reference to something requires a particular kind of epistemic contact with it. Yet you might agree that the notion (p. 649) of ‘epistemic contact with a particular’ is needed to characterize reference, while arguing that epistemic contact is to be explained as possession of a body of propositional knowledge. Minimally, you might say that what it takes to have epistemic contact with b is this: you must have a piece of propositional knowledge whose content can be specified using a term referring to b, such as ‘b’. There are many ways in which to pursue the programme of explaining ‘epistemic contact with b’ in terms of propositional knowledge relating to b. For instance, you might introduce the notion of a ‘dossier’, as follows. Suppose you have two pieces of knowledge whose contents are given by: ‘b is F’, and ‘c is G’. On the face of it you are not yet in a position to argue that anything is both F and G, even if b and c are in fact identical. To draw that conclusion you need a further premise, the identity statement ‘b is identical to c’. Suppose, in contrast, that you have two pieces of knowledge, ‘b is F’, and ‘b is G’. Here it looks as though you are in a position immediately to draw the conclusion, ‘b is both F and G’. As we might put it, in the second case, but not in the first, you are in a position to trade on the identity of the object referred to in those two pieces of knowledge. You might have a body of information relating to the same object b, and be in a position to trade on the identity of the object referred to in any two of the pieces of knowledge in that body. In such a case we can say that you have a ‘dossier’ on the object. So you could expand on the initial characterization of ‘epistemic contact with an object’ by saying that it requires a dossier of information on it, rather than just a single piece of propositional knowledge. There are a number of conditions you might think it important to impose on the body of information in the dossier. For example, Evans held that the sheer volume of detail is important, as are the reasons why you are interested in the referent in the first place. Kaplan suggested that a dossier should constitute a major part in a narrative concerning those ‘who fill major roles in that inner story which consists of all those sentences which [the subject] believes’ (1971: 136). There are other distinctions we might apply. The important point about all these variations and refinements is that they are variations and refinements internal to the project of explaining the notion of epistemic contact with an object or property in terms of possession of propositional knowledge about it. Russell had a dramatic alternative to any such approach. Russell argued that our knowledge of things cannot, in general, be explained in terms of our knowledge of truths. Russell thought that there were two sorts of knowledge: knowledge of truths, and knowledge of things. Knowledge of truths depended on knowledge of things. In particular, it depended on the kind of knowledge of things he called acquaintance:

Page 2 of 17

Consciousness and Reference Knowledge of things, when it is of the kind we call knowledge by acquaintance, is essentially simpler than any knowledge of truths, and logically independent of knowledge of truths, though it would be rash to assume that human beings ever, in fact, have acquaintance with things without at the same time knowing some truth about them. (1912: 46) Knowledge of truths depends on acquaintance with objects. For it is acquaintance with objects or properties that provides our knowledge of reference: (p. 650)

[I]t is scarcely conceivable that we can make a judgement or entertain a supposition without knowing what it is that we are judging or supposing about. We must attach some meaning to the words we use, if we are to speak significantly and not utter mere noise; and the meaning we attach to our words must be something with which we are acquainted. (1912: 46) What the subject is acquainted with fixes the references of simple referring terms, and that reference fixer is also the basis of the subject's knowledge of truths.

You might try to interpret these remarks in terms of causal chains that fix reference to physical objects. Perhaps those very causal chains are the source of knowledge of truths about the objects. The ‘right kind’ of causal chain to fix reference would be what Sainsbury (1979), for example, called an ‘epistemic chain’. When we ask what an epistemic chain is, the natural answer is that it is one which produces knowledge of truths concerning the object referred to. So the relevant notion of a causal chain is being explained in terms of propositional knowledge. This loses Russell's idea of acquaintance as a knowledge of things that is more fundamental than knowledge of truths. One way of trying to sustain a causal approach here is to shift away from the focus on proper names, and emphasize the arguably more basic case of demonstratives referring to currently perceived objects. And we could think of epistemic causation not as (a) a relation between the object and a body of propositional knowledge but rather as

(b) a relation between the object and a body of non‐conceptual contents, of the kind appealed to in scientific analyses of vision. Since these non‐conceptual, perceptual contents will be more basic than propositional knowledge, this approach might seem to give us a way of sustaining the idea of a knowledge of things more basic than knowledge of truths. The first and still the most sustained development of this approach is Evans's Varieties of Reference (1982).

This approach deviates from Russell, however, in giving no role to consciousness in providing acquaintance with objects. For Russell, awareness of the object is central to

Page 3 of 17

Consciousness and Reference acquaintance. His opening explanation of the notion, in The Problems of Philosophy, is this: We shall say that we have acquaintance with anything of which we are directly aware, without the intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truth. (1912: 25) This idea is lost by an explanation of acquaintance as epistemic causation, where the relata of the causal relation are the thing referred to and a body of non‐conceptual information. There is no reason in principle why non‐conceptual information should (p. 651) be conscious; in fact, the information‐processing contents appealed to by vision scientists are typically remote from consciousness. The point is quite explicit in Evans's development of this line of thought. Consciousness is seen as an epiphenomenon that emerges once the whole apparatus of thought and reference has been imposed on a more primitive information‐processing system:

[W]e arrive at conscious perceptual experience when sensory input is not only connected to behavioural dispositions in the way I have been describing—perhaps in some phylogenetically more ancient part of the brain—but also serves as the input to a thinking, concept‐applying and reasoning system; so that the subject's thoughts, plans and deliberations are also systematically dependent on the informational properties of the input. When there is such a further link, we can say that the person, rather than just some part of his brain, receives and possesses the information. (1982: 158) The experiential character of perception plays no role in an account of perception‐based reference to objects and properties on this account. What has been retained from Russell is the idea that the relation that fixes reference is also the ground of knowledge of truths about the object. What has been lost is the idea that it is experience of the object that explains how the thinker knows which thing is in question.

37.2 Radical Transparency Philosophers sometimes characterize perceptual experience as if it is a kind of propositional thinking. Just as you characterize the contents of someone's beliefs by specifying a particular collection of propositions they understand, so, on this view, you characterize the contents of someone's visual experiences by specifying a range of propositions they understand, towards which the relevant attitude is not ‘believes that … ’ but now ‘has a visual experience as of … ’. If you think of visual experience in this way it is hard to see how it could be what provides knowledge of the references of the terms you use. First, experience now seems to presuppose, rather than explain, your knowledge of reference. To understand those propositions you have to know the references of their Page 4 of 17

Consciousness and Reference constituents. Second, it is hard to see how we can hold on to the idea that experience is even relevant to providing knowledge of reference. One can grasp propositions in many ways: by believing them, by desiring that they be true, and so on. Visual experience has now simply been added to the list, as one among many ways in which one can take an attitude towards a proposition. Why vision should be particularly central among those ways seems now to defy explanation. And even if there is something special about vision, it is hard to see why it is specifically experience that is important; presumably one could in principle, on this approach, grasp a proposition as the content of non‐conscious vision. Finally, these problems evidently arise because this approach abandons Russell's idea of finding a kind of acquaintance with things that is more fundamental than knowledge of truths. (p. 652)

How should we characterize this non‐propositional consciousness of things? Philosophers often suppose that if there are non‐propositional elements in perception, they must be ‘sensations’ caused by the objects around us, ‘intrinsic features’ of the sensations, ‘mental paint’ as Harman called it, features with themselves no inherent link to the object. Could we use the idea of non‐propositional sensations to explain how experience provides acquaintance with the objects that cause those sensations? One possibility is that the sensation would enter here as the anchor of a definite description such as ‘whatever (if anything) caused this sensation’. But this kind of reference could not be fundamental; it depends on a more basic naming of the sensation itself, as ‘this sensation’. Moreover, this style of reference does not seem to depend particularly on the subject having experience of the object referred to. For if you are able to frame this kind of description, you presumably will also be able to frame such descriptions as ‘whatever (if anything) this sensation causes me to buy’, and so on indefinitely. The idea that it is experience of the object that inherently provides acquaintance with that very object has been lost. Finally, the idea anyway seems at odds with what Moore called the ‘transparent’ character of experience: that when we attend to our experiences, we attend not to what Harman called the ‘mental paint’—some intrinsic characteristic of the experience—but, rather, to the object itself. You might then say that there are intrinsic aspects of experience, and that they are of the object in virtue of being caused by the object, so that it is the fact of the causal link between the intrinsic aspect of the experience and the object that is important, rather than the subject having managed to frame a description in which reference is made to the intrinsic aspect of the experience. But now it is again hard to see why it should be experience that matters here: if a causal link from the object to the experience is what is important, why would it not be good enough to have a causal link from the object to some non‐conscious aspect of the perception? Moore is trying to characterize a non‐propositional notion of experience of things when he discusses the transparency of experience. He draws a distinction within our ordinary notion of ‘having a sensation’. He says that the sensation of blue and the sensation of green are both sensations; yet they are different. What is it that the sensation of blue and Page 5 of 17

Consciousness and Reference the sensation of green have in common? And in what are they different? Moore said that we have to recognize there are two components bundled together in the ordinary notion of ∼‘sensation’: [There are] in every sensation two distinct terms, (1) ‘consciousness,’ in respect of which all sensations are alike; and (2) something else in respect of which one sensation differs from another. It will be convenient if I may be allowed to call this second term the ‘object’ of a sensation: this also without yet attempting to say what I mean by the word. We have then in every sensation two distinct elements, one which I call consciousness, and another which I call the object of consciousness. (1903: 444) The analysis here does not appeal to the idea of ‘mental paint’ at all, whether representational or sensational. The idea is that all experiences are the same so far as (p. 653) their intrinsic properties go; they are all acts of consciousness, and it is this aspect of the experience that eludes introspection. It is for this reason that it is easy to be a materialist and deny the very existence of consciousness:

[When] we refer to introspection and try to discover what the sensation of blue is, it is very easy to suppose that we have before us only a single term. The term ‘blue’ is easy enough to distinguish, but the other element which I have called ‘consciousness’—that which sensation of blue has in common with sensation of green—is extremely difficult to fix. That many people fail to distinguish it at all is sufficiently shown by the fact that there are materialists. And, in general, that which makes the sensation of blue a mental fact seems to escape us: it seems, if I may use a metaphor, to be transparent—we look through it and see nothing but the blue (Moore 1903: 446) In an intriguing discussion of Moore, Van Cleve (in press) puts it very strongly when he says that ‘Moore denies that experiences have intrinsic features. Instead, they owe everything they are to their relation to objects … Moore's radical view … could perhaps be cited as the explanation of [transparency]: we are not aware of any intrinsic features of experience because there aren't any’. As the above passage makes evident, Moore does think there is something elusive in consciousness: the relation of consciousness itself, which is common to all sensation, that materialists miss. But Moore emphatically does make the point that there is no reason to think there are intrinsic features of experience that differentiate the experience of blue from the experience of green. There is no need to appeal to either the notion of a representation of colour differentiating the experiences or the notion of an intrinsic sensational feature of the experience differentiating the two colour experiences. The objects, blue in one case, green in the other, adequately differentiate the experiences.

Page 6 of 17

Consciousness and Reference The concluding paragraph of Moore's ‘Refutation of Idealism’ is worth quoting quite fully, as it brings out that his case against the idealist uses the point that the objects of awareness are material objects: When, therefore, Berkeley supposed that the only thing of which I am directly aware is my own sensations and ideas, he supposed what was false; and when Kant supposed that the objectivity of things in space consisted in the fact that they were ‘Vorstellungen’ having to one another different relations from those which the same ‘Vorstellungen’ have to one another in subjective experience, he supposed what was equally false. I am as directly aware of the existence of material things in space as of my own sensations, and what I am aware of with regard to each is exactly the same—namely that in one case the material thing, and in the other case my sensation does really exist. The question requiring to be asked about material things is thus not: What reason have we for supposing that anything exists corresponding to our sensations? but: What reason have we for supposing that material things do not exist, since their existence has precisely the same evidence as that of our sensations? That either exist may be false; but if it is a reason for doubting the existence of matter, that it is an inseparable aspect of our experience, the same reasoning will prove conclusively that our experience does not exist either, since that must also be an inseparable aspect of our experience of it. (1903: 453) This notion of Moore's, that we have non‐propositional awareness of objects, which may be sensations or physical objects, provides exactly what we need to fill out the (p. 654) view that awareness of objects is what makes thought about them possible. The reason it has to be awareness is that awareness is a generic relation between the thinker and the object: there is no such thing as a particular type of awareness without the object being there to differentiate that exercise of awareness from any other. Since awareness has this relational character, there is no question of being able to substitute for it some other relation that would be ‘just as good’, which is the problem that comes up if we think of awareness as a kind of monadic glow with which the mental life is enlivened.

Page 7 of 17

Consciousness and Reference

37.3 Partial Awareness There is some sense in which we typically do not experience all aspects of an object we perceive: experience of the object is in some sense partial. To use Frege's example, you may be in a position to refer to Venus in virtue of awareness of it as you watch the sky towards morning. And you may be in a position to refer to Venus in virtue of awareness of it as you watch the sky in the evening. But you may not yet be in a position to recognize that it is the same thing you have referred to both times. That shows that there is some sense in which your awareness of the object on these two occasions was partial. The point here is not simply that there is some broadly phenomenological difference in your experience on these two occasions. There certainly are broadly phenomenological differences in the way you are aware of the object on these occasions, but some of these differences do not matter for knowledge of reference. For example, as you are watching the sky, cloud may brush briefly over the star. There is a phenomenological change, but there may be manifest sameness of object for all that. Similarly for what happens when you move your eyes or head. Indeed, there has to be this kind of object constancy for your experience to be an encounter with physical objects. If with every head turn or movement by an object you lost track of the thing, then you would not have the kind of experience that would sustain reference to a thing at all. But the manifest sameness of the object— our ability to keep track of things—has its limits. And it passes its limit in the case of the morning star and the evening star: it is not manifest that this is the same object. There is here a difference that is reflected in the inferential behaviour of the sign. From ‘The morning star is F’ and ‘The evening star is G’ you cannot immediately infer the conclusion ‘The morning star is both F and G’. But given the premises ‘The morning star is F’ and ‘The morning star is G’ you can immediately trade on identity to conclude ‘The Morning Star is both F and G’. This is a problem for Moore's radical transparency. If your experience of the object is fully characterized simply by saying that we have a generic relation of consciousness holding between you and that thing, then we do not seem to have the resources to explain how there could be different kinds of conscious experience of the thing. Arguably the same point applies to properties, or at any rate some properties. To experience the shape of a solid object you must have some capacity to recognize (p. 655) manifest sameness of shape across movements by you or by the object. Otherwise it is hard to see how you could be said to be encountering the property of three‐dimensional shape at all. But this capacity has its limits. Particularly if you consider a large object with a complex shape, it seems entirely possible that you could encounter the shape in one way from one angle, and then, coming upon the object from a quite different direction, be unable to recognize the sameness of shape. You have some ability to keep track of sameness of shape across variation in perceptual presentation, but it has its limits. And this variation in your experience of the property matters, in that it will affect the inferential behaviour of the shape concepts you use to report the situation observed on the two encounters. It will affect, for example, whether you can immediately draw Page 8 of 17

Consciousness and Reference conclusions about whether the object has changed shape. Again, this is difficult to reconcile with Moore's radical transparency. If the full characterization of your experience of shape is given by saying that you bear the generic relation of consciousness to a particular three‐dimensional shape, then it is not possible for there to be different experiences of the same shape. This is a fundamental problem. The response usually given in the analytic tradition is to say that when an object is experienced in different ways this is a matter of different representations being associated with the two ways of experiencing the object. It has proved quite difficult to think of an alternative to this approach. Following hints from Frege, the different representations are usually taken to be different descriptions, or clusters of descriptions. So, for example, you might explain the difference between your two encounters with Venus by saying that in the one case the associated description was ‘the brightest star in the morning sky’ and in the second case the associated description was ‘the brightest star in the evening sky’. The problem being addressed here is to characterize the difference between the consciousness of an object that provides your knowledge of the reference of ‘the morning star’, and the consciousness of an object that provides your knowledge of the reference of ‘the evening star’. The strategy is to appeal to a difference in the descriptions associated with the consciousness of the object on those two occasions. And, in particular, there is a difference in the general terms used in those descriptions: the difference between ‘morning’ and ‘evening’. As I said, this type of strategy, appealing to differences in the descriptions activated in different moments of awareness of the object, seems compelling to most writers in the analytic tradition who have addressed the problem of informativeness. But the approach cannot be correct. The first difficulty is that, as noted above, the problem also seems to arise for general terms. You can be aware of one and the same property in two quite different ways, so that it is not manifest to you that it is the same property. Suppose we now try to explain how it is that you can be aware of one and the same property in two quite different ways. We can give the answer again that the difference in the two moments of awareness is a matter of different descriptions of the property having been activated. But those descriptions will themselves use general terms. For each such general term we can ask how awareness provides knowledge of the property for which it stands. But there will again be the possibility of different types of awareness of the property for which the general term stands. So these (p. 656) differences have to be characterized somehow. Somewhere this process will have to bottom out in a characterization of a way of being aware of an object that is not provided by specifying the descriptions activated in that moment of awareness. Moreover, this approach takes grasp of predicates to be more primitive than the awareness of objects that provides our knowledge of the references of singular terms. In particular, it supposes that the use of predicates in quantified expressions such as descriptions is more basic than the awareness of objects that provides knowledge of the references of singular terms. The argument of the logical atomists was that a grasp of quantified propositions depends on an understanding of atomic propositions: there must Page 9 of 17

Consciousness and Reference be singular terms as basic as predicates. Suppose we have two such basic singular terms: ‘logically proper names’. Suppose these two singular terms refer to the same concrete object, and that you cannot in inference trade on their identity of reference. And suppose that in both cases it is awareness of the object that provides knowledge of reference of the term. There must then be a difference between the awareness that provided knowledge of the reference of the one term and the awareness that provided knowledge of the reference of the other term. But this difference cannot be explained by appealing to different predicates that characterize the two modes of awareness of the object. For we agreed that there are no predicates more primitive than those names. There must, then, be some other difference between the two different ways of experiencing the object. Finally, we have to bear in mind that there can be differences in one's awareness of an object or property consistently with manifest sameness of the object or property: we do have a capacity to keep track of objects or properties across phenomenological variation in our experience of them. So some phenomenological variation is consistent with manifest sameness of the object. On a descriptivist approach to characterizing the awareness of the object that provides knowledge of the reference of a term, it is hard to see how to draw the right distinctions here. There must be variation in the associated descriptions, to acknowledge the phenomenological variation associated with turns of the head or momentary occlusion of the object. There must be similarity or some systematic correspondence in the associated descriptions, to underpin the manifest sameness of the object across these variations. It is not easy to see how to specify which similarities of description matter for manifest sameness of reference. Russell himself developed an alternative approach to the problem. Rather than appealing to a difference in type of representation associated with different ways of experiencing one and the same object, he held that ultimately reference is to objects that we can experience in only one way. So we keep the idea that we should characterize consciousness in Moore's terms, as the holding of a generic relation between the self and an object. But we should restrict the range of the relation. We should keep it restricted to objects of which the subject automatically has comprehensive knowledge. This in effect was the solution adopted by Russell and Moore, when they talked of direct awareness as a relation between the subject and a sense‐datum. Even when Moore liberalized the notion to material objects, he tended to talk of such items as ‘the front of a chair’, of which the subject might be held to have comprehensive (p. 657) knowledge. This kind of solution has not been widely endorsed in the analytical tradition, but I think that it does, in effect, live on in the phenomenological tradition. When theorists talk about ‘the ontology of the lived world’ of a subject, I think that what they have in mind is an ontology of objects each of which is comprehensively given to the subject, so that issues about partial knowledge or the informativeness of identities simply do not arise within the ontology of the lived world. The problems here have to do with the difficulty of explaining the relations between these comprehensively known objects and the partially known objects in terms of which we ordinarily think. The ‘lived chair’ of which we have comprehensive knowledge seems a Page 10 of 17

Consciousness and Reference quite different kind of object from the everyday chair, that has a history unknown to most of its users, and all kinds of forgotten objects under the cushions. The problems of explaining what the ‘lived chair’ and the ordinary chair have to do with one another are so great that you really may wind up embracing a kind of idealism, and abandoning the ordinary chair altogether.

Page 11 of 17

Consciousness and Reference

37.4 Consciousness as a Three‐place Relation Intuitively, our problem is that there can be different views of the same object, and this way of putting the problem suggests a solution. We have to factor in the standpoint from which the scene is being observed. We should think of consciousness of the object not as a two‐place relation between a person and an object, but as a three‐place relation between a person, a standpoint, and an object. You always experience an object from a standpoint. And you can experience one and the same object from different standpoints. You and I might have an argument about the best view to be had of San Francisco. You think the view of the whole peninsula from Twin Peaks can't be beaten, I prefer the view from across the bay, of the town's tallest buildings floating above the fog. What notion of a ‘view’ are we using? What is a view? To characterize a ‘view’ you say what things are in the scene. And you say from where they are being viewed. This characterization does not somehow miss out the crucial thing: the ‘mental paint’ that is induced in the spectator, or the ‘representations’ the spectator is supposed to form. You have told the whole story about the view when you have specified what is being seen and where it is being seen from. We can think of this kind of characterization as using the three‐place relation of experiencing an object from a standpoint that we need in addressing the problem of partial awareness. The notion of a standpoint must encompass more than merely the position of the observer, but to make explicit the conditions on an account of what is included we have to step back a little. Our aim is to characterize a notion of knowledge of things more fundamental than our knowledge of truths. When you have this knowledge of a thing, that constitutes your knowledge of the reference of a term referring to the (p. 658) thing. The notion of a standpoint comes in because you can have knowledge of one and the same thing from different standpoints. Earlier I remarked that Frege in effect proposed that the issues here could be structured around the notion of informativeness. In the basic cases we are considering, your understanding of two co‐referential terms t1 and t2 is provided by your having knowledge of the thing referred to. Suppose your understanding of t1 is provided by your experience of the thing from standpoint X, and your understanding of t2 is also provided by your experience of the thing from standpoint X. That is constitutive of your understanding the identity statement ‘t1 is identical to t2’ as uninformative; as an instance of the logical law of identity. Understanding the terms in this way, you have the right to trade on identity in inferring from ‘t1 is F’ and ‘t2 is G’ to ‘something is both F and G’. In contrast, suppose your experiencing the object from standpoint X provides your understanding of t1, and your experiencing the object from some quite different standpoint Y provides your understanding of the co‐referential term t2. This constitutes your understanding the identity statement ‘t1 is identical to t2’ as informative; it is not merely an instance of the logical law of identity. You do not have the right to trade on identity in an inference from ‘t1 is F’ and ‘t2 is G’ to ‘something is both F and G’. To reach that conclusion using those premises you have to add a further premise, Page 12 of 17

Consciousness and Reference ‘t1 is t2’. The points in this paragraph are all laid down in advance of any substantive description of the notion of a ‘standpoint’. These points set out the basic conditions that have to be met when we do give a substantive characterization of what it takes to be observing an object from one standpoint or another. The natural way to begin on a substantive characterization of the notion of a ‘standpoint’ is to proceed sensory modality by sensory modality. The ‘standpoint’ from which you are observing an object will in the first instance be given by specifying a particular time and place. But the significance of location for which identities are informative will depend on the specifics of the sensory modality being used. In particular, it will depend on the details of the phenomena of object constancy for the modality. Suppose you want to characterize the view that someone currently has of the Taj Mahal. We say which thing it is and which person is in question. Then to describe the standpoint explicitly we have to say which sensory modality is involved; and that will determine what further factors we have to fill in. For example, suppose the modality is vision. Then we need, further, position, but also the relative orientations of the viewer and object, how close the viewer is to the object, whether there is anything obstructing the light between them, and so on. In the case of hearing, a rather different set of factors would be relevant: not just which object was in question, but what sounds it was making, and the obstruction of light would not be to the point, though the obstruction of sound would be. We do not usually spell out all these conditions, though we are perfectly capable of articulating them when they are important in particular cases. We will have to keep in mind the dynamics of the experience; that experience is typically temporally extended. We should not think of experience of an object over time, as it moves, or as you move around it, as a matter of having a series of (p. 659) momentary views of the thing from different standpoints. It may be that if you move from position S1 to position S2, keeping your eye on the thing, it is manifest in experience that this is one and the same thing: the visual demonstrative t1 that you use at S1 is manifestly referring to the same thing as the visual demonstrative t2 that you use at S2, and the identity ‘t1 is t2’ is uninformative. Nonetheless, it may also be that if you were placed initially at S1 and then a moment later at S2 you would not be able to formulate such an uninformative identity, because you had not kept your eye on the object in the meantime and so could reasonably wonder whether you were encountering the same object again. The dynamics of experience—which things you are keeping track of over time—have to enter into the characterization of your standpoint on a scene. As I said, in practice we do not need to make all the relevant parameters here explicit, because we are able to imagine how things are from standpoints other than our current standpoint. In performing this exercise you can use the fact of the similarity of your visual system to the other person's visual system, without having to make explicit what all the relevant points of similarity are. So your knowledge of the other person's interests and of

Page 13 of 17

Consciousness and Reference the scene may be enough to allow you to determine, by imagining the other person's perception, the saliencies of the scene. In carrying out this exercise of articulating the notion of a standpoint we show how we can characterize a way of experiencing an object without appealing to either the idea that ‘ways’ are characterized by associated representations or the idea that ‘ways’ are characterized by the idiosyncracies of the mental paint involved. Rather than either the idea of an intervening level of mental representation or the idea of an intervening level of mental paint, we can simply appeal to the notion of experience as a three‐place relation between an object, an experiencer, and a standpoint. In this way we can do justice to Russell's notion of acquaintance as a knowledge of things more basic than knowledge of truths.

37.5 Revelation Why should we pursue Russell's idea that consciousness, or experience of the world, has a role to play in explaining our knowledge of reference? Intuitively, experience of things provides us with grasp of what they are. Experience of the world reveals something to us, provides us with some understanding of what is there. It is not difficult to make sense of the idea of an animal that can be said to represent its environment, even without ascribing consciousness to the animal. In the case of honey bees, for example, you might feel quite sure that they are representing the locations of targets to one another yet not confident about whether they are conscious. Such an animal is certainly representing the affordances provided by the objects around it. Without consciousness, though, it is hard to see how the animal could have any grasp of the categorical objects and properties that ground those affordances (Campbell 2002). This intuitive idea seems naturally applicable to demonstratives (p. 660) referring to perceived concrete things, such as ‘that woman’ or ‘that tree’: experience of the things provides knowledge of what is being talked about. The idea also seems appealing when we consider the names of colours: knowledge of the references of colour terms seems to be provided by experience of the colours. Russell provided a canonical text that dominates current discussion of the idea that acquaintance reveals some aspect of the world to us. However, he does not focus on the notion of a categorical property. I want to close by remarking that despite the frequency with which it is cited, this passage is currently quite misunderstood; and anyhow it does not provide the most promising way of pursuing the idea that acquaintance reveals what is out there. Russell said: The particular shade of colour that I am seeing … may have many things to be said about it … But such statements, though they make me know truths about the colour, do not make me know the colour itself any better than I did before: so far Page 14 of 17

Consciousness and Reference as concerns knowledge of the colour itself, as opposed to knowledge of truths about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely when I see it, and no further knowledge of it is even theoretically possible. (1912: 47) This passage was given a brief but influential gloss by Johnston:

Russell's view here is that one naturally does take and should take one's visual experience as of, e.g. a canary yellow surface, as completely revealing the intrinsic nature of canary yellow, so that canary yellow is counted as having just those essential and intrinsic features which are evident in an experience as of canary yellow. (1997: 138–9) The idea is now interpreted to be that experience reveals something of the nature or essence of the world to us. It is in this strong sense that experience provides us with knowledge of what we are referring to: it provides us with knowledge of the nature or essence of the thing. Most writers have taken it that the idea here is not just that if X is the nature, or essence, of the referent then experience provides you with knowledge of X. Rather, experience has to provide you with knowledge that X is the nature, or essence, of the referent.

To review the situation. Russell argued that our knowledge of truths depends on something more fundamental, our knowledge of things. Knowledge of things is provided by acquaintance with—that is, direct awareness of—those things. Currently many writers are trying to explain the intuitive notion of direct awareness here as a matter of the subject having propositional knowledge of the nature, or essence, of the referent. This way of explaining the idea immediately has far‐reaching implications. For example, in a careful recent discussion Byrne and Hilbert (forthcoming) propose that the doctrine of revelation, as applied to colour terms, should be regarded as the conjunction of two theses. First, that if it is in the nature of the colours that p, then after careful reflection on colour experience it seems to be in the nature of the colours that p. Secondly, if after careful reflection on colour experience it seems to be in the nature of the colours that p, then it is in the nature of the colours that p. As Byrne and Hilbert point out, this doctrine immediately threatens physicalism about the colours. If it is in the nature of the colours to (p. 661) be physical‐reflectance types, for instance, then by this doctrine of revelation it should seem after careful reflection on colour experience that colours are physical‐ reflectance types. But no such thing is true; you could reflect on colour experience as carefully as you liked for as long as you liked without it seeming that colours had any such physical nature. Similarly, Lewis considers formulating revelation as a thesis about colour experiences, or perhaps about the colours themselves. The idea here is that revelation is the doctrine that each type of colour experience has its own essence, E, and that having the experience provides you with propositional knowledge to the effect that this type of experience has the essence E:

Page 15 of 17

Consciousness and Reference Some philosophers think that each sort of colour experience has a simple, ineffable unique essence that is instantly revealed to everyone who has that experience. When I was shown the crayon mark and told that it was magenta (and I believed what I was told, and it was true) straightway I knew all there is to know about experience of magenta. I knew that it was the experience with the simple, ineffable, unique essence E. And that is all there is to it. (Or perhaps it is the colour magenta itself that has the simple, ineffable, unique essence that is instantly revealed to each beholder, or anyway to each beholder with normal visual capacities in normal light.) (Lewis 1997: 338) And, as Lewis remarks, this view is inconsistent with materialism, at any rate when materialism is formulated as the view that colour experiences and colours (and, presumably, everything else) have physical essences (1997: 338).

The trouble with this whole exegetical line is that Russell's comment is being interpreted as a remark about the relation between experience and propositional knowledge of the essences or natures of colours. This misses the point that Russell's remark was about knowledge of things, rather than knowledge of truths. Acquaintance with the colours is not a matter of possessing propositional knowledge about them. It is a matter of having knowledge of the thing, not knowledge of truths about natures or essences. To say that knowledge of the thing is complete is not of itself to deny the possibility of there being further propositional knowledge to be had to the effect that this thing has certain essential features. These further essential features, of which we have propositional knowledge, may indeed be physical, or of some sort quite unsuspected by the naive observer. Russell's remark about completeness of knowledge should not be read as relating to propositional knowledge of essences; the remark is, rather, his response to the problem of partial awareness. The idea is that the colours are such that there is nothing partial about our awareness of them; so we can characterize acquaintance with them fully merely by saying which colours are being encountered. There are not, on Russell's view, different ways of being acquainted with one and the same colour. The point is rather that the knowledge of the thing is complete; there is no further, non‐propositional knowledge of the thing to be had, once you have encountered it in experience. When put generally, this leads to the doctrine of special objects of awareness, which can be encountered in only one way. The advantage of this doctrine of special objects is that it lets us keep the idea of consciousness as a generic two‐place relation, so the qualitative character of a conscious experience can be fully specified (p. 662) merely by specifying the object. But, as we have seen, we do not need to hold on to the idea of consciousness as a two‐place relation: we can keep the fundamental insight yet think of acquaintance as a three‐place relation between a self, a standpoint, and the object.

Page 16 of 17

Consciousness and Reference

References Byrne, A., and Hilbert, D. R. (forthcoming), ‘Color Primitivism’, in R. Schumacher (ed.), Perception and the Status of Secondary Qualities (Dordrecht: Kluwer). Campbell, J. (2002), Reference and Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Johnston, M. (1997), ‘How to Speak of the Colors’, in A. Byrne and D. R. Hilbert (eds.), Readings on Color, i (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 137–76. Kaplan, D. (1971), ‘Quantifying In’, in L. Linsky (ed.), Reference and Modality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 112–44. Lewis, D. (1997), ‘Naming the Colors’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75: 325–42. Moore, G. E. (1903), ‘The Refutation of Idealism’, Mind, 12: 433–53. Russell, B. (1912), The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Sainsbury, M. (1979), Russell (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Van Cleve, J. (in press), ‘Troubles for Radical Transparency’.

John Campbell

John Campbell is Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, University of California at Berkeley.

Page 17 of 17

Memory

Oxford Handbooks Online Memory   Krista Lawlor The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0039

Abstract and Keywords The psychological study of memory has made exciting advances. In the last two decades neurophysiology has given us insight into what happens in the brain when we remember. First, the biology of nerve cells is much better understood; since signalling by nerve cells is altered by experience, these cells might be the elementary devices of information storage. At the higher level of brain systems, researchers have identified mechanisms that make possible various memory functions. One task for neuropsychology is to unite the results at the level of nerve cells and brain systems. One moral for the rest of us is that while we often speak of a unified capacity — memory — responsible for much that is distinctive in human life, we are really talking about a range of capacities, variously realized in the brain and nervous system. Keywords: memory, neurophysiology, information storage, brain systems, memory functions, neuropsychology, nervous system

38.1 Introduction THE psychological study of memory has made exciting advances. In the last two decades neurophysiology has given us insight into what happens in the brain when we remember (Squire and Kandel 1999). First, the biology of nerve cells is much better understood; since signalling by nerve cells is altered by experience, these cells might be the elementary devices of information storage. At the higher level of brain systems, researchers have identified mechanisms that make possible various memory functions. One task for neuropsychology is to unite the results at the level of nerve cells and brain systems. One moral for the rest of us is that while we often speak of a unified capacity—

Page 1 of 17

Memory memory—responsible for much that is distinctive in human life, we are really talking about a range of capacities, variously realized in the brain and nervous system. Likewise, in the last two decades episodic and working memory have continued to be subjects of important and productive research (Tulving 1993; Baddeley 2001; Baddeley, Conway, and Aggelton 2001). And cognitive psychology has given us insight into reconstructive processes responsible for simple recall and autobiography. Emphasizing the reconstructive nature of memory focuses attention on sources of memory distortion, a topic with great social importance (Schacter 1995). It is also an exciting time for the philosophy of memory. Old issues are enlivened by fresh research, and new issues emerge as conceptual connections are forged at the heart of philosophy of mind, language, metaphysics, and action theory.

(p. 664)

38.2 Memory and Realism about the Past

Memory tells us about the past—this is common sense. It is also common sense that the past is real, something that memory can tell us about. Scepticism in the epistemology of memory is possible, of course, as Russell (1922: 159–60) famously notes: There is no logical impossibility in the hypothesis that the world sprang into being five minutes ago, exactly as it then was, with a population that ‘remembered’ a wholly unreal past. Russell goes on to claim that the hypothesis is, like all sceptical hypotheses, uninteresting. Whether Russell is right or not about the interest of scepticism, recently realism about the past has presented the more important philosophical problem.

Realism about the past implies that statements about the past are either true or false, whether or not we can confront evidence for them. Either I was in Tanner Library on 17 November 1994 or I wasn't. Moreover, it seems we can understand such a claim despite the fact that there is no evidence now for or against. So realism about the past presents a problem for those who hold that understanding the meaning of a sentence requires being able to confront the conditions under which the sentence is true (Dummett 1969). The problem for such a broadly speaking verificationist theory of meaning is that the past is unrevisitable. (In this way, the past is not a foreign country.) One response for the verificationist (Green 2001) is to reconsider the kind of evidence that memory can provide. Our memories can after all give us evidence that we had evidence in the past. I remember the general fact of being a student at the University of Michigan in 1994. So I have evidence now that on 17 November 1994 either I had evidence that I was in Tanner Library or I had evidence I wasn't. It is only on such memorial grounds, the verificationist might argue, that we meaningfully assert statements of the form P or not‐P about the past.

Page 2 of 17

Memory Dummett suggests that such a manoeuvre is still ‘repugnant’ (2002: 28), as it conflicts with our intuition that what makes statements about the past true is independent of whether we have now any grounds whatsoever for asserting them. Modifying his earlier view, Dummett (2002) rejects radical verificationism, in favour of the view that a statement about the past is true if a suitably placed observer could have confronted evidence for it, and our knowing as much is central to our understanding such statements. Whether verificationists can meet the challenge that realism presents, the burden is not solely theirs, for the point is that our common‐sense realist convictions about the past need active defence. We must say something about how it is that we can even understand past‐tense statements, such as ‘Yesterday, it was raining’, if the truth of such statements transcends our ability to confront evidence for them. Christopher Peacocke (1999, 2001) argues that memory plays a constitutive role here: what it is to understand past‐tense statements is to have information of a kind that only a (p. 665) capacity for being causally affected by past events—that is, memory—could provide. (Compare: our understanding of spatial statements such as ‘Memorial Church is ten yards from here’ requires information about the spatial layout of the world that only perception could provide.) On Peacocke's view, a defence of realism about the past begins with the fact that memory is one of several information systems (Evans 1982) and the fact that the content of memory beliefs is externally individuated (Burge 1979). John Campbell (1994) argues on similar lines that realism about the past is a presupposition of our ordinary conception of memory as an informational system. For Campbell, however, this result about memory comes within a larger story about the conceptual requirements for self‐consciousness. Campbell argues that self‐consciousness requires one to grasp one's own causal and temporal structure: one must be able to think of oneself as having internal states that cause other internal states as well as change in external objects, and of events as occurring at particular times. Thus, self‐consciousness demands one have more powerful timekeeping sensitivities than some animals possess—one cannot simply be sensitive to time's passage in cycles or phases. Self‐consciousness, on Campbell's view, requires all the capacities needed for autobiographical memory. We will see more about proposed links between autobiographical memory and self‐ consciousness below. For now, note that Campbell's broadly Strawsonian programme shifts emphasis from the role of causation in an analysis of what memory is (Martin and Deutscher 1966; Deutscher 1989) to the role the concept of causation plays in our capacities for particular kinds of memory. New research in developmental psychology on the role of causal concepts in childhood amnesia and in cognitive ethology on the role of timekeeping in episodic memory (Hoerl and McCormack 2001) points to strong bonds between memory and capacities for causal and temporal thought.

Page 3 of 17

Memory

38.3 Memorial Representations What role do representations have in making memory possible? Is memory always mediated by memorial images, as naive indirect realism would have it? What then would distinguish memory from imagination? Or is memory an unmediated access to the past, as direct realism would have it? Such questions are the traditional concern of the epistemologist (Audi 1998). Foundational questions in the philosophy of mind also arise concerning memorial representation: Can we make sense of the notion of a memory trace? Does connectionism add to our power for modelling encoding and retrieval? Does memory store a distinctive sort of ‘non‐conceptual’ content? The dominant view of memory in contemporary philosophy of mind and cognitive science is indirect realism centring on the notion of a ‘memory trace’ or ‘engram’ (Schacter 1996). But the notion of a trace is more than simply that of a representation—a trace is a permanent, discrete information store, providing a causal link (p. 666) to the past perceptual experience, whose staying power explains or justifies one's remembering. Opponents of the notion of a memory trace object to the independence of the trace from processes of remembering (Christensen and Kornblith 1997) and point to the way remembering relies on information left in the external world (Clark and Chalmers 1998; Dennett 2000), as well as to the fact that what we call a memory is a joint product of memory trace and cue. A memory is not simply an ‘activated engram’ (Schacter 1996). Some have tried to reply to these concerns by revising the core notion, claiming a memory trace is a ‘distributed representation’ in a connectionist network, where traces are ‘dynamic’ and contribute to a ‘composite, superimposed memory representation’ (McClelland and Rumelhart 1986: 193; see also McClelland 1995; Sutton 1998). The fact that ‘the units that participate in representing one episode or event also participate in representing other episodes’ (McClelland 1995: 70) is supposed to be a strength of connectionist models in accounting for memory distortion, but critical tests of the superiority of connectionist models await development (Ratcliff and McKoon 2000). Moreover, it is unclear just what a ‘superimposed’ representation is, and how, since both memorial representation and trace are ex hypothesi changed with every new stimulus, particular experiences can be preserved with any accuracy. (It is important not to lose sight of how accurate memory can be, despite the potential for distortion.) Further clarification is needed if we are to assess the connectionist alternative. Does memory store a distinctive sort of ‘non‐conceptual content’ (Evans 1982)? The question is vexed, in no small part because the debate can be cast in terms of the existence of two kinds of content, informational versus conceptually articulated, or in terms of whether it is appropriate to ascribe contentful states to creatures who lack the conceptual resources to articulate or grasp the content. McDowell (1994) holds that the ascription of content to creatures without relevant conceptual capacities is only pragmatically appropriate; in reality computational processes in such creatures are purely syntactic as opposed to semantic or contentful. Stalnaker (2003) takes a more Page 4 of 17

Memory liberal view, arguing that while certain states or activities require conceptual resources, the content that characterizes all kinds of activities from perception and memory to speech acts can be uniformly understood in information‐theoretic terms. Michael Martin's argument (1992) for non‐conceptual content begins with the fact that one might fail, for lack of the relevant concepts or through inattention, to form a belief at the time of perception, but later one's memory of what one perceived makes new beliefs possible. So, Martin claims, one's initial experience must be characterized by non‐conceptual content, which is preserved by memory and provides the raw materials for later belief. It is not clear whether Martin's argument is decisive, however, since it seems to rest on the claim that the authority of memory derives from its being the ‘re‐presentation’ of an earlier experience. McDowell might respond that memorial experience is not the mere re‐ presentation of earlier experience, but a new experience, with newly constructed content, built out of more basic raw materials. The debate between conceptualists and non‐ conceptualists may not yet be settled, (p. 667) but Martin's insight is a good one: a more careful understanding of memorial experience may hold the key to a resolution.

38.4 Memory, Persons, Normative Psychology Traditional questions about memory and persons focus on the metaphysics of personal identity. With new appreciation for the complexities of memory, new questions about personhood come into view. In his study of multiple‐personality disorder Ian Hacking (1995) details how nineteenth century memory sciences became sources of treatment for psychological illness. One upshot of Hacking's analysis is a limited but deeply important indeterminacy in the personal past, not at the level of events—Hacking is a realist about past events—but at the level of human actions. Briefly, his argument is this: all intentional action is action ‘under a description’ (Anscombe 1959); in remembering intentional action one's description employs present concepts, which may have been unavailable to one as an actor in the past. Since it is not determined in the past which concepts one will have in future, one's agential past is likewise not fully determined, but is a story to be told in the present. Hacking's conclusion is not just Freud's that past events may be given new meaning as new conceptual resources make reconstrual in recollection possible, but the more radical claim that one's actions themselves are sensitive to reconstrual. In a sense, then, actions remembered may not have occurred, because the descriptions under which they were chosen are not the descriptions under which they now make most sense. If Hacking is right about this curious sensitivity to reconstrual of personal agential pasts, the door is opened to important normative questions about what persons should be, and what psychology should do for them: should persons have coherent pasts, and how should the therapist help in constructing a narrative past for the patient, since this construction helps to shape the facts about what the person did? (See also Engel 1998.)

Page 5 of 17

Memory

38.5 Memory and the Self Recently philosophers and psychologists have begun tracing new connections, beyond that between memory and person, between memory and a more basic notion of the self as the subject of experience, the locus of a point of view on the world, and as a potentially autonomous agent.

38.5.1 Episodic Memory To grasp how these connections emerge we must start with episodic memory. Of all the kinds of memory feat of which humans are capable, none is as gripping as (p. 668) memory for past episodes of one's life. I remember the fall I took skating when I was eight, and how many stitches were needed for the gash. Exactly what distinguishes my episodic memory of the fall from other kinds of memory, such as my semantic or declarative memory that ice is hard? (See Schacter and Tulving 1994; Schacter et al. 2000.) As noted above, Campbell (1994) argues that episodic memory is bound up with a host of conceptual capacities required for being self‐conscious. Dokic (2001) argues that episodic memory is an experience whose content is that of a past experience, where the content is preserved through a continuous causal chain or ‘information link’. Although one need not be aware of this causal link, one must be aware of the memory as having its source in one's own past. Thus, according to Dokic, one must be capable of thought about oneself, or what we might call ‘reflexive’ thought. Moreover, according to Dokic, this sort of reflexive thinking is only possible if one can think metarepresentational thoughts— thoughts involving mental representations that have mental representations as their objects. (Whether reflexivity requires metarepresentation is open to question; we shall see a specific alternative account of reflexive thought presently.) Others argue that the common‐sense conception of episodic memory involves ‘direct acquaintance’ with the past through ‘mental time travel’ or ‘reliving’ the past. How are we to make sense of such notions? Michael Martin (2001) makes an interesting stab, arguing that in episodic memory what is retained is an apprehending of an event, where the apprehending is itself an episode, and a conscious experience. We might find this perplexing: how can an experience, as opposed to a representation of the experience, be retained in memory? Martin replies that ‘memory can be experientially the same as perception through being the representational recall of such an experiential encounter’ (2001: 270). In other words, remembering counts as the retention of an experience—as reliving the past—because memorial representations are of the original encounter, and experiential sameness of memory and percept consists in linked intentional content.

Page 6 of 17

Memory Martin's focus on ‘mental time travel’ owes much to the work of the psychologist Endel Tulving. Tulving's understanding of ‘mental time travel’, however, is less focused on the notion of direct apprehension of the past, and more on an array of conceptual capacities he takes to be required for genuine episodic memory. In the early seventies Tulving's seminal research was framed by a distinction between semantic and pure‐episodic memory, or memory for events. Soon enough focus on memory for events was refined to a concern specifically for memory of events as they occur in the course of one's own life history. Tulving's most recent work expands on this theme: Episodic memory has to do with one's ‘autonoetic’ awareness of one's experiences in the continuity of subjectively apprehended time that extends both backward into the past in the form of ‘remembering’ and forward into the future, in the form of ‘thinking about’ or imagining or ‘planning for’ the future. This definition [sic] emphasizes the conjunction of three ideas: self, autonoetic awareness, and subjectively sensed time. (2001: 270) (p. 669) Now conceived as fully autobiographical, episodic memory is characterized by: (a) a capacity for thought about specific times and places of events; (b) a grasp of time as continuous, forming a framework in which the specific events of one's life have a position; (c) a capacity for self‐consciousness (i.e. ‘autonoetic awareness’); and, finally, since the relevant notion of the self is the notion of a creature with a future as well as a past, who plans future events as much as recalls past events, (d) a capacity for agency (see also Wheeler et al. 1997; Moscovitch 2000).

In (a) and (b) Tulving's claims agree with Campbell's about the role of our grasp of a space–time framework and a capacity for temporal thought. It should be noted that Tulving also claims, with many others, that because such advanced cognitive capacities are required, only humans enjoy genuine episodic memory. The debate concerning animal cognition, however, has only begun. It is now well known that animals remember specific events: scrub jays, for instance, recall the where and when of food caching (McCormack 2001), and so seem capable of thought about particular past events. But does a jay have episodic memory of the kind humans have, recollecting and planning specific events of food caching as occurring in the course of its life? Tulving hypothesizes that animals lack both self‐consciousness and the flexible cognition required for agency—that is, both (c) and (d)—and so are not capable of genuine episodic memory. Discerning just who is capable of episodic memory, then, requires greater clarity about both self‐consciousness and agency.

38.5.2 Self‐consciousness

Page 7 of 17

Memory There is broad agreement among philosophers and psychologists that episodic memory requires self‐consciousness. But agreement here is only as deep as agreement about what self‐consciousness in turn requires, and the topic of self‐consciousness has been the focus of philosophical dispute for a long time. Minimally, the consensus is that self‐ consciousness involves the capacity to entertain thoughts about oneself, or what we have called ‘reflexive’ thoughts. I have to be able to think about my fall on the ice, and my stitches, to remember the episode. So the question becomes: What makes thought reflexive? How can a representational system have thoughts about itself? Over this question, too, there has been much dispute and confusion. John Perry's work (1998) is a helpful tonic. Perry begins by distinguishing a broad set of agent‐relative thoughts of which genuinely reflexive thoughts are a subset.1 An agent‐relative thought about a thing is possible because the agent has specific means of finding out about and affecting the thing, which means are keyed to the role the thing happens to occupy with respect to the agent. For instance, I think an agent‐relative thought about the glass of water to my left ‘There's a glass of water’ because the glass is to my left—it occupies the agent‐relative role to the left—and I can both look left and reach (p. 670) left. To have a genuinely reflexive thought, Perry claims, two conditions must be met. First, one must have various normal means of finding out about and affecting the thing that occupies the agent‐relative role of identity. For instance, I can look in the mirror and touch my nose, glance down at my feet and brush the sand from them. These are normal routes of self‐ perception and self‐directed action. Second, one must be faced with information about oneself deriving from non‐normal sources, which information must be integrated with information derived from normal sources. For instance, if John Perry reads on a printed schedule that John Perry is giving a talk at noon, then if he is to get himself to the talk on time he must integrate that information with information he can gain in the normal ways. This integration task is crucial: if one were never faced with the problem of integrating objective information about oneself and information gained from normal sources, one would never need a self‐notion. Normally self‐informative perception (looking down at one's feet) and normally self‐affecting action (brushing them) could be linked without an explicit representation of oneself. (One simply brushes what one is looking at.) The representational store that integrates both kinds of information is what Perry terms a ‘self‐notion’. Possessing a self‐notion, one is in a position to think reflexive thoughts— thoughts that are about oneself. On Perry's theory of reflexive thought, then, no metarepresentational abilities are required. One needs coordinated means of investigating and acting on the thing that happens to be oneself. That makes it easier to imagine scrub jays having reflexive thoughts, and so meeting Tulving's condition (c). However, on Perry's view one need not have a self‐notion at all until one also has non‐normal avenues for gathering objective information about oneself. Much depends then on whether scrub jays (or other candidates for episodic memory) gain information about themselves through non‐normal means. More research is required to settle this question. (In carrying out our investigations here

Page 8 of 17

Memory it will be important to observe that what counts as normal means of gathering information is species‐specific. It is normal for humans to gain information about themselves by looking in a mirror from a foot or two away. This perceptual avenue presumably counts as non‐normal for a gorilla or a scrub jay.) It should be noted that some memory capacities must already come into play in order to build an enduring self‐notion and thereby to engage in reflexive ‘I’‐thoughts. And here we face a concern. If reflexive thought requires storage capacities on the scale required for full‐blown episodic memory, then we're chasing our tails in a circle, at least if we hope to define episodic memory in terms of a capacity for reflexive thought. Fortunately, if Perry is correct, it would seem little memory is called for in order to possess a self‐notion. Short‐term stores would seem enough to enable one to integrate information gained through normal and non‐normal epistemic enquiries, and to execute actions based on that information. The memory demands for reflexive thought are less than for full‐blown memory of specific events of a subject's life. So no problem of circularity arises with Tulving's requirement (c), on which episodic memory requires self‐consciousness, where that is understood minimally as reflexive thought. (p. 671)

With Tulving's requirement (d) we face a similar concern: memory capacities must also already come into play in order to be an agent, a creature who directs her actions as much as recalls them. Just how much memory is that?

38.5.3 Memory and Agency How much memory does it take to be an agent? Is memory sufficient to ground reflexive ‘I’‐thoughts also sufficient to ground an autonomous self who directs her own actions? To begin answering these difficult questions we do well to distinguish various notions of self in play. David Velleman (2006) notes that when we speak of the self, we too often simply assume that the self to whom autonomous actions are attributed is the self whose sameness constitutes personal identity over time and the self whose psychological characteristics encode a person's sense of who she is. But we should be more careful: what constitutes each of these selves may be different. It might seem that more memory is required to underwrite autonomous agency than it takes to underwrite self‐consciousness or reflexive thought. After all, as we have seen, only brief stretches of memory would seem necessary for thinking reflexive ‘I’‐thoughts, and how could that be enough to produce autonomous agency? It is important to see that this is a genuinely open question, the answer to which depends on one's theory of agency. On Velleman's view of what makes action autonomous, for instance, memory for reflexive thought is memory enough. Autonomous action, Velleman argues (2005), occurs when behaviour is governed by the desire for narrative coherence. Narrative coherence need only accrue over relatively short time frames—only long enough to say, ‘I'm reaching for Page 9 of 17

Memory the glass’ and then reach for it. Working memory sufficient to form intentions and get them acted on (what psychologists call ‘prospective memory’) suffices. Narrative coherence over longer time frames, of the sort required to ground the self as a person, isn't required to ground the self as agent. If Velleman is right, the relevant memory demands for autonomous action are less than for memory of specific events of one's life, so no problem of circularity need arise for a view, like Tulving's, on which episodic memory is defined in terms of a capacity for autonomous action. One might object that merely prospective memory cannot be enough for autonomous action. Imagine an amnesiac who makes perfect sense of his actions in intervals of several minutes, and who decides in favour of one course over another, but who lacks the larger frame of a life story (or even a significant stretch thereof) in which such local narratives fit. The amnesiac can seem both less a self and less autonomous, despite his capacities for short‐term narrative coherence. (Note that if this objection stands, a circle again threatens Tulving's proposed definition of episodic memory: if agency requires fully‐fledged autobiographical memory, then we cannot say, with Tulving, that episodic memory is defined by a capacity for agency.) How deep can memory failure go before we withhold our attribution of autonomous agency? How much memory does it take to ground each of the selves—moral, (p. 672) psychological, metaphysical—we have an interest in? We have only recently begun to have the philosophical resources to address these questions with rigour. One thing is clear: in light of recent philosophical advances into the nature of the self and self‐ consciousness we can no longer rest content with simple formulas and general truisms about the importance of memory to selfhood.

38.6 Memory and Inference That memory is central to rationality and inference is another truism that new psychological research and philosophical enquiry force us to advance beyond.

38.6.1 The Role of Inference in Memory: Source Monitoring Epistemologists routinely distinguish memory and inference, as each has a distinct role in the production of knowledge. Perhaps for this reason, questions about the role of inference in memory have not received much notice from philosophers. The recent explosion of research in psychology on suggestibility and other sources of memory distortion (Schacter 1995) promises to challenge philosophical complacency about such questions. Although memory failure and distortion can hold a grim fascination for us, what is most interesting is not the distortion itself, but the light it casts on the mechanisms at work when memory is veridical. One important paradigm that seeks a unified account of many such mechanisms is the ‘source‐monitoring framework’ (Mitchell Page 10 of 17

Memory and Johnson 2000), according to which memory for attitudes and events is driven by both subperson‐level and person‐level inferences about the original sources of one's information. If the SMF is correct, inference plays a central role, often unnoticed by the subject, in the construction of veridical memory. Philosophers have only begun to take account of the implications of the claims made by the SMF. For instance, that self‐ knowledge of one's past attitudes might involve inference contravenes at least one important theory of diachronic self‐knowledge (see Shoemaker 1996; Lawlor 2005).

38.6.2 The Role of Memory in Inference: Content Externalism and Content Preservation Clearly, memory plays a role in inference. No one could reason without the capacity to hold two thoughts together or to draw new conclusions from knowledge held in long‐term memory. Until recently, however, psychologists have tended to separate their study of memory from their study of inference. (For some new work on the role of working memory in cognition see Logie and Gilhooly 1998.) Philosophers have tended to focus on two questions about memory's role in inference. (p. 673)

(1) First, if all inference relies on memory, does that pose a problem for semantic externalism? Semantic externalism is the view, roughly, that the semantic value of words, thoughts, and other representations is determined by facts metaphysically external to the individual thinker and thus potentially outside her epistemic ken (Burge 1979). Many have held that because memory plays a central role in inference, if semantic externalism is true then validity is not a property of an inference that is knowable a priori to the inference maker (Boghossian 1992). Briefly, the argument is this. Suppose one makes an inference about a thing one remembers and takes oneself to currently perceive. One reasons: ice is slippery (memory‐based belief), and that is ice (perception), so that is slippery. Now suppose that one has unknowingly been switched from earth to Twin Earth, where the chemical composition of the stuff called ‘ice’ is not H2O, but XYZ. If semantic externalism is true, the argument goes, the semantic values of one's ‘ice’ tokens are fixed by two different environments, so one's memorial belief is framed with a token mental representation, ‘ice’, that refers to frozen H2O, but one's current perception is framed with a token mental representation, ‘ice’, that refers to frozen XZY. When the time comes to reason, tokens of the same type are taken to co‐refer, but, as our case reveals, purportedly co‐referential tokens may not in fact co‐refer, and one won't be sensitive to the difference. Consequently, the argument continues, if semantic externalism is true, then it is possible for one to reason equivocally without knowing as much. Some have taken this argument to constitute a reductio against semantic externalism, while others have argued, in a nettle‐grasping mood, that validity is thus shown to be an a posteriori property of specific inferences—knowing that one is thinking of the same things over time is required for ‘epistemically valid’ inference, and one simply cannot Page 11 of 17

Memory have such knowledge a priori (Campbell 1987; Millikan 1993). Still others, more conservatively, resolve the problem by supposing that the semantic value of token mental representations is sensitive to the context of inference (Burge 1998), so that whatever semantic externalism dictates about how the semantic values of words, thoughts, and other representations are determined, in the context of an inference the semantic value of two tokens that purport to be the same will be the same. Thus, the role of memory in inference does not disrupt our capacity to know a priori of a specific inference whether it is valid or not. The debate here rages on, and can be expected to for some time (Ludlow and Martin 1998; Nuccitelli 2003). Nonetheless, Burge's initial response retains its appeal, as it promises the least perturbation of common sense. However, it does require supposing that the reference of one's memories might shift with new environments. (2) The second question about memory's role in inference is epistemological. In the context of reasoning, one's memory must enable one to retrieve propositions (e.g. that ice is slippery), as well as to have continued access to these as one reasons. Memory thus performs a crucial service in inference, making thought content available for the duration of one's reasoning. But epistemically speaking, are new burdens added when one trusts one's memory to perform this service? Must one add to every inference a premise such as ‘my memory is working well enough to retain all the foregoing premises’? Aside from the concern that such a premise would launch a (p. 674) regress of demands to the effect that such premises are also vouchsafed, there is the additional concern that such a premise would turn all inferential justification a posteriori. After all, how do I know that my memory is working well enough unless I check? (There are further puzzles here of course about what checking could amount to, once I doubt my memory.) But certainly some of our inferences produce knowledge a priori. For example, suppose one reasons through a proof of Pythagoras's theorem. The fact that one relies on one's memory to hold premises long enough to draw the conclusion does not make one's justification for believing a2+b2=c2 a posteriori. This is common sense. As Tyler Burge (1993) puts it, memory functions in an inference to preserve content: it neither adds to justificational demands, nor enters new content into an inference (in the form of a premise concerning memory's reliability). To say as much only raises the question, why should it be that memory adds no justificational demands to inference? Burge's answer, briefly, is that one has a defeasible entitlement to trust one's memory without making memory's reliability itself a matter of further explicit judgement, because memory is a resource for reason, and reliance on such a resource in the absence of special reasons for distrust is necessary to the functioning of reason. Burge sees memory as one of several such ‘content‐preserving’ resources, along with testimony and perception. This answer, however, raises the further question, how does memory do its job of preserving content? Some have argued that because working memory involves active and ongoing reconstruction of contents, just as episodic or autobiographical memory does, no such preservation of content is possible (Christensen and Kornblith 1997). These

Page 12 of 17

Memory philosophers argue that we must change our view of justification by inference: common sense about the apriority of the conclusions of reason is overthrown in light of the reconstructive nature of all memory. To rebut this argument we must supply a specific model of how working memory might function to preserve content, while acknowledging that memory involves reconstruction. At this stage in our empirical investigations of working memory any model of how memory preserves content will be abstract, but we can nonetheless make an initial conjecture: suppose that memory preserves content in something like the way anaphoric representations preserve reference in speech. For example, when John says ‘Ken will know; he went to the meeting’, John's use of the pronoun ‘he’ refers to Ken, and in this sense manages to preserve reference throughout the duration of the utterance. If working memory involves stringing together representations in thought with anaphoric relations to each other, then content might in this way be preserved. The conjecture that working memory might involve anaphoric representation will perhaps trouble those who reject language‐of‐thought models of cognition, but for those with such scruples anaphoric thinking can itself be modelled on alternative grounds, without reliance on ‘mental pronouns’ (Lawlor 2002).

(p. 675)

38.7 Conclusion

Subjects of central importance in the philosophy of mind are illuminated when seen in light of their connection to memory. Recent work on memory has brought us to a convergence of philosophical investigations and psychological research, yielding new insights and new lines of enquiry into the nature of memorial experience, autonomous agency, self‐consciousness, and reasoning.

References Anscombe, G. E. M. (1959), Intention (Oxford: Blackwell). Audi, R. (1998), Epistemology (London: Routledge). Baddeley, A. (2001), ‘Is Working Memory Still Working’, American Psychologist, 56: 849– 64. Baddeley, C., Conway, M., and Aggelton, J. (2001) (eds.), Episodic Memory: New Directions in Research (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Boghossian, P. A. (1992), ‘Externalism and Inference’, Philosophical Issues, 2: 11–42. Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. Page 13 of 17

Memory —— (1993), ‘Content Preservation’, Philosophical Review, 102: 457–88. —— (1998), ‘Memory and Self‐knowledge’, in P. Ludlow and N. Martin (eds.), Externalism and Self‐Knowledge (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI), 351–70. Campbell, J. (1987), ‘Functional Role and Truth Conditions: Is Sense Transparent’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 61: 273–92. —— (1994), Past, Space, and Self (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Christensen, D., and Kornblith, H. (1997), ‘Testimony, Memory, and the Limits of the A Priori’, Philosophical Studies, 86: 4–20. Clark, A. (2002), ‘On Dennett: Minds, Brains, and Tools’, in H. Clapin (ed.), Philosophy of Mental Representation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 67–90. Clark A., and Chalmers, D. (1998), ‘The Extended Mind’, Analysis, 58: 10–23. Dennett, D. (2000), ‘Making Tools for Thinking’, in D. Sperber (ed.), Metarepresentations: A Multidisciplinary Perspective (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Deutscher, M. (1989), ‘Remembering “remembering”’, in J. Heil (ed.), Cause, Mind, and Reality (Kluwer, Dordrecht), 53–72. Dokic, J. (2001), ‘Is Memory Purely Preservative?’, in C. Hoerl and T. McCormack (eds.), Time and Memory (Oxford: Clarendon), 213–34. Dummett, M. (1969), ‘The Reality of the Past’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 69: 239–58. —— (2002), ‘Truth and the Past’, Journal of Philosophy, 100: 5–53. Engel, S. (1998), Context is Everything: The Nature of Memory (New York: Freeman). Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Green, K. (2001), Dummett: Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: Polity). Gunther, Y. (2003) (ed.), Essays on Nonconceptual Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Hacking, I. (1995), Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Hoerl, C., and McCormack, T. (2001) (eds.), Time and Memory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). (p. 676)

Lawlor, K. (2002), ‘Memory, Anaphora and Content Preservation’, Philosophical Studies, 109: 97–119.

Page 14 of 17

Memory —— (2005), ‘Reason and the Past: The Role of Rationality in Diachronic Self‐knowledge’, Synthese, 145/3: 467–95. Logie, R. H., and Gilhooly, K. (1998) (eds.), Working Memory and Thinking (Hove: Psychology). Ludlow, P., and Martin, N. (1998) (eds.), Externalism and Self‐Knowledge (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI). Martin, C. B., and Deutscher, M. (1966), ‘Remembering’, Philosophical Review, 75: 161– 96. Martin, M. G. F. (1992), ‘Perception, Concepts, and Memory’, Philosophical Review, 101: 745–63. —— (2001), ‘Out of the Past: Episodic Recall as Retained Acquaintance’, in C. Hoerl and T. McCormack (eds.), Time and Memory (Oxford: Clarendon), 257–84. McClelland, J. (1995), ‘Constructive Memory and Memory Distortions: A Parallel Distributed Processing Approach’, in D. Schacter (ed.), Memory Distortion (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 69–90. McCormack, T. (2001), ‘Attributing Episodic Memory to Animals and Children’, in C. Hoerl and T. McCormack (eds.), Time and Memory (Oxford: Clarendon), 285–314. McDowell, J. (1994), ‘The Content of Perceptual Experience’, Philosophical Quarterly, 44: 190–205. Millikan, R. (1993), White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Mitchell, K. J., and Johnson, M. K. (2000), ‘Source Monitoring: Atributing Memories to Sources’, in E. Tulving and F. Craik (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Memory (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 179–95. Moscovitch, M. (2000), ‘Theories of Memory and Consciousness’, in E. Tulving and F. Craik (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Memory (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 609–26. Nuccitelli, S. (2003) (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Peacocke, C. (1999), Being Known (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (2001), ‘Understanding the Past Tense’, in C. Hoerl and T. McCormack (eds.), Time and Memory (Oxford: Clarendon), 339–74. Perry, J. (1998), ‘Myself and I’, in M. Stamm (ed.), Philosophie in synthetischer Absicht (Stuttgart: Klett‐Cotta), 83–103.

Page 15 of 17

Memory Ratcliff, R., and McKoon, G. (2000), ‘Memory Models’, in E. Tulving and F. Craik (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Memory (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 571–81. Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., and the PDP research group (1986), Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, i (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Russell, B. (1922), Analysis of Mind (London: Allen & Unwin). Schacter, D. (1995) (ed.), Memory Distortion: How Minds, Brains and Societies Reconstruct the Past (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1996), Searching for Memory: The Brain, the Mind, and the Past (New York: Basic). Schacter, D., and Tulving, E. (1994), ‘What are the Memory Systems of 1994?’, in D. Schacter and E. Tulving (eds.), Memory Systems (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 1–38. Schacter, D., Wagner, A., and Buckner, R. (2000), ‘Memory Systems of 1999’, in E. Tulving and F. Craik (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Memory (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 627–43. Shoemaker, S. (1996), The First‐Person Perspective and Other Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). (p. 677)

Squire, R., and Kandel, E. (1999), Memory: From Mind to Molecules (New York: Scientific American). Stalnaker, R. (2003), ‘What Might Nonconceptual Content Be’, in Y. Gunther (ed.), Essays on Nonconceptual Content (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 95–106. Sutton, J. (1998), Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Tulving, E. (1993), ‘What Is Episodic Memory’, Current Directions in Psychological Research, 3: 67–70. —— (2001), ‘Episodic Memory and Common Sense: How Far Apart’, in A. Baddeley, M. Conway, and J. Aggelton (eds.), Episodic Memory: New Directions in Research (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 269–80. Velleman, D. (2005), ‘The Self as Narrator’, in J. Christman and J. Anderson (eds.), Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 56–76. —— (2006), Self to Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Wheeler, M., Stuss, D., and Tulving, E. (1997), ‘Toward a Theory of Episodic Memory: The Frontal Lobes and Autonoetic Consciousness’, Psychological Bulletin, 121: 331–54.

Page 16 of 17

Memory

Notes: (1) Note that in his own work Perry uses the term ‘reflexive’ to characterize a special kind of content, and not to mean, as I have here, thoughts about oneself. Perry prefers to call thoughts about oneself ‘self‐beliefs’.

Krista Lawlor

Krista Lawlor is Associate Professor of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University.

Page 17 of 17

Emotions: Motivating Feelings

Oxford Handbooks Online Emotions: Motivating Feelings   Jesse Prinz The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0040

Abstract and Keywords Historically philosophers have given considerable attention to the topic of emotions. We find important theories being proposed by Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, and Hume, among many others. In recent years, after a long hiatus, emotions have come back into vogue. Over the last few decades numerous theories of the emotions have been proposed, and there has also been a flowering of scientific research. This article does not offer a complete review of the literature. Instead, it focuses on one central debate. Roughly, it is a debate about whether emotions are thoughts or feelings. It argues that the evidence currently supports the view that emotions are feelings, and also suggests that this sheds light on the contribution that emotions make to decision making and action. Keywords: emotions, thoughts or feelings, theories of emotions, decision making, action, motivation

HISTORICALLY philosophers have given considerable attention to the topic of emotions. We find important theories being proposed by Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, and Hume, among many others. In recent years, after a long hiatus, emotions have come back into vogue. Over the last few decades numerous theories of the emotions have been proposed, and there has also been a flowering of scientific research. In this chapter I will not offer a complete review of the literature (see Prinz 2004). Instead, I will focus on one central debate. Roughly, it is a debate about whether emotions are thoughts or feelings. I will argue that the evidence currently supports the view that emotions are feelings, and I will also suggest that this sheds light on the contribution that emotions make to decision making and action.

39.1 Cognitivism Page 1 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings There are almost as many theories of the emotions as there are emotion researchers. Each contributor to this sizeable literature has a perspective on the nature of the emotions, and these perspectives often vary considerably. But within this variety a boundary can be drawn between two major classes of theories, and much of the debate about emotions has been located at the battle line. On one side, there are those who think emotions are essentially cognitive. Others deny that emotions are cognitive. In this section I will briefly present these two approaches. Within philosophy (p. 679) cognitive theories have been more popular, but I will argue that non‐cognitive theories currently enjoy more support. To say that emotions are cognitive is to say that emotions are constituted by or essentially connected to cognitive states. A cognitive state is a mental state that contains concepts. For example, being afraid may involve deployment of the concept of danger, being angry may involve the concept of a slight, and being sad may involve the concept of loss. One kind of cognitive state is a judgement. Judgements are constituted by concepts. The judgement that zebras migrate contains the concept of zebras and the concept of migration. Many cognitive theorists assume that emotions always involve judgements (Aristotle c.350BC 1984; Spinoza 1677/1994; Solomon 1976; Nussbaum 2001). For example, they say that I cannot be afraid without judging that I am in danger. Other cognitive theorists distinguish between judgements and thoughts. To judge that something is the case is tantamount to adopting the belief that it is true. If I judge that I am in danger, I must believe that I am in danger. Thoughts are less demanding. I can think about something, as when I ruminate, imagine, or reflect, without believing it. I can entertain the thought that I am in danger, even if I believe that I am not. Greenspan (1988) argues that emotions involve thoughts, rather than judgements, because we can be afraid even if we know there is not danger at hand. To illustrate Greenspan gives the example of a phobic person who knows that her phobias are irrational, but nevertheless continues to feel afraid. Armon‐Jones (1989) suggests that emotions are interpretative states. To be afraid of something is to see it as dangerous; that is, to place it under the concept of danger. Some cognitive theorists argue that emotions are nothing but cognitive states. To have an emotion is simply to make a judgement, have a thought, or conceptualize something in a certain way. This view was defended by some of the Stoic philosophers, such as Chrysippus (Nussbaum 2001). Pure cognitive theories claim that emotions do not have any other constituent parts. For example, they deny that emotions contain feelings. Pure cognitive theorists admit that we often have feelings when we emote, but they claim that those feelings are not components of our emotions. Rather, emotions can cause us to have feelings, but they need not. Pure cognitive theorists also deny that emotions necessarily involve behavioural dispositions or changes in the body. A disembodied being could have emotions on their view. To be afraid is just to deploy the concept of danger in a particular way.

Page 2 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings On the face of it pure cognitive theories may sound peculiar. Surely I can judge that something is dangerous without being afraid. Many people who smoke regard cigarettes as dangerous, but don't fear them. To use a common metaphor, emotions are not cool judgements; they are hot. In response, pure cognitive theorists can try to capture the heat of emotions by distinguishing between two different ways of thinking about danger. When I think about danger in an emotional way, it captures my attention, and leads me to focus, perhaps perseveratively, on certain features of my situation. If I am afraid of the spider on my pillow I may focus all my attention on it, and I may be flooded by thoughts about how it might harm me (see Öhman et al. 2001). A cool thought about spiders would not occupy so many of my cognitive resources. (p. 680)

This attempt to capture the heat of emotions is certainly right about one thing. Emotions do tend to promote certain patterns of thinking and attention. (See de Sousa 1987 for a theory that places emphasis on this fact.) But critics of pure cognitive theories should not be satisfied. For it seems possible to have a perseverative, attention‐demanding series of thoughts without having an emotion. Imagine a teenage boy who has a pet tarantula and delights in the fact that tarantulas are dangerous creatures. Whenever he sees his beloved pet he might attend to it and ruminate compulsively on the hideous agony its venom would cause. Still, we might imagine that this teenager takes perverse pleasure in these thoughts, and has no fear. Intuitively, fear requires more than thoughts; it requires a distinctive feeling. Or consider another example. Suppose a woman says she loves her husband, and, in keeping with the pure cognitive theory, she focuses her attention on him when he's in the room, and thinks compulsively about all of his merits. But imagine that she has no feelings, no flutter in her heart, no arousal when he nears. Imagine that despite her being fully cognizant of his merits they leave her unmoved. It would be fair to say she no longer loves him. By comparison, someone who is indifferent to jazz composition might cognitively understand that Charlie Parker was a great soloist without ever enjoying his work. Fear, love, and pleasure require more than mere thoughts; they seem to require feelings. The heat of emotions seems to have a non‐cognitive character. Recognition of this fact has led some cognitive theorists to adopt impure theories. They concede that emotions are not wholly exhausted by cognitive states. In addition, they say that emotions involve feelings. For example, Spinoza (1677/1994) argued that emotions are judgements that are accompanied by a feeling of pleasure or pain. Descartes (1649/1985) argued that emotions are judgements that follow felt movements of our animal spirits—substances that convey information about changes in our body. Many psychologists defend impure cognitive theories as well (Scherer 1984; Frijda 1986; Lazarus 1991; Roseman 1994). According to a popular class of views, emotions are feelings that are caused by appraisals. An appraisal is a judgement about a relationship between an organism and its environment that bears on well‐being (Lazarus 1991). On many psychological models we are constantly assessing our well‐being, by unconsciously and automatically asking ourselves questions such as: Does the present situation concern me? Is it consistent or inconsistent with my goals? What are my options for coping with Page 3 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings it? Am I to blame for this situation or is someone else? How certain am I about the outcome? Lazarus and Smith (1993) call these molecular appraisals, and Scherer (1984) calls them stimulus evaluation checks. For these psychologists each emotion corresponds to a different constellation of answers to questions like these. Fear arises when I judge that a situation concerns me, that it's inconsistent with my goals, that it is caused by something other than me, that the outcome is uncertain, and that my coping options include finding a way to escape. When I make this collection of judgements a feeling follows, and that feeling is defined as fear. Defenders of impure cognitive theories concede that emotions include a non‐cognitive feeling component, but they insist that a feeling would not qualify as an emotion if it were not accompanied by a cognitive state. But this raises a (p. 681) question: Why are cognitive states necessary for emotions? Emotional feelings can arise without any thoughts, conceptualizations, or judgements. Think about what happens when you trip while walking across a room: you immediately experience what feels like surprise. Or imagine hearing a blood curdling scream; it would send a shiver of fear down your spine. Or recall a time when you've accidentally taken a sip of rotten milk; the result is extreme disgust. Or imagine if a stranger knocked into you while passing on the street; you'd probably experience a sudden feeling of anger. Or think about what happens when your lover tickles you; you giggle with delight. In each of these cases an intense feeling arises extremely quickly, and the feeling is recognizable as an emotion. The examples suggest that emotions can be triggered by perceptual experiences without the help of thoughts, judgements, or conceptualizations. The sound of a scream can instil fear; the taste of rotten milk can trigger disgust. Cognitive states do not seem to be necessary for emotions after all. In response to examples of this kind cognitive theorists have two choices. They can either argue that, despite appearances, there are cognitive states in each of these cases, or they can deny that these cases qualify as emotions. The latter strategy is not especially promising. These seem to be paradigm cases of emotions: anger at being physically harmed, delight in play, surprise at an unexpected event, and so on. An adequate theory of emotions must accommodate cases like these. Cognitive theorists can do that only by saying that each case involves a covert thought or judgement. If cognitive theories are right, then when you taste the rotten milk you form the thought that the milk is contaminated and incongruent with your goals. I think that this is extremely implausible for three reasons. First, it would bad engineering. If certain perceptual events, such as rotting food, tickling, sounds of distress, and physical assaults, have consistent emotional implications, then there is no need for an intervening judgement; we can move directly from perception to emotional response without any intervening step. Second, in each of the imagined cases there is no conscious experience of a judgement, but there is a conscious experience of a feeling, and that feeling can be recognized as an emotion on its own. There is a distinctive feeling of disgust which differs from the feeling of delight, and both differ from anger and fear. If we discovered a person who had a delight experience without an accompanying judgement, she would insist that she was delighted. What right would a theoretician have to say ‘No, you only think you're delighted’? Third, there is Page 4 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings evidence from neuroscience that emotions can be elicited subcortically. For example, there is a pathway from low‐level perceptual centres (the pulvinar and superior colliculus) to the amygdala which can trigger responses that people will experience as emotions (LeDoux 1996). Seeing a snake, for example, can trigger a fear feeling before the snake's appearance has been processed by the neocortex. Subcortical structures are not believed to be the locus of judgement or thought. There is no evidence that structures such as the colliculus or the amygdala harbour concepts, such as danger. The pulvinar and the colliculus are responsive to simple perceptual features, and the amygdala contains some nuclei that respond to perceptual features and others that send commands to brain structures that orchestrate responses in the body (including the autonomic nervous system, the endocrine system, and stereotype responses (p. 682) in the musculuskeletal system). There is no place for judgement beneath the cortical mantle. Thus, there is very strong evidence for emotion induction in the absence of cognitive states.

39.2 Non‐cognitivism This leads us to non‐cognitive theories of emotion. According to defenders of non‐ cognitive theories, emotions have no cognitive components, and they can occur in the absence of any judgement, thought, or conceptualization. For most non‐cognitive theorists emotions are identified with feelings, but there is some disagreement about what those feelings are. According to some non‐cognitive theories emotional feelings are sui generis: they cannot be reduced to any other kind of feeling. According to others emotional feelings are reducible. William James (1884) and Carl Lange (1885) argued that emotions are reducible to bodily feelings: each emotion is experienced as a felt pattern of changes in the body. Lange emphasized vascular changes; emotions are felt changes in blood flow. James had a more encompassing view, citing heart rate, muscle tension, respiration, and facial expressions. James was a functionalist, in a Darwinian sense, and he regarded these bodily changes as adaptive. Eyes widen in fear to take in more information, and the heart races to facilitate flight. Darwin (1872/1998) pointed out that our hair follicles stand on end when we are afraid, and this may be a vestige from our earlier mammalian ancestors who were covered with hair; piloerection can increase apparent girth in a hairy mammal and that can scare off a would‐be predator. According to James, emotions arise when a thought or perception of a precipitating event triggers a pattern of bodily changes, and those changes are felt; the feeling of the bodily changes is the emotion. James argued that if you were to systematically subtract each bodily symptom of an emotion, there would be nothing left. It seems impossible to imagine the feeling of fear without imagining tensed muscles, a racing heart, and strained breathing. James's theory enjoys considerable empirical support (Damasio 1994; Prinz 2004; Robinson 2005). In study after study emotional feelings have been linked to the body. For example, when emotions occur, there are measurable changes in autonomic response (e.g. Levenson et al. 1990), and neuroimaging studies show that brain areas associated Page 5 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings with the body are active when people experience emotions (e.g. Damasio et al. 2000). There is also evidence that people who are given false information about their bodily states can form false beliefs about their emotional attitudes (Valins 1966), and induction of bodily states can lead people to report emotion‐like experiences (Marañon 1924; Duclos et al. 1989). There is evidence too that people who are better at reporting their bodily states (e.g. at perceiving their heart rate) are more aware of their emotions (Schnall and Laird 2007). Collectively such findings suggest that emotional feelings are not sui generis; they are somatic. The most plausible non‐cognitive theory identifies emotions with felt changes in the body. (p. 683)

If James's theory of emotions is the most plausible non‐cognitive theory, then cognitivists must show that it is false. They must show that felt changes in the body are either not necessary for emotions or not sufficient. Let's begin with necessity. Opponents of James can try to establish that bodily changes are not necessary by identifying emotions that occur without bodily changes. Most people grant that our simplest emotions, such as fear, anger, and disgust, have homologues in non‐human animals, and may usually have associated behavioural responses. We flee in fear, aggress in anger, and withdraw or expel in disgust. The somatic states associated with these emotions may be an evolutionary residue of these behaviour programmes. But some of our emotions are more sophisticated, and less likely to have homologues in non‐human animals. Consider evaluative emotions. These include moral emotions, such as guilt and shame, and aesthetic appreciation, which Hume (1739–40/1978) called a calm passion, because it is not associated with strong arousal. Emotions of social regard are also not traditionally related to body states: consider pride, envy, and esteem for others. I grant that these emotions sometimes seem to occur without patterned changes in the body. There are, for example, no facial expressions associated with guilt or esteem, and it's rare to feel your heart racing when looking at art or viewing another's possessions with envy. But closer analysis tells another story. Each of these emotions can affect the body. Guilt is associated with reparative behaviours, such as submissively approaching the party who's been wronged. Shame is associated with gaze avoidance and blushing. Aesthetic experiences can take our breath away. Pride is associated with smiling and exhilaration. The envious person stares longingly and disdainfully at envied persons and possessions. Esteem often blends bodily responses associated with surprise, submission, and happiness. Ultimately it's an empirical issue whether these emotions have bodily concomitants, and current research suggests that they do. For example, moral and aesthetic emotions have been studied using neuroimaging, and in each case researchers have found activation in brain areas associated with bodily responses, such as the cingulate cortex and the insula (e.g. Moll et al. 2003; Vartanian and Goel 2004). Work in ‘neuroeconomics’ suggests that envy is associated with those brain structures as well; they become more active when one player in a game receives a lower monetary award than another player (Sanfey et al. 2003). Bodily concomitants can also be studied behaviourally. For example, recent experiments have shown that pride has a recognizable Page 6 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings expression, which includes a smile, a tilted back head, and expanded shoulders or chest (Tracy and Robins 2004). Obviously, each alleged counter‐example to James's theory would have to be carefully considered, but so far the prognosis looks good. Whenever an emotion has been studied in the lab, evidence for a somatic component has been found. So far, no one has identified an emotion that leaves the body unperturbed. Defenders of impure cognitive theories could concede this point. They could admit that every emotion involves a perceived change in the body, just as James claimed. But they might deny that such bodily experiences are sufficient. Cognitive theorists claim that emotions require judgements as well. Earlier I argued that this is implausible, but that argument was based on cases in which emotions arise immediately after (p. 684) a perceived event. Cognitive theorists might reply by arguing that some emotions cannot be elicited in this way; some emotions require prior thoughts or judgements. The emotions that I have just been considering are often regarded as examples. Evaluative and social emotions are associated with sophisticated mental capacities. Cognitive theorists insist that a person cannot feel guilty without judging that she has done something wrong, and a person cannot feel pride without believing that her accomplishments are praiseworthy. In light of these cases one might try to split the differences between cognitivists and non‐cognitivists. One might say that some emotions (e.g. fear in response to snakes) are non‐cognitive, while others (e.g. shame and envy) have essential cognitive components. This would be inelegant, of course; it would force us to conclude that emotions are not a natural kind (Griffiths 1997). Alternatively, the non‐ cognitivist can try to argue that evaluative and social emotions do not have necessary cognitive components after all. This strikes me as a promising line of response. It is plausible that the emotions under consideration can be triggered by perception, in the absence of judgement. Consider guilt. Imagine that I accidentally step on your foot, and you squeal in pain. I might feel a sharp pang of guilt, and begin making amends before I have formed any judgements or thoughts. Notice how people immediately and instinctively hold up their hands apologetically and defensively and raise their eyebrows when they bump into each other. Or consider envy. It's easy to imagine that the mere appearance of another person's being rewarded could elicit an aversive emotional state, especially if we expected or desired the reward ourselves. This probably occurs in many mammalian species. Imagine waiving a food treat in front of one mouse and then giving it to another. My guess is that this perceptual experience will trigger a rodent homologue of envy: an aversive response to something possessed by a conspecific. Judgement does not seem necessary. Similar examples can be devised for any of the emotions that I have been considering. In response the cognitive theorist might insist that the eliciting perceptions in these cases qualify as thoughts. Perhaps when the mouse perceives a conspecific getting a coveted food reward that perception qualifies as the thought ‘He got the food that I wanted’. I think this is a sensible response, but it does not undermine James's theory. At this point the cognitive theory collapses into a notational variant of the non‐cognitive approach. Traditionally cognitive theories have insisted that emotions require the deployment of fairly abstract concepts, such as danger, insult, loss, and contamination. On appraisal Page 7 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings theories, for example, emotion elicitation takes three steps: there is a perception of a specific event, a construal of that event under one of these abstract concepts, and a subsequent emotional response. On the present story there are only two steps: a perception of a specific event and an emotion. If one wants to call perceptions of events ‘thoughts’, then the present story technically qualifies as a cognitive theory, but the label is terribly misleading, because traditional non‐cognitivists have always claimed that emotions are triggered by perceptions when they are not triggered by more abstract judgements. In light of this we might redefine the divide between cognitivists and non‐ cognitivists as a debate about (p. 685) whether emotions can occur in the absence of abstract concepts, as opposed to concrete representations of specific events. On this way of framing the debate the cognitive theorist cannot undermine non‐cognitivism by claiming that perceptions are thoughts. If all emotions can be perceptually triggered, then no emotions require cognitive states in the sense that is relevant to this debate (i.e. abstract cognitive states). If guilt and envy can be perceptually triggered, then James's theory of the emotions extends to cases that have been regarded as counter‐examples. If all emotions can be perceptually triggered and all emotions involve perceptions of the body, then emotions are a natural kind, and James's account applies to the entire category. This would be a victory for non‐cognitivists. Let me consider one more standard objection to non‐cognitivism. In the examples I have been considering, emotions are states triggered by precipitating events. But talk of triggering gives the impression that emotions have a merely causal relation to their elicitors, rather than a semantic relation. Pepper can trigger a sneeze and acidic food can trigger indigestion, but we would not say that the sneeze is about pepper or that indigestion refers to acidic food. In contrast, we do say that emotions are about their elicitors. We get angry at those who insult us, and we are afraid of things that go bump in the night. In a word, emotions are intentional. Indeed, they have two kinds of intentional object. Every token experience of an emotion is about some ‘particular object’ (e.g. fear of this snake in my path), and every emotion type has a ‘formal object’ which is the feature of the world that it alerts us to (e.g. fear concerns danger and sadness concerns loss) (Kenny 1963). Mere bodily sensations are usually thought to lack formal and particular objects; a mere twinge isn't a representation of anything (except perhaps some state of the body). Therefore, James's bodily theory of emotions does not explain how emotions can refer to their objects (Pitcher 1965). This objection is sometimes presented as if it were a principled and fatal blow to the Jamesian theory: it's assumed that bodily feelings are just not the kinds of things that can have intentional objects. But I think the objection is far from fatal; it just shows a lack of imagination. Some bodily sensations probably lack intentional objects, or refer, at most, to bodily states. Think of twinges and tingles. But there is no reason to assume that bodily sensations could not refer to things outside the body. To see whether they can, we need to ask more generally: How does a mental state come to refer? Philosophers of mind and language typically distinguish between two different routes to references. On the one hand, a mental state can refer by description. The concept expressed by ‘the fattest worm in my garden’ refers by describing something. But mental states can also refer by Page 8 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings causation. Philosophers of mind and language have argued that many of our mental states refer to their objects by being causally related to them in some way. There are three kinds of causal approach that have been developed in the literature (Stich and Warfield 1994). On a causal‐history approach, a mental state refers to what actually caused it to be generated; on a nomological approach, a mental state refers to whatever would reliably cause it to be activated; and on a teleological approach, a mental state refers to whatever has the function of causing it to be activated (i.e. those causes in virtue (p. 686) of which it managed to be replicated in the past). Much of the work on intentionality involves refinements of these three basic approaches. Obviously, if emotions do not contain thoughts or judgements they cannot refer by description. An experience of a racing heart does not describe something as dangerous or insulting. But bodily experiences could refer causally. Suppose that seeing a snake triggers a pattern of bodily responses in me. That bodily pattern was caused by the snake, so it could refer to the snake by means of its causal history. In addition, bodily patterns of this kind would be reliably caused by snakes and by a variety of other potentially harmful things, so it could refer nomologically to the class of dangers. And, finally, the pattern of bodily responses, which is an experience of the body preparing for flight, may have been passed down to us in evolution in virtue of being caused by dangerous things; the bodily pattern is a teleological adaptation that plays a role in escaping dangers. In sum, the most popular causal theories of reference can be readily applied to emotions even if emotions are feelings of bodily changes (Prinz 2004). Indeed, these theories seem to entail that such feelings refer. It looks like a straightforward consequence of both nomological and teleological theories that the bodily sensation associated with fear is about danger, because that response is caused by dangerous things in a lawlike way, and it has been passed on through the genome in virtue of its role in successfully reacting to danger. Thus, nomological and teleological theories could account for the formal objects of emotions. In addition, on any given occasion the bodily response associated with fear will have a causal history relating it to some specific elicitor. A token instance of fear might be caused by a snake, and it can be said to refer, by its causal induction, to that snake. Thus, causal history can account for the particular object of an emotion. Other accounts of the intentionality of emotions may be available to the Jamesian as well. Notice that, in addition to being caused by precipitating events, our emotions also have behavioural effects that are related to external objects. An angry person might aggress against someone and the frightened person may flee from something. One could account for the particular object of an emotion by identifying the person, event, or thing towards which emotional behaviours are directed. This proposal is consistent with James's theory. If a bodily sensation leads me to flee from a snake, then we can say that the sensation is about the snake. The details of this proposal, like all the others, would need to be worked out. I am not here offering a fully developed theory of how emotions refer. I am merely pointing out that there are many resources available for explaining how emotions refer, and these resources are fully available to those who identify emotions with bodily

Page 9 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings feelings. A feeling of a racing heart, tense muscles, and strained breathing can represent danger. I conclude that the bodily theory expounded by William James has the resources to accommodate all emotions, and it can be defended against standard objections to non‐ cognitivism. If I am right, then emotions can occur in the absence of abstract thoughts, and they do not have thoughts as components. Instead, emotions are feelings of changes in the body, caused by thoughts or perceptions, and they represent formal and particular objects by means of causal relations.

(p. 687)

39.3 Emotions and Decision Making

The non‐cognitive theory of emotions has important implications. Much of the work in the philosophy of mind has focused on concepts, beliefs, and judgements. If emotions were purely cognitive states, then they would not make a distinctive contribution to decision making. But emotions do make a distinctive contribution. To see this, imagine what would happen if we didn't have emotions. Imagine a person who could make perfectly accurate judgements but couldn't emote. Such a person might discover one day that her house is on fire, and she might know that fire is dangerous and potentially fatal, but these two true beliefs would not be sufficient to motivate her to leave her house. One can recognize that something is dangerous, or threatening, or contaminated, without caring about it. Emotions make us care. When we emote, we are motivated to act. A person who is afraid of fire will be motivated to leave. The Jamesian theory of emotions is well suited for explaining the link between emotions and motivation. For James, fear is a feeling of a bodily change, and that bodily change is a preparation for flight. Therefore, if a person experiences fear it is ordinarily because her body has already initiated the early stages of escape behaviour. It's built into James's theory that we have behavioural programmes that are activated by certain entities and events, whether real or imagined. Dangerous things set the flight programme in motion, and fear is the experience of that programme at work. We find such experiences motivating. When we perceive our bodies in flight mode, we have an urge to flee. By analogy, the feeling of being tired is an experience of our bodies trying to sleep. It takes energy to resist what our bodies have already set out to do. Metaphorically, an emotion is like a ball rolling down a hill; once the action tendency is set in motion, it is easier to go with the flow than to resist it. If our bodies are trying to flee, we feel motivated to give in. If this is right, then each emotion comes along with a disposition to act in a certain way. Psychologists call such dispositions ‘action tendencies’ (Frijda 1986). Fear comes with a flight tendency, anger comes with an aggression tendency, and delight comes with a tendency to approach and explore. In some cases the same emotion label actually covers a family of different felt action tendencies. Fear coincides with flight in many cases, but it is also associated with freezing and fighting, depending on context. In each case we also Page 10 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings need to use contextual information to figure out how to carry out the action for which we're prepared. If anger comes with a motivation to aggress, we still need to figure out how to channel the aggression—we must decide who to aggress against and how, or whether we should resist the urge. Without emotions, we would not be motivated to act. Emotion deficits have been investigated in the lab. Damasio (1994) has studied patients with injuries in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex. These individuals are perfectly intelligent, and they come out normal on all standard cognitive tests, but they make bad decisions. They can't hold down their jobs, they go into business with charlatans, their marriages fall apart, and they behave in socially inappropriate ways. In a gambling task developed by one of Damasio's colleagues it is shown that they (p. 688) play losing strategies (Bechara et al. 1997). Interestingly, these patients will often say that they knew the winning strategy but they couldn't bring themselves to play it. Damasio and his colleagues discovered that performance on the gambling task and, presumably, all the bad decisions these people make in daily life are the result of an emotion disorder. These patients have emotions, but their brain injuries disrupt their ability to reliably anticipate the emotional consequences of their actions. Without this ability they make infelicitous choices. Just as we need fear to be motivated to flee a burning house, we need to be able to anticipate the sting of defeat to avoid losing strategies when gambling or choosing business partners. Damasio's patients seem to have a general deficit in anticipating negative emotions. There are also more selective deficits in emotions. People with bilateral amygdala damage tend not to experience fear, and they engage in high‐risk behaviours (Adolphs et al. 2005). People with insula damage caused by Huntington's disease sometimes lose their capacity for disgust, and they don't avoid things that most of us would find repellent (Phillips et al. 1997). Psychopaths seems to suffer from a lack of guilt and empathy, and as a result they are prone to engage in antisocial behaviour (Hare 1993). Anhedonic depressives, who do not experience joy, lose their motivation to seek new experiences or experiences that have been rewarding in the past (Chapman et al. 1976). These examples underscore the importance of emotions. Each emotion makes a distinctive contribution to motivation, and without them decision making would be impaired. Emotions probably aren't the sole source of motivation. We have basic drives, such as hunger and thirst. Some fundamental goals, such as procreation, social interaction, and shelter may drive behaviour without emotions; that's a possibility that should be empirically investigated. It's also plausible that emotions are unnecessary for instrumental desires; once a goal is in place, we may be motivated to pursue courses of action that help realize that goal. But emotions may play a central role in establishing the goals that we seek, and in steering us away from hazards and towards rewards. Moreover, we often use emotional conditioning to shape behaviour. We teach children to avoid dangers by instilling fear (‘Drugs will harm you!’), and we inculcate moral values by instilling guilt and shame (‘No one likes people who hit!’). Without emotions, we would expose ourselves to risks, miss out on opportunities, and we would be indifferent to the

Page 11 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings dictates of morality. Human life would certainly be very different if we didn't emote, and survival would be difficult if not impossible.

References Adolphs, R., Gosselin, F., Buchanan, T. W., Tranel, D., Schyns, P., and Damasio, A. R. (2005), ‘A Mechanism for Impaired Fear Recognition After Amygdala Damage’, Nature, 433: 68–72. Aristotle (c.350 BC/1984), ‘Rhetoric’, in The Rhetoric and Poetics of Aristotle, ed. E. P. J. Corbett, trans. W. R. Roberts (New York, NY: Modern Library). Armon‐Jones, C. (1989), Varieties of Affect (Toronto: University of Toronto Press). (p. 689)

Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., and Damasio, A. R. (1997), ‘Deciding

Advantageously Before Knowing the Advantageous Strategy’, Science, 275: 1293–5. Chapman, L. J., Chapman, J. P., and Raulin, M. L. (1976), ‘Scales for Physical and Social Anhedonia’, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 85: 374–82. Damasio, A. R. (1994), Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (New York: Gossett/Putnam). Damasio, A. R., Grabowski, T. J., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Ponto, L. L. B., Parvizi, J., and Hichwa, R. D. (2000), ‘Subcortical and Cortical Brain Activity during the Feeling of Self‐ generated Emotions’, Nature Neuroscience, 3: 1049–56. Darwin, C. (1872/1998), The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. 3rd edn., ed. P. Ekman (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Descartes, R. (1649/1985), ‘The Passions of the Soul’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, i, ed. and trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 325–404. Duclos, S. E., Laird, J. D., Schneider, E., Sexter, M., Stern, L., and Van Lighten, O. (1989), ‘Emotion‐specific Effects of Facial Expressions and Postures on Emotional Experience’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57: 100–8. Frijda, N. H. (1986), The Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Greenspan, P. (1988), Emotions and Reasons (London: Routledge). Griffiths, P. E. (1997), What Emotions Really Are (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press). Hare, R. D. (1993), Without Conscience: The Disturbing World of the Psychopaths Among Us (New York: Simon & Schuster).

Page 12 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings Hume, D. (1739–40/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby‐Bigge, rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). James, W. (1884), ‘What Is An Emotion?’, Mind, 9: 188–205. Kenny, A. (1963), Action, Emotion and Will (London: Routledge). Lange, C. G. (1885), Om sindsbevaegelser: et psyko‐fysiologisk studie (Copenhagen: Lunds); repr. in The Emotions, ed. C. G. Lange and W. James, trans. I. A. Haupt (Baltimore, Md.: Williams and Wilkins, 1922), 188–205. Lazarus, R. S. (1991), Emotion and Adaptation (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Lazarus, R. S., and Smith, C. (1993), ‘Appraisal Components, Core Relational Themes, and the Emotions’, in N. Frijda (ed.), Appraisal and Beyond (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 233–70. LeDoux, J. E. (1996), The Emotional Brain (New York: Simon & Schuster). Levenson, R. W., Ekman, P., and Friesen, W. V. (1990), ‘Voluntary Facial Action Generates Emotion‐specific Autonomic Nervous System Activity’, Psychophysiology, 27: 363–84. Marañon, G. (1924), ‘Contribution à l’étude de l'action émotive de l'adrenaline’, Revue Française d'Endocrinologie, 2: 301–25. Moll, J., de Oliveirra‐Souza, R., and Eslinger, P. J. (2003), ‘Morals and the Human Brain: A Working Model’, Neuroreport, 14: 299–305. Nussbaum, M. C. (2001), Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of the Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Öhman, A., Flykt, A., and Esteves, F. (2001), ‘Emotion Drives Attention: Detecting the Snake in the Grass’, Journal of Experimental Psychology General, 130: 466–78. Phillips, M. L., Young, A. W., Senior, C., Brammer, M., Andrew, C., Calder, A. J., Bullmore, E. T., Perrett, D. I., Rowland, D., Williams, S. C. R., Gray, J. A., and David, A. S. (1997), ‘A Specific Neural Substrate for Perceiving Facial Expressions of Disgust’, Nature, 389: 495– 8. Pitcher, G. (1965), ‘Emotion’, Mind, 74: 324–6. Prinz, J. J. (2004), Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Robinson, J. (2005), Deeper than Reason: Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press). (p. 690)

Page 13 of 15

Emotions: Motivating Feelings Roseman, I. (1994), ‘Phenomenology, Behaviors, and Goals Differentiate Discrete Emotions’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67: 206–21. Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. A., Aronson, J. K., Nystrom, L., and Cohen, J. D. (2003), ‘The Neural Basis of Economic Decision Making in the Ultimatum Game’, Science, 300: 1755– 7. Scherer, K. R. (1984), ‘On the Nature and Function of Emotion: A Component Process Approach’, in K. R. Scherer and P. Ekman (eds.), Approaches to Emotion (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 293–317. Schnall, S., and Laird, J. D. (2007), ‘Facing Fear: Expression of Fear Facilitates Processing of Emotional Information’, Social Behavior and Personality, 35: 513–24. Solomon, R. C. (1976), The Passions (New York: Doubleday). Sousa, R. de (1987), The Rationality of Emotions (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Spinoza, B. (1677/1994), ‘Ethics’, in A Spinoza Reader, trans., and ed. E. Curley (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), 85–265. Stich, S., and Warfield, T. A. (1994) (eds.), Mental Representation: A Reader (Oxford: Blackwell). Tracy, J. L., and Robins, R. W. (2004), ‘Show Your Pride: Evidence for a Discrete Emotion Expression’, Psychological Science, 15: 194–7. Valins, S. (1966), ‘Cognitive Effects of False Heart‐rate Feedback’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 4: 400–8. Vartanian, O., and Goel, V. (2004), ‘Neuroanatomical Correlates of Aesthetic Preference for Paintings’, NeuroReport, 15: 893–7.

Jesse Prinz

Jesse J. Prinz is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the City University of New York, Graduate Center. His research focuses on the perceptual, emotional, and cultural foundations of human psychology. He is author of Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perception Basis (MIT Press 2002), Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion (Oxford University Press 2004), and The Emotional Construction of Morals (Oxford University Press 2009). He also has two forthcoming books: The Conscious Brain (Oxford University Press) and Beyond Human Nature (Penguin/ Norton). All of these books bring research in the cognitive sciences to bear on traditional philosophical questions, and, in particular, all defend and extend core tenets of classical empiricism.

Page 14 of 15

Intention and Intentional Action

Oxford Handbooks Online Intention and Intentional Action   Alfred R. Mele The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0041

Abstract and Keywords Intention, intentional action, and the connections between them are central topics of the philosophy of action, a branch of the philosophy of mind. One who regards the subject matter of the philosophy of mind as having at its core some aspect of what lies between environmental input to beings with minds and behavioural output may be inclined to see the philosophy of action as concerned only with the output end of things. That would be a mistake. Many intentional actions depend for their development on the processing of input — both from the environment and from the body. Keywords: intention, intentional action, philosophy of action, philosophy of mind, behavioural output, processing of input

INTENTION,

intentional action, and the connections between them are central topics of the

philosophy of action, a branch of the philosophy of mind. One who regards the subject matter of the philosophy of mind as having at its core some aspect of what lies between environmental input to beings with minds and behavioural output may be inclined to see the philosophy of action as concerned only with the output end of things. That would be a mistake. Many intentional actions depend for their development on the processing of input—both from the environment and from the body. Try to imagine yourself cooking a meal or driving to work without processing such input. Conceptualizing and explaining intentional actions of intelligent agents—or some central subset of such actions—is the primary business of the philosophy of action, and properly conducting that business requires a firm understanding of most of the ins and outs of the philosophy of mind.

40.1 Intentions Page 1 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action Presumably, there is some interesting connection between intentions and intentional actions. But what are intentions? And what is the connection? In this section I describe (p. 692) two competing approaches to characterizing intention and distinguish among some types of intentions.1 It is generally agreed that intentions are closely linked to desires and beliefs. Intention has a motivational dimension, and ‘desire’ (like ‘want’) is often used in the literature as an umbrella term for motivation.2 Having an intention also is widely regarded as requiring the satisfaction of a belief condition of some sort. Few philosophers of action are inclined to assert that a person who believes that her chances of winning today's lottery are about one in a million intends to win the lottery, no matter how strongly motivated she is to win.3 However, theorists are divided on how tight the connection is between intentions, on the one hand, and desires and beliefs, on the other. Some— attracted, perhaps, by the popular idea that desire and belief are the most fundamental representational states of mind4—hold that intentions are reducible to combinations of desires and beliefs (Audi 1973, 1997; Beardsley 1978; Davis 1997; Ridge 1998). Others have argued that attempts at such reduction are doomed to failure (Davidson 1980: ch. 5; Searle 1983; Brand 1984; McCann 1986a; Bratman 1987; Harman 1997). I discussed this dispute in Mele (1992a: ch. 9), where I weighed in on the side of the anti‐ reductionists. Here I am content to observe that the central issue is whether the settledness that intention encompasses can be captured in terms of beliefs and desires. Functions plausibly attributed to intentions include (1) initiating and sustaining intentional actions, (2) guiding intentional behaviour, (3) helping to coordinate agents' behaviour over time and their interaction with other agents, and (4) prompting and appropriately terminating practical reasoning.5 Some philosophers have advanced non‐ reductive accounts of intention designed to accommodate many or all of these functions (Searle 1983; Brand 1984; McCann 1986a; Bratman 1987; Mele 1992a; Harman 1997). According to a representative account of this kind (Mele 1992a), intentions are executive attitudes toward plans. Plans—which range from simple representations of ‘basic’ actions to complex strategies for achieving remote goals—constitute the representational contents (p. 693) of intentions.6 What distinguishes intentions from other practical attitudes—for example, desires to act—is their distinctive practical nature. Although one can desire to do something without being at all settled on doing it, to intend to do something is, in part, to be settled on doing it (but not necessarily irrevocably). Such settledness on a course of action constitutes a psychological commitment to executing the pertinent plan of action, a commitment of a kind arguably constituted exclusively by intentions.7 Two ways of coming to intend to A—an actional and a non‐actional way—should be distinguished. Many philosophers have claimed or argued that to decide to A is to perform a mental action of a certain kind—an action of forming an intention to A (see e.g. Kaufman 1966: 34; McCann 1986a: 254–5; Frankfurt 1988: 174–6; Mele 1992a: 156; 2003a: ch. 9; Kane 1996: 24; Pink 1996: 3; Searle 2001: 94). On my view, deciding to A is a momentary mental action of intention formation, and it resolves uncertainty about what Page 2 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action to do (Mele 2003a: ch. 9). In saying that deciding to A is momentary, I mean to distinguish it from, for example, a combination of deliberating and deciding. A student who is speaking loosely may say, ‘I was up all night deciding to major in English’ when what he means is that he was up all night deliberating or fretting about what major to declare and eventually decided to major in English. Not all intentions are actively formed, or so I have argued elsewhere. For example, when I intentionally unlocked my office door this morning, I intended to unlock it. But since I am in the habit of unlocking my door in the morning and conditions were normal, nothing called for a decision to unlock it (Mele 1992a: 231). If I had heard a fight in my office, I might have paused to consider whether to unlock the door or walk away, and I might have decided to unlock it. But given the routine nature of my conduct, there is no need to posit an act of intention formation in this case. My intention to unlock the door may have been acquired without having been actively formed. Some of our intentions are for the non‐immediate future and others are not. I might decide on Tuesday to attend a meeting on Friday, and I might decide now to phone my father now. The intention formed in the former decision is aimed at action three days in the future. (Of course, if I need to prepare for the meeting—or need to write a note on my calendar to remind myself of it—the intention may motivate relevant overt conduct sooner than that.) The intention I form when I decide to phone my father now is about what to do now. I call intentions of these kinds, respectively, distal and proximal intentions (Mele 1992a: 143–4, 158).8 Proximal intentions also include intentions to continue doing something that one is doing and intentions to start A‐ing (e.g. start running a mile) straight away.

40.2 Analysing Intentional Action: some Problems (p. 694)

Next on the agenda are some problems faced by anyone intent on analysing intentional action. As I mentioned, it is natural to suppose that intention and intentional action are importantly related. The same is often said of reasons and intentional action. For expository purposes it will be useful to formulate a pair of proto‐analyses of doing something intentionally, one framed in terms of intentions and the other in terms of reasons. With the stipulation that ‘A’ is an action variable, the following will do:9 A1. Necessarily, S intentionally A‐ed if and only if S A‐ed in the way that S intended to A. A2. Necessarily, S intentionally A‐ed if and only if S A‐ed for a reason.

Page 3 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action Both proto‐analyses enjoy intuitive support. Again, there presumably is some important connection between what we intend to do and what we do intentionally. Similarly, it seems, intentional action is a species of behaviour intimately bound up with agents' desires and beliefs; and desires, perhaps typically in conjunction with beliefs linking desired goals to prospective instrumental behaviour, arguably constitute reasons for action.10 In this section I consider four general problems for the proto‐analyses. (p. 695)

40.2.1 Side Effects Consider the following from Gilbert Harman (1997: 151): ‘In firing his gun’, a sniper who is trying to kill a soldier ‘knowingly alerts the enemy to his presence’. Harman claims that although the sniper ‘does not intend to alert the enemy’, he intentionally alerts the enemy, ‘thinking that the gain is worth the possible cost’. If Harman is right, A1 and A2 are both false. Not only does the sniper not intend to alert the enemy, he does not alert them for a reason either. He has no reason for alerting the enemy, even if he does have a reason to fire his weapon despite the cost of alerting the enemy. Michael Bratman makes the same general claim as Harman, illustrated by a scenario featuring a runner who reluctantly wears down some heirloom shoes (Bratman 1987: 123; see Ginet 1990: 75–6). Harman's sniper and Bratman's runner do not unknowingly, inadvertently, or accidentally perform the actions at issue. For that reason, many will deny that the sniper unintentionally alerted the enemy and that the runner unintentionally wore down his shoes. But that denial does not, in any obvious way, commit them to holding that the actions in question are intentional. Perhaps there is a middle ground between intentional and unintentional action. Some philosophers have argued that actions an agent in no way aims at performing but that are not performed unknowingly, inadvertently, or accidentally are properly located on that middle ground. They may be non‐intentional, as opposed to unintentional (see Lowe 1978; Mele and Sverdlik 1996: 274). There is evidence that, on the topic of side‐effect actions, Harman and Bratman are more sensitive to ‘the folk concept’ of intentional action than their opponents are. Joshua Knobe presented subjects with the following story: S1. The vice‐president of a company went to the chairman of the board and said, ‘We are thinking of starting a new program. It will help us increase profits, but it will also harm the environment.’ The chairman … answered, ‘I don't care at all about harming the environment. I just want to make as much profit as I can. Let's start the new program.’ They started the new program. Sure enough, the environment was harmed. (2003b: 191) He reports that 82 per cent of his 38 respondents said that the chairman intentionally harmed the environment (2003b: 192). Plainly, the chairman is not aiming at harming the environment.

Page 4 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action (p. 696)

There also is evidence that in responding as they do to this story lay folk are especially sensitive to the ‘badness’ of the action at issue. Knobe presented another group of subjects with a similar story that substitutes a good side effect for the bad one: S2. The vice‐president of a company went to the chairman of the board and said, ‘We are thinking of starting a new program. It will help us increase profits, and it will also help the environment.’ The chairman … answered, ‘I don't care at all about helping the environment. I just want to make as much profit as I can. Let's start the new program.’ They started the new program. Sure enough, the environment was helped. (2003b: 191) He reports that 77 per cent of his 40 respondents said that the chairman did not intentionally help the environment (2003b: 192). Evidently, respondents' attributions of intentionality vary with their moral assessment of the side‐effect actions at issue. Knobe also asked respondents to S1 to indicate how blameworthy the chairman is on a scale from 0 to 6 and asked respondents to S2 to indicate how praiseworthy he is on the same scale. The mean rating for blame was much higher than that for praise (Knobe 2003b: 193). Knobe suggests that this asymmetry is a source of the asymmetry in intentionality judgements.

How concerned should philosophers of mind and action be with majority judgements of lay folk about what is or is not done intentionally in relatively straightforward cases such as these? There is no single correct answer. Philosophers with the project of analysing ‘the folk concept’ of intentional action should definitely be concerned with such judgements. What about philosophers whose primary business is building an adequate theory about how agents produce their actions? Such philosophers do not aim to construct a theory that will handle all actions, including such actions as Ann's unknowingly frightening some ants—or harming the environment—when she starts her lawnmower and Bob's accidentally driving his car into a ditch. Most such philosophers are concerned with a species of goal‐directed action, and ‘intentional action’ may be the ordinary English expression that most nearly names their target. Of course, an action theorist's predictions about what lay folk would deem to be intentional or unintentional in particular cases may be biased by her or his theoretical interests. This undoubtedly happens. But if it is discovered that most lay folk are happy to count some non‐goal‐ directed actions as intentional and if it is decided that ‘the folk concept’ of intentional action embraces such actions, philosophers with the project of developing a theory of action‐production can retain their target and accommodate ordinary usage by modifying their name for it; they can call it ‘intentional goal‐directed action’. If that sounds redundant, bear in mind that agents of goal‐directed actions may be as simple as mosquitos, and mosquitos presumably do not act intentionally. Differences in philosophical aims are, I suspect, a source of some disagreements in the literature about the precise nature of intentional action.11

Page 5 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action

(p. 697)

40.2.2 Belief Constraints

Such anticipated side‐effect actions as the chairman's harming the environment are apparent counter‐examples to the thesis—dubbed by Bratman the ‘simple view’—that intentionally A‐ing entails intending to A. Some putative belief constraints on intentions, or rational intentions, also pose apparent problems for that thesis and for proto‐analysis A1. Bratman argues that intention has a normative side that includes requirements that an agent's intentions be internally consistent (individually and collectively), consistent with the agent's beliefs, and means–end coherent (Bratman 1987; see Harman 1997). Rational intentions, he maintains, satisfy those requirements, and he contends that S rationally intends to A only if, ‘other things being equal’, S does ‘not have beliefs inconsistent with the belief that [he] will A’ (1987: 116). The normative demands figure significantly in a much‐discussed argument that Bratman uses against the simple view (1987: ch. 8).12 The argument turns on an example featuring a pair of video games and an ambidextrous player whom I call Amber. Amber's task is to hit video targets with video missiles. In the main case she simultaneously plays two games, each with its own target and trigger, and she knows that the machines are ‘so linked that it is impossible to hit both targets’ (1987: 114). (She knows that hitting a target ends both games, and that ‘if both targets are about to be hit simultaneously’ both machines shut down before the targets can be hit.) Amber simultaneously tries to hit the target on machine 1 (T1) and tries to hit the target on machine 2 (T2). She succeeds in hitting T1—‘in just the way that [she] was trying to hit it, and in a way which depends heavily on [her] considerable skill’—but, of course, she misses T2. If Amber hit T1 intentionally, proponents of the simple view must say that she intended to hit it. Since Amber's attitude toward hitting that target is not relevantly different from her attitude toward hitting T2, they apparently must also hold that she intended to hit T2. Bratman claims that having both intentions, given what Amber knows (namely, that she cannot hit both targets), would be irrational. Yet it seems perfectly rational of Amber to have proceeded as she did. So given the point about the symmetry of Amber's attitudes toward the targets, Bratman concludes that she did not have either intention. And if Amber hit T1 intentionally in the absence of an intention to hit it, the simple view and A1 are false. Some critics of the simple view are also critical of the idea that intentions are reducible to complexes of beliefs and desires (e.g. Bratman, Harman, and Mele), and Hugh McCann (1997) argues that they are in danger of having to settle for an unwanted reductive analysis of intention. Bratman's suggestion that a ‘guiding desire’ to hit T1 can play the role of an intention (1987: 137) is the primary target of McCann's objection. McCann observes that once it is conceded that desires can stand in for intentions, reductionists will justifiably ask what functional need there is for a notion of intention that is irreducible to desire and belief. However, opponents (p. 698) of the simple view need not follow Bratman in appealing to guiding desires. On my own view, for example, intentions Page 6 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action to try to A can stand in for intentions to A, but intentions to try to A are intentions (Mele 1992a: ch. 8).13 The agent's attitude toward A‐ing is not one of intending to A, but neither is it merely one of desiring to A. It is, rather, an intending‐to‐try attitude toward A‐ing, and intending to try is a species of intending. There is nothing irrational about Amber's intending to try to hit T1 while also intending to try to hit T2.14 McCann (1986b, 1997) and Frederick Adams (1986) are leading proponents of the simple view. McCann claims that ‘we get at least the beginning of a correct distinction’ between intentional and unintentional action if we endorse the simple view, and that distinguishing between non‐intended intentional actions and non‐intended non‐intentional ones ‘promises to be a most intractable problem’ (1986b: 191–2). Adams asserts that ‘we rely (at least implicitly) on the Simple View to distinguish’ intentional from unintentional actions (1986: 285). However, Knobe's subjects seem not to be relying on the simple view when they judge that the chairman intentionally harms the environment. Now, according to McCann, ‘the Simple View … pertains to the everyday concept of intending, not a stipulated one’ (1997: 219). Presumably, he would have said the same, if asked, about the concept of intentional action to which the view pertains. Some of Knobe's data give McCann reason to doubt that his concept of intentional action is a folk concept of such action. In a follow‐up study Knobe asked some people whether the chairman in S1 intentionally harmed the environment and asked others whether he intended to harm it: 87 per cent of the 15 respondents to the former question said that he intentionally did this whereas only 29 per cent of the 17 respondents to the latter question said that he intended to do it (Knobe 2004: 185). This result is troublesome for the simple view understood as a view about ‘the folk concepts’ of intention and intentional action.15

40.2.3 Intrinsically Motivated Actions I turn to reasons and to A2. Again, on a popular account, the reasons for which we act— effective reasons—are complexes of beliefs and desires (Davidson 1980). For example, the reason for which I crossed the road might be constituted by a desire to get to the other side and a belief that doing so requires a crossing. This account of effective reasons seems not to do justice to intrinsically motivated actions—actions done for their own sakes, from ‘intrinsic’ desires. When something, A, is done for its own sake alone, it is not done from a desire for something further, F, and a belief that identifies A‐ing as suitably related to F. However, if the reasons for which we A are sometimes constituted wholly by intrinsic desires to A, such cases can easily be (p. 699) handled (Mele 1992a: ch. 6). Intrinsically motivated actions arguably are a problem not for A2 itself but for a particular conception of effective reasons. Rosalind Hursthouse (1991) appeals to a species of intrinsically motivated action, ‘arational action’, in an attempt to undermine A2 (also see Quinn 1993: 236–52; Scanlon 1998: 38). Examples of arational actions include striking an inanimate object in anger and gouging out the eyes in a photograph of a hated person. She also adduces, in another category, ‘actions prompted by odd physical cravings’—for example, licking something Page 7 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action furry when ‘seized by a sudden desire’ to do so (1991: 62–3). Such actions, as Hursthouse observes, often are not done for the sake of some further goal, and they typically seem unreasonable. But it would be a mistake to infer that they are done for no reason at all. If our reasons can be every bit as bizarre as our actions, proponents of A2 have no special cause for worry. A man with an irrational urge to drink a can of paint (Davidson 1980: 4) and the knowledge that drinking the paint requires removing the lid may pry off the lid for a reason, and I have not encountered compelling grounds for thinking that he cannot drink the paint for a reason, too—a reason constituted by an intrinsic desire to drink it.

40.2.4 Luck A more interesting problem for A2 has attracted little attention (as a problem for that thesis). The popular thesis that all actions done for a reason are intentional (Audi 1997: 104) is challenged by some cases of lucky success. Ann, who has never fired a gun, is offered a large cash prize for hitting the bull's‐eye on a distant target that even experts normally miss. She carefully aims and fires, hitting the target dead centre in just the (direct) way she hoped she would. Many people, I think, would happily (but perhaps mistakenly) say that Ann's hitting the bull's‐eye—that action—was done for a reason.16 After all, she wanted the money and believed that to get it she must hit the bull's‐eye, and this helps to explain her carefully aiming and firing at the target. But was Ann's hitting the bull's‐eye an intentional action? Suppose that Ann has no natural talent with firearms: she tries equally hard to win even larger prizes for duplicating the feat, fires hundreds of additional rounds at the target, and does not even come close. Here philosophers' intuitions differ. According to Christopher Peacocke, an agent who makes a successful attempt ‘to hit a croquet ball through a distant hoop’ intentionally hits the ball through the hoop (1985: 69). But Brian O'Shaughnessy maintains that a novice who similarly succeeds in hitting the bull's‐eye on a dart board does not intentionally hit the bull's‐eye (O'Shaughnessy 1980: ii. 325; see Harman 1997: 151–2). Luck is also a problem for A1. Just suppose that Ann, who mistakenly thinks that modern weaponry makes target shooting extremely easy, intends to hit the bull's‐eye by aiming and firing at it. She luckily hits it in just the way intended, but was (p. 700) her hitting it an intentional action? Readers inclined to answer affirmatively should consider a similarly benighted person who intends to disarm a bomb. She thinks that all she need do to disarm it is to punch in any ten‐digit sequence of numbers, whereas, in fact, only one ten‐ digit code will work; and wanting to disarm the bomb, she intends to disarm it by entering ten digits. If she luckily punches in the right code, thereby disarming the bomb, does she disarm it intentionally? (Does she disarm it for a reason—perhaps one constituted by a desire to save the townsfolk and a belief that she can ensure her doing that by disarming the bomb?) The stories I have spun in this subsection feature either morally neutral or morally positive lucky actions. Morally negative properties of actions apparently have a

Page 8 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action significant influence on folk judgements about what is and is not done intentionally in cases of lucky action. Knobe (2003a: 313) finds that people respond very differently to the following two stories: S3. Jake desperately wants to win the rifle contest. He knows that he will only win the contest if he hits the bull's‐eye. He raises the rifle, gets the bull's‐eye in his sights, and presses the trigger. But Jake isn't very good at using his rifle. His hand slips on the barrel of the gun, and the shot goes wild. Nonetheless, the bullet lands directly on the bull's‐eye. Jake wins the contest. S4. Jake desperately wants to have more money. He knows that he will inherit a lot of money when his aunt dies. One day he sees his aunt walking by the window. He raises his rifle, gets her in his sights, and presses the trigger. But Jake isn't very good at using his rifle. His hand slips on the barrel of the gun, and the shot goes wild. Nonetheless, the bullet hits her directly in the heart. She dies instantly. Knobe reports that 28 per cent of the 18 respondents to S3 said that Jake intentionally hit the bull's‐eye whereas 76 per cent of the 21 respondents to S4 said that he intentionally killed his aunt (2003a: 313–14). Obviously, the main difference between the cases is a moral one.17

Knobe's result is confirmation for my conjecture elsewhere that a story like S4 would get ‘a significantly higher intentionality rating’ from untutored respondents than a story like S3 (2001: 40). I also conjectured, however, that with a group of subjects to whom it had recently been made salient that people can be blameworthy for things they do unintentionally (e.g. that a drunk driver who loses control of his car and unintentionally kills a family of five can be blameworthy for killing them) the difference in intentionality ratings of stories like S3 and S4 would shrink significantly (2001: 41). Knobe tests the latter conjecture too. He reports that the result of an experiment with people primed in this way is very similar to the original (p. 701) result: 84 per cent of the 32 respondents said that Jake intentionally killed his aunt in S4 and 40 per cent of the 25 respondents said that he intentionally hit the bull's‐eye in S3 (Knobe 2003a: 318). As in the case of lay judgements about side‐effect actions, how concerned philosophers of mind and action should be with results such as these depends partly on what their aims are.18

Page 9 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action

40.3 Causalism versus Anti‐Causalism A popular approach to understanding both the nature of action and the explanation or production of actions emphasizes causation. The conjunction of the following two theses may be termed standard causalism.19 (1) An event's being an action depends on how it was caused. (2) Proper explanations of actions are causal explanations. Familiar causal theories of action feature as causes such mental items as beliefs, desires, intentions, and related events (e.g. acquiring a proximal intention to A). On an attractive theory of action, actions are analogous to money in a noteworthy respect. The piece of paper with which I just purchased a drink is a genuine US dollar bill partly in virtue of its having been produced (in the right way) by the US Treasury Department. A duplicate bill produced with plates and paper stolen from the Treasury Department is a counterfeit dollar bill, not a genuine one. Similarly, according to one kind of causal theory of action, a certain event is my buying a drink—an action—partly in virtue of its having been produced ‘in the right way’ by certain mental items (Davidson 1980; Brand 1984).20 An event someone else covertly produces by remote control—one including visually indistinguishable bodily motions not appropriately produced by mental states of mine—is not a purchasing of a drink by me, even if it feels to me as though I am in charge.21 Causalism typically is embraced as part of a naturalistic stand on agency according to which mental items featured in causal explanations of the actions of physical beings in some way depend on or are realized in physical states and events. In principle, causalists can welcome any viable solution to the mind–body problem that supports an important place for ‘the mental’ in causal explanations of actions, (p. 702) including viable solutions according to which what does the causal work (in physical agents) is physical states and events that realize beliefs, desires, intentions, events of intention acquisition, and the like. Arguably, a mental item that figures in a genuine causal explanation of an action need not itself be a cause; its place in such an explanation may be secured partly by its relation to a physical cause that realizes it (see Mele 1992a: ch. 2; also see Jackson and Pettit 1988, 1990; Jackson 2000). The idea that actions are to be explained, causally, in terms of mental states or events is at least as old as Aristotle: ‘the origin of action—its efficient, not its final cause—is choice, and that of choice is desire and reasoning with a view to an end’ (Nicomachean Ethics, 1139a31–2). It continues to have a considerable following (including Goldman 1970; Davidson 1980; Brand 1984; Bishop 1989; Velleman 1989, 2000; Mele 1992a, 2003a). Owing partly to the influence of Wittgenstein (1953) and Ryle (1949), causalism fell into disfavour for a time. The first major source of its revival is Donald Davidson's ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’ (1963; 1980: ch. 1). There, in addition to rebutting familiar arguments against causalism and developing a positive causalist view, Davidson presents non‐causalists with a difficult challenge. Addressed to philosophers who hold that when we act intentionally we act for reasons, Page 10 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action the challenge is to provide an account of the reasons for which we in fact act that does not treat (our having) those reasons as figuring in the causation of the relevant behaviour (or, one might add, as realized in physical causes of the behaviour). The challenge is particularly acute when an agent has two or more reasons for A‐ing but A‐s only for only one of them. Here is an illustration: Al has a pair of reasons for mowing his lawn this morning. First, he wants to mow it this week and he believes that this morning is the most convenient time. Second, Al has an urge to repay his neighbor for the rude awakening he suffered recently when she turned on her mower at the crack of dawn and he believes that his mowing his lawn this morning would constitute suitable repayment. As it happens, Al mows his lawn this morning only for one of these reasons. In virtue of what is it true that he mowed his lawn for this reason, and not the other, if not that this reason (or his having it), and not the other, played a suitable causal role in his mowing his lawn? (Mele 1997a: 240) In Mele (2003a: ch. 2) I review detailed attempts to answer this challenge (Wilson 1989; Ginet 1990; Sehon 1994; Wallace 1999) and argue that they fail. Space constraints preclude pursuing the issue here.

40.4 Two Alleged Problems for Causalism In this section I discuss a pair of alleged problems for causalism: causal deviance and vanishing agents. (p. 703)

40.4.1 Causal Deviance Deviant causal chains raise difficulties for causal analyses of action and of doing something intentionally. The alleged problem is that whatever causes are deemed both necessary and sufficient for a resultant event's being an action or for an action's being intentional, cases can be described in which, owing to a deviant causal connection between the favoured causes (e.g. events of intention acquisition) and a resultant event, that event is not an action, or a pertinent resultant action is not done intentionally. The most common examples of deviance divide into two types.22 Cases of primary deviance raise a problem about a relatively direct causal connection between mental items (or their neural realizers) and resultant bodily motion. Cases of secondary deviance focus on behavioural consequences of intentional actions and on the connection between

Page 11 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action these actions and their consequences. The following are, respectively, representative instances of the two types of case: A climber might want to rid himself of the weight and danger of holding another man on a rope, and he might know that by loosening his hold on the rope he could rid himself of the weight and danger. This belief and want [or, one might suppose, his intention to let go of the rope] might so unnerve him as to cause him to loosen his hold [unintentionally]. (Davidson 1980: 79) A man may try to kill someone by shooting at him. Suppose the killer misses his victim by a mile, but the shot stampedes a herd of wild pigs that trample the intended victim to death. (Davidson 1980: 78) Instructive attempts to resolve the problems such cases pose highlight four claims (Searle 1983: chs. 3–4; Brand 1984: ch. 1; Thalberg 1984; Audi 1997; Harman 1997; Mele and Moser 1997; Mele 2003a: ch. 2). (1) Obviously, A is an intentional action only if it is an action; and in many cases of deviance the pertinent event seems not to be an action. For example, the climber's ‘loosening his hold’ is more aptly described as the rope's slipping from his fingers. A non‐action cannot falsify a claim of the form ‘an action is intentional only if it is caused in way w’ (although a non‐action might falsify a claim about actions, an issue discussed shortly). (2) A proper analysis of intentional action may preclude there being a gap between an intentional action's psychological causal initiator (or what realizes it) and the beginning of the action. If, for example, every intentional action necessarily has the acquisition of a proximal intention (again, in the basic case, an intention to A straight away) as a proximate cause, there is no room between cause and the beginning of action for primary deviance.23 Perhaps the climber's loosening his hold also is not an intentional action because it lacks a proximate cause of the right sort. (3) Intention has a continuous guiding function in the development of intentional action. Arguably, because the climber's loosening his hold is not guided by a pertinent intention, it is not an (p. 704) intentional action. (4) An action's being intentional depends on its fitting the agent's conception or representation of the manner in which it will be performed—a condition violated in Davidson's shooting scenario, standardly interpreted. How close the fit must be is, of course, an issue that requires attention (see Mele and Moser 1997). An analysis of intentional action that incorporates these four claims would yield the correct judgement about Davidson's two cases.

George Wilson challenges claim (2). Sometimes, Wilson observes, ‘intentions cause states of nervous agitation that positively enable the agent to perform the type of action intended’ (1989: 252). He offers the example of a weightlifter whose ‘intention to lift the weight then caused a rush of nervous excitement … necessary for him to [raise] the great weight even slightly’. However, this point and example arguably leave the requirement of proximate causation untouched. What is required is not that intention‐inspired nervousness, agitation, or the like play no role in the production of intentional actions, but rather that they not fill a gap between the acquisition of a pertinent proximal intention and action in such a way that intention acquisition figures only mediately in the production of the corresponding action. In Wilson's example, one may contend, there is Page 12 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action no gap between intention acquisition and the beginning of the lifting that is filled by nervousness. Rather, one may argue, intention acquisition proximately initiates the lifting —which action, according to some causalists, begins before the weight's rising (Brand 1984: ch. 1; see Davis 1979; Davidson 1980: ch. 3; Hornsby 1980; McGinn 1982: ch. 5; and Adams and Mele 1992)—while also producing nervousness required for the agent's even budging the weight. Proximal intentions typically are not momentary states. Presumably, the intention to lift the weight in the case at hand is at work as long as the lifting continues. Even if nervousness were required for the occurrence of the agent's muscular movements themselves, a nervousness‐producing proximal intention to lift the weight whose acquisition is a cause of a corresponding intentional lift would, in conjunction with the nervousness, figure in the proximate initiation of those movements.24 If, instead, the causal role of an intention to lift the weight were exhausted by the intention's issuing in nervousness and the nervousness were somehow to result in the upward movement of limbs and weight independently of any pertinent intention present at the time, the ‘weightlifting’ would not be intentional. We would have then a case that, aside from its failure to proffer an intuitively appealing mechanistic explanation of the focal occurrence, is of the same kind as familiar instances in the literature of non‐intentional occurrences caused by intention‐inspired nervousness; for example, the case of the climber. The point about the continued functioning of proximal intentions blunts an objection John Bishop raises to Myles Brand's position on primary deviance. Bishop observes that deviance can break in after intention acquisition has (properly) initiated (p. 705) a causal chain but before bodily movement occurs and deprive the agent of control over his motions (1989: 139). In such a case, although an agent's motions may accord with his intention, he does not act intentionally. On Brand's view, however, the proximal intentions to A that initiate intentional A‐ings also sustain and guide them: ‘Given that intention is in part guidance … of activity, the intention continues as long as guidance … continues’ (Brand 1984: 175; see Searle 1983; Thalberg 1984; Alston 1986; Mele 1992a, 2003a: ch. 2; Mele and Moser 1997). In a case of the kind Bishop imagines, guidance is absent. (For Bishop's own response to primary deviance see his 1989: ch. 5.) Some causal theorists who assess cases of primary deviance as attempted counter‐ examples to a causal account of what it is for an action to be intentional dismiss them on the grounds that they are not cases of action at all (Brand 1984: 18; Thalberg 1984). If this diagnosis is correct, primary deviance poses an apparent problem for the project of constructing a causal analysis of action. Can causalists identify something of a causal nature in virtue of which it is false that the climber performed the action of loosening his grip on the rope? In a discussion of primary deviance Alvin Goldman remarks: ‘A complete explanation of how wants and beliefs lead to intentional acts would require extensive neurophysiological information, and I do not think it is fair to demand of a philosophical analysis that it provide this information. … a detailed delineation of the causal process that is Page 13 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action characteristic of intentional action is a problem mainly for the special sciences’ (1970: 62; see also 166–9). Goldman's remark strikes some readers as evasive (McCann 1974: 462– 3: Bishop 1989: 143–4); but he does have a point. A deviant causal connection between an x and a y is deviant relative to normal causal routes from xs to ys. Moreover, what counts as normal here is perspective‐relative. From the point of view of physics, for example, there is nothing abnormal about Davidson's examples of deviance. And, for beings of a particular kind, the normal route from intention to action may be best articulated partly in neurophysiological terms. One way around the problem posed by our neuroscientific ignorance is to design (in imagination, of course) an agent's motor‐control system. Knowing the biological being's design, we have a partial basis for distinguishing causal chains associated with overt action (that is, action essentially involving peripheral bodily motion) from deviant motion‐ producing chains. If we can distinguish deviant from non‐deviant causal chains in agents we design—that is, chains not appropriate to action from action‐producing chains—then perhaps we would be able to do the same for normal human beings if we were to know a lot more than we do about the human body. I pursue this line of thought in Mele (2003a: ch. 2), where I develop an account of the place of intentions (or their physical realizers) in the causal initiating, sustaining, and guiding of overt actions performed by agents I design. Space constraints oblige me to set this topic aside here.

(p. 706)

40.4.2 Vanishing Agents

Some philosophers claim that causalism is inconsistent with there being any actions at all, that it makes agents vanish. A. I. Melden writes: ‘It is futile to attempt to explain conduct through the causal efficacy of desire—all that can explain is further happenings, not actions performed by agents. … There is no place in this picture … even for the conduct that was to have been explained’ (1961: 128–9). Thomas Nagel expresses a similar worry: ‘The essential source of the problem is a view of persons and their actions as part of the order of nature, causally determined or not. That conception, if pressed, leads to the feeling that we are not agents at all. … my doing of an act—or the doing of an act by someone else—seems to disappear when we think of the world objectively. There seems no room for agency in [such] a world … there is only what happens’ (1986: 110– 11). Straightforwardly interpreted, Nagel's worry is not very worrisome. Tigers and bears are part of the natural order. Setting aside the mind–body problem and radical sceptical hypotheses (it is all a dream, the only biological entities are brains in vats, and the like), it seems clear that such animals act. Tigers and bears fight, run, eat, and so on. When they do these things they are acting. The same is true of us, even if we are part of the natural order. And what is it not to be part of the natural order? Supernatural beings—for example, gods and ghosts—are outside the natural order. That a being needs to be supernatural in order to act is an interesting thought, but I will not try to undermine it

Page 14 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action until I see an argument for it that commands respect. Another way not to be part of the natural order is to be abstract in the way numbers are often said to be. Human beings are not abstract in that way. David Velleman voices a variant of Nagel's worry. He contends that standard causal accounts of action and its explanation do not capture what ‘distinguishes human action from other animal behavior’ and do not accommodate ‘human action par excellence’ (1992: 462; see 2000: ch. 1). He also reports that his objection to what he calls ‘the standard story of human action’ (1992: 461), a causal story, ‘is not that it mentions mental occurrences in the agent instead of the agent himself [but] that the occurrences it mentions in the agent are no more than occurrences in him, because their involvement in an action does not add up to the agent's being involved’ (1992: 463). Velleman says that this problem would remain even if the mind–body problem were to be solved (1992: 468–9), and, like Nagel (1986: 110–11), he regards the problem as ‘distinct from the problem of free‐will’ (Velleman 1992: 465, n. 13). Velleman here runs together two separate issues. Human agents may be involved in some of their intentional actions in ways that tigers and bears are involved in many of their intentional actions. Human agents do not vanish in such actions. Scenarios in which human agents vanish are one thing; scenarios is which actions of human agents do not come up to the level of human action par excellence, whatever that may be, are another. Typical causalists are entitled to complain that Velleman has been unfair to them. In his description of ‘the standard story’ (1992: 461) he apparently has in mind the sort of thing found in the work of causalists searching for what is common to (p. 707) all (overt) intentional actions, or all (overt) actions done for reasons, and for what distinguishes actions of these broad kinds from everything else. If some non‐human animals act intentionally and for reasons, a story with this topic should apply to them. Also, human action par excellence may be intentional action, or action done for a reason, in virtue of its having the properties identified in a standard causal analysis of these things. That the analysis does not provide sufficient conditions for, or a story about, human action par excellence is not a flaw in the analysis, given its target. If Velleman were to believe that causalism lacks the resources for accommodating human action par excellence, he might attack ‘the standard story’ on that front, arguing that it cannot be extended to handle such action. But Velleman himself is a causalist. Moreover, causalists have offered accounts of kinds of action—for example, free or autonomous action and action exhibiting self‐control (the contrary of weakness of will)—that exceed minimal requirements for intentional action or action done for a reason.25 Their story about minimally sufficient conditions for action of the latter kinds is not their entire story about human actions. Locating interesting differences between some intentional human actions and the intentional actions of non‐human animals is an important project. Good work on it will continue to emerge, including work exploring potential roles for higher‐order attitudes and other relatively sophisticated attitudes in understanding philosophically interesting differences (see Frankfurt 1988, 1999; Bratman 1999; Velleman 2000; Mele 2003a: ch. Page 15 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action 10). That work will be more useful and less likely to mislead if its claims are consistent with the theses that to be a human agent is to be a human being who acts and that many non‐human animals act.26

40.5 Conclusion I am not sure where the philosophy of action and its work on intention and intentional action are headed. Owing to its location at the intersection of the philosophy of mind, ethics, and metaphysics, the philosophy of action can be pulled in several directions at once. I have heard it suggested that philosophical work on intention and intentional action will be rendered otiose by discoveries in neuroscience about how intentional actions are produced. I do not see that happening. What it is for something to be an intentional action is a conceptual matter that cannot be settled wholly empirically. The same is true of intention. Thus, whether specific neuroscientific discoveries are discoveries about intentional actions and intentions or something else is also a partly conceptual question that cannot be settled wholly empirically. Elsewhere I have argued that scientists and philosophers can benefit from one another in their (p. 708) efforts to understand and explain intentional behaviour (Mele 2003a, 2006: ch. 2, in press). That, however, is much too long a story to be told here.27

References Adams, F. (1986), ‘Intention and Intentional Action: The Simple View’, Mind and Language, 1: 281–301. Adams, F., and Mele, A. (1992), ‘The Intention/Volition Debate’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 22: 323–38. Alston, W. (1986), ‘An Action‐plan Interpretation of Purposive Explanations of Actions’, Theory and Decision, 20: 275–99. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957), Intention (Oxford: Blackwell). Aristotle (1925), Nicomachean Ethics, in The Works of Aristotle, ix, ed. W. Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Audi, R. (1973), ‘Intending’, Journal of Philosophy, 70: 387–402. —— (1991), ‘Autonomy, Reason, and Desire’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 11: 1–14. —— (1997), ‘Acting for Reasons’, in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 75–105.

Page 16 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action Beardsley, M. (1978), ‘Intending, in A. Goldman and J. Kim (eds.), Values and Morals (Dordrecht: Reidel), 163–84. Bishop, J. (1989), Natural Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Brand, M. (1984), Intending and Acting (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Bratman, M. (1987), Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1999), Faces of Intention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Davidson, D. (1963), ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’, Journal of Philosophy, 60: 685–700; repr. in Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon, 1980) 3–20. —— (1980), Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon). —— (1985), ‘Replies to Essays I–IX’, in B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson (Oxford: Clarendon), 195–229. Davis, L. (1979), Theory of Action (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall). Davis, W. (1997), ‘A Causal Theory of Intending’, in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Frankfurt, H. (1988), The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (1999), Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Ginet, C. (1990), On Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Goldman, A. (1970), A Theory of Human Action (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall). Harman, G. (1986), Change in View (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1997), ‘Practical Reasoning, in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Hornsby, J. (1980), Actions (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Hursthouse, R. (1991), ‘Arational Actions’, Journal of Philosophy, 87: 57–68. Jackson, F. (2000), ‘Psychological Explanation and Implicit Theory’, Philosophical Explorations, 3: 83–95.

Page 17 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action Jackson, F., and Pettit, P. (1988), ‘Functionalism and Broad Content’, Mind, 97: 381–400. (p. 709)

—— (1990), ‘Program Explanation: A General Perspective’, Analysis, 50: 107–17. Kane, R. (1996), The Significance of Free Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Kaufman, A. (1966), ‘Practical Decision’, Mind, 75: 25–44. Knobe, J. (2003a), ‘Intentional Action in Folk Psychology: An Experimental Investigation’, Philosophical Psychology, 16: 309–24. —— (2003b), ‘Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language’, Analysis, 63: 190–4. —— (2004), ‘Intention, Intentional Action and Moral Considerations’, Analysis, 64: 181–7. Lowe, E. J. (1978), ‘Neither Intentional Nor Unintentional’, Analysis, 38: 117–18. McCann, H. (1974), ‘Volition and Basic Action’, Philosophical Review, 83: 451–73. —— (1975), ‘Trying, Paralysis, and Volition’, Review of Metaphysics, 28: 423–42. —— (1986a), ‘Intrinsic Intentionality’, Theory and Decision, 20: 247–73. —— (1986b), ‘Rationality and the Range of Intention’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 191–211. —— (1997), ‘Settled Objectives and Rational Constraints', in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 204–22. McGinn, C. (1982), The Character of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Melden, A. (1961), Free Action (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). Mele, A. (1992a), Springs of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1992b), Recent Work on Intentional Action’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 29: 199–217. —— (1992c), ‘Acting for Reasons and Acting Intentionally’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73: 355–74. —— (1995), Autonomous Agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1997a), ‘Agency and Mental Action’, Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 231–49. —— (1997b), ‘Introduction’, in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 1–26.

Page 18 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action —— (2001), ‘Acting Intentionally: Probing Folk Notions’, in B. Malle, L. Moses, and D. Baldwin (eds.), Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 27–44. —— (2003a), Motivation and Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2003b), ‘Intentional Action: Controversies, Data, and Core Hypotheses’, Philosophical Psychology, 16: 325–40. —— (2005), ‘Action’, in F. Jackson and M. Smith (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 334–57. —— (2006), Free Will and Luck (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (in press), Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Mele, A., and Moser, P. (1997), ‘Intentional Action’, in A. Mele (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 223–55. Mele, A., and Sverdlik, S. (1996), ‘Intention, Intentional Action, and Moral Responsibility’, Philosophical Studies, 82: 265–87. Mill, J. S. (1843/1961), A System of Logic, 8th edn. (London: Longmans, Green). Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press). O'Connor, T. (2000), Persons and Causes (Oxford: Oxford University Press). O'Shaughnessy, B. (1980), The Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Peacocke, C. (1985), ‘Intention and Akrasia’, in B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson (Oxford: Clarendon), 51–73. Pears, D. (1984), Motivated Irrationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Pears, D. (1985), ‘Intention and Belief’, in B. Vermazen and M. Hintikka (eds.), Essays on Davidson (Oxford: Clarendon), 75–88. (p. 710)

Pink, T. (1996), The Psychology of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Quinn, W. (1993), Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Ridge, M. (1998), Humean Intentions', American Philosophical Quarterly, 35: 157–78. Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson). Scanlon, T. (1998), What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

Page 19 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). —— (2001), Rationality in Action (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Sehon, S. (1994), ‘Teleology and the Nature of Mental States’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 31: 63–72. Smith, M. (1994), The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell). Thalberg, I. (1977), Perception, Emotion, and Action (Oxford: Blackwell). —— (1984), ‘Do Our Intentions Cause Our Intentional Actions?’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 21: 249–60. Thomson, J. (1977), Acts and Other Events (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press). Velleman, J. D. (1989), Practical Reflection (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). —— (1992), ‘What Happens When Someone Acts?’, Mind, 101: 461–81. —— (2000), The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Clarendon). Wallace, R. J. (1999), ‘Three Conceptions of Rational Agency’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 2: 217–42. Wilson, G. (1989), The Intentionality of Human Action (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press). Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (New York: Macmillan).

Notes: (1) See Wilson (1989) for a third approach, according to which intentions are not attitudes. (2) On motivation see Smith (1994) and Mele (2003a). (3) A relatively popular claim among philosophers is that agents intend at a time t1 to A at a time t2—where t1 and t2 may or may not be identical—only if they believe at t1 that they (probably) will A at t2. (Proponents—some of whom omit the parenthetical qualifier— include Audi 1973, 1991, 1997, Beardsley 1978, Harman 1986: ch. 8, 1997, Velleman 1989, and Davis 1997). The proposal is designed to capture, among other things, the confidence in one's success that intending allegedly involves. In Mele (1992a: ch. 8) I defend the less demanding claim that intending at t1 to A at t2 requires that, at t1, one lack the belief that one (probably) will not do A at t2. (The person might have no belief on the matter.) Other alternatives include the requirement that S believe to a ‘degree’ (even

Page 20 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action a degree associated with a subjective probability significantly less than 0.5) that he will A (Pears 1984: 124; also see Pears 1985) and the requirement that S believe that ‘there is some chance that he can’ A (Davidson 1985: 215). (4) For resistance to this idea see Searle (1983) and Brand (1984). (5) On the first pair of functions see Brand (1984), Thalberg (1984), Bishop (1989), and Mele (2003a: ch. 2). On the second pair see Harman (1986, 1997) and Bratman (1987, 1999). For discussion of all four functions see Mele (1992a: ch. 8). (6) Roughly speaking, basic actions differ from non‐basic actions in not being performed by way of performing another action. (7) The commitment aspect of intention receives detailed treatment in Bratman (1987). See also Audi (1991) and Mele (1992a: chs. 9–10). For a more detailed summary of the dispute between belief/desire reductionists about intention and their opponents see Mele (1997b: 17–19). (8) Searle makes a case for the importance of what he calls ‘intentions in actions’ (1983: ch. 3). As far as I can tell, they are tryings. On this matter see Mele (1992a: 183–6). (9) By the end of the 1970s a lively debate over the question of action‐individuation had produced a collection of relatively precise alternatives. Imagine that Don flips the switch, turns on the light, illuminates the room, and—unbeknownst to him—alerts a prowler to his presence (Davidson 1980: 4). How many actions does he perform? Davidson's coarse‐ grained answer is one action ‘of which four descriptions have been given’ (1980: 4; also see Anscombe 1957). A fine‐grained alternative treats A and B as different actions if, in performing them, the agent exemplifies different act‐properties (Goldman 1970). On this view, Don performs at least four actions, since the act‐properties at issue are distinct. An agent may exemplify any of these act‐properties without exemplifying any of the others. One may even turn on a light in a room without illuminating the room: the light may be painted black. Another alternative, a componential view, represents Don's illuminating the room as an action having various components, including (but not limited to) his moving his arm, his flipping the switch, and the light's going on (Thalberg 1977; Thomson 1977; Ginet 1990). Where proponents of the coarse‐grained and fine‐grained theories find, respectively, a single action under different descriptions and a collection of intimately related actions, advocates of the various componential views locate a larger action having smaller actions among its parts. In this chapter I proceed in a neutral way regarding the leading contending theories of individuation. Readers may read my action variable ‘A’ in accordance with their preferred theory of action‐individuation. The same goes for the term ‘action’. (10) This broadly Davidsonian conception of reasons for action is controversial. Some philosophers contend that Davidsonian reasons for action are not reasons at all. T. M. Scanlon, for example, argues that ‘desires almost never provide reasons for action in the way described by [this] model’ (1998: 43). Philosophical work on reasons for action tends Page 21 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action to be guided primarily either by a concern with the explanation of actions or by a concern with the evaluation of actions or their agents. In work dominated by the former concern, reasons for action tend to be understood as states of mind along broadly Davidsonian lines. Philosophers with the latter concern may be sympathetic or unsympathetic to this construal, depending on their views about standards for evaluating actions or agents. For example, a theorist whose evaluative concern is with rational action and who holds that the pertinent notion of rationality is subjective—in the sense that a proper verdict about the rationality or irrationality of an agent's action is to be made from the perspective of the agent's own desires, beliefs, principles, and the like, rather than from some external, or partly external, perspective—may be happy to understand reasons for action as states of mind. A theorist with a more objective conception of rational action or rational agency also is likely to have a more objective conception of reasons for action. Such a theorist may find it natural to insist that many or all reasons for action are facts about the agent‐ external world. If there are agent‐external justificatory reasons for action, it may be that intentional actions are to be relatively directly explained at least partly in terms of Davidsonian reasons and that when external justificatory reasons contribute to explanations of intentional actions they do so less directly, by way of a causal contribution made by an agent's apprehending such a reason to his acquiring a Davidsonian reason. An exploration of the possibility of external justificatory reasons and of their compatibility with the existence of Davidsonian reasons quickly takes one well beyond the philosophy of action into moral philosophy and value theory. For discussion of these possibilities see Mele (2003a: chs. 3–6). (11) On these issues see Mele (2001, 2003b). (12) For a more comprehensive survey of the literature on this example see Mele (1992b: 202–5). (13) My view is a version of Bratman's ‘single‐phenomenon view’ (Bratman 1987: 112–13, 119–27). (14) For further discussion see Mele (1997b: 22–3). (15) Incidentally, Knobe asked parallel questions about the chairman in S2 who benefitted the environment without caring whether he did. 20 per cent said that he intentionally benefitted the environment and none said that he intended to benefit it (Knobe 2004: 185). (16) For resistance see Mele (1992c). Incidentally, intuitions tend to shift when the agent succeeds in a way that diverges significantly from her plan, or from her (perhaps tacit) assumptions about what a successful A‐ing would involve. If the bullet had ricocheted off several rocks into the bull's‐eye, would Ann's hitting the bull's‐eye have been done for a reason?

Page 22 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action (17) If hitting the bull's‐eye seems to be a more difficult task than killing the woman, that may account for part of the difference in the respondents' judgements. Knobe also asked about variants of these cases in which ‘Jake is an expert marksman. His hands are steady. The gun is aimed perfectly’. Here 95 per cent of the respondents said that he intentionally killed his aunt and 79 per cent said that he intentionally hit the bull's‐eye (Knobe 2003a: 314). This difference in responses might be partially accounted for by differences in respondents' assumptions about difficulty. In an ideal test, it would be clear that the moral and non‐moral tasks are equally difficult. For a pair of cases of this kind see Mele and Sverdlik (1996: 281–2). (18) For a review of problems for A1 and A2 posed by sudden and impulsive actions and by subsidiary actions see Mele (1992b). (19) I borrow the term ‘causalism’ from Wilson (1989). (Wilson is a non‐causalist.) (20) Alternative conceptions of action include: an ‘internalist’ view according to which actions differ experientially from other events in a way that is essentially independent of how, or whether, they are caused (Ginet 1990); a conception of actions as composites of non‐actional mental events or states (e.g. intentions) and pertinent non‐actional effects (e.g. an arm's rising) (Mill 1843/1961; Searle 1983); and views identifying an action with the causing of a suitable non‐actional product by appropriate non‐actional mental items (Dretske 1988)—or, instead, by an agent (Bishop 1989; O'Connor 2000). (21) This view does not identify actions with non‐actional events caused in the right way. That would be analogous to identifying genuine US dollar bills with pieces of printed paper that are not genuine US dollar bills and are produced in the right way by the US Treasury Department, and so identifying genuine US dollar bills would be absurd. (22) For a third type see Mele (1992a: 207–10). (23) ‘Proximate cause’ may be defined as follows: x is a proximate cause of y if and only if x is a cause of y and there is nothing z such that x is a cause of z and z is a cause of y. (24) Here I set aside cases in which a nervousness‐producing intention to lift the weight issues in a distinct intention to lift the weight that has a more direct causal role in the lifting. Such cases pose no special problems. (25) Many compatibilists are causalists about action. For a causalist account of self‐ control see Mele (1995). (26) For discussion of a third alleged problem for causalism—the problem of so‐called negative actions (e.g. intentionally not voting in an election)—see Mele (2003a: 146–54). (27) Parts of this chapter derive from Mele (1992a, 1992b, 1997b, 2003a, 2003b, and 2005).

Page 23 of 24

Intention and Intentional Action

Alfred R. Mele

Alfred R. Mele is the William H. and Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy at Florida State University and director of the Big Questions in Free Will Project (2010– 13). He is the author of Irrationality (1987), Springs of Action (OUP, 1992), Autonomous Agents (1995), Self-Deception Unmasked (2001), Motivation and Agency (OUP, 2003), Free Will and Luck (OUP, 2006), and Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will (OUP, 2009). He also is the editor or coeditor of The Philosophy of Action (1997), Mental Causation (1993), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality (OUP, 2004), Rationality and the Good (2007), and Free Will and Consciousness: How Might They Work? (2010).

Page 24 of 24

Folk Psychology

Oxford Handbooks Online Folk Psychology   Adam Morton The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0042

Abstract and Keywords We describe people in terms of their beliefs, desires, emotions, and personalities, and we attempt to explain their actions in terms of these and other such states. These are folkpsychological concepts; they are the ones we use when we think of people in terms of their minds. By ‘folk psychology’ it is meant whatever serves this linking role for folkpsychological concepts. Much philosophical writing about concepts would suggest that the linking must be done primarily by beliefs or theories; a central question is whether this is so for folk-psychological concepts. Keywords: folk psychology, belief and desire, concepts of emotion, human action, physical world, state of mind

WE describe people in terms of their beliefs, desires, emotions, and personalities, and we attempt to explain their actions in terms of these and other such states. These are folk‐ psychological concepts; they are the ones we use when we think of people in terms of their minds. (Strawson 1959 called them ‘M‐concepts’.) Let us leave it fairly vague what is to count as a folk‐psychological concept, taking as core examples the concepts of belief and desire and concepts of emotion, and then including as folk psychological concepts any concepts whose primary function is to enter into combination with the core examples to give explanations and predictions of human action. (It is important to remember, though, that explaining and predicting action is not the only purpose of ascribing states of mind. Often, for example, the ascription is part of an inference to a conclusion about the physical world, as when we say ‘She seems to be lying, so there is probably something hidden in the basement’.) Usually when there are concepts there are beliefs or theories, whose structure allows us to understand the concepts by linking them to other concepts and to experience. By ‘folk psychology’ let us mean whatever serves this linking role for folk‐psychological concepts. Much philosophical writing about concepts would

Page 1 of 18

Folk Psychology suggest that the linking must be done primarily by beliefs or theories; a central question is whether this is so for folk‐psychological concepts.

Page 2 of 18

Folk Psychology

41.1 Theory The idea now labelled ‘folk psychology’ arose around the 1970s when a number of philosophers, often influenced by Sellars's description (1956) of ‘the myth of Jones’ and by Quine's assimilation (1953) of all of our thinking to explanatory (p. 714) hypotheses, began to explore the consequences of assuming that individual people acquire from their cultures an explicit theory which postulates that individuals have beliefs, desires, and other states, which interact in specific ways to produce actions. (Typical examples are Putnam 1960, Dennett 1978, Churchland 1979.) This theory would be the common‐sense precursor of psychological theories developed as part of the scientific approach to human nature. The position had many attractive features. First, it fitted very neatly with the dominant account at the time of the nature of mental states, functionalism, according to which, roughly, mental states are any states of an organism which interact in the right ways. The right ways can then be taken as those described by folk psychology. Second, the position also provided a new take on the old epistemological problem of other minds. The traditional argument from analogy was intellectually discredited, but now it became possible to see each person's reason for attributing states of mind to others as an inference to the best explanation, in which the ‘hypothesis’ that another has states interacting in the way required by folk psychology emerges as the best explanation of the person's actions. And, third, it became possible to formulate a new range of philosophical questions analogous to old‐fashioned scepticism about the existence of other minds but much more varied and plausible. Is folk psychology true? Is it a first approximation to an eventual scientific psychology? Might it eventually be replaced by a theory based on experimental evidence? These questions are much saner than other‐minds scepticism: one can quite naturally imagine the answers to any of them going either way. But is there such a folk‐psychological theory? The overwhelming consensus among philosophers and psychologists is that there is not, if what we have in mind is an explicit theory that can be expressed in ordinary language and that is learned by children from adults through its linguistic presentation. The most basic reason is that we cannot produce the theory in sufficient detail to determine, for example, the situations in which normal folk psychologists will take a stronger motive to overrule a weaker one. To that extent what Morton (1980) called the ‘theory theory’ is clearly false. But there are many unrefuted theory theories still in contention: for there are many more promising ways of understanding ‘theory’. Instead of debating theory/no theory, it is clearer to follow Nichols and Stich (2003) and contrast information‐rich and information‐poor accounts of folk psychology. Information‐rich accounts postulate a source of articulated principles to guide attribution, understanding, and prediction. The principles may not be formulated in spoken language or available to conscious reflection, but they guide our more explicit judgements. They may originate in innate information‐processing routines, reflection on the actions of others, or innate constraints on the explanations of others. According to Page 3 of 18

Folk Psychology information‐poor accounts, on the other hand, the fundamental features of our thinking about mind are determined by routines and capacities which do not embody any assumptions about how one state of mind leads to another.

Page 4 of 18

Folk Psychology

(p. 715)

41.2 Simulation

To see how an information‐poor account can be formulated consider ‘simulation’ accounts of mental‐state ascription. There are two influential models, one due to Jane Heal (1995) and the other to Robert Gordon (1995). Heal's model applies best to cases in which one person has to predict what another person will do given an intellectual problem. Suppose that one person, A, is predicting which of ‘some fish fish for fish’ and ‘some dogs dog for dog’ another person, B, will judge to be a grammatical English sentence, or what B will say when asked the product of 120×13. The natural way for A to solve the problem of predicting B's response is not to think about B's thought processes directly but simply to solve the problem herself and then to suppose that B will give the correct answer; that is, the one that A has just come up with. This procedure is information‐poor in that A's thinking does not need to represent any suggestion about how B thinks. A just has to think, and then to transfer the result. The other pioneering simulation account, Gordon's, applies best to cases in which a person is predicting another person's decision. Suppose that A is driving behind B and sees a deer run into the road in front of B's car. A can anticipate B's braking heavily and swerving to the left. A will then also brake, before seeing B's brake lights, and may decide not to swerve left in the hope of missing both B and the deer. One way in which A could form this expectation about B's behaviour is by deciding what she would do in B's place, where this means not thinking about B's decision but making it, feeding into her own decision‐making processes the facts about B's situation and then taking the result not as an intention for her own action but as a prediction about B's. A crucial part of the capacity to think of others as minds, on such an account, is being able to take one's own decision processes ‘off line’ and use them to form expectations about other people's actions. To do this one has to be able to take the other person's point of view, at least to the extent of understanding what aspects of the situation are and are not known to the other person, and one has to be able to insulate it from the processes by which one turns decisions into actions. As Currie (1995) and others have pointed out, these capacities are also required for conditional thinking, in which one feeds into one's decision processes some hypothetical facts and then stores the outcome as a conditional decision, not to be acted on unless the facts turn out to be actual. The contrast between simulation and theory should not be made too stark. In most cases a Gordon‐type simulation will have to be guided by some information about how it is to be performed. (‘The driver ahead can see the deer because it is nearer to him than it is to me, and so I can take that information into the simulation; but he may not know that I am close behind, so I can leave that information out.’) In many cases, too, a simulation will also require information about the target person's (p. 716) desires, which may not be the same as those of the ascriber. (Suppose the driver ahead is known to hate deer more than he loves his car. Then in order to predict his actions one has to replace one's own aversion to a collision with an aim towards one.) So even an information‐poor simulation Page 5 of 18

Folk Psychology account will have to make use of information about when and how to simulate, and this information is potentially very rich. Or consider how a Heal‐type account can apply to situations in which the target person's problem‐solving capacities are greater or less than those of the ascriber. (Their grasp of English syntax is feeble; their arithmetic is brilliant or eccentric.) Then in addition to solving the problem oneself one will have to apply some correction or transformation, to come up with the other person's solution. Most real cases will have some element of this, and will as a result require guidance from some beliefs about the other's problem‐solving capacities and how to take them into account (Heal 2000; Morton 2002: ch. 2). The line between applying a theory and reproducing the other person's thinking in your own mind is also vague. Suppose for example one is anticipating a person's actions by using a theory of belief/desire/action. Ascriptions of beliefs and desires will be needed, and there will usually be unmanageably many possibilities consistent with the person's prior behaviour. A natural approach to the problem is to use one's own desires and beliefs as a first approximation, adjusting the ascription as needed later on. In fact, we do unreflectively assume that others believe that the sky is above the earth and that death is to be avoided, in the absence of very strong evidence to the contrary. As Goldman (1989) has pointed out, this amounts to a kind of simulation: one uses one's own assessment of the situation as a guide to the thinking of the other. (The default ascriptions are information‐rich in that a lot of information about the environment is taken into account, and information‐poor in that one entertains fewer thoughts about the other person's thinking.) Information‐poor procedures have generally been found attractive when the task of anticipating another person's actions by tracing their beliefs and desires and reasoning is too daunting. In fact, even in the most favourable cases it is hard to see how one could anticipate actions purely by use of a theory of motivation. The reason is the combinatorial explosion of possible lines of reasoning. Given a desire for a small cup of coffee and enough coins to operate a machine that vends a large cup of decent coffee, a person might of course use the coins to buy the coffee and drink half of it, but she might also wait till someone else buys a cup and then buy half of it from them, or buy a cup and then sell half of it to another, or any of indefinitely many other actions, all of them easily rationalizable in terms of her beliefs and desires. But in many real situations we feel sure —somehow—what lines of thought people are likely to follow. It might then seem miraculous that this confidence succeeds, that people do quite often do what we expect them to. The reason, though, is that we do not blindly follow out all possible lines of reasoning available to a person. Instead, we expect people to follow reasoning that seems natural to us, the reasoning we ourselves would follow. And, of course, we adjust this expectation given what we learn about particular people's peculiarities. (p. 717)

Page 6 of 18

Folk Psychology The question of the exact mix of cognitively demanding information‐rich theory and less demanding information‐poor procedures remains very puzzling. It seems clear that we very rarely get to a prediction of what someone will do by combining explicit information about the person's beliefs and desires with explicit information about how human beings combine beliefs and desires to form intentions. On the other hand, it seems clear that we normally deploy a rich variety of information, about particular people and about people in general, in forming our expectations of what they are likely to do. Here is a suggestion about how the pieces fit together, a reasonable suggestion given the current state of the debate, but definitely a speculation. There are three basic resources, on this suggestion. The first is a core folk‐psychological theory, which specifies the basic characteristics of the basic psychological states. Call it the ‘category theory’, as it outlines the general categories of states that can be ascribed to people. It postulates informational states that represent the world as it is taken to be, target states that represent the world as the person aims to make it, emotions and other dispositions to types of behaviour, and processes of reasoning that lead from beliefs and desires to intentions or actions. Most of this theory is in place in four‐year‐old children, and parts of it emerge very early in life. But the theory does not specify what informational and target states there are. (It is neutral on the relation between what someone ‘thinks’, what she ‘supposes’, and what she ‘believes’, or between what she ‘wants’, ‘needs’, and ‘would like’.) It does not specify what forms reasoning takes. (It simply says that people think and form intentions, and consider evidence and change their beliefs.) And it does not embody any ideas about rationality. (Wishful thinking is as likely as syllogisms, according to the core theory.) The category theory becomes more powerful if it is scaffolded with some other skills. One obvious skill is linguistic. In learning to speak one acquires one's culture's vocabulary of mental‐state terms and learns how to ascribe them. Belief‐ascription—in particular, knowing what state is ascribed to a person when someone says ‘she believes that p’— must be especially hard to learn, as the rules governing it are extremely subtle (Braun 1998). Given a command of the language, one can attribute to people the states ascribed to them by other people or themselves, as a basis for thinking about their minds. (How much of this ascription is literally true, and how much is part of a social web of mutual ascriptions which domesticated adults cannot easily act contrary to? That is not the kind of question that the philosophers or psychologists thinking about folk psychology pay a lot of attention to. For an exception see Kusch 1999.) And, given language, a great stock of platitudes, logical principles, folk generalizations, and old wives' tales becomes available, some of which will apply in almost any situation. No amount of linguistic competence will allow one more than a primitive level of prediction and explanation without the second basic resource. That is simulation: the capacity to use one's own information and thinking as a guide to the thought of other people. One has to be able to say where a person's beliefs and desires might take her, for which the core theory gives no help. There are two related and possibly (p. 718) prior capacities from which capacities of a generally simulational kind can develop. The first is Page 7 of 18

Folk Psychology the capacity, which develops early in normal children, to track the gaze of another person, to know where the other is looking. This allows a child to know which of the situations she is observing are also part of the information available to another. The second is the capacity for conditional thinking, which allows you to see what conclusions you would have come to if you had had counterfactual information and aims. Mastering counterfactual thinking requires that one learn how to separate beliefs and desires into consistent strands: wondering what would happen if the chair were put on the table involves separating off one's belief that the chair is not on the table, just as one has to when thinking what someone will do who thinks that the chair is on the table. The capacity to follow another person's gaze is an essential prerequisite to using one's own mind to model the thinking of another. Conditional thinking on the other hand provides increasingly subtle ways of using information about another. For example, it allows one to explore the consequences of the fact that someone has not noticed something. They are both part of a third resource, neither category theory nor simulation. Let me call it the ‘how‐to manual’. This is a body of information about what kinds of simulation work under what conditions, and about what information about another person can be used as input to one's own thinking in modelling another's. It must also have an element of knowing how: how to use what one knows about others to fine‐tune one's simulation of them. I call it a manual rather than a theory as it is likely to consist of a large number of rough generalizations and unconnected facts, and even of little tricks that work only for anticipating the thinking of particular individuals. Still, the manual is a body of rich if disparate information, largely second‐order information about how to use the first‐order information one has about other's minds to guide one's information‐poor explanatory capacities. The suggestion of a three‐component capacity is conjectural. But the problems it addresses must be faced by any account of folk psychology. Once we accept that we use both information‐rich and information‐poor procedures, we must ask how they are combined. Are there standard ways of combining the basic components, which come more or less inevitably to human beings living human social lives? Or does each person work with their own improvised tool kit, made up from the same basic parts joined together in the ways that work for that person? We don't know.

Page 8 of 18

Folk Psychology

41.3 Development and Evolution The capacity to understand one another as minds is a core human attribute. Human knowledge and social life would be impossible without it. Social life is the more fundamental; in terms of our abilities to know people's aims, intentions, beliefs, and personalities we can enter into cooperative activities in ways that minimize the danger of cheating or free‐riding. Our capacity for knowledge is in a way a special case of this. (p. 719) We negotiate a complex structure of sources of information largely by treating it as a social network in which a delicate cooperation is needed so that each person gets the information they need. Non‐human animals do not have these capacities in anything like human form, and human infants have to go through a considerable process of development or learning before they can exercise adult competence. If therefore we could understand how individual humans come to acquire mind‐ascribing capacities and how humanity as a species came to possess them, we would understand something very basic about what it is to be human. To psychologists, as to philosophers, the idea that our capacity to think in mental terms is based on a theory was immediately very appealing. But psychologists immediately supposed that the ‘theory of mind’ must be an implicit theory that develops during a child's first few years of life. Early writers in the theory‐of‐mind movement, such as Wellman (1990) and Perner (1991), supposed that a child moves towards a theory the core of which postulates that human beings have representations of the environment, some in the form of beliefs and some in the form of desires. A key theoretical aim was to understand false‐belief problems, the surprising difficulty children before the age of three have in attributing false beliefs. The experimental data, originally due to Wimmer and Perner (1983), concerns situations in which unambiguous evidence of a fact is available to a child but not to a ‘target’ person. For example candy is moved from one container to another, in the sight of the child but not of the target person. An adult would unhesitatingly ascribe to the target person a false belief, the belief that makes sense in the absence of the evidence. But small children instead ascribe to the target person a true belief, the belief that they themselves have formed in response to the evidence. They say that the target person will look for the candy in the place to which it has been moved, although she has not seen it moved. The phenomenon is robust under a number of variations. It certainly shows that small children have difficulty with knowing when others will and will not make inferences. The difficult thought is: Evidence E is not available to X, so X will not have made the inference ‘E therefore not p’. It does suggest that the concepts of knowledge and ignorance are easier to grasp than the concept of belief, for small children have little problem understanding that people can lack particular true beliefs. (That is why hide‐and‐seek is not a conceptual problem: the child can think ‘X does not believe I am here’ even though she may have difficulty with ‘X believes that I am there when I am here’.) It is not clear how much trouble small children have with false beliefs when understanding inference is Page 9 of 18

Folk Psychology not required: for example when an authority simply announces that X thinks the candy is in location L (when in fact the child knows that it is in location L′). There does not seem to be a robust phenomenon of children then expecting X to look in location L′. Nor are false‐ belief difficulties insuperable; suitable coaching can improve the performance of children who are under the threshold. But the threshold is real and does mark a point in the development of normal human children. Some older children with developmental difficulties, notably autistic children, have the same difficulties with false‐belief tasks that young children have, even though their general intelligence is on a level with (p. 720) children who are well past the threshold. Great apes, such as chimpanzees, bonobos, and gorillas, do not solve analogues of classic false‐belief tasks successfully, even though deliberate deception and distraction is not uncommon in their social life. It is as if they too can understand ‘p, but X does not believe p’ but cannot understand ‘p, but X believes not p’. The rival accounts of folk psychology that we have already seen can be used to explain what is going on in false‐belief tasks. Simulation accounts fit very naturally with the pre‐ threshold child's behaviour: she models the target person's beliefs on her own and predicts that the target person will do what she would do. What the child struggles to learn, on these accounts, is how to keep facts available to herself but not to the target person out of her modelling of the other's thinking. Theory theory accounts, on the other hand, can explain very simply what the child past the threshold has learned. She has improved her theory of thinking so that it includes a clause ‘if X cannot observe that P then, other things being equal, X will not believe that p’. (This combined with the fact that X initially believes that not p, will entail that X will continue to hold the false belief that not p.) Each account's strength as applied to the false‐belief situation links to a weakness. When a simulation account suggests that in passing the crucial threshold children learn how to be selective about which of their own beliefs to use in modelling another person's thinking, it draws attention to the absence of any account of how one makes this selection. Since a selection is suitable or not depending on the situation of the target person, including that person's beliefs and desires, it must be guided by some reflection on the person's mind (at a minimum, reflection on whether the person was paying attention to the crucial inference‐triggering evidence). On the other hand, when a theory theory suggests that the crucial transition consists in improving the child's theory of inference, it draws attention to its ascription to the child of a theory of inference. But, as we have seen, explicit theories of inference are unmanageable monsters, quite useless for predicting what conclusions a person will arrive at. The speculative account in the previous section, according to which a core theory specifies simply that people have beliefs and desires, and avoids any commitments about inference, can be used to get around these problems. Suppose that at the earlier stage of children's development the core theory makes available to them the thought that others have beliefs, but that children rely for the content of these beliefs largely on simple rules such as: When a person can perceive something they have true beliefs about it; when Page 10 of 18

Folk Psychology something is obvious and a person has a belief about it then they believe the obvious. For updating the beliefs ascribed to a person in the face of evidence children would simply use their own belief changes as a guide to the thinking of the other person. Then, as they pass the threshold they would learn which of their own inferences can be used to model other people's thinking under which circumstances. They would do this by forming a theory—not a theory of inference but rather a theory of how to track someone else's reasoning with their own. Some of the applications of this theory are very subtle and complicated, and in principle the theory could continually improve throughout a person's life, but at the threshold stage (p. 721) it can consist of some fairly simple principles such as ‘Model X's belief changes only using information available to X’. If this suggestion is correct, a child emerges past the false‐belief threshold with a conceptual structure characteristic of adult thinking about minds, though the range and power of her thinking about personality and motive may be much less than that of most adults. It consists of a collection of simulational capacities sandwiched between two theories, the category theory and the how‐to manual mentioned above. The suggestion here does not fit easily into a simple evolutionary story of how human mental‐state ascription developed from the capacities of other apes. It neither points to a single crucial conceptual development which characterizes the human situation, nor allows us to see a clear series of steps leading from primate sociality to human thinking. For the basic elements of the category theory can be expected to be found in other apes, and the crucial false‐belief threshold consists not in a development of this theory but in a series of small accretions to the how‐to manual, which is much more dependent on language and on social interaction. And though the suggestion may of course be wrong, recent comparative primate work has marked a retreat from the once‐fashionable view (Byrne and Whiten 1988; Byrne 1995) that the cooperation and deception in primate life makes it likely that many primates, and in particular chimpanzees, bonobos, and gorillas, possess many of the capacities essential to human thinking about mind, which require just a little tweaking and reconnecting to come together in their human form. Now, in contrast, the consensus (Povinelli and Eddy 1996; Sterelney 2004: ch. 4) is that ape capacities to track the attention of other apes, and to take account of information in the possession of others, are much more limited than we had for a while supposed, and that there are far more discontinuities than continuities with human cognition. That is not to say that we should see human folk psychology as emerging in a discontinuous evolutionary leap. In fact, it is much easier to give plausible accounts of its origins than for the origins of, say, human language. It is not deeply puzzling how folk psychology could have evolved, though we do not know nearly enough to choose from among the possible routes. Our ancestors, like other apes, had the capacity to recognize dozens of individual conspecifics and remember their important characteristics; they could judge the mood of individual conspecifics by attention to their gaits and faces; they could form long‐term and temporary coalitions for purposes as diverse as hunting and raising offspring; they could commit themselves to cooperative behaviour in situations in which it was in the interests of each individual to Page 11 of 18

Folk Psychology defect from such behaviour, and estimate the likelihood that another individual would defect; they could participate in routines for distribution of food and other resources and detect individuals who were abusing the routines. Many of these capacities were based on special‐purpose cognitive processes aimed at specific types of situation, which, if evolutionary psychologists are correct (Barkow et al. 1992), still operate in human thought. But when we consider the effect of the slow accretion of capacities such as these we can see many ways in which they can scaffold the development of more general‐ purpose capacities, and in (p. 722) particular the attribution of information‐bearing states like those the philosophers and developmental psychologists have focused on. Part of one story might go as follows. Proto‐humans engage in cooperative hunting and foraging which requires them to keep track of what situations are perceivable to which others. This has a conceptual requirement, that they be able to represent the relation ‘X sees that p’, and a ‘pragmatic’ requirement, that they be able to figure out what one might be able to see from position p under current conditions. (These might be taken as among the precursors of the two folk‐psychological theories mentioned above.) As these capacities improve, over thousands of years, language develops and with it the capacity to register reports of what people have seen, or take themselves to have seen, from places outside one's field of view. Then the eventual combination of these three things— the concept of perception, the ability to take a perspective, and the understanding of verbal reports—results in the roots of an understanding of knowledge or belief. (The co‐ evolution of folk psychology and language is something we have to understand in order to get much further with these questions. The topic is very promising, but also very hard to handle responsibly.) A similar story could be told for the evolution of the capacity to use attributions of belief and desire to anticipate behaviour. It would be a separate story, though, requiring a different, if overlapping, set of social skills as its starting point. (I would conjecture that crucial to this second story might be the capacity to manipulate others with misleading information, and to resist such manipulation.) Even when we combine the origin‐of‐belief story and this practical‐reasoning story we do not have a full account, though. We need to explain how the conceptual and pragmatic components of these and other metacognitive skills come together to form a relatively integrated body of cognitive routines for connecting information, desire, emotion, and all the other states we attribute. It is plausible that this integration could not happen without language and its specific vocabulary for states of mind and more particularly its resources for using attributions in explanations of actions. There are alternative stories, and the present evidence is not going to decide between them. The important point, though, is that we can see in principle how the evolution of folk psychology is possible. The crucial element is ‘niche construction’ (Sterelny 2004: ch. 8): the way in which a set of attributes can permit an animal, particularly a social animal, to change its environment in ways that allow other attributes to evolve. In the case at hand the first attributes are those that allow specific forms of cooperative activity, the

Page 12 of 18

Folk Psychology niche is stable social life in which more effective cooperation and resistance to exploitation pays off, and the other attributes are the components of folk‐psychological competence.

Page 13 of 18

Folk Psychology

41.4 Epistemological Questions Folk psychology allows us to attribute states of mind to others, and to use these attributions to predict what others will do. Do we know what states of mind others are (p. 723) in, or what they will do? Are our beliefs about these things reasonable, or justified, or worth holding on to? It is not immediately obvious that these questions get answered with Yes. Compare crude folk meteorology. People look at the sky and smell the wind and consider the behaviour of plants and animals, and by instinct and traditional lore come up with opinions about whether it is a good time for the harvest. Sometimes they are right and sometimes they are wrong. They are wrong significantly often. The explanations they give have little to do with cold fronts or wind patterns in the stratosphere. Often supernatural or simply superstitious elements play an important role. It is far from obvious that the old‐time farmer has a reasonable belief that the crops should be taken in early this year. Are our beliefs about one another any different? Two basic considerations pull in opposite directions here. On the one hand, our attempts to understand one another are largely successful, in that human social life and human science flourish, and without an effective folk psychology they would be impossible. Isn't success it's own justification? On the other hand, there is a now enormous body of social‐ psychological experiment which shows how wrong we often are about one another and ourselves. Among our failings, we think that people are more likely to repeat patterns of behaviour than in fact they are (Nisbett and Ross 1980); we underestimate how much people's opinions are affected by their social situations (Festinger 1964); we are often completely wrong about the reasons for which we have made choices (Nisbett and Wilson 1977; Kornblith 1989; Gopnik 1993); and we overestimate the accuracy of people's memory for details of events they have experienced (Loftus 1979; Conway 1997). We seem to make many, and systematic, mistakes. Focus first on true beliefs. Human social competence entails that very often we anticipate one another's actions correctly. And it is not pushing this fact very much further to conclude that we are often accurate about other people's emotions (e.g. whether they are enraged or conciliatory) and about the information on which they are acting (e.g. whether someone has seen the letter which would bring about rage and confrontation). Accuracy about these things is consistent with error in other attributions that we make along the way to them. In particular, we may be right about what someone will do and wrong about why they will do it. The reasoning we attribute to someone in the course of predicting their action may contain thoughts the person will not think, and more profoundly may represent as causes of the person's action thoughts that are merely incidental. In fact, the psychological data on errors of attribution suggests that we are much less accurate about why we (and others) think what we do than about what we think. In the domain of mind, our explanations are even more suspect than our beliefs. (A potentially sceptical possibility is that our social competence relies less than we think on our beliefs, also, and

Page 14 of 18

Folk Psychology instead on specific social skills for whose success folk psychology narrowly construed takes undeserved credit, see Morton 2002: ch. 1; Bermúdez 2004.) These too‐brief considerations suggest that it is important here to separate questions of justification from questions of knowledge. One of the original motives for postulating folk psychology was to uncover a body of beliefs that would result from a reasonable inference from our observations of other's actions. That motive was in (p. 724) accordance with an ‘internalist’ epistemology, according to which beliefs are to be held to standards of evidence and reasonable inference. It does not now seem very promising. (The nearest contemporary account to such an ambition may be Gopnik and Meltzoff's account (1997) of the child as little scientist, going from one systematic explanation of the world and human nature to another.) But the possibilities of alternative ‘externalist’ approaches to epistemology are much clearer now than they were in the early days of folk psychology. On an externalist approach the central aim of beliefs is that they reliably represent the world, whether or not they result from acceptable reasoning. Knowledge becomes a more central concept than justification. (For the contrast between internalism and externalism in epistemology see Goldman 1986.) Information‐poor models of attribution, notably simulationist models, fit the externalist approach very well. There is little information in the model to constitute a justification of the conclusion arrived at, but that conclusion is very often right. For example, on a co‐cognitive picture of predicting someone's solution to a problem, as described by Heal, one does almost no attributing of any intermediate states to the target person. One simply has learned a routine of using one's own thinking as a guide to the other person's, and this leads one to attribute to the other a belief that, most of the time, is what in fact the person will be thinking. Epistemological considerations are not going to determine which account of folk psychology is true. And although information‐poor accounts have a natural affinity to externalist epistemology, many information‐rich accounts can be incorporated into both internalist and externalist approaches. The facts that make an epistemology of folk psychology sustainable or not are deeply connected, though, with questions about the integration of folk psychology into the rest of our scientific and other beliefs. There are two extreme possibilities. At one extreme there is the combination of folk psychology as explicit theory with a conviction of its basic incompatibility with the truth about the mind– brain. That is eliminative materialism, and leads us to expect either that large parts of folk psychology should be replaced with beliefs better grounded in scientific fact or that it should be treated as a useful fiction. Beliefs derived from folk psychology are unjustified and thus untenable. At the other extreme there is the combination of folk psychology as simulation with a conviction that it makes very few factual assertions about states of mind or the causes of behaviour. That view (we might call it ‘quietist compatibilism’) leads us to expect that folk psychology can coexist with almost any scientific view of mind, since it makes so few substantive claims. Folk‐psychological assertions are reliable and thus should be relied on. Neither position will find many defenders, since folk psychology makes more true assertions and is more essential to our social and intellectual lives than is claimed by a crude eliminativism, and makes more substantive claims about our states of mind and our reasons for action than is claimed by a simple quietism. The truth must Page 15 of 18

Folk Psychology lie somewhere between these extremes. And anywhere between these extremes we are going to be faced with a delicate mixture of true and false beliefs, very often with true beliefs derived from false beliefs, and very often with roughly reliable routes to conclusions about other people producing numbers of false beliefs as by‐products. Is this an acceptable situation? Is it one that we should or can (p. 725) try to change? If one is committed to an internalist epistemology one will find the situation uncomfortable, even if perhaps inevitable. For an externalist, though, it is a fairly typical example of the price we have to pay to get beliefs that serve reliably for particular purposes.

References Barkow, J., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (1992) (eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Development of Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Bermúdez, J. (2004), ‘The Domain of Folk Psychology’, in A. O'Hear (ed.), Mind and Persons (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 25–48. Braun, D. (1998), ‘Understanding Belief Reports’, Philosophical Review, 107: 555–96. Byrne, R. (1995), The Thinking Ape: The Evolutionary Origins of Intelligence (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Byrne, R., and Whiten, A. (1988) (eds.), Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intelligence in Monkeys, Apes, and Humans (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Churchland, P. (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Conway, M. (1997), Recovered Memories and False Memories (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Currie, G. (1995), ‘Imagination and Simulation: Aesthetics Meets Cognitive Science’, in M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Mental Simulation: Applications and Evaluations (Oxford: Blackwell), 151–69. Dennett, D. C. (1978), Brainstorms (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT). Festinger, L. (1964), Conflict, Decision and Dissonance (Palo Alto, Calif.: Stanford University Press). Goldman, A. (1986), Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1989), ‘Interpretation Psychologized’, Mind and Language, 4: 161–85.

Page 16 of 18

Folk Psychology Gopnik, A. (1993), ‘How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First‐person Knowledge of Intentionality’, Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 16: 1–14. Gopnik, A.A., and Meltzoff, A. (1997), Words, Thoughts, and Theories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Gordon, R. (1995), ‘Simulation Without Introspection, or Inference from Me to You’, in M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications (Oxford: Blackwell), 53–67. Heal, J. (1995), ‘How to Think About Thinking’, in M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications (Oxford: Blackwell), 33–52. —— (2000), ‘Other Minds, Rationality, and Analogy’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 74: 1–19. Kornblith, H. (1989), ‘Introspection and Misdirection’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67: 410–22. Kusch, M. (1999), Psychological Knowledge: A Social History and Philosophy (London: Routledge). Loftus, E. (1979), Eyewitness Testimony (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Morton, A. (1980), Frames of Mind: Constraints on the Common‐sense Conception of the Mental (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Morton, A. (2002), The Importance of Being Understood: Folk Psychology as Ethics (London: Routledge). (p. 726)

Nichols, S., and Stich, S. P. (2003), Mindreading (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Nisbett, R., and Ross, L. (1980), Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall). Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. (1977), ‘Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes’, Psychological Review, 84: 231–59. Perner, J. (1991), Understanding the Representational Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Povinelli, D., and Eddy, T. (1996), ‘What Young Chimpanzees Know About Seeing’, Monographs of the Society for the Study of Child Development, 61: 1–152. Putnam, H. (1960), ‘Minds and Machines’, in S. Hook (ed.), Dimensions of Mind (New York: New York University Press), 148–79. Quine, W. V. (1953), ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, in Quine, From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press), 20–46. Page 17 of 18

Folk Psychology Sellars, W. (1956), ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’, in H. Feigl and M. Scriven (eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press), 253–329. Sterelney, K. (2004), Thought in a Hostile World (Oxford: Blackwell). Strawson, P. (1959). Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Methuen). Wellman, H. (1990), The Child's Theory of Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Wimmer, H., and Perner, J. (1983), ‘Beliefs About Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children's Understanding of Deception’, Cognition, 13: 103–28.

Adam Morton

Adam Morton has a Canada Research Chair in Epistemology and Decision Theory at the University of Alberta. He is currently working on intellectual virtues of adaptation to one's own and human limitations, while writing on imagination and morality in a scattered way that he hopes eventually to bring together. He is the author of seven books, most recently On Evil (Routledge 2004) and The Importance of Being Understood (Routledge 2002).

Page 18 of 18

Other Minds

Oxford Handbooks Online Other Minds   Anita Avramides The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0043

Abstract and Keywords It is a serious question both in philosophy and the history of ideas just how our conception of mind has evolved. There is something of a consensus that Descartes introduced a particular conception and one, interestingly, that can be seen to take shape against the backdrop of an evolving scientific conception of the world. This scientific account of the world had no room for mind, and Descartes helped things along by hiving off the mind, so to speak, into its own realm. In Descartes's world-view mind and body are distinct, and distinct substances. Keywords: conception of mind, scientific conception, conception of the world, Descartes, mind and body, behaviour, mental antecedents

THE

topic is other minds. Shall we say, the problem is that of other minds? Yes and no. Yes,

if what is meant is that there is an issue here that raises philosophical perplexity and must be addressed. No, if what is meant is that there is a specific problem that can be formulated thus: How can I know that there are other minds? Recent study in the philosophy of mind has tended either to overlook or to attempt to downplay issues here. And where there is engagement with the issues, there is little agreement even about what the question is that ought to be occupying philosophers. This is reflected in two recent books devoted to the topic: Hyslop (1995) (see also Hyslop and Jackson 1972) and Avramides (2001).1 The author of the first, Alec Hyslop, claims that there is a problem about how we justify our belief that there are other minds, and argues that that justification is to be achieved through analogical reasoning. In proposing this solution Hyslop here is following a traditional line—albeit one that has fallen out of favour in recent decades. In the second book, I take the line that there is no epistemological problem concerning the existence of other minds, although there is a philosophical perplexity that must be addressed and there is much that needs to be said about why so many philosophers think that there is such a problem here. The philosophical perplexity

Page 1 of 17

Other Minds that arises concerns how we are to understand the concept of mind as one general enough to cover others as well as oneself.2 Questions about others have rarely been to the fore in philosophical discussion. Rather, comments on the topic of others, appended to discussions of other issues, (p. 728) are to be found from time to time—especially since the work of René Descartes. Discussions in more recent times have tended to take their cue from some remarks by John Stuart Mill. One could identify a Cartesian tradition within which problems about our knowledge of the mind of another arise. Mill is located in this tradition, as is Alec Hyslop. Pace Hyslop, the analogogical argument has been largely rejected in recent times in favour of a more contemporary scientific approach and an argument from best explanation (see, for example, Pargetter 1984). The argument from best explanation can be placed alongside the analogical argument as a reply to a question concerning our knowledge of the mind of another, which question arises within the Cartesian tradition with its very particular conception of mind. There have, however, been those who deny that the question to which these forms of argument purport to be a reply is a real question. These philosophers argue that this question only arises because a very particular conception of mind has been adopted. Furthermore, reasoning of the sort employed by these forms of argument can only issue in conjectures or hypotheses—albeit highly confirmed conjectures or very probable hypotheses. What it cannot do is issue in the sort of certainty that some think is requisite when it comes to our relations with others. Philosophers of this school would argue that the existence of others is foundational to all our reasoning and so cannot be the result of any reasoning. It may be thought overly tendentious to claim that there is no question about our knowledge of another mind. Surely questions about others arise all the time— philosophical discussions aside. In my daily life questions arise about whether another feels as much pain as I do, and in some cases I can question whether another feels any pain at all. We have all questioned from time to time whether the colour one sees is the same as that which others experience. And the medical profession is bedevilled by questions concerning the experiences of patients who are paralysed or in a coma. Children—and infants in particular—can leave us pondering about how their mental lives square with ours. Can questions here really be dismissed? Not at all. But we must be careful what question is being asked. Philosophers start with these questions but soon find themselves asking how I can know that there is any mind other than my own. Indeed, it is often argued that the very possibility of the former sorts of question brings in its wake the more radical question and, thereby, raises the possibility of solipsism—of my aloneness in the universe. If we want to forestall the question of solipsism, we need to do so in such a way that allows for questions of the less radical sort to arise. It is a serious question both in philosophy and the history of ideas just how our conception of mind has evolved. There is something of a consensus that Descartes introduced a particular conception and one, interestingly, that can be seen to take shape against the backdrop of an evolving scientific conception of the world. This scientific

Page 2 of 17

Other Minds account of the world had no room for mind, and Descartes helped things along by hiving off the mind, so to speak, into its own realm. In Descartes's world‐view mind and body are distinct, and distinct substances. As Gilbert Ryle was to comment four centuries later: When Galileo showed that his methods of scientific discovery were competent to provide a mechanical theory which should cover every occupant of space, Descartes found in himself (p. 729) two conflicting motives. As a man of scientific genius he could not but endorse the claims of mechanics, yet as a religious and moral man he could not accept, as Hobbes accepted, the discouraging rider to those claims, namely that human nature differs only in degree of complexity from clockwork. (1949: 20) Descartes's solution was to introduce, alongside physical sorts of things, mental sorts of things. Just as there is physical ‘stuff’, and physical events, states, processes, and the like, so Descartes posited that there is mental ‘stuff’, and mental processes, events, states, and the like. The latter consists of, inter alia, beliefs, desires, sensations, and they are taken to work just like physical processes, states, and events: they cause other processes, states, and events. Mental causation may seem in evidence; however, the understanding of this process has eluded intellectual grasp, and one of the outstanding problems of this Cartesian legacy is to understand this process of mental causation. In particular, we need to understand how ‘stuff’ so different as the mental and the physical can interact in so intimate a way that, as Descartes remarked, ‘I am not merely present in my body as a sailor is present in a ship’ (1641/1984: 56).3 There is a particular closeness here, and this needs to be reflected in our understanding of mind in relation to body.

Once the mind and body have been separated in this Cartesian way, questions arise not just concerning the mind's relation to body, but also concerning the mind's relation to other minds. Descartes's conception of mind and world is such as to raise the radical epistemological questions: ‘How do I know that the world of bodies external to my mind exists?’ and ‘How do I know that there are any minds other than my own?’.4 The second of these questions is sometimes masked by the fact that Descartes—like many other philosophers—is prone to talk of our knowledge of the external world. Cursory inspection of his writings reveals, however, that he is not entitled to the plural pronoun here. What is most significant is the fact that throughout his Meditations, for example, Descartes writes entirely from the first‐person perspective. And the Archimedean point from which he attempts to draw the whole world is captured in the proposition I am; I exist. In so far as there is a world of bodies or minds external to Descartes's own, this is something that requires argument. Unlike his observation about the relation of mind to body, what Descartes failed to note is that there is also a particular sort of closeness involved in the relation of one mind to another. This Cartesian conception and its repercussions for our knowledge of another mind are nicely captured by Augustine, a philosopher who, in his thinking about mind, is often said to have ‘anticipated’ Descartes. Augustine writes:

Page 3 of 17

Other Minds ‘Know thyself’ is not said to the mind as ‘Know the cherubim and seraphim’; for they are absent, and we believe concerning them, according to that belief they are declared to be certain celestial powers. Nor again as it is said, ‘Know the will of that man’, for it is not within (p. 730) our reach to perceive at all, either by sense or understanding, unless by corporeal signs set forth (1974: 10, 9, 12, p. 140) The problem, as Augustine sees it, is that we cannot perceive another's will. And Augustine explains that the case of another is very different from one's own. He writes:

But when it is said to the mind ‘Know thyself’; then it knows itself by the very act by which it understands the word ‘thyself’; and this for no reason than that it is present to itself. (1974: 10, 9, 12, p. 140) This division between what is possible in one's own case and what is not possible in the case of another is repeated throughout the history of philosophy.5

The problem seems clear. All these philosophers, like Descartes, begin with themselves, with the first person. They find that there is one thing that is known intuitively and, thus, with certainty. This is either myself, or my existence. And what is then observed, quite correctly, is that there cannot be a similar relation to another. I cannot know another immediately and intuitively; I cannot know another in this way. Nor can I perceive the mind of another. When it comes to knowing about the mind of another there is a question to be answered, and it is not at all clear how to go about answering it. And the question is a radical sceptical one. A positive reply to this question is required as a bulwark against solipsism. Sometimes it is acknowledged that a reply to this radical question will still leave us with questions concerning the particular contours of this other mind: just what the other is thinking and feeling (call this ‘weak scepticism’). Sometimes, however, it is allowed that the argument that justifies our belief in the existence of another mind justifies, as well, our belief that that mind is (roughly) like our own. Very occasionally in the history of the topic one finds the weak sceptical question raised but not the more radical one. An example of this can be found in the work of one of Descartes's immediate successors, Nicolas Malebranche. Unlike Descartes, Malebranche clearly separates out three kinds of knowledge: knowledge of body, of one's own mind, and of other minds. And concerning our knowledge of another mind—which he takes it that we know about ‘by conjecture’—Malebranche makes an important distinction between our knowledge of another's sensations and of his thoughts (see esp. 1674/1997: bk. III, pt. ii, ch. 7, sect. V, p. 239). In connection with both sensations and thoughts, however, the conjecture that Malebranche has in mind seems clearly to do with what the other is feeling and thinking. Malebranche is not asking the radical sceptical, ‘How do I know that another mind exists?’. This is especially notable as the parallel question concerning the existence of bodies is clearly identified by Malebranche (see esp. 1674/1997: (p. 731) bk. III, pt. ii). According to Charles McCracken, Malebranche acknowledges that there is a crucial difference between our knowledge of the existence of bodies and our knowledge of the Page 4 of 17

Other Minds existence of minds: while it may be possible to deny the former, it is not possible to deny this possibility. McCracken suggests that the latter follows from the fact that Malebranche holds that in the case of minds or souls I am assured of their existence from consideration of the ‘whole moral order’ (1983: 81). Malebranche is astute in many of his observations here, but I take his greatest insight to be an understanding of the very depth and significance of our relation to others. Despite it being possible—indeed, necessary— to raise questions about our knowledge of the nature of another mind, it is difficult to imagine questioning the existence of other minds. With this observation Malebranche acknowledges something that (it is arguable that) Descartes missed: my relations to others are such that to question them—to question the existence of others—may not be a real possibility. Nevertheless, solipsism has been taken by many philosophers to be a real possibility. Arguments such as the one from analogy or best explanation are designed to show that, despite this possibility, it is not likely actually to be the case. It does, however, remain possible that I am alone in the universe. I would venture that the argument from analogy is the most natural way to argue here. After all, that there are minds—is any mind—has something to do with behaviour, and we do tend to think about others on the model of ourselves. The argument from analogy is thought to lurk in many texts, stretching right back in the history of the subject. It has been attributed to philosophers such as St Augustine, Descartes, Locke, and Berkeley—despite the fact that all the texts in all these cases arguably have alternative readings.6 The fact that the argument has been so widely attributed testifies, I believe, to its hold over much philosophical thinking about the mind. The argument proceeds as follows: (i) I know that I have a mind; (ii) I observe that my mind is the antecedent condition for my behaviour; (iii) I observe behaviour in the bodies of others similar to that which I know in my own case to be the result of mental antecedents; I conclude, by analogy, that this behaviour in others is the result of the existence of other minds.7 I mentioned the argument from analogy earlier, as both a traditional response and one lately adopted by at least one prominent contemporary writer on the subject. What is not clear is whether this argument can address the philosophical question of solipsism or deal with radical sceptical issues. Arguments from analogy are not only proposed in connection with the mind; they are used in the sciences. In an early paper Hyslop gives the following example of the use of analogy in science: Helium has a characteristic spectrum, the nature of which was determined by experiments carried out on earth. It was then observed that light from the sun displayed this spectrum, and it was inferred that helium was present on the sun (Hyslop and Jackson 1972: 169). Thomas Reid, in the mid‐eighteenth century, discussed the use of analogy in the study of the planets—as well as medicine (p. 732) and politics. This use he took to be unobjectionable, but Reid insisted on a contrast between our thinking about the planets and our thinking about the mind. Reid's point is that in the case of mind reasoning by analogy (along with what he called hypothesis and conjecture) yields unstable and insecure foundations for knowledge (1785/1969: vol. I, ch. iii, p. 41).

Page 5 of 17

Other Minds According to Reid, stability and security are the result of first principles, on which more below. Where Hyslop and others see a parallel between our thinking concerning scientific matters and our thinking concerning others, Reid notes an important difference. Reid's objection to employing analogy when the subject is mind is insightful. It is echoed in a comment by F. H. Bradley, who is reported to have held that we don't want inferred friends who are mere hypotheses to explain physical phenomena (see Urmson 1982: 61).8 Although this objection has sometimes been raised in more recent times to the argument from analogy, philosophers tend to emphasize other objections. One of these other objections also draws on a disanalogy with the use of the argument in the sciences: it is pointed out that in the case of another mind but not in the sciences the conclusion drawn is logically uncheckable. A second objection is that in the case of mind but not in the sciences the argument proceeds from one case alone. Hyslop discusses, and attempts a defence against, these two objections in some depth. There is also a third objection, that arises out of the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein. According to this objection the argument from analogy goes wrong not in the way it derives its conclusion but in the formulation of its very first premise: I know that I have a mind. The problems here are various and complex. One way to formulate them is due to Norman Malcolm (1966) and draws on considerations from Wittgenstein's private‐language argument. Another is due to P. F. Strawson and draws on considerations concerning our concept of mind (see esp. Strawson 1959). Around the mid‐twentieth century there was a heightened interest in the problem of other minds, and a considerable number of those writing on the topic thought that the Wittgensteinian considerations of the third objection pretty much demolished the argument from analogy.9 In any case, for those who did not favour this objection, the other two objections were considered sufficient for the argument to lose favour.10 Those who object to the argument from analogy on the grounds that our model should not be that of the physical sciences will be even less impressed by the argument that has come to replace it in many contemporary circles: the argument from best explanation. It is fair to say that at the start of the twenty‐first century this argument is either explicitly or implicitly held by the majority of philosophers. The argument was championed in an early paper by C. S. Chihara and J. A. Fodor (1966). Chihara and Fodor's paper was designed to diminish the impact that Wittgenstein's writing was taken to have had on the problem of other minds, while at the same time to promote another—more scientific— approach to this problem. Chihara and (p. 733) Fodor claim that Wittgenstein was right to point out that we learn conceptual connections when we learn a language. However, where they saw Wittgenstein as arguing that those connections are between words like ‘pain’ and characteristic patterns of behaviour, they proposed that the real conceptual connection is between our concept of one mental state and that of a wide variety of other mental states. Chihara and Fodor argue against (their understanding of) Wittgenstein's post‐Tractatus writings on philosophical psychology—against, that is, what they label Wittgenstein's ‘logical behaviourism’ and his ‘operationalist’ approach to meaning.11 Chihara and Fodor take as their starting point the Wittgensteinian idea that the connection between, say, pain and pain behaviour is ‘criterial’. The notion of a criterion is contrasted by Wittgenstein with that of a symptom (see esp. 1958: 24–5); the introduction Page 6 of 17

Other Minds of this contrast marks one of Wittgenstein's distinctive contributions to the philosophy of psychology. The understanding of this contrast has bedevilled many a philosopher. Chihara and Fodor understand that the notion of a criterion lies at the heart of Wittgenstein's ‘logical behaviourism’, and they characterize the distinction between a criterion and a symptom thus: ‘[I]f we are justified in claiming that one can tell, recognize, see, or determine that ‘Y’ applies on the basis of the presence of X, then either X is a criterion of Y or observations have shown that X is correlated with Y’ (1966: 409). They then challenge this Wittgensteinian idea by arguing that it overlooks the possibility that we determine that ‘Y’ applies by appeal neither to criteria nor to observed correlations. In particular, it overlooks the possibility that justification of existential statements in some cases ‘depend[s] … on appeals to the simplicity, plausibility, and predictive adequacy of an explanatory system as a whole’ (1966: 411). In response to the Wittgensteinian thought that in learning a language we learn complex criterial connections between terms such as ‘pain’ and behaviour, Chihara and Fodor point out that what we learn is a complex web of interrelated mental concepts that we use to explain the behaviour of others. They write: It is to such a conceptual system that we appeal when we attempt to explain someone's behaviour by reference to his motives, intentions, beliefs, desires, or sensations. In other words, in learning the language, we develop a number of intricately interrelated ‘mental concepts’ which we use in dealing with, coming to terms with, understanding, explaining, interpreting, etc., the behaviour of other human beings (as well as our own). (1966: 413)

Page 7 of 17

Other Minds Instead of taking behaviour as criterial of pain, Chihara and Fodor hold that the behaviour on the basis of which mental predicates are applied might properly be thought of as supplying evidence for the existence of the mental processes we postulate. In this respect behaviour should be thought of as analogous to the Wilson cloud‐chamber track on the basis of which we detect the presence and motion of charged (p. 734) particles, and our interrelated mental concepts should be thought of as analogous to the physical theory in which the properties of these particles are formulated. On this way of looking at things, the belief that other people feel pain ‘provides the only plausible explanation of the facts I know about the way that they behave in and vis à vis the sorts of situations I find painful’ (1966: 414). Chihara and Fodor insist that this argument is not committed to the idea that the child learns what pain is from his or her own case. They suggest that it would be possible for a child to learn the concept of pain before—or even in the absence of—experiencing pain. What the child would have learned is the complex web of conceptual connections including the concept of pain that goes to understanding and explaining another's behaviour. Furthermore, Chihara and Fodor follow Chomsky and suggest that the system of mental concepts that the child comes to have may not require explicit teaching or training in the use of language but may develop quite naturally in the child in response to very little training. In other words, it may be innate. They point out that this way of looking at things has the interesting result that there is no asymmetry in the use of mental predicates. Whether I use the predicate to apply to myself or to another, I am applying a predicate that picks out a state or process that interacts with other mental states and explains a certain way of behaving.

Chihara and Fodor offer a powerful and radical challenge to an equally powerful and radical idea that can be found in Wittgenstein's post‐Tractatus writing on the philosophy of psychology. As arguments from best explanation have come in the sciences to replace arguments by analogy, it is not surprising that this is the argument that has come to find favour in the philosophy of mind. It is thought that this new argument avoids some of the objections that were considered to have sunk the earlier argument from analogy. In particular, it is claimed that this argument does not rely on extension from one's own case. (Although this in itself raises the equally difficult issue of whether such an argument can be thought to be true to the first‐person perspective.12) What is not clear is that the argument from best explanation best addresses the issues that Wittgenstein was concerned to address. The main part of my complaint against Chihara and Fodor (as well as Fodor in some of his subsequent, solo, discussions of these issues) is that the approach is wholly scientific. This is bound to yield difficulties when the approach is taken with a text that professes a fundamental distinction between science and philosophy. The difficulties affect the interpretation of Wittgenstein that one finds in Chihara and Fodor's work, as well as the alternative proposal for our understanding of mind that we find there. Of course, Chihara and Fodor hope to break down this distinction. I am not sure the problem doesn't begin with Chihara and Fodor's discussion of a criterion. Like so many others, Chihara and Fodor cannot comprehend what Wittgenstein is looking for here, and they are mesmerized by the undeniable fact that one can have, for example, pain behaviour in the absence of pain and vice versa. They (p. 735) cannot see any way to acknowledge this fact without running away with the point and they end up having to hold that one can make sense of the idea of pain in the absence of any Page 8 of 17

Other Minds behavioural manifestation. The problem with saying this is that it completely divorces the idea of pain—or, more generally, a mental phenomenon—from activity, and it allows for the possibility of our aloneness in the universe. And the two go together. Chihara and Fodor, however, divorce the two: their account of mental activity—of the mind as the activating cause of behaviour—leaves in place the question of our aloneness in the universe. The only answer they can give to this question is that it is highly improbable that we are alone. Sceptical questions are not to everyone's taste, but they do lie at the heart of many important philosophical issues. They are clearly not to Fodor's taste (see, for example, Fodor 1994: 292), but they did concern Wittgenstein. In one of the very few places where Fodor does address the sceptic he writes that what he is committed to is ‘minimal scepticism’. Fodor says that we can distinguish logical from moral certainty, and that it is the latter—not the former—that can be achieved concerning another's (state of) mind (1968: 60–3).13 What Fodor is mainly concerned to distance himself from is the idea that we can achieve logical certainty concerning another. In response to the sceptical question of whether we can know that there are other minds or whether we have a reason to suppose that another has a mind, Fodor writes: ‘it would be pertinent to inquire into his use of know’, or ‘to inquire into what his concept is of “having a reason” ’ (1968: 61). What Fodor does not do here is explain what is his use of ‘know’. One thing that is clear is that Fodor's use of ‘know’ is such that one can be said to know even where there is the possibility of radical scepticism concerning the mind of another. Solipsism may be ‘absurd’, but it is possible given Fodor's concept of mind (1968: 64–6). Fodor and Chihara emphasize that aspect of Wittgenstein's notion of a criterion involved in telling (recognizing, seeing) that another is in pain on the basis of the presence of a certain behaviour. And Fodor rightly understands that Wittgenstein is concerned with a kind of certainty concerning other minds—a kind of certainty that does not allow for any (logical) distance between one mind and another. This is the certainty—or better, the assurance— one person has vis‐à‐vis another when he runs to help when there has been a serious accident. There are circumstances in which doubt is out of place. And where doubt is out of place so is the radical sceptical question. This is not just a matter of pragmatics. (We should recall that Fodor was an early champion of Grice against Wittgenstein here.) It is not just what we would say, but what this tells us about what we are talking about. Fodor —and so many philosophers working in philosophy of mind today—take it that when we talk about mind we are talking about something that acts as the characteristic cause of the behaviour it is invoked to explain. On this conception of mind, all the observable behaviour could be present while the mind is absent. Of course, this is highly unlikely (or God most probably did not arrange things in this way), but it is not impossible—not impossible given the sort of thing the mind is. If, however, we take behaviour in relation to the world and (p. 736) to others as our starting point, this could not be the case. Where Fodor emphasizes what he takes to be Wittgenstein's insistence on a logical connection between mind and behaviour, I would emphasize a conception of mind which is such that it makes no sense to speak of mind in the absence of such behaviour. There is nothing to tie mind to behaviour, and hence one mind to another, on Fodor's way of thinking about Page 9 of 17

Other Minds the mind. It may seem absurd to deny that there are other minds, but Fodor offers no understanding of why this is the case (1968).14 What we do know is that it is possible— logically possible for it to be the case that God made a world that consists of one mind only. But appeal to God is unnecessary. The starting point is not God, but one mind in relation to another and the world.15 The certainty this alternative starting point gives us is not best expressed as a certainty that allows for no error. (After all, no one can deny that there may be instances of behaviour that are mere behaviour, lacking mind.) The certainty at issue here is best thought of as a surefootedness vis‐à‐vis others. It is my behaviour towards another in certain circumstances that leaves no room for doubt—no room for the sceptic to ask his questions. It is not enough to say I have very good reason to believe that another is in pain. It is not enough to argue that my theory that he is in pain is the simplest, most plausible, and predictively adequate explanation of his behaviour. This leaves us at best with a well‐confirmed hypothesis that the other is in pain. On this picture of things my surefootedness towards others is merely a matter of the way I am—it tells us nothing about the deep absurdity of the radical sceptical question that purports to show that this surefootedness could be radically in error. It is not a matter of knowing that I am not alone in the universe, it is not a matter of having a good reason to think that I am not alone. Reid recognized this. Reid writes about the child even before its first birthday who ‘clings to its nurse in danger, enters into her grief and joy, is happy in her soothing caresses, and unhappy in her displeasure’ (1785/1969: essay I, ch. iii, sect. 41, pp. 633– 4). There is no room for doubt. And this is not to say that the child knows that its nurse is another mind. As Reid insists, that there are minds in our fellow creatures is a first principle, and one that must be in place before we even can begin to talk about knowing. First principles leave no room for the sceptic. Like Wittgenstein after him, Reid directed much of his intellectual energy to showing the error of scepticism. If one understands the operation of first principles, one will understand the closeness of our relations to others. The existence of another mind is not the result of arguing by analogy and hypothesis; it is a matter of first principles. Reid is clear that it is possible to be wrong about first principles, but he writes that when first principles are brought into dispute ‘they require to be handled in a way peculiar to themselves’ (1785/1969: essay I, ch. ii, p. 33). Reid is here (p. 737) recognizing the important and unique part played by such principles as that ‘there is life and intelligence in our fellow men with whom we converse’. And he understands that there is something fundamentally misguided about reasoning by analogy or hypothesis to the existence of this fellow intelligence. Despite his insights into the place of first principles, however, Reid's work does not go far enough in its understanding of the sceptic's mistake. What Reid fully understood was the kind of certainty—the kind of surefootedness—that one intelligence has vis‐à‐vis another. Furthermore, he understood that one's conviction of the existence of other intelligent beings is ‘absolutely necessary’ and fundamental to all reasoning and all knowledge (1785/1969: essay I, ch. iii, 41, p. 635; see Malebranche 1674/1997). But Reid did not link up this necessity with our concept of mind. It was Wittgenstein who tried to show how these observations about our relationship to others have repercussions for how we should Page 10 of 17

Other Minds understand this concept. Until this conceptual work is done, it is arguable that the sceptic cannot be fully silenced. The insistence on first principles can look like a dogmatic assertion of common sense in the face of philosophical objection. It is only when we take seriously the place of behaviour in our concept of mind that we can begin to understand that which we find so hard to deny (the importance of our relations to others). Chihara and Fodor aim to expose the errors of what they called ‘logical behaviourism’. They insist that mind is only contingently related to behaviour. Theirs is a concept of mind that leads to insecurity in our relations to others. It is the fundamental nature of our relations to others that Chihara and Fodor fail to appreciate. And their failure to appreciate this has led them to believe that the methods of science and theory are appropriate when it comes to our knowledge of other minds. This is where one ends up if one naturalizes an essentially Cartesian conception of mind. Perhaps the integration of mind and world requires that we revise our very conception of mind. When we do this, the question that lies at the heart of so much thinking about other minds—‘How do I know that other minds exist?’—fades away. It is not a question of knowledge. It is a matter of understanding aright our relationship to others. It is a matter of understanding that others must be taken to be in place before questions of knowledge can arise. Collectively we can ask questions about the far‐off planets, about subatomic particles, and the like. But without this community of minds these questions cannot arise. The real question concerning others is not how I know that they exist; it is, ‘What is my conception of mind such that I can understand how it can include myself as well as others?’. The conception of mind that I am rejecting is at the heart of several philosophical problems. The problem of solipsism may be the most obvious, but there is an ancillary problem which is also pressing. As I have explained, discussion often concentrates, misguidedly, on the epistemological problem of other minds. What is often overlooked is the conceptual difficulty that one gets into if one begins with a conception of mind that leaves room for radical scepticism. The difficulty is in comprehending both the generality and unity of our concept of mind.16 On the Cartesian (p. 738) conception of mind we come by our concept as the result of some experience in our own case. It is because we come by our concept in this way that epistemological questions concerning others are so pressing. But antecedent to these questions is another: How do I come by my concept of another mind? The concept I have acquired through experience of things in my own case is a concept that, by its very nature, cannot yet apply to another. Philosophers have taken this to be the problem to which Wittgenstein is referring when he writes in Philosophical Investigations 302: If one has to imagine someone else's pain on the model of one's own, this is none too easy a thing to do: for I have to imagine pain which I do not feel on the model of pain which I do feel.

Page 11 of 17

Other Minds Colin McGinn (1984) has suggested that things are ‘none too easy’ here because the concept gained through experience of things in one's own case bears the ‘inexpungible stamp’ of the first‐person mode of presentation by which one acquires that concept. The problem is that it is not at all clear how we are to move from such a concept to one that includes others. This is the problem of generality. The problem of unity serves to exacerbate the problem of generality, and is inherent in that problem. The problem here is that we need to understand the generality of the concept in such a way as to incorporate others while at the same time maintaining that inexpungible stamp of the first person. It is ‘none too easy’ to see how this can be done. Part of the work that needs to be done here is to explore how best to understand what McGinn has characterized as the inexpungible stamp of the first person.

The conception of mind that I am urging be rejected can be glimpsed in the thought— expressed so well in the writings of St Augustine (see above)—that the mind of another cannot be perceived. The naturalness of this thought masks a difficulty: what would it be to perceive another mind? It is not just that another's mind is over there, so to speak, inside another's body. It is not just that the behaviour I observe blocks my view of the other's mind. (If only I could peer around it and perceive the other's mind.)17 The problem lies in trying to comprehend what it is we would be perceiving. As is so often observed, we do not perceive our own mind. How we are to understand this is not easy to comprehend, but philosophers have been prone to talk of intuition, immediate knowledge (again, see above). Yet when it comes to another, we gesture at perception. Perhaps we should employ the light hand of analogy here and conclude that as we do not perceive our own mind we should not think of perception in connection with the mind of another. But if not perception, what? This question bedevils us. Whatever the thinking concerning the mind of another, many philosophers have understood that in our own case mind is a matter of agency. Here we may remind ourselves of some things Berkeley has written. Berkeley distinguishes between ideas and spirits: ‘things so wholly different, that when we say, they exist, they are known, or the like, these words must not be thought to signify anything common to both natures’ (1710/1975a: 142). And Berkeley cites as the reason for this difference the fact that ideas are passive while (p. 739) spirit is active. This activity that is so evident in connection with mind is the key to our understanding its nature. It is a real question how we are to understand something whose nature is essentially active. I am not sure it is sufficient to say that it is the sort of thing that can serve as the cause of behaviour. These thoughts, in their turn, put pressure on the idea of causation as the correct way to understand the relation of mind to behaviour. This is a topic too large to engage in now. It is enough that we begin to appreciate the pressures here, and the reasons for them. Another large topic that I do want briefly to touch on is the asymmetry that has been taken to exist in connection with the way mental predicates apply to oneself and to others, which several philosophers have highlighted. Alex Hyslop, for example, begins his book with the statement that the problem of other minds is generated by an asymmetry in respect of knowledge (1995: 6). Davidson notes that self‐knowledge is unmediated while knowledge of others is mediated by behaviour. Chihara and Fodor have suggested that it may be thought to be a virtue of their approach that there is no asymmetry here: mental predicates apply in both cases as the cause of behaviour. It is arguable, however, that Page 12 of 17

Other Minds Chihara and Fodor seek to abolish the wrong problem. It seems hard to deny that there is some sort of asymmetry here. But it is an interesting question just what the asymmetry here amounts to. Pace Hyslop (and many others) I do not think the asymmetry is one of knowledge. (This would follow from my views about the foundational nature of my relations to others.) There is, however, an asymmetry in the use of mental predicates, in connection with myself and with others. Not only do I not observe my behaviour when I speak of my pain, but I don't even think of it. My pain is, in some sense, more immediate than that, and in connection with this we insist that the questions that can arise here are severely circumscribed. And no matter how close I am to another, questions continue to arise over just what she is thinking and feeling. (This is the weak scepticism I referred to above. It now arises divorced from the question of a more radical scepticism.) It is these sorts of observations that are reflected in the claim that there is an asymmetry of knowledge here. But we may, perhaps, reflect on these observations in a different way. Concerning the asymmetry he observed in connection with the mind, Wittgenstein once wrote: My words and actions interest me in a completely different way than they do someone else. (1998: 10e) Wittgenstein seems here to be offering us another way of thinking about the asymmetry we observe, and one in keeping with the idea that our attitude here is not cognitive. An asymmetry lies at the heart of our use of mental terms, and it is something we need to understand. At the same time we also need to understand how our concept of mind is such that it can apply to others as well as oneself. As I see it, understanding these things is part and parcel of responding to Descartes's challenge: how to understand the peculiar closeness of mind and body—a closeness that is echoed in a closeness that Descartes missed: the closeness of myself to others.

References Augustine (1974), ‘De Trinitate’, in P. Schaff (ed.), Nicene and Post‐Nicene Fathers of the Christian Church, iii (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Erdmans). Avramides, A. (2001), Other Minds (London: Routledge). Berkeley, G. (1710/1975a), ‘A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge’, in The Philosophical Works, ed. M. R. Ayers (London: Dent), 61–129. —— (1713/1975b), ‘Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous’, in The Philosophical Works, ed. M. R. Ayers (London: Dent), 129–209. Bilgrami, A. (1992), ‘Other Minds’, in J. Dancy and E. Sosa (eds.), A Companion to Epistemology (Oxford: Blackwell), 317–23.

Page 13 of 17

Other Minds Chihara, C. S., and Fodor, J. A. (1966), ‘Operationalism and Ordinary Language: A Critique of Wittgenstein’, in G. Pitcher (ed.), Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations (London: Macmillan), 384–419. Davidson, D. (1991), ‘Three Varieties of Knowledge’, in P. Griffiths (ed.), A. J. Ayer Memorial Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 153–66. Descartes, R. (1641/1984), ‘Meditations on First Philosophy’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ii, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–62. Fodor, J. A. (1968), Psychological Explanation: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Psychology (New York: Random House). —— (1994), ‘Jerry A. Fodor’, in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), 292–300. Hyslop, A. (1995), Other Minds (Dordrecht: Kluwer). Hyslop, A., and Jackson, F. C. (1972), ‘The Analogical Inference to Other Minds’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 9: 168–76. McCracken, C. J. (1983), Malebranche and British Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon). McGinn, C. (1984), ‘What is the Problem of Other Minds?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 58: 119–37. Malcolm, N. (1966), ‘Knowledge of Other Minds’, in G. Pitcher (ed.), Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations (London: Macmillan), 371–83. Malebranche, N. (1674/1997), The Search after Truth, trans. and ed. T. M. Lennon and P. J. Olscamp (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Mill, J. S. (1872), An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, 4th edn. (London: Longman, Green, Reader, & Dyer). Nagel, T. (1986), The View From Nowhere (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Pargetter, R. (1984), ‘The Scientific Inference to Other Minds’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62: 158–63. Reid, T. (1785/1969), Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, introd. B. A. Brody (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (Harmondsworth: Penguin). Strawson, P. (1959), Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Methuen). Urmson, J. (1982), Berkeley (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Page 14 of 17

Other Minds Wittgenstein, L. (1958), The Blue and Brown Books (New York: Harper). —— (1998), The Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology: The Inner and the Outer, ii, trans. C. G. Luckhardt and M. A. E. Ane, ed. G. H. von Wright and H. Nyman (Oxford: Blackwell).

Notes: (1) These are the only books to be devoted to this topic since the 1960s. (2) See Bilgrami (1992), who introduces the problem as a conceptual, and not an epistemological, one. In The View from Nowhere Thomas Nagel remarked: ‘The interesting problem of other minds is not the epistemological problem, how I can know that other people are not zombies. It is the conceptual problem, how I can understand the attribution of mental states to others’ (1986: 19–20). For a detailed discussion of Nagel here see Avramides (2001: ch. 9). (3) Note that simply adopting materialism is no help here—not until such a move can offer an acceptable explanation of the distinctive character of mind. (4) Donald Davidson has written: ‘If there is a logical or epistemic barrier between the mind and nature, it not only prevents us from seeing out; it also prevents a view from the outside in’ (1991: 154). (5) See, for example, George Berkeley, who writes concerning others: ‘A human spirit or person is not perceived by sense, as not being an idea; … Hence it is plain, we do not see a man—if by man is meant that which lives, moves, perceives, and thinks as we do’ (1710/1975a: 148). Concerning oneself Berkeley writes: ‘I know what I mean by the terms I and myself … and I know this immediately, or intuitively, though I do not perceive it as I perceive a triangle, a colour, or a sound’ (1713/1975b: 232). (6) See Avramides (2001) for a discussion of alternative readings. (7) I base this formulation of the argument on a passage from the writings of John Stuart Mill (1872: 243–4). (8) Urmson claims that Bradley made this claim in response to the argument from analogy, although he does not cite the reference. (9) Bilgrami (1992) ignores altogether the first two of these further objections to the argument from analogy and concentrates on variations of the third, Wittgensteinian, objection. (10) Hence the need for a book like Hyslop's by the 1990s.

Page 15 of 17

Other Minds (11) Thus, they write: ‘To hold that the sceptical premiss is false is ipso facto to commit oneself to some version of logical behaviourism where by ‘logical behaviourism’ we mean the doctrine that there are logical or conceptual relations of the sort denied by the sceptical premiss'; and, ‘It is clear that Wittgenstein thought that analysing the meaning of a word involves exhibiting the role or use of the word in the various language‐games in which it occurs … This notion of analysis leads rather naturally to an operationalistic view of the meaning of certain sorts of predicates’ (1966: 387, 388). (12) A difficulty, curiously enough, that many philosophers are inclined to raise as a fairly decisive objection in connection with what they see as Wittgenstein's ‘behaviourism’. It is interesting to note that this difficulty may also arise in connection with Chihara and Fodor's work. (13) Descartes, too, writes of ‘moral certainty’, which he describes as ‘sufficient … for application to ordinary life’ (1641/1984: 289–90). (14) To be fair, Fodor correctly insists that there is no direct line from ‘S is certain’ or ‘The denial of S is absurd’ to ‘S is necessary’ or ‘S is true a priori’. My complaint is that Fodor's examples, which allow for alternative understandings of ‘the denial of S is absurd’ don't cut very deep. They certainly do not help us to understand the sort of absurdity involved in denying the existence of others. (15) The work of Descartes and Davidson illustrates these two positions: where Descartes relies on God to guarantee our knowledge of the external world, Davidson posits a triangle consisting of one's own mind, another mind and the world (see esp. Descartes 1641/1984; Davidson 1991). (16) For a detailed of discussion of these issues see Avramides (2001: pt. 3). (17) See n. 4 above.

Anita Avramides

Anita Avramides is Fellow and Tutor, St. Hilda's College, University of Oxford. Cowley Place, Oxford, OX4 1DY.

Page 16 of 17

Introspection

Oxford Handbooks Online Introspection   Cynthia Macdonald The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0044

Abstract and Keywords ‘Introspection’ is a term used by philosophers to refer to a special method or means by which one comes to know certain of one's own mental states; specifically, one's current conscious states. It derives from the Latin ‘spicere’, meaning ‘look’, and ‘intra’, meaning ‘within’; introspection is a process of looking inward. Introspectionist accounts of selfknowledge fall within the broader domain of theories of self-knowledge, understood as views about the nature of and basis for one's knowledge of one's own mental states, including one's beliefs, desires, conscious thinkings, and sensations. Theories of selfknowledge are motivated by the apparent need to account for a number of striking features of at least some such knowledge, which ordinary empirical knowledge, including knowledge of the mental states of others, is typically thought to lack. Keywords: introspection, mental states, conscious states, self-knowledge, conscious thinkings, sensations

Page 1 of 30

Introspection IT is a bleak winter day. I am gazing out of the window as I sit at my desk. A friend looks over and asks me what I am thinking. I reply: ‘I'm thinking that a holiday in the sun would be nice’. This avowal seems to be a report on a current mental state of mine, of which I am aware. I am not only thinking that a holiday in the sun would be nice, but know what I am thinking, and I seem to know it in a way that my friend does not. How do I know what I am currently thinking? ‘Introspection’ is a term used by philosophers to refer to a special method or means by which one comes to know certain of one's own mental states; specifically, one's current conscious states. It derives from the Latin ‘spicere’, meaning ‘look’, and ‘intra’, meaning ‘within’; introspection is a process of looking inward.1 Introspectionist accounts of self‐ knowledge fall within the broader domain of theories of self‐knowledge, understood as views about the nature of and basis for one's knowledge of one's own mental states, including one's beliefs, desires, conscious thinkings, and sensations.2 Theories of self‐ knowledge are motivated by the apparent need to account for a number of striking features of at least some such knowledge, which ordinary empirical knowledge, including knowledge of the mental states of others, is typically thought to lack. Knowledge of certain of one's mental states is said to be epistemically direct or immediate in some sense (for example, in being non‐inferential and/or non‐evidence‐based), and so privileged and/or authoritative, perhaps in being incorrigible, or infallible, or transparent to oneself (or all three of these). Introspectionist theories attempt to account for some, (p. 742) or all, of these features by reference to a special method by which this knowledge is obtained. There is considerable disagreement, however, amongst those working in the area of self‐ knowledge—even amongst introspectionists, as we shall see—whether such knowledge possesses the features just mentioned, and if so, to what extent. Partly by way of clearing the ground for discussion of the introspectionist position, therefore, I begin, in Section 43.1 below, by characterizing two classical but radically opposed positions on self‐ knowledge, one broadly Cartesian (Descartes 1641/1984) and the other Rylean (Ryle 1949). Whereas the Cartesian position takes certain self‐knowledge to be distinctive in the ways described above, the Rylean one denies that self‐knowledge is distinctive in any way at all. I set out some reasons that might be adduced against the Rylean position, delaying discussion of the Cartesian one until Section 43.3. In Section 43.2 I discuss some examples of ‘deflationary’ positions on self‐knowledge, ones that take some such knowledge to be distinctive in at least some of the ways mentioned above (specifically, in being authoritative) but reject the view that there is a special method or way by which one obtains such knowledge. I give some reasons why these positions might be thought to be unsatisfactory. Finally, in Section 43.3 I revisit the Cartesian position along with other introspectionist positions distinguishable from it, and conclude by recommending my own position over the others. Since the case for an introspectionist position is intuitively stronger for knowledge of one's own sensations than for knowledge of one's own propositional attitudes, even when

Page 2 of 30

Introspection these are currently consciously undergone, my focus in what follows will be, by and large, on how introspectionist accounts of self‐knowledge of current conscious propositional attitudes fare.

43.1 Two Classical Positions Philosophical accounts of self‐knowledge are concerned with a wide variety of mental states, which can be loosely grouped under two main sorts: propositional attitudes and sensations (McGinn 1982). Propositional attitudes are states such as those of believing, desiring, or thinking that p, for some propositional content p, which consist in a subject's bearing an attitudinal relation to a propositional content (as does, for example, my belief that water is transparent). Sensations are states such as those of being in pain, having a reddish visual experience, and seeming to see a round red apple. States of this sort have a characteristic phenomenological, or felt, quality, which is typically thought to be an essential part of their nature. As the examples cited indicate, included in this sort are both bodily sensations and perceptual experiences, where the latter have intentional objects (i.e. objects that may or may not have actual existence). Suppose, now, that I am currently, consciously thinking a thought with a given propositional content, say the content water is transparent, while thinking about, or reflecting on, it, as when, for example, I think to myself, I am currently, consciously (p. 743) thinking that water is transparent. And suppose that my so‐called second‐order thought—my thought that I am currently consciously thinking that water is transparent— constitutes knowledge. What is the status of this knowledge? Descartes held that we know some of our intentional states, namely those that we are consciously undergoing while we are thinking about them, in an epistemically direct and authoritative way.3 His paradigm for this kind of knowledge was the cogito, which includes not just thoughts like I am now thinking, but ones like I am thinking that water is transparent. Descartes thought that he had this special kind of knowledge because of the special epistemic relation he bore to his thoughts while he was thinking them. Many have construed this epistemic relation as being at the very least immediate, in the sense of being non‐evidence‐based (see Alston 1971; Davidson 1984, 1987, 1988; Burge 1985, 1988; Heil 1988, 1992; Wright 1989).4 This immediacy is thought to extend beyond knowing that one is in a given intentional state—say, a state of thinking—to knowing what the content of that state is—say, a state of thinking that water is transparent. According to this picture my knowledge of what I am currently, consciously thinking is not based on evidence. I do not normally go through a process of inference from my (first‐ order) thought, say, that water is transparent, to arrive at my (second‐order) reflective thought that I am thinking that water is transparent. My first‐order thought and my second‐order reflective thought about it are not normally mediated by some further thought or experience which serves as evidence justifying my knowledge of my first‐order Page 3 of 30

Introspection thought. I do not use my first‐order thought as a ground or reason for my second‐order thought. I do not typically feel the need to justify my second‐order thought on the basis of my first‐order one. Of course, it does sometimes happen that I am challenged by others, or am in a state of self‐doubt about what I am currently consciously thinking. And in these cases I might engage in a justificatory process. But these are not the typical cases. This generates a puzzle. My knowledge of my current, consciously entertained thoughts is not based on evidence, and beliefs that are not based on evidence are not normally thought to be more reliable than beliefs that are so based. Why, then, is my knowledge of what thoughts I am currently, consciously thinking authoritative? What is it about this knowledge that confers upon me, but not on others, whose beliefs about my thoughts are evidence‐based, this special epistemic right? (p. 744)

The mere fact that I think my thoughts whereas others do not cannot be the answer, true though this might be, since it does not by itself explain my favoured position with regard to knowledge of the contents of these thoughts. It may be that one cannot think a thought without thinking its content. But thinking a content and knowing that a thought has that content are distinct matters. Further, since not all knowledge is authoritative, knowing authoritatively that a thought has the content it does is another matter still. The Cartesian view is that it is the epistemically direct or immediate nature of the relation between the subject of the second‐order thought and the first‐order thought reviewed in thinking that second‐order thought which explains the authoritative nature of cogito‐type thoughts. This view is associated with a particular conception of the mind, according to which it is a kind of inner theatre, viewable by a kind of ‘inner eye’ (McDowell 1986, 1998; Wright 1998). The immediate objects of one's thoughts are ‘inner’: mental phenomena such as sensations, perceptual experiences, and current, conscious thinkings. By attending to these so‐called inner objects, one can know both one's own mind and what seems to be the case in the world beyond one's mind. Further, the existence and the nature not only of one's sensations but also of one's contentful thoughts is independent of what may or may not exist beyond one's mind. The Cartesian conception of the mind is associated with a commitment to the view that subjects have privileged access to their own current, consciously entertained thoughts. This is so not just in the sense that they are in a better position than others to ‘view’ them, and so to know them as the thoughts they are, but also in the stronger sense that their knowledge of such thoughts is either incorrigible, in that they cannot be shown to be mistaken about them, or infallible, in that they simply cannot be mistaken about them, or both. For the Cartesian, the special status of such thoughts that derives from the immediate, non‐evidence‐based relation between subject and thought makes for a kind of transparency of the thought reviewed to the reviewing subject, but not to others, where a transparent thought is one that is both infallible and certain, or indubitable, in that it is Page 4 of 30

Introspection impossible for there to be any grounds for doubting that one has it and what its content is (Alston 1971). This transparency is due to the special method by which a subject has access to the contents of her own intentional states, which differs from others' access to those contents, and this is what confers an epistemic advantage on the subject in the sense of better placing her to know what the contents of those states are. The Cartesian account is thus a sort of introspectionist account of self‐knowledge, what we might call a direct observational one (which we will revisit in Section 43.3). This view contrasts sharply with the Rylean one. For the Cartesian, the special status of self‐knowledge is a datum that serves as a secure basis on which to construct a theory of knowledge in general. For the Rylean, however, self‐knowledge does not have any distinctive status. Unlike the Cartesian, the Rylean denies that there are features peculiar to self‐knowledge that need accounting for by any theory (p. 745) of self‐knowledge (as distinct from a theory of knowledge in general). As Ryle himself puts it: The sorts of things that I can find out about myself are the same as the sorts of things that I can find out about other people, and the methods of finding them out are much the same. A residual difference in the supplies of residual data makes some differences in degree between what I can know about myself and what I can know about you, but these differences are not all in favour of self‐knowledge. In certain quite important respects it is easier for me to find out what I want to know about you than it is for me to find out the same sorts of things about myself. In certain other important respects it is harder. But in principle, as distinct from practice, John Doe's ways of finding out about John Doe are the same as John Doe's ways of finding about Richard Roe. (1949: 155–6) What ‘privileges’ self‐knowledge over knowledge of others, when it does, is just the fact that we are more often able to observe our own behaviour than we are able to observe the behaviour of others, and so we have more data of the same kind (rather than data of a different kind) on which to base such knowledge.

Ryle's main objection to the view that self‐knowledge is distinctive is to the idea of privileged access, or a special way of knowing one's own inner states, of the kind presumed by the Cartesian; namely, a sort of ‘inner’ perception of one's mental episodes. His objection is that if self‐knowledge involved a second‐order perception‐like awareness, or consciousness, of a first‐order state, this second‐order awareness would itself have to be conscious, in which case it would itself require the subject to be aware of it by means of a ‘third‐order’ awareness of the second‐order state, and so on into infinity. However, Sosa (2003) claims that this argument rests on a confusion between a conscious episode (such as my consciously thinking that water is transparent) and being conscious of that episode (as I am when I am reflecting on my conscious thinking that water is transparent). I can be in a state of consciously thinking that water is transparent without being in a state of being conscious of that state. So I can be in a state of consciously

Page 5 of 30

Introspection thinking that I am thinking that water is transparent without being in a state of being conscious of that state.5 The Rylean alternative to the Cartesian model is to construe self‐knowledge as a matter of bringing one's future behaviour into step with one's present behaviour in such a way as to make for a ‘fit’ between the two. One does this by being in a ‘frame of mind’ or ‘being prepared’ to say or do things in future circumstances by ‘being alive’ to, or observing, what one is now doing (Ryle 1949: 179). So self‐knowledge requires (p. 746) observation of one's own behaviour.6 Since one can ‘be alive’ to what others are now doing by observing their behaviour (even while being in a different frame of mind from them), there is no difference in kind between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others. Ryle gives an example of a lecturer and a listener. The lecturer is alive to what she is doing, and prepared for the parts of the lecture she has not yet given, but her frame of mind is different from that of the listener, since she is creative while the listener is receptive. Still, the listener is alive to what the speaker is doing. A neo‐Rylean version of the position (McGeer 1996), which goes further in attempting to account for the authoritative status of self‐knowledge, construes self‐knowledge as a matter not just of there being a kind of fit between what one avows when one says ‘I believe that p’ and what one goes on to do or say, but of a subject's actually ensuring that there is that fit, by making her future actions and verbal behaviour fit her avowals. In that case, the truth‐makers for one's avowals are not one's present ‘inner perceptions’ of ones present inner states, but the future deeds that follow the words, which one brings about.7 The Rylean position is undermined by the fact that it seems so obviously true that, in at least some cases, there is an epistemic asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others and that this is due to the fact that subjects often know what they are thinking when they make avowals without appeal to evidence from their own behaviour as well before engaging in any such behaviour (Boghossian 1989), and by the fact that the arguments attacking the Cartesian alternative, which give support to this apparent truth, are not compelling.8 The Rylean account may fit some cases of self‐ knowledge, specifically, cases of knowledge of one's own non‐episodic mental states, such as one's standing beliefs, particularly ones about which one is self‐deceived, but it is the episodic ones, like the cogito‐type cases, knowledge of which seems peculiarly authoritative. The neo‐Rylean attempt to rescue authority while maintaining the central claim that avowals are not reports on inner states that underlie and cause behaviour by claiming that one's ability to ensure that one's future behaviour fits with and makes true one's avowals suffers from these problems as well as from problems of its own. It has the consequence, for example, that one cannot explain why people make the avowals they do when they do, as well as allowing almost any first‐order belief which one can make true by undertaking a course of action, such (p. 747) as my belief now that the balloon will pop (which I can make true by undertaking a course of action involving a dart), to count as authoritative (Brueckner 2001).

Page 6 of 30

Introspection

43.2 Some Deflationary Accounts One might agree with the assessment of the Rylean position and with the view expressed by the Cartesian that at least some self‐knowledge is distinctive, even to the extent of agreeing that the cogito‐type cases are cases of this kind, but still reject the view, to which the Cartesian is committed, that what makes such knowledge distinctive has to do with a special method or way in which it is obtained. One might instead maintain that self‐knowledge is no special cognitive achievement: it is knowledge, and it is authoritative, but it is not arrived at in a special way (or, indeed, in any ‘way’ at all). There are a number of different positions that are of this general kind, and here I can only canvass a few. One stems from considerations about the nature of interpretation (Davidson 1984, 1987, 1989). According to this, there is an asymmetry between self‐ knowledge and knowledge of others because the grounds for self‐ascriptions of beliefs differ from the grounds for other‐ascriptions of beliefs. One argument for this stems from considerations concerning the nature of interpretation. When another interprets my speech, she must work out, from the external conditions in which my utterances occur, both what my utterances mean and what the contents of my beliefs expressed by those utterances are. But I do not need to work out what my utterances mean; when I say ‘The balloon is red’ I know what I mean by this. This knowledge is not based on evidence, observation of my own behaviour, or inference. Further, when another sets out to interpret my utterance, she needs to work out whether I hold the sentence uttered true; that is, whether I believe that it is true. My utterance itself along with other factors external to me provide defeasible empirical evidence for whether I do hold that sentence true. Unlike my interpreter, however, I do not need to rely on this evidence to determine whether I hold that sentence true. So, just as I do not have to work out what I mean by my utterance, I do not need to work out whether I hold the sentence uttered true. But if I know what my utterance of that sentence means, and I know that I hold that sentence true, I know what I believe. One response to this argument is that it does not explain how I know that I hold a sentence true, that is, how I know that I believe that it is true, and so does not explain how I know what I believe. Without an explanation of this, the argument seems to presume rather than explain authoritative self‐knowledge (Gallois 1996). Davidson (1991) gives a different argument for the position, however, which doesn't depend on the nature of interpretation. According to this, although an interpreter must work out, from the external conditions in which my utterances occur, both the meanings of my utterances and the contents of my beliefs, I do not have to do this. But since whatever determines the contents of my beliefs also determines the contents of my beliefs about my beliefs, I cannot be mistaken about what I believe. My authority with (p. 748) regard to my beliefs about my own beliefs and other mental states consists in the fact that such beliefs are infallible: whatever I think I believe I know I believe.9

Page 7 of 30

Introspection In a similar vein, Burge (1988, 1996, 1998) argues that the authoritative status of certain self‐knowledge—the kind of knowledge involved in the cogito‐type cases—is due to the fact that they are contextually self‐verifying. In his opinion, the proper way to view the cogito‐type cases is as ones in which one's first‐order thought is literally contained within, or is a constituent of, one's second‐order thought, which is contextually self‐verifying for the reason that in thinking the reflective thought one makes that thought true. One makes it true because in thinking the reflective thought one brings into being the first‐order thought upon which one is reflecting. The relation between first‐ and second‐order thought is non‐causal, at least in part because there are not here two separate acts of thinking: there is no first‐order thought, considered as a state distinct from the second‐ order, reflective one, to serve as one of the relata of the causal relation. Although there are differences between these two versions of the deflationary position, both are committed to the view that certain self‐knowledge is authoritative just because one and the same content is the content of both the first‐order thought or belief and the content of the so‐called second‐order thought or belief about the first‐order one. This being so, it is impossible that one should be in error about what that content is. One cannot have a thought of a certain contentful type and misidentify it. Since to think a thought is to think its content, to think of it as a thought with a different content would be to think a different thought altogether. Some may object to this position on the grounds that it relies on a particular conception of what is involved in thinking second‐order thoughts about one's first‐order thoughts, but this conception is false because all second‐order thoughts or beliefs about first‐order ones involve distinct thoughts/beliefs. However, this would not by itself show that, in the cogito‐type cases, such thoughts are not contextually self‐verifying, since this feature of such cases might be explained differently. For example, it might be maintained that a necessary condition of thinking a reflective thought with a given content is that that content refers to a first‐order thought content, and that a necessary condition for this is that the contents of the two thoughts are of the same type. If so, then although it would be true that thinking such a second‐order thought suffices for its being true, and that thinking it makes it true, this would not be because there is no first‐order thought content distinct from the reflective one to which it is causally related. (p. 749)

There is, however, another, deeper problem with this type of position. Even if we agree that certain cases of self‐knowledge are special because their contents are infallibly known, and even if we agree that this is due to the fact that there is just one content thought and thought about, the authority awarded to their subjects by this means alone does not seem to have much to do with epistemology. In one clear sense of ‘authority’, someone whose knowledge is authoritative is in a better epistemic position, or is epistemically better placed, or better justified, than another to claim to have that knowledge. But this deflationary position does not award a subject's self‐knowledge authoritative status for this reason. The authority here is simply to do with the fact that a Page 8 of 30

Introspection subject of a second‐order, complex thought, which includes as a constituent a first‐order thought, thinks a thought with a single content. It is enough for authority that the thinker simply thinks that thought, since thinking it makes it true. There is a further question whether, on this type of account, self‐knowledge counts as a form of knowledge at all. It has been argued that in order for a mental state to count as a genuine form of knowledge it must be a genuine cognitive achievement—something that a subject can strive, and fail, to possess (Wittgenstein 1953; Wright 1989, 1998; Moran 1997, 2001). But this type of deflationary position does not allow for that. Davidson and Burge develop their positions on self‐knowledge against the background of a common presumption. Both are externalists with regard to the contents of propositional attitudes. Briefly, externalism is the view that certain intentional states of persons have contents that are ‘world‐involving’ in that they depend on the existence of objects and/or other factors beyond the bodies of their subjects (Putnam 1975; Burge 1979, 1985, 1988; Davidson 1984, 1987, 1989—though Burge's view specifically concerns anti‐ individualism). Externalism has been thought to compromise the presumption of authoritative self‐knowledge in virtue of its commitment to the view that the empirically discoverable determinants of a subject's thoughts might be better known to be what they are by another who has better knowledge of those determinants. Suppose, to use a well‐ worn example, that in the distant galaxies there is a planet, Twin Earth. Twin Earth is a duplicate of earth in every way, physically and phenomenologically described, apart from this: the substance that fills lakes, rivers, and streams and has all of the phenomenological qualities of water is constituted not by H2O but by a different chemical structure, XYZ (Putnam 1975). Now consider a situation on earth in which a subject, who knows nothing about chemistry and Twin Earth, believes that she is currently thinking that water is transparent. Her justification for this seems weaker than that of another individual who, knowing about chemistry and Twin Earth, knows that the water content in question relates to H2O, and that the subject has not (unbeknownst to her) been transported to Twin Earth. This seems to be a case where externalism conflicts with authoritative self‐knowledge, intuitively understood. The deflationary position taken up by Davidson and Burge responds to this threat by maintaining that since whatever determines the (water) content of the subject's first‐ order state to be what it is also determines the content of the second‐order state, (p. 750) and since the content of the first‐order one just is the content of the second‐order one, error with respect to the content of the first‐order thought is not possible. While this may explain why the subject's thoughts about her water thoughts on earth are infallible, and also why her Twin's thoughts about her (water*) thoughts on Twin Earth are infallible, it does not really respond to the worry expressed by the above situation. That concern has to do with the fact that another, who has knowledge that the subject does not about both earth and Twin Earth, and water and water*, is better justified in her knowledge that the subject is indeed thinking that water is transparent. And she is better justified because she has, whereas the subject does not, discriminative knowledge—that the subject is thinking a water, rather than a water*, thought. Switching cases, where the subject has Page 9 of 30

Introspection unwittingly been transported from earth to Twin Earth, are intended to illustrate the force of this threat. In one such case a subject is told that she has been transported to Twin Earth during sleep but is not told when the switch occurred, so that when asked which thought she was thinking a year ago she has no idea, even though she suffers no memory impairment (Boghossian 1989).10 Another version of the deflationary position that presumes the truth of externalism is held by McDowell (1986, 1998). Unlike the version just discussed, this one does not attempt to explain what makes for authoritative self‐knowledge. On the contrary, it takes a sceptical stance on the view that there is something problematic about the claim that subjects have authoritative self‐knowledge—indeed, infallible self‐knowledge—that needs explaining. According to it, this is an illusion, whose source is the ‘fully Cartesian’ conception of the inner, which construes the mental domain as autonomous with respect to the world beyond the mind to the extent that a subject could think exactly the thoughts that she thinks in the world as it is (p. 751) in a world in which there is nothing beyond her mind. Once the source of the so‐called problem is exposed and the Cartesian grip is dislodged, one is free to view the inner and outer domains as ‘interpenetrating’ by construing the infallibly knowable appearances expressed by avowals of the form ‘It seems to me that I am thinking that that F is G’ disjunctively, as constituted either by the fact that I am indeed manifestly thinking that that F is G or by the fact that that merely seems to me to be the case.11 A question that arises is whether this view can account for authoritative self‐knowledge any better than does the Davidson/Burge view. Suppose that I am in a situation in which I am thinking a singular tiger thought—say, I am thinking that that tiger has stripes—but am ignorant of the facts of biology and Twin Earth. On the present view I can have infallible knowledge that it seems to me that I am thinking that that tiger has stripes consistently with externalism because what I infallibly know is either that I am indeed manifestly thinking that that tiger has stripes or that that merely seems to me to be the case, and this is compatible with another person's better knowledge of which of the two disjuncts is in question. But in this situation another has this knowledge because she has discriminative knowledge that I do not—knowledge about the facts of biology and Twin Earth, where there are no tigers but only pligers (creatures that have all the phenomenological properties of tigers but differ in their biological constitution), knowledge that the tiger content in question relates to tigers rather than pligers, and knowledge that I have not (unbeknownst to me) been transported to Twin Earth. Because she knows this, she not only knows which disjunct is in question but knows the fact, disjunctively construed, that I know. Further, and more importantly, she seems better justified than I am to know, when it seems to me that I am thinking that that tiger has stripes, that what it seems to me that I am thinking is either this: I am indeed manifestly thinking that that tiger has stripes, or this: that that merely seems to me to be the case.12 Finally, there is a ‘neo‐expressive’ version of a deflationary position canvassed by Dorit Bar‐On (2004), whose aim is to develop a view on avowals that respects two features that are naturally associated with them: (1) that they are semantically continuous and truth‐ Page 10 of 30

Introspection conditionally interchangeable with other unproblematic statements, and (2) that they exhibit epistemic asymmetries with these other unproblematic, truth‐conditionally equivalent statements. Her view is that avowals (p. 752) are self‐ascriptions of, but not judgements about, one's mental states, events, etc., and are expressions of one's mental states, but not reports on them. This combination of views allows her to maintain that avowals are both true and epistemically more secure than other self‐ascriptions and other‐ascriptions. Bar‐On recognizes that there is an inherent tension in this combination of views. On the one hand, the view that avowals are expressions of, rather than reports on, one's mental states encourages the view that they are not truth‐evaluable. On the other hand, the view that avowals are self‐ascriptions of mental states and are truth‐evaluable encourages the view that they are not expressions of, but are rather reports on, one's mental states. Bar‐ On's attempt to show how these views can be held in combination involves arguing that the special epistemic security that avowals enjoy does not have an epistemic basis at all. This is the core of her account, and what makes it deflationary. According to it, the special epistemic security that avowals enjoy has its source in the fact that subjects are immune to error in self‐ascribing present mental states and (in the case of intentional avowals) in assignments of intentional objects to such states. This immunity to error is in turn due to the expressive nature of avowals, rather than to any recognition‐ based introspective self‐knowledge. Thus, the asymmetry between certain self‐ ascriptions, on the one hand, and other self‐ascriptions and other‐ascriptions, on the other, is due to the fact that the former, but not the latter, are immune from error because they are expressions of rather than reports on one's mental states. This puts the account in the same category as those, mentioned above, which take some self‐knowledge to be distinctive in being infallible but deny that there is any special method or means by which it is obtained. Evidently, the main problem for all of the deflationary accounts considered here is that, although all concede that certain self‐knowledge is authoritative in being infallible, infallibility does not account for authority in the sense that seems to matter for a genuine epistemic asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others. Further, there is a question whether, on deflationary accounts, subjects' infallible ‘knowledge’ of the contents of their own mental states deserves to be called knowledge at all.

43.3 Some Introspectionist Accounts The preceding discussion encourages the thought that if self‐knowledge is a genuine form of knowledge and there is an epistemic asymmetry between it and knowledge of the mental states of others, something like an introspectionist account is required to explain

Page 11 of 30

Introspection it. The Cartesian position is just one of these. In this final section I will explore this and a few other such positions and conclude by recommending my own. As noted earlier, introspectionist views attempt to account for some or all of the features associated with certain self‐knowledge by appeal to a special method or way in which one comes to know one's own mental states. Like deflationary accounts, (p. 753) they recognize an asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others. Unlike deflationary ones, however, they attempt to explain how it is that at least some self‐ knowledge possesses some or all of the features associated with the asymmetry. It is important to the introspectionist view that the relevant knowledge concerns one's own current, conscious mental states, whether these are propositional attitudes or sensations. While all introspectionist accounts appeal to a special method or way in which knowledge of one's own mental states is obtained, they differ in their accounts of what this method is, how it works, and whether the knowledge delivered by it has all of the features of self‐ knowledge listed at the outset of Section 43.1 associated with the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others. This section will discuss three such accounts. All are in agreement that one clear feature marks the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others, namely the epistemic directness or immediacy of such knowledge, and that appeal to introspection is what explains this feature. The first is what I earlier called the direct‐observation account (see Gertler 2003). Its most famous expositor was Descartes, but a version of it was also held by Russell (1910), who maintained that subjects have direct epistemic access to their own mental states in virtue of being directly acquainted with them. More recently, versions have been endorsed by Chisholm (1981), Langsam (2002), and Chalmers (2003). While Chisholm's version is decidedly Cartesian, others, such as Chalmers's version, restrict the account to knowledge of one's sensation states. The reason why one might think it particularly plausible in the case of sensations, including visual experiences such as being appeared to redly, is that it is plausible to hold that no appearance/reality distinction applies to them.13 What distinguishes the direct‐observation account from other introspectionist ones is not, or not merely, that it is observational, since, as we shall see, the inner‐sense account to be discussed shortly is also an observational one. It is that the relation between the knowing state and the mental state known is held to be unmediated by any further mental state or mechanism in the subject. Chalmers (1996), for example, maintains that the knowing state is partly constituted by the phenomenal state known. This is thought to distinguish the kind of method involved in knowing one's own mental states from the kind of method involved in ordinary observation, or perception, of things in the world around one in at least two important respects. First, in ordinary perception the objects or phenomena perceived are distinct from, and can exist independently of, their being perceived. Second, and more importantly for present purposes, in ordinary perception there is a state of perceptual experience that mediates between objects of perception and beliefs/ judgements about them, and a perceptual mechanism whose (p. 754) operation is causally Page 12 of 30

Introspection responsible for delivering that experience.14 But according to the direct‐observation account, knowledge of one's current conscious mental states is unmediated by any other mental states, experiential ones included. Such knowledge is epistemically direct and immediate in just the way described earlier in connection with the Cartesian model: it is non‐evidence‐based in being non‐inferential and unmediated by any further mental state. One way of putting the point might be to say that knowledge of one's own current conscious mental states is constitutively rather than merely contingently and causally related to the first‐order states that partly constitute such knowledge (see Shoemaker 1994). This being so, one question that arises with this account, no less than with the deflationary ones discussed in Section 43.2, is whether on it self‐knowledge has the status of being genuine knowledge. Wright (1989, 1998), for example, argues that knowledge involves the application of concepts, with respect to which error must be possible. If this is right, then in order to be able to know, say, that I am thinking that the apple on my desk is round, I need not just to think that the apple on my desk is round but also to have the concept of round and the concept of thinking and apply these correctly, where correctness implies the possibility of error. However, on the direct‐observation account, where self‐knowledge of mental states is construed in the way that Chalmers construes it, knowledge of one's own current conscious mental states is infallible. If I think that I am thinking that the apple in front of me is round, then I know that I am thinking that the apple in front of me is round. Wright's view is that on this kind of account self‐knowledge is not genuine knowledge. Even if Wright is mistaken about this and the account does not compromise the status of self‐knowledge as knowledge, it does jettison the epistemic asymmetry between self‐ knowledge and knowledge of others, since this is connected with the notion of one's being epistemically better placed, or being better justified, than another to know one's own current conscious mental states. That notion seems to require that the reviewing thought and the thought reviewed be distinct existences, contingently and causally related. But this is just what the direct‐observation account, specifically the constitution view, denies. Somewhat surprisingly, then, this account suffers from the same sorts of problems that bedevil deflationary accounts. Further, as the discussion of deflationary accounts showed, there is a general problem reconciling authoritative self‐knowledge with externalism about mental content, and the direct‐observation account suffers from this problem as well. If externalism is true, what individuates the contents of certain mental states is the relations those states bear to factors beyond the bodies of their subjects—ones concerning which subjects themselves may be ignorant. So another's better knowledge of those relations may put her in a better position, or make her better justified than subjects themselves, to know what the contents of their current conscious thoughts are. (p. 755)

Page 13 of 30

Introspection Later, at the end of this section, I will suggest a way of developing the direct‐observation account that seems capable of avoiding these problems. But first let us consider a couple of other introspectionist accounts. According to one of these, the inner‐sense account, introspection is viewed as a kind of inner perception. Versions of it have been held by Locke and Kant. Locke claimed: This Source of Ideas, every Man has wholly in himself … And though it be not Sense; as having nothing to do with external Objects; yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be call'd internal Sense (1690/1975: II.i.4) Kant described introspection as ‘inner sense, by means of which the mind intuits itself or its inner state’ (1787/1998: A23/B37; p. 157). More recently, the inner‐sense account has been championed by philosophers such as Armstrong (1968, 1981) and Lycan (1987, 1996, 2004), both of whom also hold a particular view about what it is to be a conscious state (although commitment to this is not required by commitment to the inner‐sense account of self‐ knowledge). According to this, to be a conscious state is to be the object of higher‐order awareness by a perception‐like faculty. This view is known as the higher‐order‐perception theory of consciousness (one of a family of such theories, another of which is the higher‐order‐thought theory of consciousness—see Rosenthal 1997).

The inner‐sense account differs from the direct‐observation one in important ways. First, and most obviously, it takes knowledge of one's own current, conscious states to be mediated by a causal, perception‐like process involving a perception‐like mechanism. Armstrong's position is that introspection involves a kind of self‐scanning process by which subjects are made aware of their own mental states (1981: 61), involving an internal scanner or monitor that takes first‐order states as inputs and outputs second‐ order ones, where these are distinct and contingently, causally related to one another. Lycan (1996: 14) describes it as ‘the functioning of internal attention mechanisms directed at lower‐order psychological states and events’. Armstrong's position takes the internal scanner to be in principle capable of scanning the lower‐order mental states of others, so that the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others is merely a contingent matter. Lycan's does not take the analogy with perception to be so complete as this, since it takes introspection to involve the use of primitive lexemes in a language of thought. This makes introspective self‐knowledge ineffable. Second, the inner‐sense account attributes only one feature of those associated with the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others described at the outset of our discussion to self‐knowledge; namely, that it is direct and immediate, and this only in the sense that it is non‐inferential. Self‐knowledge has this feature because a subject need not know the causal relations that hold between her introspecting state and the state introspected when she knows her own mental state. One objection to the account is that self‐knowledge cannot be like perception because in perception there are three items (perceived object, perceptual experience, (p. 756) and belief/judgement based on it) whereas in self‐knowledge there are only two (first‐order Page 14 of 30

Introspection mental state and belief/judgement based on it) (Shoemaker 1994; Rosenthal 1997). To this the response has been made that the inner‐sense view is not committed to construing introspection as like perception in every respect (Lycan 1996: 28).15 Since, however, the presence of an experiential state seems to be essential to perception, the absence of any such state in introspective self‐knowledge is a crucial difference. Another objection is that self‐knowledge cannot be like perception because in perception the relation between the object perceived and the perceptual state is contingent and causal. Applied to introspection this has the consequence that knowledge of one's current conscious states is fallible. The inner‐sense account acknowledges both that it is possible for a subject to be in a first‐order mental state and fail to know that she is because her internal monitor is malfunctioning, and that it is possible for a subject to be in a second‐ order, introspecting state without being in the corresponding first‐order state (Lycan 1996). However, Shoemaker (1994) argues that if the connection between first‐order and second‐order states involved in introspection is contingent and causal, self‐blindness (a condition in which one is introspectively ‘blind’ to one's own first‐order mental states without any cognitive malfunction) should be possible, due to a breakdown in the internal monitor. But it is impossible, because normal rationality—specifically, rational‐belief revision—requires access to one's own first‐order states. So the requirements on normal rationality show that first‐order states are not independent of second‐order ones in the way required by the inner‐sense account. In response, one might agree that the inner‐sense view is incompatible with Shoemaker's strong sense of ‘rational’ but claim that there is a weaker sense with which it is compatible. This is the sense that is relevant when one considers very young children, who are not yet capable of rational belief revision but are capable of adjusting their beliefs about the world in response to changes in their environments. 16 But a more general worry about the account remains. Shoemaker's principal objection to the inner‐sense account is that the relation that holds between the first‐order and second‐ order states involved in self‐knowledge is non‐contingent and constitutive, and it is essential to human rationality that it be so. It is significant that the account marks an asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of (p. 757) others but takes it to consist merely in contingent facts about the method of knowing and the way in which the method operates. It fails to account for nearly all of the features associated with the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others because it rejects the view that self‐knowledge possesses them. But this robs the account of a satisfactory explanation of why at least some self‐knowledge is epistemically special; a fact that the classically Cartesian account hoped to explain by appeal to introspection. Some will claim that this cannot be accounted for by any model that construes the relation between knowledge of one's own mental states and those states themselves as contingent and causal (Burge 1996, 1998; Gertler 2000).

Page 15 of 30

Introspection Further, and relatedly, the inner‐sense view suffers from a problem mentioned earlier in connection with deflationary positions, that of reconciling authoritative self‐knowledge with externalism about mental content. According to it, the authoritative status of certain self‐knowledge is a purely contingent matter, arising from the reliability of the introspective perception‐like faculty. As it happens, this faculty is in general reliable. But despite this, if externalism is true, another may be better placed than I am to know the contents of my intentional states because she may have better knowledge of the beyond‐ the‐body factors that individuate the contents of those states. This is because the internal scanner or monitor can only detect what is internal to the subject, not what is beyond the body. A third type of introspectionist account agrees with the inner‐sense view that knowledge of one's own mental states is perception‐like, but denies that it involves the operation of any inner process or mechanism in addition to the process of perception itself. This view is known as the displaced‐perception account (Dretske 1994, 1995, 1999). Whereas the inner‐sense account takes introspection to be a matter of ‘looking inwards’, and attending to one's inner states, the displaced‐perception account takes introspection to be a matter of ‘looking outwards’, and attending to the objects of normal perception, such items as trees, oranges, and human beings. Versions of it have been held by Evans (1982) and Dretske (1994, 1995, 1999, 2006). As Evans describes it: [I]n making a self‐ascription of belief, one's eyes are, so to speak, or occasionally literally, directed outward—upon the world. If someone asks me ‘Do you think there is going to be a third world war?,’ I must attend, in answering him, to precisely the same outward phenomena as I would attend to if I were answering the question ‘Will there be a third world war?’ I get myself in a position to answer the question whether I believe that p by putting into operation whatever procedure I have for answering the question whether p. (1982: 225)17 This is displaced perception, since in perception one directs one's attention to the object perceived, whereas in self‐knowledge one directs one's attention not to one's (p. 758) inner state, but outward, to a state or feature of the world beyond one. According to this account, one ‘perceives’ one's own mental state by perceiving something else.

Evans's version of the account speaks of self‐ascriptions of beliefs, and his use of ‘think’ in the above example is most plausibly construed as functioning like ‘believe’. The displaced‐perception account seems ideally suited to explain cases like these. This is because it is plausible to maintain that it is in the nature of belief that beliefs aim at the truth of what is believed. So it is not surprising that when asked what I think about a possible or actual state of the world beyond me my attention is drawn not to the inner workings of my mind but to factors in that world. But things seem otherwise when the issue is not about what one believes, but about what one is currently consciously thinking. When asked what I am thinking, rather than what I think is or will be the case in the

Page 16 of 30

Introspection world beyond me, the more plausible view is that my attention turns not outward but inward. This is all the more apparent in cases of self‐knowledge of one's sensation states. Dretske's version of the account is connected with his teleorepresentationalist view of mental content. According to this, what gives a mental state its content—its meaning—is what its teleofunction is to indicate, what it represents. Just as what a petrol gauge's pointer's resting at E represents is that the petrol tank is empty, what my belief that water is transparent represents is that water is transparent. Dretske draws on analogies with devices such as petrol gauges and thermometers, where it is plausible to say that one becomes aware of one fact by becoming aware of another in general, in order to explain how it is that one becomes aware of one's own mental states of thinking, believing, and experiencing. So, just as one knows that the petrol tank is empty by perceiving the petrol gauge, one knows that one thinks that it is raining by perceiving the rain falling outside one's window. In general, one knows what properties one's own sensory or propositional state has not by attending to the state itself but by attending to what that state is of or about: To know what the experience is like, what properties it has, it is enough for the experiencer to ‘look at’ what the experience is an experience of (something that, as the experiencer, he cannot help but be doing). That will tell him what the relevant properties of the experience are. (Dretske 1999: 112) Dretske's view is that the knowledge that one has of one's own mental states is special in that it is not only authoritative, but infallibly so. (p. 759)

But how is this possible? On the representational view of mental content the factors that determine the properties, or content, of an experience or other mental state are extrinsic, or relational. That is to say, the representational view is externalist about mental content. How, then, can one know authoritatively, let alone infallibly, what the properties of one's own propositional or sensory states are? This is explained by appeal to the distinction between ‘thing’ awareness and ‘fact’ awareness, a distinction that is brought explicitly into play in order to help explain why the possession of these features by self‐knowledge is compatible with externalism. 18 What I know authoritatively when I know that I am thinking that water is transparent, or that I am having an experience as of a red round apple, is what I am thinking or having, rather than that I am thinking or having it. That is, I am authoritative about the content of my thought or experience, but not about the fact that I am having a thought or experience with that content. As Dretske puts the point: Introspection is not how we know that we think and feel. It is how we know what we think and feel. Introspection is no more a way of knowing that we think and feel than is perception, our primary way of knowing what else is in the world, a Page 17 of 30

Introspection way of knowing that there is something else in the world … We cannot see that there is an external world, although the things we come to know by seeing (that there is beer in the fridge, keys in my pocket) imply that there are things (namely, beer and keys) outside my mind. (1999: 137) The idea is that when I am ϕ‐ing that p, for some attitude ϕ and some propositional content p, I can infallibly know that it is p that I am ϕ‐ing, but know only fallibly, if at all, and by some other means, that it is ϕ‐ing (that p) that I am doing.

In order to see why Dretske thinks that self‐knowledge of content is infallible, we need to understand an analogy he uses to demonstrate this. Consider an instrument, like a petrol gauge or a thermometer, that represents the value of a quantity, Q, say, temperature. When it isn't malfunctioning, it correctly represents the quantity of a source to which it is connected. So, for example, when athermometer is functioning properly, when it registers (or ‘says that’) the source has Q of 37 °C, the source does have a Q of 37 °C. It carries this information, but does not say that it carries this information. But suppose we were to rewire it so that that one state, registering the source as having a Q of 37 °C, could ‘say that’ the source to which it is connected has a Q of 37 °C, but could also say something about itself—that it is representing (p. 760) the source as having a Q of 37 °C. We might do this simply by affixing to it the label ‘Value that Q is representing’ (Dretske 1999: 134). This instrument now does two things by being in one state: it both represents the state of its source, and it represents itself as representing the state of its source. Although the instrument is fallible about the first thing it does (since it can malfunction), it is infallible about the second thing it does (even when it is malfunctioning). One objection to this is that merely affixing a ‘self‐representing’ label to a representational state is not sufficient to produce self‐knowledge of that state (White 1987; Lycan 1996). The problem with it is that genuine self‐knowledge involves not just representing the representational content of one's state to oneself, but representing that content to oneself as the representational content of one's state; and having a functional ‘Value that Q is representing’ does not suffice for this, since it does not suffice to ensure self‐knowledge of the representational content of one's state. But even if it did, there would remain the problem that such knowledge, being infallible, is subject to the sorts of objections raised in connection with other introspectionist and deflationist accounts discussed above: that infallibility does not suffice to explain how a subject could be better placed than another to know the contents of her own state, and further, and more strongly, that it is questionable whether it deserves to be called ‘knowledge’ at all. Because the account is externalist, it is also subject to the same sorts of objections based on switching examples discussed in Section 43.1. It is true that simple switching will not be a problem for the account, since the semantics associated with it is teleological, taking the determinants of mental content to be causal‐historical, and a simple switch will not suffice for a change in the content of, say, a water thought. But the type of switching example discussed in Section 43.1 remains problematic for the account (Boghossian 1989). This is because, in the envisaged scenario, the subject has not only been Page 18 of 30

Introspection unwittingly transported from earth to Twin Earth, but she also remains there for a long enough period for the causal‐historical factors that determine content to determine her thoughts about the watery stuff to be water* thoughts. Evidently, apart from the inner‐ sense view, all of the accounts, both deflationary and introspectionist, thus far considered suffer from the same sorts of objections: one stemming from commitments to the infallibility of knowledge of one's own current conscious state, and the other stemming from considerations having to do with externalism about mental content. The inner‐sense view does not suffer from objections of the former sort, but then again the asymmetry between self‐knowledge and knowledge of others doesn't amount to much on this view either, since self‐knowledge doesn't have the special epistemic status it is typically thought to have. Let me conclude by recommending my own version of an introspectionist account, a version that I think is capable of avoiding many of these problems (see Macdonald 1995, 1998a, 1998b). Although it makes use of an observational analogy in order to defend a position on authoritative self‐knowledge, it does not do so in what might appear to be the obvious way; namely, by appeal to something like an ‘inner sense’. Rather, it appeals to more abstract and general features of (p. 761) observation of external things, specifically features of observable properties, which help to explain our direct and immediate access to them, and this distinguishes the position from other introspectionist accounts discussed above. The position is principally intended to account for authoritative self‐ knowledge of intentional states of a particular kind—the current, conscious thinkings— but can be generalized to the more obvious case of sensations. The view is motivated by the thought that we can get a firmer grip on what makes for such knowledge by looking at how such notions as ‘direct access’ and ‘immediate access’ work in other areas where they have a natural home. One such place is in perception. Consider certain observable properties of objects of perception, like being brown, or being rectangular. When I know that, say, the table visually present in front of me is brown, or that it is rectangular, this knowledge is in a certain sense direct and immediate. One explanation of how I can know directly or immediately that this instance is of a particular colour property, or of a particular shape property, is that it is presented to me as an instance of that property through my sense of sight. I simply see it as brown, as rectangular, non‐inferentially and in an unmediated way. This is not true of other properties of objects of perception. Water, for example, is an instance of the chemical structural property H2O, but it is not manifested to me as an instance of that property through one of my senses. So certain properties seem to be ones of which we have direct or immediate awareness in perception because they are observable: whether objects are instances of them can be determined just by unaided observation (but not, perhaps, by unconceptualized experience) of those objects. 19 Certain features of observable properties characterize their direct and immediate accessibility in a way that marks them off from other properties. One is that they are epistemically basic or fundamental to knowledge of objects that instance them. The point Page 19 of 30

Introspection is that such properties are the ones by which objects that instance them are typically known in the first place. Knowing an object through instances of certain properties and not others favours certain ones epistemically. Another is that they are in general as they appear to normal perceivers in normal circumstances. This is true both for the primary qualities, such as that of being rectangular, where the connection between an object's being an instance of the property and how things look to normal observers in optimal conditions is thought to be a posteriori and contingent, and for the secondary ones, like that of being brown, where the connection between these and the best opinion of normal observers under optimal conditions is thought to be a priori, and, further, thought by some to determine the nature of the property itself. 20 (p. 762)

The rationale for focusing on the example of observable properties in perception is not to argue that self‐knowledge is just like perceptual knowledge. There are clearly important and fundamental differences between these two sorts of knowledge. Crucially, there is a certain kind of phenomenology to perception of observable properties (for example, the experience of something's looking wet is distinctive and very different from the experience of something's looking red) that attaches to the contents of one's perceptual experiences. This seems to be lacking in the case of self‐knowledge of one's thoughts, since, as noted earlier, there seems to be no analogue of a perceptual experience in the knowledge one has of one's own thoughts at all. Despite this difference, there are important affinities that can help us to understand better the nature (and extent) of authoritative self‐knowledge. In particular, the two above‐mentioned features of observable properties of perception apply to contentful properties in these special cases of authoritative self‐knowledge in a way that can help us to see why subjects have immediate awareness of them and so authoritative knowledge of their own thoughts. When I think about my own current, conscious intentional states while undergoing them, I think about them first and foremost as states of certain contentful types. Further, when I think about my states in this way, they are in general of the contentful types I take them to be. What makes for authority, when I have it, is that only I can be the subject of my intentional states, so that when I think about my intentional states as states of particular contentful types I am the only one to whom those contents appear to me in this epistemically basic and favoured way. So normally (i.e. barring special cognitive failures) when I think about my current conscious intentional states while undergoing them I am authoritative about the contents of those states. Because the two features that characterize observable properties of perception are abstract and general, they are not tied to cases of observation alone. Those who appeal to such phenomena as ‘intellectual experience’ or ‘intellectual intuition’ in their accounts of authoritative self‐knowledge may well appeal to such features (see, for instance, Burge 1996 and Bealer's theory of the a priori— 1999). This distinguishes the position from other introspectionist ones. Further, the account is not tied to any particular conception of the cogito‐type cases; specifically, to the conception that takes second‐order thoughts Page 20 of 30

Introspection about first‐order ones to contain the first‐order ones as constitutents. It can construe such cases as involving both a thinking of a first‐order thought and a reflective thinking about that thought by the same subject, where the truth of the reflective one requires that it match the one reflected upon both with respect to content and with respect to the attitude. When successful, in reflection, the subject thinks a content of the same type as that tokened in the first‐order thought (that is, she thinks the content again) in the same attitudinal mode (p. 763) and presents it as the content of the first‐order thought. 21 This differentiates the view from the type of position held by Dretske (1999) discussed above, with its attendant difficulties. In thinking again the same content as that contained in one's first‐order thought, a subject is brought into direct epistemic contact with the content of that first‐order thought itself. But because there are here not one but two thoughts with their own contents, error is possible. This makes self‐knowledge, even in the cogito‐type cases, a genuine cognitive achievement. Finally, the account seems to be compatible with externalism. The kind of epistemic access subjects have to the contents of their thoughts in such cases, in being direct and immediate, contrasts with the epistemic access others have to those contents. When I am currently consciously thinking and thinking about a thought with a given externalistically individuated content, another may be in a better position than I am to know what content is available for me to think, and so to think about. But that other is not in a better position to grasp, and so to know, the particular content that constitutes the subject matter of my thought, about which I am thinking. When I am both thinking it and thinking about it, I have, whereas another does not, a special kind of epistemic access to the content of that thought. Being in that position gives me an epistemic purchase on it that no other has. While it is true that this does not give me better discriminative knowledge of the contents of my thoughts, it is plausible to hold that, if externalism is indeed true, I could not be in a better position than another who has better knowledge of my environment to have such knowledge. But that does not compromise my authoritative knowledge of what I am currently consciously thinking (Burge 1988, 1998).22

References Alston, W. (1971), ‘Varieties of Privileged Access’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 8: 223–41. Armstrong, D. (1968), A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul). —— (1981), ‘What Is Consciousness?’, in Armstrong, The Nature of Mind and Other Essays (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 56–67. Bar‐On, D. (2004), Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self‐Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Bealer, G. (1999), ‘A Theory of the A Priori’, Philosophical Perspectives, 13: 29–55. Page 21 of 30

Introspection Bermúdez, J. (1998), The Paradox of Self‐Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Boghossian, P. (1989), ‘Content and Self‐knowledge’, Philosophical Topics, 17: 5–26. Brueckner, A. (2001), ‘Problems for the Agency Model of Self‐knowledge’, Dialogue, 40: 545–54. (p. 764)

Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. —— (1985), ‘Cartesian Error and the Objectivity of Perception’, in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought (Tucson, Ariz.: University of Arizona Press), 62–76. —— (1988), ‘Individualism and Self‐knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy, 85: 649–63. —— (1996), ‘Our Entitlement to Self‐knowledge’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96: 91–116. —— (1998), ‘Memory and Self‐knowledge’, in P. Ludlow and N. Martin (eds.), Externalism and Self‐Knowledge (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI), 351–70. Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (2003), ‘The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief’, in Q. Smith and A. Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 220–72. Chisholm, R. (1981), The First Person (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press). Davidson, D. (1969), ‘On Saying That’, Synthese, 19: 130–46; repr. in Davidson, Inquiries Into Truth and Interpretation: Philosophical Essays, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 93–108. —— (1984), ‘First Person Authority’, Dialectica, 38: 101–11; repr. in Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 3–14. —— (1987), ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60: 441–58; repr. in Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 15–38. —— (1988), ‘The Myth of the Subjective’, in M. Benedikt and R. Berger (eds.), Bewusstsein, Sprache und die Kunst (Vienna: Österreichische Staatsdruckerei),

Page 22 of 30

Introspection repr. in M. Krausz (ed.), Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation (Notre Dame, Ill.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1989), 159–72, and in Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 39–52. —— (1989), ‘What is Present to the Mind?’, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 36: 3–18; repr. in Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 53–68. —— (1991), ‘Epistemology Externalized’, Dialectica, 45: 2–3, 191–202; repr. in Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 193– 204. —— (2001), Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (Oxford: Clarendon). Descartes, R. (1641/1984), ‘Meditations on First Philosophy’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ii, trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–398. Dretske, F. (1994), ‘Introspection’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94: 263–78. —— (1995), Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1999), ‘The Mind's Awareness of Itself’, Philosophical Studies, 95: 103–24. —— (2006), ‘Representation, Teleosemantics, and the Problem of Self‐knowledge’, in G. Macdonald and D. Papineau (eds.), Teleosemantics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 69– 84. Evans, G. (1982), The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon). Gallois, A. (1996), The World Without, The Mind Within: An Essay on First‐Person Authority (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Gertler, B. (2000), ‘The Mechanics of Self‐knowledge’, Philosophical Topics, 28: 125–46. —— (2003), ‘Self‐knowledge’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2003 edition, , accessed 2008. (p. 765)

Heil, J. (1988), ‘Privileged Access’, Mind, 97: 238–51.

—— (1992), The Nature of True Minds (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Kant, I. (1787/1998), The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. P. Guyer and A. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Page 23 of 30

Introspection Langsam, H. (2002), ‘Externalism, Self‐knowledge, and Inner Observation’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80: 42–61. Locke, J. (1690/1975), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon). Lycan, W. (1987), Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (1996), Consciousness and Experience (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). —— (2003), ‘Dretske's Ways of Introspecting’, in B. Gertler (ed.), Privileged Access and First Person Authority (Aldershot: Ashgate), 15–29. —— (2004), ‘The Superiority of HOP to HOT’, in R. J. Gennaro (ed.), Higher‐order Theories of Consciousness (Amsterdam/Philadelphia, Pa.: Benjamins), 93–113. Macdonald, C. (1995), ‘Externalism and First‐person Authority’, Synthese, 104: 99–122. —— (1998a), ‘Externalism and Authoritative Self‐knowledge’, in C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 123–54. —— (1998b), ‘Self‐knowledge and the ‘Inner Eye”’, Philosophical Explorations, 1: 83–106. McDowell, J. (1986), ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space’, in P. Pettit and J. McDowell (eds.), Subject, Thought, and Context (Oxford: Clarendon), 137–68; repr. in McDowell, Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998), 228–59. —— (1994), Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1998a), ‘Response to Crispin Wright’, in C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 47–62. —— (1998b), Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). McGeer, V. (1996), ‘Is “Self‐knowledge” an Empirical Problem? Renegotiating the Space of Philosophical Explanation’, Journal of Philosophy, 92: 485–515. McGinn, C. (1982), The Character of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). McLaughlin, B. (forthcoming), ‘Self‐knowledge’, Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Moran, R. (1997), ‘Self‐knowledge: Discovery, Resolution, and Undoing’, European Journal of Philosophy, 5: 141–61. —— (2001), Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self‐Knowledge (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).

Page 24 of 30

Introspection Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “meaning”’, in Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 215–71. Rosenthal, D. (1997), ‘A Theory of Consciousness’, in N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 729–53. Russell, B. (1910), ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11: 108–28; repr. in Russell, Mysticism and Logic (London: Allen & Unwin, 1963), 152–67. Ryle, G. (1949), The Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes & Noble). Shoemaker, S. (1968), ‘Self‐reference and Self‐awareness’, Journal of Philosophy, 65: 555– 67. —— (1994), ‘Self‐knowledge and Inner Sense’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54: 249–314. Sosa, E. (2003), ‘Consciousness and Self‐knowledge’, in B. Gertler (ed.), Privileged Access and First Person Authority (Aldershot: Ashgate), 253–62. White, S. (1987), ‘What is it Like to Be a Homunculus?’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 68: 148–74. (p. 766)

Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell). Wright, C. (1988), ‘Moral Values, Projection and Secondary Qualities’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 62: 1–26. —— (1989), ‘Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy of Mind: Sensation, Privacy, and intention’, Journal of Philosophy, 86: 622–34. —— (1992), Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). —— (1998), ‘Self‐knowledge: The Wittgensteinian Legacy’, in C. Wright, B. Smith, and C. Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 13–46.

Notes: (1) Although, as McLaughlin (forthcoming) points out, this is misleading: introspectionists do not suppose that there is such an organ as ‘the mind's eye’, nor do they suppose that introspection is literally visual. (2) This contrasts with another use of the term ‘self‐knowledge’, to apply to knowledge of the subject of mental states, or the self, and its nature (see e.g. Shoemaker 1968; Evans 1982; Bermúdez 1998). This use will not form part of our discussion. Page 25 of 30

Introspection (3) See his Meditations, especially Meditation 2: ‘Lastly, it is also the same “I” who has sensory perceptions, or is aware of bodily things as it were through the senses. For example, I am now seeing light, hearing a noise, feeling heat. But I am asleep, so all this is false. Yet I certainly seem to see, to hear, and to be warmed. This cannot be false; what is called “having a sensory perception” is strictly just this, and in this restricted sense of the term it is simply thinking’ (1641/1984: 19). (4) Some, like Wright, emphasize the non‐evidence‐based character of such knowledge, whereas others, like Heil, emphasize its non‐empirical‐èvidence‐based character. Alston gives an illuminating account of the different senses that might attach to the notion of direct access. He argues that the notion of directness that is relevant to self‐knowledge is epistemic, not causal, and is explicable in terms of being non‐evidence‐based, where this is distinct from being non‐inferential. Heil (1992) endorses the view that the notion of directness is epistemic, not causal. Gertler (2003) distinguishes two senses of ‘direct’ in ‘direct access’, one epistemic (what is here characterized as ‘non‐inferential’) and the other metaphysical (here characterized as ‘unmediated’). (5) Of course, according to higher‐order theories of consciousness this is not a confusion, since it is definitional that ‘conscious state’ means ‘mental state that one is aware of being in’. See, for example, Lycan (1996, 2003), who claims that ‘a state of a subject, or an event occurring within the subject, is a conscious state or event, as opposed to an unconscious or subconscious state or event, iff the subject is aware of being in the state or hosting the event’ (2003: 3). Higher‐order theories will be touched on briefly in Section 43.3. As Sosa (2003) notes, Ryle does have another main objection to the Cartesian model, which is that self‐knowledge does not always rest on introspection, but this, even if true, does not show that self‐knowledge does not sometimes rest on introspection, and this is all that the Cartesian model needs in order to be vindicated. (6) As he puts it: ‘Our knowledge of other people and ourselves depends upon our noticing how they and we behave’ (1949: 181). (7) Thus, McGeer says: The view I propose involves putting special emphasis on our own agency by recognizing that we are actors as well as observers and so can be good, even excellent, ‘predictors’ of our future behavior because we have the power to make these ‘predictions’ come true. Put simply, we are able to ensure a fit between the psychological profile we create of ourselves in first‐person utterances and the acts our self‐attributed intentional states are meant to predict and explain simply by adjusting our actions in appropriate ways. (1996: 507)

Page 26 of 30

Introspection (8) As Davidson puts it, ‘Ryle was wrong. It is seldom the case that I need or appeal to evidence or observation in order to find out what I believe; normally I know what I think before I speak or act. Even when I have evidence, I seldom make use of it’ (1987: 441). (9) Davidson typically couches this argument in terms that speak of presumptions of knowledge of meaning and the like, but, as the second of his arguments clearly indicates, there is more to the position than the presumption of authority. Here is a passage where the argument makes no use of it: An interpreter must discover, or correctly assume on the basis of indirect evidence, what the external factors are that determine the content of another's thought; but since these factors determine both the contents of one's thought and the contents of the thought one believes one has (these being the same thought), there is no room for error about the contents of one's own thought of the sort that can arise with respect to the thoughts of others. (1991: 196)

(10) It is not clear that this case shows that Burge's account is defective, unlike the example given in the paragraph immediately preceding this one. Burge (1998) has responded to it by maintaining that authoritative self‐knowledge does not extend to cases of discriminative knowledge, and this is particularly so where memory is involved: I have maintained that the individual may not know whether yesterday he had an aluminum or twaluminum thought. He does not have discriminative knowledge of this form. But memory need not work by discrimination; it can work through preservation. The memory need not set out to identify or pick out an aluminum rather than a twaluminum thought, trying to find one by working through the obstacles set by the switches. Preservative memory normally retains the content and attitude commitments of earlier thinkings, through causal connections to the past thinkings. That is one of its functions—maintaining and preserving a point of view over time. It need not take a past thought as an object of investigation, in need of discrimination from other thoughts. Memory need not use the form ‘Yesterday I was thinking a—type of thought’, where the memory attempts to identify the thought content as an object. Again, if it did, the individual might perhaps err by using a thought appropriate to the second environment in making an attribution to a thought event in the first environment. … The memory need not be about a past event or content at all. It can simply link the past thought to the present, by preserving it. (1998: 357)

Page 27 of 30

Introspection It might be thought that the example in the paragraph immediately preceding this in the text makes essential use of the notion of discriminative knowledge, since the authoritative status of the subject's self‐knowledge seems to be compromised by another's better knowledge, not only of the facts of chemistry, but also of Twin Earth and XYZ. But the point can be made equally effectively in terms of another's better knowledge of the facts of chemistry, without appeal to knowledge of Twin Earth.

(11) Thus, McDowell says: Short of the fully Cartesian picture, the infallibly knowable fact—its seeming to one that things are thus and so—can be taken disjunctively, as constituted either by the fact that things are manifestly thus and so or by the fact that that merely seems to be the case. On this account, the idea of things being thus and so figures straightforwardly in our understanding of the infallibly knowable appearance; there is no problem about how experience can be understood to have a representational directedness towards external reality. (1986: 150)

(12) Again, it might be claimed that authoritative self‐knowledge does not extend to cases of discriminative knowledge and that this counts as one such case (see n. 10), but then the point can be put in terms of another's better knowledge of the facts of biology, without appeal to knowledge of Twin Earth and pligers. (13) Chisholm gives as examples of ‘self‐presenting’ properties not just feeling sad, but thinking about a golden mountain, being appeared redly to, and believing oneself to be wise, where a self‐presenting property is defined as ‘a property which is such that, if while having it, you consider your having it, then you will believe yourself to have it’ (1981: 81). Further, ‘the foundation of our knowledge consists of certain subjective—or ‘Cartesian’—apprehensions'. (1981: 92). (14) Those who hold, with McDowell (1994), that perception itself is unmediated by an unconceptualized experiential state, but who hold that one's own perceptual states can be introspectively known in the observational way, will deny that there is this contrast but claim to be introspectionists with respect to self‐knowledge (see Langsam 2002). (15) Thus, Lycan says: ‘The inner‐sense theorist does not contend (at least neither Armstrong nor I contend) that internal monitoring is like external perception in every single respect. And in particular, we should not expect internal monitoring to share the property of involving some presented sensory quality at its own level of operation’ (1996: 28). (16) In a similar vein, Lycan (1996) responds to Shoemaker's analogous argument with regard to pain by distinguishing between a strong and a weak sense of ‘pain’ and insisting, against Shoemaker's claim that:

Page 28 of 30

Introspection at least certain kinds of pain behaviour … are intelligible as pain behaviour only on the assumption that the subject is aware of pain, for to see them as pain behaviour is to see them as motivated by such states of the creature as the belief that it is in pain, the desire to be rid of the pain, and the belief that such and such a course of behaviour will achieve that result (Shoemaker 1994: 274) that the weak sense is a legitimate one.

(17) Evans continues: If a judging subject applies this procedure, then necessarily he will gain knowledge of one of his own mental states: even the most determined sceptic cannot find here a gap in which to insert his knife. (1982: 225) This indicates that he takes at least some self‐knowledge to be infallible. But in fact he goes on to say that more is involved in knowing whether I believe that p than just following whatever procedure it takes to determine whether p. At the very least it involves possessing the concept of belief, as it applies not just to oneself but also to others. Still, he claims, this further requirement need not involve looking inward. Note that Evans does not endorse this model for self‐knowledge of experiences (1982: 226 ff.). Note also that, as in the case of at least some inner‐sense models, the appeal to perception and ‘looking inwards’ in the displaced‐perception account may be metaphorical (see n. 1). As the Evans quote in the text indicates, the key idea in the account seems to be that one comes to know what one thinks, believes, etc. not by appealing to any of one's inner states but by appealing to an outer state of the world, and this leaves it open whether the relevant state is one that is available to perception. Thanks here to John Williams.

(18) Thus, he says: Everyone (even externalists) assume, mistakenly, that what we know by introspection is not only (in the case of thought) what we think, the content of our current propositional attitude, but also that we think it, the fact that we occupy a mental state having this proposition as its content. If this assumption is false, if what we know by introspection is that it is pumpkins one is thinking (wondering, worrying, deciding) about without knowing, at least not in the same way, that one is thinking (wondering, worrying, or deciding) about pumpkins, then there is no threat to externalism. What the teleosemanticist says is constituted by external, historical, relations—the fact that one is mentally representing pumpkins—is not the fact that introspection yields: that it is pumpkins one is mentally representing. (Dretske 2006: 76)

(19) The distinction I am after can be captured by means of the distinction between seeing x and seeing that p. I can both see that the table is brown and see the table's

Page 29 of 30

Introspection brownness; but although I can see that the liquid before me is H20, I cannot see its ‘H20‐ ness’. Only the former counts as a case of direct epistemic access. (20) However, unlike Wright (1988, 1992), who holds that one's authority with respect to one's own states consists in the fact that subjects’ best opinions concerning those states fix the extensions of content types, the view I favour is that one's authority consists in the fact that one does not normally in reflection misidentify the object of one's reflection. Reflection is, in one respect at least, an appropriate characterization of the special relation that subjects’ second‐order thoughts bear to their first‐order ones. In physical reflection—say, in a mirror—under certain ideal conditions, the object is not normally misrepresented. So the object is as it appears to be. But the reflection does not determine the object to be what it is. Similarly, in mental reflection the reflecting thought does not determine the thought reflected upon to be what it is. (21) How might ‘aboutness’ or reference to the first‐order content be secured? Roughly, in the way suggested by Davidson's paratactic analysis of sentences involving indirect discourse (1969/2001). Suppose I think to myself I am currently thinking that water is transparent. This second‐order thought can be understood as a compression or abbreviation of something like: I am currently thinking a thought whose content is the same as the following: water is transparent. When I think this thought, I present my thought as having the same content as that of another current thought of mine, and I do this correctly if I am a samethinker with regard to these two thoughts (rather than a ‘samesayer’, as in Davidson's original suggestion). (22) I would like to thank Bill Lycan, Graham Macdonald, and participants at the 2005 Australian Association of Philosophy Conference, Dunedin, New Zealand, for comments on this chapter.

Cynthia Macdonald

Cynthia Macdonald, University of Manchester

Page 30 of 30

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge

Oxford Handbooks Online Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge   Jessica Brown The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0045

Abstract and Keywords The distinctive claim made by semantic externalism is that a subject's thought contents are partly individuated by her environment, and do not supervene on her ‘inner states’, such as her brain states. One of the main objections to this position is the claim that it is incompatible with self-knowledge. A subject's knowledge of her own thoughts seems quite different from her knowledge of what others think. A subject uses behavioural evidence to know what others think. However, typically, a subject can know what she herself thinks without inferring this from her own behaviour, and even prior to manifesting any behaviour which could constitute grounds for such an inference. Keywords: self-knowledge, semantic externalism, inner states, brain states, behavioural evidence, second-order thoughts

THE distinctive claim made by semantic externalism is that a subject's thought contents are partly individuated by her environment, and do not supervene on her ‘inner states’, such as her brain states. One of the main objections to this position is the claim that it is incompatible with self‐knowledge. A subject's knowledge of her own thoughts seems quite different from her knowledge of what others think. A subject uses behavioural evidence to know what others think. However, typically, a subject can know what she herself thinks without inferring this from her own behaviour, and even prior to manifesting any behaviour which could constitute grounds for such an inference. Exceptions may be provided by cases of self‐deception and the unconscious. However, for the most part a subject can have a priori knowledge of what she thinks (call this ‘privileged access’ for short). Since semantic externalism is a thesis about thought content, the threat it poses to privileged access specifically concerns a subject's knowledge of her thought contents, rather than her attitudes to those contents. There are two main ways to fill out that Page 1 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge threat: what Davies (1998) usefully distinguishes as the ‘achievement’ and ‘consequence’ problems. According to the achievement problem, semantic externalism makes it difficult for a subject to achieve privileged access. For instance, it has been argued that since semantic externalism claims that a subject's thought contents are partly individuated by her environment, a subject would need to use empirical information about her environment in order to know her thought contents. According to the consequence problem, the combination of semantic externalism (p. 768) and privileged access has absurd consequences. Both supporters and opponents of semantic externalism accept that it would be a serious objection to semantic externalism if it were incompatible with privileged access. Thus, semantic externalists have argued that semantic externalism is compatible with privileged access, whereas their opponents have argued for incompatibility.

44.1 The Achievement Problem The achievement problem can be vividly illustrated by the well‐known device of a slow‐ switch case (see Putnam 1975). In such a case a subject is switched between two different environments spending enough time in each that a semantic externalist would accept that the change in environments affects the subject's thought contents. Suppose that S is an ordinary earth subject who is ignorant of the chemical composition of water. In virtue of the facts that she interacts with samples of water and is part of a linguistic community some of whose members know the chemical composition of water, semantic externalists accept that S has the concept of water. For instance, she believes that water is wet. Now suppose that after many years on earth S is unwittingly switched to Putnam's Twin Earth, a planet which is an exact duplicate of earth except that the watery liquid there has the chemical composition, XYZ, and some Twin Earthians, but not S, know this. Semantic externalists would accept that the switch affects S's thought contents, say that S acquires a new concept, twater, and thus comes to think that twater is wet. Since it's part of the case that S is switched unwittingly between the planets, it may seem that, as a result of the switch, S may make a mistake about her thoughts. Perhaps, after the switch, she would take herself to believe that water is wet when she actually believes that twater is wet. Thus, semantic externalism may seem to threaten privileged access by undermining a subject's reliability about her thought contents. Alternatively, the incompatibilist may formulate her challenge using the notion of a discriminative capacity. Consider S on earth when she thinks that water is wet. Plausibly, without empirical investigation S cannot distinguish this situation from the alternative situation in which she is instead on Twin Earth thinking that twater is wet. For Twin Earth seems just like earth and water seems just like twater. But, then, it may be said, on earth S cannot know a priori that she thinks that water is wet for, without empirical information, she cannot distinguish the actual situation in which she thinks that water is wet from the alternative situation in which she is instead on Twin Earth thinking that twater is wet. These two Page 2 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge ways of putting the incompatibilist challenge reflect the intuitive connection of knowledge with, on the one hand, reliability and, on the other, discriminative abilities. We would deny that a subject has perceptual knowledge that the bird in front of her is a crow if she would mistake another common bird, say a rook, for a crow. Further, we would deny that a subject has perceptual knowledge that that bird is a crow if she cannot perceptually distinguish crows and rooks. (p. 769)

A certain compatibilist response to the achievement problem has become standard. According to this standard response, even if semantic externalism is true, a subject is reliable about her thought contents. Compatibilists point out that a subject's environment individuates not only her thoughts about the world (her ‘first‐order’ thoughts), for example the thought that water is wet, but also her thoughts about her thoughts (her ‘second‐order’ thoughts), for example the thought that she thinks that water is wet. So there could not be a mismatch between the concepts she uses at first and second order which could lead to her falsely judging that she thinks that twater is wet when, in fact, she thinks that water is wet. Some focus on the fact that certain second‐order thoughts are self‐verifying (Burge 1988; Heil 1988). Consider a second‐order thought of the form ‘I believe that I think that p’, where thinking that p is construed to mean entertaining the thought that p which one does when one has any propositional attitude to the content p, such as believing that p, desiring that p, or doubting that p. Such second‐order thoughts are self‐verifying: in believing that I think that p, I do entertain the content p, or think it. Thus, it is impossible to falsely believe that one thinks that p even in a slow switch. Others focus not on the logical properties of second‐order thoughts, but on the fact that second‐order thoughts result from a reliable causal process. In particular, they argue that the second‐order belief that one thinks that p is caused by the relevant first‐order thought (that p), which also helps determine the content of the second‐order belief (Gibbons 1996, 2001). Two concerns arise about whether the standard response fully answers the achievement problem. The first questions whether the extent of one's reliability about one's thoughts is sufficient to defend privileged access. The second questions whether reliability, however extensive, can answer the incompatibilist's concerns about discriminative abilities. First, consider the extent of a subject's reliability about her thoughts. Notice that a second‐ order thought is self‐verifying only if it ascribes a current thought. By contrast, a second‐ order belief that one thought that p in the past is not self‐verifying. Believing that I thought that p entails that I now think that p in the sense of entertaining the thought that p. However, it leaves it open whether I thought that p at the relevant earlier time. The problem of knowledge of past thoughts is exacerbated on certain externalist views which hold that, after a switch a subject loses certain concepts (e.g. Ludlow 1995b; Heal 1998; Tye 1998; though see Burge 1993 for a different view). For instance, on this view, once S has been switched to Twin Earth she gains the concept twater and loses the concept water. As a result, after the switch she no longer has the conceptual resources to think

Page 3 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge that water is wet, let alone know that she used to think this. On this view, a victim of a slow switch may be unable to have a priori knowledge of some of her past thought contents. Initially, it may seem that even if the standard response cannot be applied to show how semantic externalism is compatible with privileged access to past thoughts, this need not undermine its application to current thoughts. However, Boghossian (1989) argues that if semantic externalism undermines a subject's a priori knowledge of her past thoughts it also undermines her a priori knowledge of her current thoughts. If he were right, then the standard response would not merely have (p. 770) a restricted application, but would fail altogether. Boghossian's argument exploits what he calls a ‘platitude’ about memory: if S knows that p at t1, and if at (some later time) t2 S remembers everything S knew at t1, then S knows that p at t2. Let S be the subject of a slow switch so that t1 is a time before the switch at which S thinks that water is wet, and t2 is a time sufficiently after the switch for the switch to have affected S's thought contents. Boghossian says that we can stipulate that S forgets nothing between t1 and t2. Boghossian appeals to the stipulation and his ‘platitude’ to argue that if at t2 S does not know a priori that at t1 she thought that water is wet, then at t1 she did not know a priori that she thought that water is wet. In this way Boghossian seeks to extend a lack of privileged access to past thoughts to current thoughts also. However, even if we accept that, post switch, S cannot know a priori what she thought before the switch, we need not accept with Boghossian that this undermines S's ability to know a priori her current thoughts. If between t1 and t2 S loses the concepts required to think what she knew at t1, then at t2 she cannot know what she earlier knew. We may either see this as undermining Boghossian's stipulation that she forgets nothing between t1 and t2 (Brueckner 1997) or, leaving the stipulation in place, as undermining Boghossian's ‘platitude’ (Ludlow 1995b). Some argue that a subject's reliability about her thoughts is restricted in a different way, to her thought contents, rather than to her attitudes to those contents. Bernecker (1996) and Gibbons (2001) argue that Burgean semantic externalism makes it possible that a subject may suppose that she has an attitude to a content when she lacks that attitude. Burge accepts that a subject may have a concept despite incompletely understanding it. Applying this idea to attitude concepts, Gibbons and Bernecker suppose that a subject has the concept of belief while taking it to have a wider application than it in fact has. As a result, a subject may believe that she believes that p although, in fact, she does not believe that p. It seems, then, that the standard response to the achievement problem needs qualification: although a subject cannot falsely judge that she thinks that p, on some versions of semantic externalism a subject may falsely judge that she has a certain attitude to the content p and may be unable to recall some of her earlier thoughts. However, these caveats need not worry the compatibilist unduly. As long as the conditions which give rise to these mistakes are rare then, on a fallibilist conception of knowledge,

Page 4 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge these errors do not show that in general subjects lack privileged access to their present and past propositional attitudes. However, the standard response faces a second, and more serious, worry; namely, that it fails to fully answer that strand in the achievement problem which concerns discriminative abilities rather than reliability (Vahid 2003; Brown 2004: 33–73). The incompatibilist argued that S cannot know a priori that she thinks that water is wet since she cannot non‐empirically distinguish the actual situation in which she has this thought from the alternative in which she is on Twin Earth thinking that twater is wet. Stressing that a subject is reliable about her thought contents does not provide any obvious answer to this worry about discrimination. To answer this worry, the compatibilist needs to show either that S can non‐empirically distinguish the actual and twin situation, or that such an ability is not required for a priori knowledge (p. 771) of her thoughts. (Here I'm focusing on the impact of discriminative abilities on self‐knowledge; a distinct worry concerns their impact on reasoning; see Boghossian 1992; Goldberg 1997, 1999.) The first of these options seems unpromising and has been rejected by many prominent anti‐individualists (e.g. Burge 1988; Falvey and Owens 1994). It is part of the case that S is unaware of the switch in her environment and her thoughts. After the switch, on being asked, she would claim that she now expresses the same thought by ‘Water is wet’ as she used to many years ago. Even if told that she has been switched, but not when, she could not identify which thoughts involve the concept water and which involve the concept twater (Burge 1988; Goldberg 1997). It initially seems, then, that S cannot non‐ empirically distinguish water and twater thoughts. In response the compatibilist may suggest that there is a further test for having a discriminative ability which S can pass; namely, being able to act differentially with respect to the two kinds of thoughts. For instance, she may argue that although S reports her water and twater thoughts using the same word ‘water’, since ‘water’ has a different meaning on earth and Twin Earth S reports the relevant thoughts as having different contents. Alternatively, she may argue that S acts differentially with respect to water and twater thoughts when her actions are typed intentionally. For instance, a reaching which is caused by the desire for water would be typed as a reaching for water whereas a reaching which is caused by the desire for twater would be typed as a reaching for twater. However, on further consideration this compatibilist response fails. If a subject can distinguish two types of thing, then she can usually act differentially with respect to those types for a wide range of actions within her behavioural repertoire. However, there is a very large range of actions within S's behavioural repertoire that she cannot perform differentially with respect to water and twater thoughts. For example, suppose that before the switch we convince S of the truth of semantic externalism and forewarn her that she will be switched in such a way as to change the concept she expresses with ‘water’. However, we do not tell her when the switch will take place. We ask her to press a button when her thought contents change. It seems plausible that S will fail to pass this test even if we offer her a large reward, say one million pounds, for doing so. Similar arguments show that S cannot act differentially with respect to water and twater Page 5 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge thoughts by stamping her feet, clasping her hands, wiggling her ears, etc. In summary, S does not have the action abilities we would expect if she genuinely had the ability to distinguish the two types of thought (Brown 2004: 50–8). It seems, then, that the compatibilist should accept that S cannot non‐empirically distinguish water and twater thoughts. Instead, many hold that this ability is not required for S to have a priori knowledge of her thought contents (e.g. Burge 1988; Falvey and Owens 1994). However, there is little detailed argument for this view. (For an exception see Falvey and Owens 1994.) Further, certain difficulties face any attempt to show that knowledge requires only reliability and not discriminative abilities. A first problem is that these two phenomena typically go hand in hand so that it's hard to construct cases which show that knowledge requires one rather than the other. A second problem arises from the motivations for the reliabilist approach to (p. 772) knowledge, which holds that a true belief is knowledge if produced by a reliable process (Vahid 2003; Brown 2004: 45–8). Key proponents of this view motivate reliabilism by the idea that knowledge requires discriminative abilities (Goldman 1976, 1986; McGinn 1984). It seems hard, then, for a compatibilist to argue that S can non‐empirically distinguish water and twater thoughts, or that knowledge does not require discriminative abilities. An alternative potential defence of compatibilism attempts to finesse the issue of whether knowledge requires discriminative abilities or merely reliability by using the well‐known notion of a relevant alternative (see e.g. Goldman 1976). It's widely acknowledged that, on pain of scepticism, not all alternatives are knowledge‐undermining, but only those which are ‘relevant’ or ‘nearby’. Perhaps the compatibilist could argue that the possibility that one is in a twin scenario thinking a twin thought is not a relevant alternative? Since there is no Twin Earth, the possibility that one is on Twin Earth thinking twater thoughts does not seem relevant. However, there are more realistic examples of slow switches in which a subject is slowly switched between two linguistic groups in which a word has different meanings (Ludlow 1995a; Butler 1997). (For instance, ‘professor’ and ‘chip’ have different meanings in American and British English.) However, even if such examples succeed in showing that slow switches are sometimes relevant, this leaves space for a compatibilist to argue that they are not generally relevant (Warfield 1992; Sawyer 1999; Brown 2004). If that were so, then semantic externalism would be compatible with the claim that, typically, a subject can have a priori knowledge of her thoughts. In summary, there are a number of avenues for the compatibilist to explore to provide a full answer to the achievement problem. She may provide new arguments to show that knowledge requires only reliability and not discriminative abilities; alternatively she may argue that slow switches are not usually relevant. However, even if the compatibilist can solve the achievement problem, she still faces the consequence problem, according to which the joint assumptions of semantic externalism and privileged access have an absurd consequence and are thus incompatible.

Page 6 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge

44.2 The Consequence Problem According to privileged access, a subject can have a priori knowledge of her thought contents, for example that she thinks that water is wet. Incompatibilists argue that it follows from semantic externalism that there are a priori knowable entailments from thought to the environment; for example, that any subject who thinks that water is wet is in an environment which contains water. If that is right, a subject could combine her a priori knowledge of the relevant entailment with her a priori knowledge that she thinks that water is wet to gain the a priori knowledge that her environment contains water. But, incompatibilists say, that's absurd and so semantic externalism is incompatible with privileged access (McKinsey 1991; Brown 1995; Boghossian 1997). (p. 773)

There are three main ways for the compatibilist to reply to the consequence problem. First, she could accept that a subject can have a priori knowledge of her thought contents and of entailments from her thoughts to her environment but deny that she can thereby acquire a priori knowledge of her environment (the denial of ‘transmission’). Second, she could accept that a subject's a priori knowledge of her thoughts and the relevant entailments provide a priori knowledge of her environment but deny that such knowledge is problematic. Third, she could deny that it follows from semantic externalism that there are a priori knowable entailments from thought to the environment. I will examine each option in turn. (Since privileged access is an assumption for reductio, one cannot respond to the consequence problem by denying that a subject can have a priori knowledge of her thought contents.) According to the first response, even if a subject knows a priori that she thinks that water is wet and that if she thinks that water is wet then her environment contains water, she cannot combine these pieces of knowledge to gain by inference a priori knowledge that her environment contains water. In other words, the relevant inference is a counter‐ example to the principle of transmission for a priori knowledge, according to which if a subject knows a priori that p and she also knows a priori that p entails q, then she can know a priori that q by that inference (Davies 1998, 2000, 2003; McLaughlin 2000, 2003; Wright 2000, 2002, 2003). There are a number of problems with this first response. Some reject the claim that transmission fails across the relevant inference (Brewer 2000; Beebee 2001; Pritchard 2002; McLaughlin 2003; Brown 2003, 2004; Pryor 2004; Silins 2005). However, a more serious objection is that even if transmission does fail, this would not answer the consequence problem. Notice that the claim that transmission fails across the inference merely amounts to the claim that one cannot acquire a priori knowledge of the environment in one way (namely via the target inference); it leaves it open whether one has that a priori knowledge on some other basis. But plausibly the alleged absurdity consists merely in the idea that one could have a priori knowledge that one's environment Page 7 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge contains water, however this knowledge is supposedly acquired (Brown 2003; McKinsey 2003). In that case, denying that one could acquire the a priori knowledge in one way, namely via the inference, would not answer the consequence problem. For it would leave it open that one has the a priori knowledge in some other way. We may put the point more formally using the principle of closure. According to closure for a priori knowledge, if S knows a priori that p, and she knows a priori that p entails q, then she can know a priori that q, where it is left unspecified whether she knows that q via the inference, or independently of that inference. Closure is weaker than transmission and may hold even if transmission fails. Even if one cannot know a priori that q via inference from one's a priori knowledge that p and that p entails q, one may have a priori knowledge that q on some other basis. Indeed, on one prominent account of the failure of transmission, whenever transmission fails, closure holds (Wright 2002). Assuming closure for a priori knowledge, if one knows a priori that one thinks that water is wet, and that one's thinking that water is wet entails that one's environment contains water, then (p. 774) one can know a priori that one's environment contains water. On the assumption that it's absurd to suppose that one has a priori knowledge that one's environment contains water however acquired, then semantic externalism and privileged access are incompatible. It seems, then, that the consequence problem relies only on closure for a priori knowledge. So the problem is not resolved by arguing that the relevant inference is a counter‐ example to transmission. Given the failure of the first response to the consequence problem, let us turn to the second. The second response defends the compatibility of semantic externalism and privileged access by arguing that it's not absurd that a subject could have a priori knowledge of her environment. One way to support this claim would be by performing a modus ponens on the incompatibilist's modus tollens. The incompatibilist argues that since it is absurd that one could have a priori knowledge of one's environment, semantic externalism and privileged access are incompatible. Some compatibilists counter that since semantic externalism and privileged access are both true, it follows that one can have a priori knowledge of one's environment. That one can have such knowledge is just an epistemic consequence of the metaphysical theory of semantic externalism (Sawyer 1998; Warfield 1998). However, the compatibilist modus ponens is unlikely to convince the incompatibilist. Compatibilists would be better served by a defence which goes beyond such a modus ponens. Some have tried to undermine the alleged absurdity of a priori knowledge of one's environment by drawing attention to the conditions for having the concept water. Some externalists suggest that a subject who meets the conditions for having the concept water would thereby already know her environment contains water (Sawyer 1998; Brewer 2000). For instance, if she acquires the concept by interacting with water, say by drinking it or washing in it, she would thereby acquire the empirical knowledge that her environment contains water. If that's right, then there's no danger that a subject could combine her a priori knowledge of her thoughts and externalism to gain new knowledge about her environment. Rather, in order to think with the concept water and know that she thinks that water is wet, she would already have empirical knowledge that her Page 8 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge environment contains water. However, this line of thought does not resolve the consequence problem. The alleged absurdity in supposing that a subject has one kind of knowledge, a priori knowledge, of some environmental fact seems in no way lessened by supposing that she has some other kind of knowledge, empirical knowledge, of that same fact (Davies 2000). A different way of casting doubt on the alleged absurdity of the claim that a subject can have a priori knowledge of her environment is to suggest that the relevant knowledge is, in a certain sense, weak. Say that knowledge is ‘weakly’ a priori if that knowledge is warranted otherwise than on the basis of empirical evidence, and ‘strongly’ a priori if, in addition, it is empirically indefeasible (McLaughlin 2000). If one's knowledge of one's thoughts and the entailments from thought to the world is strongly a priori, then one's knowledge of the relevant environmental conditions would also be strongly a priori. It does indeed seem implausible that one could have strongly a priori knowledge that one's environment contains water, that is knowledge indefeasible by empirical evidence. However, if one's a priori knowledge of either (p. 775) one's thoughts or the entailments from thought to the world is weak, then one's a priori knowledge that the relevant environmental condition obtains would also be weak. Understood in this way, would knowledge of one's environment be any less absurd? It seems not. For it remains problematic that one could know, say, that one's environment contains water without basing that knowledge on any empirical evidence. One's allegedly problematic knowledge of the environment might be construed as weak in the different sense that it has only a low level of epistemic support. Contextualism offers one model of how one may be in a very weak epistemic position with respect to the relevant knowledge (DeRose 2000; Hohwy 2002). Contextualists allow that one can know a proposition while having no evidence or argument for it in contexts in which its negation is not contextually relevant. For instance, Lewis suggests that in ordinary contexts one can know that one is not a brain in a vat merely by supposing that one is not. However, one's epistemic position with respect to this proposition is very weak, so weak that as soon as the sceptic mentions the possibility that one is a brain in a vat one's knowledge disappears. Perhaps the kind of knowledge at issue in the consequence problem could be viewed in this way. The idea, then, would be that in the context of semantic externalism we presuppose certain claims about our environment, claims which are entailed by our having the thoughts we take ourselves to have. Ordinarily such presuppositions amount to a priori knowledge, but knowledge so weak it would disappear in a context in which the possibility that these conditions do not obtain becomes relevant. Although contextualism is controversial, we can separate from that view the idea that our a priori knowledge of the relevant environmental conditions amounts to a presupposition that those conditions obtain, a presupposition that we can legitimately make so long as the possibility that they do not obtain is not relevant. If our a priori knowledge of environmental conditions is understood in this very weak way, perhaps it is less problematic.

Page 9 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge It may be, then, that this last way of filling out the second response could be developed to show that it is not absurd that one have a priori knowledge of one's environment. However, one would not need to defend the possibility of such a priori knowledge if the consequence problem could be stopped at an earlier stage. This is precisely what the third response attempts to do. The third response denies that it follows from semantic externalism that there are a priori knowable entailments from thought to the world. A first concern is whether semantic externalism establishes any entailments from thought to the world, whether a priori knowable or not (Brueckner 1992; Gallois and O'Leary‐ Hawthorne 1996: 11–12). The standard Twin Earth thought‐experiments most obviously establish a counterfactual dependence of thought on the world. For instance, Putnam's thought‐experiment most obviously shows that Oscar who is actually on earth with the concept of water would instead have had the concept of twater if he had counterfactually been brought up on Twin Earth. This counterfactual claim does not entail that it is a necessary condition for having the concept of water that one's environment now contains water, or used to contain water (I leave the second disjunct implicit in what follows). (p. 776)

In fact, further consideration shows that semantic externalism does establish entailments from thought to the world. However, the difficulty for incompatibilists has been to show that a subject could have the a priori knowledge of these entailments required by the consequence problem. To illustrate this consider Putnamian semantic externalism. Let us set aside chemically knowledgeable subjects who, as semantic externalists accept, can have the concept of water in a waterless world. Instead, let us consider a subject who has no idea what the chemical composition of water is. Semantic externalists accept that such a subject may have the concept of water in an environment which contains water and/or if she is part of a linguistic community with the concept of water. However, it's hard to see how such a subject could have the concept of water if she were instead in an environment without water or other speakers. What would determine that she has a concept which applies to all and only H2O? So semantic externalism establishes the following principle: (A) If S has the concept of a natural kind and is ignorant of its fundamental properties, then either she is in an environment which contains instances of that kind, or she is part of a linguistic community with the concept of that kind (Brown 1995).

Page 10 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge To use (A) to gain a priori knowledge of a specific entailment between her thought and empirical facts about the world, a subject needs a priori knowledge that she has the concept of a natural kind. However, such knowledge is not available. It is an empirical matter whether a term which is intended to name a natural kind actually does so. A term intended to name a natural kind may fail to do so because the exemplars form a heterogeneous motley of several natural kinds (e.g. ‘jade’) or, more radically, because we were mistaken in thinking that there are such exemplars (Gallois and O'Leary‐Hawthorne 1996: 6–7; Boghossian 1997: 168; McLaughlin and Tye 1998). Nor does it help if, as Boghossian (1997) suggests, principle (A) is reformulated to concern the notion of a term which is intended to name a natural kind. A subject can infer no fact about her environment from the fact that she has a term which is intended to name a natural kind unless she also knows that it is not the case that the relevant term fails to name a natural kind. But a subject cannot know a priori that that's so, regardless of whether, in such a situation, the term would express no concept, or express a concept different from that which it expresses when it does name a natural kind. (For discussion of these options see Boghossian 1997; Brown 2004.) If a subject intends a term to name a natural kind but it fails to do so then she would still believe that it's not the case that it fails to name a natural kind. So even if she believes correctly that a term does not fail to name a natural kind, this belief does not constitute a priori knowledge.

Incompatibilists may hope to avoid these problems by targeting the consequence problem not just at natural‐kind concepts, but, rather, a broader range of concepts (Brown 2001, 2004: 300–1). To set up this broadening, notice that any concept whatsoever is partly individuated by its application conditions. For instance, the natural‐kind concept water is partly individuated by the fact that it applies to all and only (p. 777) H2O. The non‐ natural‐kind concept sofa is partly individuated by the fact that it does not apply to large armchairs. Semantic externalists accept that a subject can have a concept even if she is ignorant of its application conditions or, as Burge puts it (1979), if she ‘incompletely understands’ it. One kind of incomplete understanding is misunderstanding where a subject has a mistaken view about the kinds of thing to which a concept applies. For instance, Burge's arthritis patient mistakenly thinks that arthritis applies to problems of the thighs. A different kind of incomplete understanding is agnosticism where a subject is unsure whether a concept applies to a certain kind of thing where there is a determinate fact about whether the concept does, or does not, apply to that kind of thing (Burge 1979: 77). Note that merely being unsure about whether a concept applies to certain types of thing need not amount to being agnostic about it in the sense defined, since there may be no fact of the matter whether the concept applies to the relevant type of thing or not; in that case, the subject would not incompletely understand the concept. Semantic externalists accept that a subject who incompletely understands a concept in either of these senses may possess that concept if she is part of a linguistic community with that concept and/or, in the case of natural‐kind concepts, if her environment contains instances of the relevant kind. However, it seems hard to understand how a subject could have a concept despite incompletely understanding it unless her environment aids her in one of these two ways. Thus, (B) If S has a concept despite incompletely understanding it, then either she is part of a linguistic community with that concept or, in the case of a natural kind concept, she is in an environment which contains instances of the relevant kind (Brown 2001).

Page 11 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge A subject could use (B) to gain a priori knowledge of a specific entailment between her thoughts and the world only if she knows a priori that she has a concept despite incompletely understanding it. However, a subject cannot know a priori that she misunderstands a concept. For she would need empirical information about linguistic usage to know that she has an incorrect view of how the concept is applied. Further, a subject cannot know a priori that she is agnostic about a concept. A subject is agnostic about a concept when she is unsure whether it applies to things of a certain kind when there is a determinate fact about whether or not it applies to things of that kind. While a subject may know a priori that she is unsure whether the concept applies to things of a certain kind, she cannot know a priori that there is a determinate fact about whether it applies to things of that kind as opposed, say, to her mistakenly thinking that there is such a determinate fact (Brueckner 2002; Brown 2004). On the semantic‐externalist view defended by Burge, incomplete understanding of concepts is rife, where such incomplete understanding may include thinking that there is a determinate fact about whether a concept applies to things of a certain kind, even though there is not.

In conclusion, the consequence problem fails to show that semantic externalism is incompatible with privileged access. For it does not follow from semantic externalism that there are a priori knowable entailments from thought to the environment which (p. 778) a subject could use to gain a priori knowledge of her environment. Earlier we saw that there are several potential ways for a compatibilist to answer the achievement problem, either by showing that knowledge requires only reliability and not discriminative abilities, or by showing that twin thoughts are not relevant. If such lines of thought can be fruitfully developed, then semantic externalism would not, after all, be incompatible with privileged access.

References Beebee, H. (2001), ‘Transfer of Warrant, Begging the Question and Semantic Externalism’, Philosophical Quarterly, 51: 356–74. Bernecker, S. (1996), ‘Externalism and the Attitudinal Component of Self‐knowledge’, Noûs, 30: 262–75. Boghossian, P. (1989), ‘Content and Self‐knowledge’, Philosophical Topics, 17: 5–26. —— (1992), ‘Externalism and Inference’, Philosophical Issues, 2: 1–28. —— (1997), ‘What the Externalist Can Know A Priori’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 97: 161–75. Brewer, B. (2000), ‘Externalism and A Priori Knowledge of Empirical Facts’, in P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 415–32. Brown, J. (1995), ‘The Incompatibility of Anti‐individualism and Privileged Access’, Analysis, 53: 149–56. —— (2001), ‘Anti‐individualism and Agnosticism’, Analysis, 61: 213–24. Page 12 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge —— (2003), ‘The Reductio Argument and Transmission of Warrant’, in S. Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism, Scepticism, and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: CSLI), 117–30. —— (2004), Anti‐individualism and Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Brueckner, A. (1992), ‘Semantic Answers to Scepticism’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73: 200–19. —— (1997), ‘Externalism and Memory’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78: 1–12. —— (2002), ‘Anti‐individualism and Analyticity’, Analysis, 62: 87–91. Burge, T. (1979), ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73– 121. —— (1988), ‘Individualism and Self‐knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy, 85: 649–63. —— (1993), ‘Content Preservation’, Philosophical Review, 102: 457–88. Butler, K. (1997), ‘Externalism, Internalism and Knowledge of Content’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57: 773–800. Davies, M. (1998), ‘Externalism, Architecturalism, and Epistemic Warrant’, in C. Wright, B. C. Smith, and C. Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 321–61. —— (2000), ‘Externalism and A Priori Knowledge’, in P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 384–432. —— (2003), ‘The Problem of Armchair Knowledge’, in S. Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism, Scepticism, and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: CSLI), 23–57. DeRose, K. (2000), ‘How Can We Know that We're Not Brains in Vats?’ Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl. vol. 37: 121–38. Falvey, K., and Owens, J. (1994), ‘Externalism, self‐knowledge, and scepticism’, Philosophical Review, 103: 107–37. Gallois, A., and O'Leary‐Hawthorne, J. (1996), ‘Externalism and Scepticism’, Philosophical Studies, 81: 1–26. (p. 779)

Gibbons, J. (1996), ‘Externalism and Knowledge of Content’, Philosophical Review, 105: 287–310. —— (2001), ‘Externalism and Knowledge of the Attitudes’, Philosophical Quarterly, 51: 13–28.

Page 13 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge Goldberg, S. (1997), ‘Self‐ascription, Self‐knowledge, and the Memory Argument’, Analysis, 57: 211–19. —— (1999), ‘The Relevance of Discriminatory Knowledge of Content’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 80: 136–56. Goldman, A. (1976), ‘Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy, 73: 771–91. —— (1986), Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press). Heal, J. (1998), ‘Externalism and memory’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 77: 95–110. Heil, J. (1988), ‘Privileged Access’, Mind, 97: 238–51. Hohwy, J. (2002), ‘Privileged Self‐knowledge and Externalism: A Contextualist Approach’, Philosophical Quarterly, 83: 235–52. Ludlow, P. (1995a), ‘Externalism, Self‐knowledge, and the Prevalence of Slow Switching’, Analysis, 55: 45–9. —— (1995b), ‘Social Externalism, Self‐knowledge and Memory’, Analysis, 55: 157–9. McGinn, C. (1984), ‘The Concept of Knowledge’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9: 529– 54. McKinsey, M. (1991), ‘Anti‐individualism and Privileged Access’, Analysis, 51: 9–16. —— (2003), ‘Transmission of Warrant and Closure of Apriority’, in S. Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism, Scepticism, and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: CSLI), 97–116. McLaughlin, B. (2000), ‘Self‐knowledge, Externalism, and Scepticism’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 74: 93–117. —— (2003), ‘McKinsey's Challenge, Warrant Transmission and Scepticism’, in S. Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism, Scepticism, and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: CSLI), 79–96. McLaughlin, B., and Tye, M. (1998), ‘Content Externalism and Privileged Access’, Philosophical Review, 107: 349–80. Pritchard, D. (2002), ‘McKinsey Paradoxes, Radical Scepticism, and Transmission of Knowledge Across Known Entailments’, Synthese, 130: 279–302. Pryor, J. (2004), ‘Is Moore's Argument an Example of Transmission Failure?’, Philosophical Issues, 14: 349–78.

Page 14 of 16

Semantic Externalism and Self‐Knowledge Putnam, H. (1975), ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge (Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press), 131–93. Sawyer, S. (1998), ‘Privileged Access to the World’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76: 523–33. —— (1999), ‘An Externalist Account of Introspective Knowledge’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 80: 358–78. Silins, N. (2005), ‘Transmission Failure Failure’, Philosophical Studies, 126: 71–102. Tye, M. (1998), ‘Externalism and Memory’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 72: 77–94. Vahid, H. (2003), ‘Externalism, Slow Switching and Privileged Self‐knowledge’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66: 370–88. Warfield, T. (1992), ‘Privileged Self‐knowledge and Externalism are Compatible’, Analysis, 52: 232–7. —— (1998), ‘A Priori Knowledge of the World: Knowing the World by Knowing our Minds’, Philosophical Studies, 92: 127–47. Wright, C. (2000), ‘Cogency and Question‐begging: Some Reflections on McKinsey's Paradox, and Putnam's Proof’, Philosophical Issues, 10: 140–63. (p. 780)

—— (2002), ‘Anti‐sceptics Simple and Subtle: Moore and McDowell’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 330–48. —— (2003), ‘Some Reflections on the Acquisition of Warrant by Inference’, in S. Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism, Scepticism, and Self‐Knowledge (Cambridge, Mass.: CSLI), 57–78.

Jessica Brown

Jessica Brown: Professor in Arché Philosophical Research Center for Logic, Language, Metaphysics and Epistemology, Philosophy Departments, The University of St Andrews, Edgecliffe, The Scores, St Andrews, KY16 9AL. UNITED KINGDOM. Email: jab30@st‐andrews.ac.uk

Page 15 of 16

Self‐Deception

Oxford Handbooks Online Self‐Deception   Kent Bach The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind Online Publication Date: Sep 2009 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0046

Abstract and Keywords Is self-deception really a matter of deliberately getting oneself to believe something contrary to something else one already believes and, if so, how can one succeed at it? Colloquial phrases for it, like ‘fooling yourself’ and ‘lying to yourself’, evoke paradox. Although this article stresses the more recent philosophical work on the subject, most work on self-deception has focused on this paradox and sought ways to clear the air of it. The article focuses on the puzzles and questions of contemporary philosophical interest. Keywords: self-deception, contemporary philosophy, irrationality, lying model, epistemic support, intentional action

Nothing is so easy as to deceive oneself; for what we wish, we readily believe. Demosthenes (384–22 BC) SOMETIMES we have to face facts we'd just as soon ignore, give up on hopes that once seemed realistic, and accept unpleasant surprises. We all experience rude awakenings. When something disappointing or even shocking transpires, sooner or later we adjust—but not always. There are times when we respond differently and put our heads in the sand. In the language of pop psychology, we are unable to ‘face up’ to things that are ‘too painful to deal with’ and ‘go into denial’. Sometimes just the opposite occurs: we can't stop dwelling on some terrible possibility and, as a result, we're convinced it's for real. Naturally it's easier to see these tendencies in others than in ourselves. Their thinking on some matter strikes us as biased, distorted, or clouded by how they would like things to be or how they fear things are. They seem irrational, and their irrationality seems motivated.

Irrationality can occur without being motivated, as shown by the widespread biases, flaws, and errors in human reasoning identified by cognitive psychologists, but motivation or emotion can surely add to it. Your rational abilities can be affected by the sudden death of a loved one or the unexpected news that you have cancer. So it should not seem puzzling that grief and dread, or other powerful emotions like rage and panic, can disrupt Page 1 of 19

Self‐Deception normal thinking. Our concern, though, is with something less extreme. Self‐deception is of special interest, and puzzling, partly because it does not disrupt one's overall rational faculties and, if anything, exploits them. When we spot instances of it, we wonder how even intelligent people can come to believe things for reasons that do not begin to support these beliefs, and how can they fail to believe things for which the evidence is obvious and compelling. How can normal people's thinking, though usually fairly responsive to rational and evidential considerations, (p. 782) be distorted by motivational factors in regard to particular subjects? The self‐deceiver seems aware of the relevant evidence and of its import, but manages to resist it somehow. We think they ‘should know better’. The main philosophical question asked about this phenomenon is prompted by its very name. Is self‐deception really a matter of deliberately getting oneself to believe something contrary to something else one already believes and, if so, how can one succeed at it? Colloquial phrases for it, like ‘fooling yourself’ and ‘lying to yourself’, evoke paradox. Although our discussion will stress the more recent philosophical work on the subject (see Mele 1987 for a survey of work up to that time), most work on self‐ deception has focused on this paradox and sought ways to clear the air of it. Space limitations preclude taking up the scattered remarks made about self‐deception (or relevant to it) by such diverse thinkers as Plato, Aristotle, Butler, Hume, Kierkegaard, Marx, Nietzsche, and Sartre, and possible connections between self‐deception and the various ‘defence mechanisms’ proposed by Freud, such as denial, repression, projection, and reaction formation. We will focus on the puzzles and questions of contemporary philosophical interest.

Page 2 of 19

Self‐Deception

45.1 The Lying Model An insensitive boss thinks his employees like and respect him, a mediocre young artist thinks his work is too subtle to be appreciated by the art market, an abused wife thinks her husband won't beat her again, an alcoholic thinks he takes but ‘a little nip now and then’, the mother of an obvious murder suspect thinks ‘there must be some mistake’. With appropriate details filled in, these would all be typical cases of self‐deception. Self‐deception is commonly described as ‘lying to oneself’. That is how Raphael Demos (1960) thought of it when he introduced the subject into the journals under that very description. The ‘lying’ model, as we'll call it, portrays the self‐deceiver as believing a certain thing, generally something he wishes were not so, and as motivated to get himself to believe otherwise, which he does deliberately. However, he does not change his mind, at least not in the usual way of replacing one belief with a contrary one. Rather, he adds the contrary belief to his stock of beliefs, and does so in the face of evidence that is inadequate by his own standards. Meanwhile, the original belief retains its epistemic support and may continue to play a role in his overall thinking, though of course not consciously, since presumably he would disavow it. It might seem, then, that the self‐ deceiver thinks something that is contrary to what he believes ‘deep down’, and that he is aware, at least ‘at some level’, of what he is doing in getting himself to believe something else. Just as we say the akratic agent acts ‘against his better judgement’, so the self‐ deceiver thinks against his. Like other words ending in ‘‐tion’, the word ‘self‐deception’ exhibits a process– product ambiguity. It can refer to either the process of deceiving oneself or to the state of being self‐deceived. Both seem paradoxical on the lying model. It represents (p. 783) the product of self‐deception, being self‐deceived, as holding contradictory beliefs at the same time (at least temporarily) and the process that leads to it, deceiving oneself, as driven by an intention to form a belief that conflicts with a belief one already has. However, if one were aware that one had such an intention, one could not carry it out. No wonder paradox looms, never mind psychological implausibility. It was no surprise that shortly after being endorsed by Demos the lying model was forcefully challenged (Canfield and McNally 1961; Siegler 1962, 1963). The lying model is paradoxical precisely because it views self‐deception on the model of deceiving someone else. When you lie to someone, you tell them something that you yourself do not believe, with the aim of getting them to believe it. (It is convenient to assume that a lie—or a self‐deception—must be false, but what really matters is not its truth‐value but that the liar disbelieve or at least doubt it.) Assuming you don't provide any tell‐tale evidence of your deceitfulness, your deception can succeed if they find you trustworthy and find what you tell them credible. There's nothing puzzling about what happens in deceiving another, because the deceiver and the deceived are two different

Page 3 of 19

Self‐Deception people. But how can one deceive oneself in this way? How can you lie to yourself and succeed? Presumably the self‐deceiver's intention must be conscious if it is to be carried out. But how, in so far as the self‐deceiver is aware of what he's doing, could he keep from thwarting it in the course of trying to carry it out? It is important to appreciate that the trouble with the lying model isn't merely that it has the self‐deceiver being both agent and patient. After all, there's nothing puzzling about feeding oneself or washing oneself. Deceiving oneself seems puzzling more in the way that fighting oneself or carrying oneself might seem puzzling, at least until we notice that what we call ‘fighting oneself’ and ‘carrying yourself’ are not the same sorts of things as we do when we fight or carry someone else. More apt is the case of informing oneself. When you inform someone else of something, you provide them with information you already have. However, informing yourself can't be like that. You seek out and acquire information that you don't already have. Similarly, perhaps, deceiving yourself is not like deceiving someone else.

Page 4 of 19

Self‐Deception

45.2 Intentionalist Alternatives Even if the lying model takes the phrase ‘self‐deception’ too literally, deceiving oneself could still be an intentional action. Any view that it is would have the virtue of distinguishing it from such other processes as denial, repression, and mere wishful thinking. But what sort of intentional action could it be? Not just any way of causing oneself to be deceived qualifies as self‐deception. For example, one could leave faulty evidence around with the aim of later forgetting that one did so. That would be to mislead oneself intentionally but, as Brian McLaughlin points out, it would not be a case of self‐ deception properly so called (1988: 39–45). Mark Johnston makes a similar point against what he calls the ‘time‐lag theory’, insisting that self‐deception (p. 784) is more direct than that theory suggests (1988: 76–8). Self‐deception doesn't seem to involve explicit practical reasoning, much less deliberate scheming. Still, it seems to be intentional. One idea is that the self‐deceiver's intention is unconscious. This would explain why he disavows what he's doing, but that explanation seems ad hoc at best. Or one might adopt a compartmental or even homunculus model. Here the idea is to avoid paradox by claiming that the two beliefs are segregated or partitioned, perhaps one confined to the unconscious or each belonging to a different subperson. The strategy, of course, is to dissociate the victim from the intending agent, so as to avoid representing either as inconsistent or irrational. It is true that people sometimes say that ‘part of me’ thinks this and ‘part of me’ thinks that, but it is hard to take such language literally. However, such ideas generate mysteries of their own. Besides, as Johnston points out, if self‐deception really were a matter of one subperson deceiving another, as on the homunculus model, its motivation would be a mystery. For even if there were identifiable subpersons of the required sorts—a culprit and a victim—why would one's deceiving the other even be relevant to the person's being deceived? We can grant that ‘as a result of his own activity [the self‐deceiver] gets into a state in which he is misled, at least at the level of conscious belief’ without accepting the presupposition, which generates the paradox of self‐ deception, that this is the ‘reflexive case of lying’ (Johnston 1988: 65). Johnston warns against the tendency of theorists to ‘over‐rationalize mental processes that are purposive but not intentional’ (1988: 65). Perhaps we deem intentional the self‐ deception we observe in others (not in ourselves, of course) merely because it is purposeful and so obviously motivated, but to deny that self‐deception is intentional is not to deny that it is motivated or even that it involves an active effort, albeit not a deliberate one (see Bach 1981: 365–8). To be sure, one could maintain that the lying model accurately captures the concept of self‐deception but deny that there are any actual instances of it. That is, one might claim that the term ‘self‐deception’ is a misnomer for something else. Alternatively, one could give up on the lying model but keep on using the term for the phenomenon in question, whatever it is (assuming there aren't various phenomena that go by the same name). One could try to account for the reference of the term extensionally, by generalizing from features of typical cases to which we apply the Page 5 of 19

Self‐Deception term and seeking an account that rings true psychologically and does not give rise to paradox. That would be preferable to an account on which the questions ‘What is self‐ deception?’ and ‘How is it possible?’ do not have compatible answers.

45.3 Deflationary Approaches Much of the fog shrouding the subject of self‐deception might be lifted once we give up the assumptions that at least at some point in the process of deceiving oneself one must harbour two conflicting beliefs simultaneously and be acting intentionally to be (p. 785) acting purposively. But if the self‐deceiver isn't acting intentionally, what is he doing, and how does he manage to do it? Let's first take up the question of ends and then address the question of means. According to the first deflationary approach to be sketched (it is a rough composite of Bach 1981, Johnston 1988, Whisner 1993, and Hales 1994), the key to understanding self‐ deception is appreciating the role of attention and inattention. In typical cases (atypical ones will be taken up in the next section) the self‐deceiver is afraid to face up to some troubling truth (or at least warranted proposition), call it q. His current conscious thoughts do not reflect the fact that he believes that q or at least recognizes the force of the evidence for q. However, he need not believe something else to the contrary (call it the proposition that p), much less get himself to do so. Being self‐deceived that p doesn't require believing that p but merely thinking as if one did. This is the functional equivalent of believing that p, but only so far as one's current conscious thoughts (and utterances) are concerned. Normally, if one believes that p then whenever the question whether p arises or the thought of p occurs one is disposed to think that p, affirmatively and immediately. When one is self‐deceived that p one has that disposition even if one does not believe that p. Moreover, since the self‐deceiver does not consciously think as if he believed the unpleasant truth that q, the belief that is being resisted, this belief is prevented from playing its full functional role, and, even if he believes that q, he resists the disposition to think that q when the question of q arises or the thought of q occurs. (Philosophers sometimes distinguish ‘occurrent’ belief from ‘dispositional’ belief, but that seems to be just a misleading way of distinguishing between affirmatively thinking something at the moment and actually holding the belief.) The same ideas can be put without the p's and q's. Whereas a belief about something normally causes one to think the very thing one believes (when the subject comes up), this is not what happens in self‐deception. Rather than adopt a new, contrary belief, what the self‐deceiver does is keep himself, at least on a sustained and recurrent basis, from thinking what he believes (or would otherwise believe). No contrary belief is needed to suppress or inhibit the effect that the unpleasant belief normally has on his thinking. It is enough for the self‐deceiver to clutter his mind with contrary thoughts. In that way the truth of the warranted belief is kept from being settled for him.

Page 6 of 19

Self‐Deception It is instructive to compare this deflationary view with an ostensibly different approach taken by Georges Rey (1988). He thinks that the self‐deceiver does hold a pair of contradictory beliefs but only in an attenuated way. Rey does not suppose, as the orthodox view does, that the self‐deceiver has two fully‐fledged but conflicting beliefs. Rather, the two beliefs are of distinct kinds, playing distinct psychological roles. The unwarranted belief is a ‘central belief’ and the self‐deceptive belief is an ‘avowed belief’. A central belief is a functional state that tends to play a certain role in reasoning (and in action), whereas an avowed belief is, as the name suggests, what one (sincerely) admits to believing. Ordinarily, what one centrally believes and what one avowedly believes are the same, but in self‐deception the two pull apart. (p. 786)

The obvious objection to Rey's view is that avowed belief is not really a kind of belief, just as counterfeit money is not really money. People don't always believe what they sincerely avow; a belief does not have to be possessed to be sincerely expressed. It is enough that the self‐deceiver seem to have it, and from his own point of view avowing it is the way of seeming to have it. If the proposition that p is what he is deceiving himself about, it is enough that he think that p whenever the thought of p occurs to him. The self‐deceiver's ‘avowed belief’ that p is his thought that p and what he would sincerely avow to others as his belief, but not what he actually believes. After all, this is what we mean when we describe a self‐deceiver as refusing to admit or to face up to something; we are accusing him of disavowing a belief and avowing something else. Avowal plays a role in other accounts of self‐deception as well. For example, Robert Audi, who distinguishes the state of being self‐deceived from the act of deceiving oneself, claims that someone who is self‐deceived that p must sincerely avow that p, or at least be disposed to sincerely avow it (1988: 94). Audi requires further that the self‐deceiver unconsciously know (or at least believe) that not‐p. Brian McLaughlin agrees with Audi that self‐deception involves an unconscious or, as he calls it, an ‘inaccessible’ belief (1988: 48–53). However, it seems that the suppressed belief can't be ‘too’ unconscious or inaccessible for, as Allen Wood has observed, in cases of self‐deception (as opposed to traumatic repression, for example), ‘the psychically upsetting awareness is dangerously close at hand’ (1988: 359). It is tempting to indulge in Freudian metaphors here and say that the suppressed belief, assuming that being self‐deceived involves having one, must be relatively ‘near the surface’ rather than ‘deep in one's unconscious’, and threaten to become conscious. This language can be avoided by capturing Wood's observation dispositionally: being self‐deceived involves a disposition both to resist consciously thinking something that one believes (or at least takes there to be strong evidence for and normally would believe) and to affirmatively think something contrary to that proposition. Indeed, in so far as having this self‐deceptive thought keeps one from thinking the suppressed one, this is really just one disposition.

Page 7 of 19

Self‐Deception What does it take to exercise that disposition? That is, what keeps one from affirmatively thinking the nasty thought about the touchy subject? One obvious technique is rationalization, the process of fabricating plausible but phoney reasons for rejecting the warranted proposition and for buying into the preferred alternative. Rationalization can both get one into the state of being self‐deceived and, when the touchy subject comes up, keep one in that state. Rationalization is not the only technique for keeping a nasty thought from occurring or for suppressing it when it does occur. Johnston (1988), McLaughlin (1988), and I (Bach 1981) have each identified others. One technique is evasion; that is, diverting one's attention from the troublesome subject and focusing it elsewhere, with one's imagination supplying alluring possibilities. Even though one appreciates the weight of the evidence, one avoids the implications of that evidence by thinking about other things. Evasion, in the form of changing the subject, is especially effective in interpersonal contexts. (p. 787)

Another technique falls somewhere between evasion and rationalization: with the help of a good imagination, one conjures up fanciful alternatives to the warranted proposition and implicitly uses these mere possibilities to keep the case for that proposition unsettled. I have called this technique ‘jamming’, because of the radio/radar analogy (Bach 1981: 361–2). One sticks to the subject but clutters one's mind with contrary thoughts. To the extent that one's mind is redirected to appealing though epistemically idle possibilities, one avoids thinking as if one believed that proposition. The persistent occurrence of such thoughts provides a kind of perverse evidential support for the self‐ deceptive proposition. Evasion and jamming play supporting roles in the process of deceiving oneself and keeping oneself self‐deceived, by diverting the self‐deceiver from his occasional doubts. Rationalization provides the foundation. It plays for him the role that the party line or official doctrine plays in a political, religious, or other social group (family, business, charity), providing not only canonical support for what he thinks but also the terms for spinning it to others.

45.4 ‘Twisted’ Self‐deception It is often overlooked by self‐deception theorists, myself included (Bach 1981), that a person can be self‐deceived that p without wishing that p. Donald Davidson (1985) observed that self‐deception is not always similar to wishful thinking and is sometimes more like what Dion Scott‐Kakures (2000) calls ‘unwelcome believing’. It is illustrated by the stock example of the jealous husband who believes on flimsy grounds that his wife is having an affair. Mele calls this ‘twisted’ self‐deception (2001: 94 ff.). If like ‘straight’ self‐

Page 8 of 19

Self‐Deception deception the twisted kind involves motivated belief and mishandling of evidence, it poses a special puzzle, since its motivation is not the result of desire. Why, after all, would anyone deceive himself into thinking something he would rather not be so? It might be objected that the case of twisted self‐deception does not really undermine the claim that self‐deception is invariably motivated by desire. Of course, one could construe desire so broadly as to include motivation of any kind, but that would be to trivialize the objection. Rather, the idea is that the negative emotions that can give rise to self‐ deception, such as fear, anger, envy, and jealousy, have desires associated with them and that these are what motivate the self‐deception (see Mele 2003). However, it seems to me that to understand the motivation behind twisted self‐deception we need to look deeper. Compare and contrast twisted and straight self‐deception. In the straight case the self‐ deceiver refuses to confront a painful truth and draw the obvious conclusion from the strong evidence available to him. He thinks up reasons to the contrary, however flimsy, conjures up alternative possibilities, however idle, or just gets his mind off the unpleasant subject. In the case of twisted self‐deception, on the other hand, the self‐deceiver is preoccupied with the subject. Whether it's his wife's (p. 788) infidelity, his boss's lack of appreciation for his accomplishments, or his neighbour's vendetta against him, he lacks solid evidence for the unwelcome state of affairs and yet is disposed to treat isolated bits of flimsy evidence as showing that it obtains. Yet presumably he doesn't want, as the case may be, his wife to be unfaithful, his boss not to appreciate him, or his neighbour to have it in for him. So what motivates his thinking? It seems to me that in such cases the source of the motivation for the twisted self‐ deceiver's thinking is his inability to get his mind off the subject. (That in turn requires further explanation, of course.) The mere possibility of what he fears is enough to keep it in mind, and its staying there is enough to make it seem far more realistic than it actually is. The more realistic it seems, the more significant seem the stray bits of flimsy evidence for it and the more easily the evidence against it can be dismissed. The twisted self‐ deceiver weighs the evidence in accordance with the degree to which it occupies his attention. He dismisses some evidence not because it seems weak; rather, it seems weak because he dismisses it, because he can so easily put it out of mind. Meanwhile, the threads of evidence that support his fear seem strong because thoughts of them keep recurring. Of course, he doesn't treat the degree to which a piece of evidence occupies his attention as reason to weigh it accordingly; rather, its degree of occupying his attention causes him to weigh it accordingly—and he doesn't realize that this is why he so weighs it. What motivates the twisted self‐deceiver's thinking, then, is the fear itself (or whatever the anxious emotion). The twisted self‐deceiver can't get his mind off some undesired possibility, whereas the straight self‐deceiver can't face up to some undesired actuality. Because he is consumed with that possibility, the twisted self‐deceiver keeps thinking of evidence in its favour to the exclusion of evidence against it. In contrast, the straight self‐deceiver, because he can't face up to a certain actuality, dismisses its very possibility. He downplays, dismisses, Page 9 of 19

Self‐Deception or even disregards pieces of evidence for it. Evidence favouring the alternative to that actuality keeps grabbing his attention and makes that alternative seem not only plausible but convincing. Despite these differences, the two types of self‐deceivers have something in common: their thinking is driven by possibilities and considerations they attend to and is resistant to possibilities and considerations they downplay or disregard. Self‐deception is a kind of self‐distraction. This is not an intentional act, but a motivated process. In processes like that of becoming or remaining self‐deceived one's attention plays a skewed version of its normal role. In everyday life, with our limited cognitive resources and limited time in which to deploy them, we must be selective in what we consider when faced with a given question. We cannot spend time and effort on each thing that might come to mind just to determine that it is not worth considering. Indeed, at every moment we implicitly but effectively judge that certain things are not worth considering by not considering them at all, or at least not for long. We dismiss remote possibilities and flimsy evidence summarily, deeming them absurd, inconceivable, or highly improbable (these are example of what in Bach 1994 I call ‘exclusionary categories’), and take more seriously the ones that remain. With our limited time and resources, we count on our ability to make reliable snap judgements (p. 789) about what is worth considering. Reliability requires being equally responsive to considerations favouring and opposing the truth of the proposition in question. But this is not what happens in self‐deception. The processes that lead the self‐deceiver to think of certain considerations and not others and to take some seriously and to dismiss others are not evidentially constrained in the way they normally are for him.

45.5 Self‐deception and Cognitive Psychology Irrationality can occur without being motivated. It is generally accepted that human reasoning exhibits various systematic deficiencies (for pioneering work on this see Nisbett and Ross 1980, and Kahneman et al. 1982), deficiencies that generally do not need special motivation to manifest themselves. For example, people overgeneralize from small data samples, overweigh data that confirm their antecedent beliefs, treat recently encountered examples as representative of an entire phenomenon, and see patterns in random data and imagine causal connections between successive but unrelated events. Cognitive psychologists have identified a wide variety of common biases, flaws, and errors in reasoning, such as base‐rate neglect, belief perseverance, confirmation bias, hindsight bias, and the recency effect, and informal logicians have catalogued numerous fallacies. On the other hand, some psychologists have argued, under the rubric of ‘bounded rationality’ and ‘default reasoning’, that to some extent these apparent deficiencies are actually virtues, at least from a practical and evolutionary point of view (see Gigerenzer and Selten 2001). Various cognitive short cuts in the ‘adaptive toolbox’ enable ‘quick and dirty’ evaluations of real‐life situations to yield on‐the‐spot judgements and decisions. Perhaps both sides are correct to some extent. People need to be able to Page 10 of 19

Self‐Deception jump to conclusions but also need to know when to think twice (see Bach 1984). Whatever the ultimate verdict about the rationality of normal human cognitive processes, it is plausible that the phenomenon of self‐deception, though motivated, is continuous with normal, unmotivated cognitive phenomena. This is the basis for Alfred Mele's version (1997, 2001) of the deflationary approach. According to his account, which focuses on entering self‐deception rather than maintaining it (and assumes that the proposition in question must be false), a person enters self‐deception in acquiring a belief that p if although his data favour not‐p over p the person treats these data in a motivationally biased way and is thereby caused, in a non‐deviant way, to come to believe that p. However, as Dion Scott‐Kakures (2002) has argued, these conditions are not strong enough to exclude certain motivated beliefs that do not count as self‐deceptive. He argues that to count as deceiving oneself, rather than merely be engaged in wishful or anxious thinking, a person must exercise a sophisticated reflective capacity, however deficiently. Genuine self‐deception requires misapprehending the effect of desire (p. 790) or anxiety on one's thinking and misjudging the degree to which one's belief is warranted. The self‐deceiver ‘engages in various cognitive strategies, encounters recalcitrant data that must be explained away, generates friendly theories, [whereas] in wishful thinking a proposition is precipitously and directly embraced’ (2002: 600). What distinguishes both Mele's and Scott‐Kakures's accounts from other deflationary accounts is their suggestion that the processes that subserve self‐deception are continuous with those underlying ‘unmotivated or accuracy directed hypothesis testing’ (Scott‐Kakures 2002: 599). Mele thinks that the route to error in self‐deception is no different in kind from motivationally neutral routes. He specifically mentions overweighting positive evidence, downplaying negative evidence, selective evidence‐ gathering, and selective attention. To be sure, motivation can amplify these tendencies, but they don't have to be motivated to occur. Indeed, in moderation these tendencies support a reasonable degree of epistemic conservatism. As some epistemologists and philosophers of science advise, there is much to be said for not being too quick to challenge one's core beliefs or entrenched theories. So perhaps there is no clear boundary between reasonable conservatism and excessive caution or even outright dogmatism or, for that matter, between motivated and unmotivated irrationality, and perhaps the same processes are at work. To illustrate this idea, Mele and Scott‐Kakures both invoke a particular cognitive model, according to which people implicitly adopt different ‘confidence thresholds’ for accepting and for rejecting a given hypothesis (see Friedrich 1993; Trope and Lieberman 1996). People do this because they differentially assess the cost of wrongly believing something and of wrongly believing its negation. Costs and confidence thresholds affect both how hypotheses are evaluated and how far one is willing to go in testing them before making up one's mind. How does this bear on self‐deception? The self‐deceiver may cling to a certain proposition, say that his child is innocent of a horrible crime, when the cost of wrongly believing it is much less than the cost of wrongly believing its negation, that his Page 11 of 19

Self‐Deception son is guilty. This makes the proposition much easier to believe than to disbelieve. Recognizing that self‐deception is not a one‐shot affair but requires ongoing resistance to the emergence of the truth, Scott‐Kakures suggests that ‘in self‐deception motivation plays a continuing or recurring role—mediated by the asymmetry in error costs—in the generation of belief’, adding that ‘in wishful thinking it plays a merely triggering role’ (2002: 600). However, the process thus motivated is of a piece with normal cognition.

Page 12 of 19

Self‐Deception

45.6 Self‐deception and Self‐Knowledge We have already taken note of the suggestion that part of what distinguishes self‐ deception from other sorts of motivated irrationality, such as wishful thinking and (p. 791) delusional thinking, is that it utilizes, however perversely, a higher capacity for self‐knowledge. Of course, there is something lacking in the self‐deceiver's use of that capacity, in so far as he disregards the evidence provided by his behaviour, resists his own normal standards of evidence, and disavows his obvious motives. It seems that even if the self‐deception does not directly concern facts about himself, he finds ways to interpret what he says, does, thinks, and feels in a special light so as to maintain his antecedent self‐conception. Considerations of this sort have led some to suppose that self‐deception is inherently about oneself, that being self‐deceived about anything includes being self‐deceived about oneself. Indeed, Richard Holton (2001) contends that the role of the word ‘self’ in ‘self‐ deception’ is to indicate not that self‐deception is action on oneself but, like self‐ promotion or self‐effacement, that it is essentially about oneself. People do, after all, deceive themselves about their motives, as when they invent explanations for their shameful deeds, and about their abilities, as when they make up excuses for their abject failures. And, no doubt, people who are nasty, obnoxious, phoney, incompetent, or boring often seem to make an active effort to deceive themselves into thinking otherwise. Of course, examples like this do not show that self‐deception is always about oneself, but perhaps that is true in an indirect way. Consider the case of the mother who ‘can't believe’ that her son, the prime suspect in a murder case, is a killer. Like people whose self‐deception is about themselves, she shows little self‐reflection and self‐criticism in the area of her self‐deception. David Sanford gives another example, of a person who makes cruel jokes and, without appreciating their impact on their victims, always thinks of himself as ‘just kidding’ (1988: 164). In general, Sanford suggests, self‐deceivers ‘misapprehend [their] attitude structures’, and, as Annette Barnes adds, they fail to appreciate how their desires, wishes, fears, or motives have guided their reasoning on the subject and shaped their beliefs about it (1998: 102). However, it does not seem that this lack of self‐reflection necessarily amounts to further self‐deception. In particular, failure to recognize one's attitudes or to appreciate their impact on one's thinking doesn't entail being positively mistaken, much less self‐deceived, about them as well as the matter one is primarily self‐deceived about. Besides, in so far as most people are not generally reflective or self‐critical about their reasoning anyway, it seems excessive to accuse them of being self‐deceived about themselves whenever they are self‐deceived about anything else.

Page 13 of 19

Self‐Deception

45.7 Self‐deception and other People Self‐deception is not an exclusively private affair. There are at least three ways in which it ties in with other people. First, self‐deceivers frequently have occasion to behave in ways that enlist others’ cooperation. Even if others are not convinced, they will tend to play along because it's rude and uncomfortable to expose someone else's faults. Even knowing this, the self‐deceiver will tend to take others’ acquiescence as (p. 792) corroborating evidence. This enables him to ‘believe his own false advertising’, as William Ruddick (1988: 381) so aptly puts it, and ‘to dismiss evidence, not just linguistically launder it’ (Ruddick 1988: 386). A self‐deceiver exercises ‘evasive, as well as persuasive, linguistic skills’, such as using socially sanctioned jargon or euphemism, to discourage others from making him face up to some unpleasant fact, never mind rubbing his nose in it. Indeed, we all engage in what Erving Goffman (1959) calls ‘impression management’ to give others the opportunity to provide us with evidence for our own self‐conception. Then there is the matter of social role‐playing and the question of authenticity, of ‘being true to oneself’, as opposed to what Sartre (1958) called mauvaise foi (bad faith). We play along with other people's expectations of what we are. We get caught up in our social roles, such as being a waiter, a gourmet, or a doctor, and do not spell out to ourselves what we are really doing (Fingarette 1969/2000). Instead, like politicians we feign sincerity and feign acceptance of others' sincerity. If we all do this, who's fooling who? How do we distinguish hypocrisy from self‐deception (see Statman 1997)? Finally, there is an epistemological question about self‐deception and other people: How do we know when we've correctly identified instances of it? Perhaps we attribute self‐ deception to people much more readily than we should. Maybe we can't think of a better explanation for why they believe something that strikes us as completely absurd. We fail to recognize, even after questioning and challenging them, that they have a set of core beliefs about the subject matter from the perspective of which the suspect belief makes perfectly good sense (for example, that everything happens for a good reason or that one's child is incapable of violence). So we think they must be deceiving themselves. Similarly, we may suppose that people are more thoughtful than they really are, hence that they must be making the special effort characteristic of self‐deception in order to think as they do. For example, we suppose that they must be unconsciously aware of the obvious character flaws or annoying habits that we associate with them and must therefore do something to hide these traits from themselves.

45.8 Further Issues

Page 14 of 19

Self‐Deception Self‐deception raises various other questions. For example, what is the relationship between self‐deception and weakness of will? Arguably, self‐deception is itself a case of weakness of will: just as weakness of will involves acting against one's better judgement, so self‐deception involves thinking against one's better judgement. And certainly self‐ deception can facilitate weak‐willed action by leading to error about what one's better judgement is. Then there are moral questions pertaining to self‐deception. Is deceiving oneself something one can't help, or is one responsible for it? (p. 793) If the latter, is it always blameworthy? When we attribute self‐deception to someone, we tend to regard them as guilty of it, but perhaps there is something to be said in its favour, at least sometimes. Shelley Taylor (1989) documents cases in which people benefit from believing that they are fully recovered from cancer even if they are not, have more control over their surroundings than they actually do, will succeed at tasks that they are likely to fail at, and so on. Indeed, there is plenty of psychological evidence that most people, or at least most college students (the usual subjects of studies), think of themselves as above average (this is the so‐called Lake Wobegon effect), or at least not below average, as to intelligence, attractiveness, etc. Self‐deception touches on a variety of important issues in philosophy and psychology. It raises questions about the nature of belief and about the relation of belief to reasoning, desire, emotion, and the will. It ties in with broad psychological questions about the workings of the cognitive processes involved in reasoning, memory, and attention, and to such other psychological topics as motivation, self‐esteem, and the unconscious. And there is a specific psychological question about self‐deception that we haven't addressed at all: Why are people motivated to engage in self‐deception so selectively, on some topics and not others? That is: Why, why do people deceive themselves when they do?

References Audi, R. (1988), ‘Self‐deception, Rationalization, and Reasons for Acting’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 92–120. Bach, K. (1981), ‘An Analysis of Self‐deception’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 41: 351–71. —— (1984), ‘Default Reasoning: Jumping to Conclusions and Knowing When to Think Twice’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65: 37–58. —— (1994), ‘Emotional Disorder and Attention’, in G. Graham and L. Stephens (eds.), Philosophical Psychopathology (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 51–72. Barnes, A. (1998), Seeing Through Self‐deception (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Canfield, J., and McNally, P. (1961), ‘Paradoxes of Self‐deception’, Analysis, 21: 140–4. Page 15 of 19

Self‐Deception Davidson, D. (1985), ‘Deception and Division’, in E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Oxford: Blackwell), 138–48. Demos, R. (1960), ‘Lying to Oneself’, Journal of Philosophy, 57: 588–95. Fingarette, H. (1969/2000), Self‐deception, with a new chapter (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press). Friedrich, J. (1993), ‘Primary Error Detection and Minimization (PEDMIN) Strategies in Social Cognition: A Reinterpretation of Confirmation Bias Phenomena’, Psychological Review, 100: 298–319. Gigerenzer, G., and Selten, R. (2001) (eds.), Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Goffman, E. (1959), The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (New York: Doubleday). (p. 794)

Hales, S. D. (1994), ‘Self‐deception and Belief Attribution’, Synthese, 101: 273–89. Holton, R. (2001), ‘What is the Role of the Self in Self‐deception?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101: 53–69. Johnston, M. (1988), ‘Self‐deception and the Nature of Mind’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 63–91. Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A. (1982) (eds.), Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). McLaughlin, B. P. (1988), ‘Exploring the Possibility of Self‐deception in Belief’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 29–62. Mele, A. R. (1987), ‘Recent Work on Self‐deception’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 24: 1–17. —— (1997), ‘Real Self‐deception’, with open peer commentary and author's response, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20: 91–136. —— (2001), Self‐deception Unmasked (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). —— (2003), ‘Emotion and Desire in Self‐deception’, in A. Hatzimoysis (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 163–79. Nisbett, R., and Ross, L. (1980), Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall).

Page 16 of 19

Self‐Deception Rey, G. (1988), ‘Towards a Computational Account of akrasia and Self‐deception’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 264–96. Ruddick, W. (1988), ‘Social Self‐deceptions’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 380–9. Sanford, D. H. (1988), ‘Self‐deception as Rationalization’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 157–69. Sartre, J. P. (1958), Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Washington Square). Scott‐Kakures, D. (2000), ‘Motivated Believing: Wishful and Unwelcome’, Noûs, 34: 348– 75. —— (2002), ‘At Permanent Risk: Reasoning and Self‐knowledge in Self‐deception’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 576–603. Siegler, F. A. (1962), ‘Demos on Lying to Oneself’, Journal of Philosophy, 59: 469–75. —— (1963), ‘Self‐deception and Other Deception’, Journal of Philosophy, 41: 29–43. Statman, D. (1997), ‘Hypocrisy and Self‐deception’, Philosophical Psychology, 10: 57–75. Taylor, S. E. (1989), Positive Illusions: Creative Self‐deception and the Healthy Mind (New York: Basic). Trope, Y., and Lieberman, A. (1996), ‘Social Hypothesis Testing: Cognitive and Motivational Mechanisms’, in E. Higgins and A. Kruglanski (eds.), Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles (New York: Guilford), 239–70. Whisner, W. N. (1993), ‘Self‐deception and Other‐person Deception: Toward a New Conceptualization of Self‐deception’, Philosophia, 22: 223–40. Wood, A. W. (1988), ‘Ideology, False Consciousness, and Social Illusion’, in B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self‐deception (Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press), 345–63.

Further Reading Ainslie, G. (2001), Breakdown of Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Canfield, J., and Gustavson, D. F. (1962), ‘Self‐deception’, Analysis, 23: 32–6. Dupuy, J.‐P. (1998) (ed.), Self‐deception and Paradoxes of Rationality (Stanford, Calif.: CSLI). Page 17 of 19

Self‐Deception Fingarette, H. (1998), ‘Self‐deception Needs no Explaining’, Philosophical Quarterly, 48: 289–301. Gardiner, P. L. (1970), ‘Error, Faith and Self‐deception’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 70: 197–220. Goleman, D. P. (1985), Vital Lies, Simple Truths: The Psychology of Self‐deception (New York: Simon & Schuster). Gur, R. C., and Sackheim, H. A. (1979), ‘Self‐deception: A Concept in Search of a Phenomenon’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37: 147–69. Haight, M. R. (1980), A Study of Self‐deception (Sussex: Harvester). Hamlyn, D. W. (1971), ‘Self‐deception’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 45: 45–60. Heil, J. (1984), ‘Doxastic Incontinence’, Mind, 93: 56–70. Jones, D. H. (1989), ‘Pervasive Self‐deception’, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 27: 217– 37. Kunda, Z. (1987), ‘Motivated Inference: Self‐serving Generation and Evaluation of Causal Theories’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53: 636–47. —— (1990), ‘The Case for Motivated Reasoning’, Psychological Bulletin, 108: 480–98. Lazar, A. (1999), ‘Deceiving Oneself or Self‐deceived?’, Mind, 108: 263–90. Lockard, J. S., and Paulhus, D. L. (1988) (eds.), Self‐deception: An Adaptive Mechanism? (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice‐Hall). Loungeway, J. L. (1990), ‘The Rationality of Escapism and Self‐deception’, Behavior and Philosophy, 90: 1–20. Martin, M. W. (1985) (ed.), Self‐deception and Self‐understanding: New Essays in Philosophy and Psychology (Lawrence, Kan.: University Press of Kansas). Martin, T. (1998), ‘Self‐deception and Intentional Forgetting: A Reply to Whisner’, Philosophia, 26: 181–94. Pears, D. (1984), Motivated Irrationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press). —— (1991), ‘Self‐deceptive Belief Formation’, Synthese, 89: 393–405. Quattrone, G., and Tversky, A. (1984), ‘Causal Versus Diagnostic Contingencies: On Self‐ deception and on the Voter's Illusion’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46: 237–48.

Page 18 of 19

Self‐Deception Rorty, A. O. (1983), ‘Akratic Believers’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 20: 175–83. —— (1994), ‘User‐friendly Self‐deception’, Philosophy, 69: 211–28. Sackheim, H. A., and Gur, R. C. (1985), ‘Voice Recognition and the Ontological Status of Self‐deception’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48: 1365–8. Scott‐Kakures, D. (1996), ‘Self‐deception and Internal Irrationality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56: 31–56. Siegler, F. A. (1968), ‘An Analysis of Self‐deception’, Noûs, 2: 147–64. Silver, M., Sabini, J., and Miceli, M. (1989), ‘On Knowing Self‐deception’, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 19: 213–47. Szabados, B. (1973), ‘Wishful Thinking and Self‐deception’, Analysis, 33: 201–5. —— (1974), ‘Self‐deception’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 4: 41–9. Talbott, W. J. (1995), ‘Intentional Self‐deception in a Single Coherent Self’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55: 27–74. (p. 796)

Whisner, W. N. (1998), ‘A Further Explanation and Defence of the New Model of Self‐ deception: A Reply to Martin’, Philosophia, 26: 195–206. Wilkes, K. V. (1994), ‘Psychology and Politics: Lies, Damned Lies and Self‐deception’, Philosophy, 37: 115–29.

Kent Bach

Kent Bach is Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Department of Philosophy, San Francisco State University.

Page 19 of 19

Index

Index   The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind Edited by Ansgar Beckermann, Brian P. McLaughlin, and Sven Walter Print Publication Date: Jan 2009 Subject: Philosophy Online Publication Date: Sep 2009

(p. 797)

Index

ability, see capacities aboutness, see intentionality access consciousness 514 n. 3 & 4, 520, 526 direct 741–4, 753–5, 761–3 privileged 741–5, 767–74, 777, 778 acquaintance 648–51 immediate 271–82, 299, 303 action 339–47, see also behaviour at a distance, see causation at a distance guiding 234 intentional 547, 691–708 and morality 695 n. 10, 696, 700 side effects of 695, 696 rational 609, 694–9 Adams, F. 529, 530, 698, 704 Adolphs, R. 688 after‐images 262, 274, 275 agency 588, 589 and memory 671, 672 agents 547 and free will 706, 707 intentional 357, 362 vanishing, 706, 707 Aggelton, J. 663 Alexander, S. 42, 210, 213 Allen, C. 49 Allen‐Hermanson, S. 208 Alston, W. P. 581 n. 8, 705, 743, 734 Alter, T. 290 Angell, J. R. 642 n. animals human 582–9 Page 1 of 37

Index non‐human 67, 185, 229–32, 244, 342, 382, 402, 405, 448, 604–6, 665, 669, 683 anomalism, see also anomalous monism psychological 96–9 psychophysical 99–102 anomalous monism 35–8, 95–108, 111–13 and supervenience 105–7 Anscombe, G. E. M. 98, 494 n., 667, 694 n. 9 anthropomorphism 340 anti‐individualism, see individualism, anti‐ Antony, L. 97, 111, 119, 607, 622 n. a posteriority 316–19, 325–8 appearances 515–20 and self‐knowledge 751, 753, 761, 762 a priority 315, 317, 319, 324–32, 673, 674 transmission of 773, 774 Ariew, A. 387 n. 1 Aristotle, 152, 193, 208, 241, 275, 500–2, 504, 678, 679, 702, 782 Armon‐Jones, C. 679 Armstrong, D. 131, 181, 200, 201 n., 241, 488, 755, 756 n. 15 artificial intelligence 132 ascription, see attribution Ashwell, L. 324 associationism 626–8 attention focal 499, 501, 502, 568, 573 and self‐deception 785–93 attitudes, propositional 49, 95, 100, 101, 113, 117–20, 346, 355, 361–3, 407–19, 459–69, 478–81 and attitude predicates 408–18 as causally efficacious 407, 413 as semantically evaluable 407, 413 attributions of 100, 101, 355, 413–6, 633–5, 640, see also folk psychology core vs. derivative cases of 414 existence and reality of 418 individuation of types of 412–7, 425, 426, 432–5 measurement‐theoretic account of, see measurement‐theory and propositional attitudes attribution of belief 356 of content 356–64 of mental concepts 296, 298, 305 of propositional attitudes, see attitudes, propositional Audi, R. 665, 692, 693 n. 7, 699, 703, 786 Augustine, 729–31, 738 Aunt Bubbles machine 618–24 autism 719 autonomy, see free will Avramides, A. 88, 727, 731 n. 6, 737 n. Aydede, M. 304 awareness 260, 261, 270–4, 278, 498–505 Page 2 of 37

Index higher‐order 242, 243 of awareness 500, 501 partial 654–7 (p. 798) Bach, K. 227 n. 4, 356 n. 8, 507 n. 28, 781, 784–9 Baddeley, A. 663 Bain, D. 475 n. 3, 479–81, 488 Baker, L. 45, 49, 68, 72, 73, 93 n. 7, 109, 111, 116 n. 7, 120, 121 n. 15 & 18, 131, 588 n. Balog, K. 292, 301, 306, 308, 324 Bar‐On, D. 751, 752 Barkow, J. 721 Barnes, A. 791 Barnes, J. 208 Baron‐Cohen, S. 344 Bayne, T. 566, 567, 570, 573, 574 n. Bealer, G. 300, 762 Beardsley, M. 692 Bechara, A. 688 Beckermann, A. 152, 155, 156, 169 n. 24, 408 Beebee, H. 773 behaviour 731–9 explaining 284–9, 339–49, 351, 356, 360–5, 713–25 predicting 339–49, 351, 356, 360–5, 713–25 behaviourism in psychology 569 logical 129–31, 152, 153, 211, 302, 733, 737 belief 226–8, 233, 239–49, 352–6, 361–5, 478–80, 631, 633–5, 638–40, 692–709, see also attitudes, propositional and rationalization 784–7 and self‐deception, see self‐deception avowal 782–6, 791 as reliable indicator 364 as source of information 364 de dicto vs. de re 228 dispositional vs. occurrent 785, 786 belief box 346 Benecke, E. 88 Bennett, J. 82, 131, 142, 271, 570, 581 n. 8, 633 Bennett, K. 46, 63 Bennett, M. R. 344 Berkeley, G. 190, 194, 198, 199, 202, 210, 546, 626, 643, 653, 730 n., 731, 738 Bermúdez, J. L. 457, 458, 459, 461 n., 463 n., 467, 469, 636–9, 641, 723, 741 n. 2 Bernecker, S. 770 Bickle, J. 43 n. Bilgrami, A. 727 n. 2, 732 n. 9 binding problem 556 biosemantics 394–406 Bird, A. 430 Bishop, J. 692 n. 5, 701 n. 20, 702–5 Page 3 of 37

Index Blackburn, S. 194, 195, 370 Blackmore, S. 570 Blitz, D. 207 Block, N. 43, 44, 48 n., 112 n. 4, 129, 130, 132, 145, 147, 148, 156 n., 158, 159, 162–5, 225, 255, 264 n. 12, 271 n., 296 n. 15, 297 n. 19, 306–8, 327, 328, 347, 348, 357, 375, 382, 434, 475 n. 3, 480 n., 481 n. 10, 482 n. 11, 483, 486, 514 n. 3, 520, 615 n. 8, 617–19, 625 n. 16 Blockhead 434 Boghossian, P. 264 n. 12, 425, 431 n. 15, 673, 746, 750, 760, 769–72, 776 Bontly, T. D. 43 Boring, E. G. 273 Boyd, R. 112 n. 5 Braddon‐Mitchell, D. 160 n. 9, 324, 638 Bradley, F. 561 n. 52, 732 brain bisection 570, 573 Brand, M. 692, 701–5 Brandom, R. 186 n., 345, 422 n. 1, 423, 446, 468 Brann, E. 595 n. Bratman, M. 692, 693 n. 7, 695, 697, 698, 707 Braun, D. 717 Brentano, F. 67, 118 n., 248, 474, 476 n., 477, 481, 498, 500, 502–4, 520, 569, 609, 613 Brentano’s thesis 474, 481, 609, 613 Brewer, B. 458, 460 n., 773, 774 bridge laws, 98, 101, 112, 156, 157 British emergentists 41, 165, 207 Broad, C. D. 41, 90, 156–9, 165, 171, 210, 212 Brook, A. 344, 565, 567, 568 n. 1, 569 n. 3 Brown, D. H. 273 n. Brown, J. 24, 354 n. 4, 355 n. 5, 767, 770–3, 776, 777 Brueckner, A. 747, 770, 775, 777 Budd, M. 597 n. 4, 600 n. 13 Burge, T. 106, 111, 116 n. 7, 133, 352–7, 363, 364, 368, 369, 374, 375, 392, 450, 504 n. 22, 507 n. 28, 625 n. 17, 665, 673, 674, 743, 748–51, 757, 762, 763, 769–71, 777 Butler, J. 581 n. 6, 782 Butler, K. 772 Byrne, A. 256 n., 262 n. 10, 265 n., 268, 279 n., 287, 427, 459 n., 460, 475 n. 3, 479, 481 n. 10, 484–6, 660 Byrne, R. 344, 721 Campbell, D. 35 n. 8 Campbell, J. 199, 246 n., 465 n., 469, 507, 648, 659, 665, 668, 669, 673 Canfield, J. 783 capacities causal 33 cognitive 357 psychological 285 Carey, S. 616 Carnap, R. 153, 211, 570 Carroll, S. 88 Carruthers, P. 247, 248, 305, 306, 642, 643 Page 4 of 37

Index Casey, E. 599 n. 9 Cassam, Q. 569 n. 3 (p. 799) Caston, V. 500 n. 12, 502 n. 16 category, see kinds causal exclusion 38–46 argument from 38–41 objections and responses to the argument from 42–6 principle of 39 causal closure principle 38, 79, 80, 111, 114, 115, 124, 125, see also closure, causal causal inheritance principle 47, 114, 124 causalism 701, 702 problems for 702–7 causation 31, 32 accounts of 85, 89–93 and contact 31–4 and explanation 104, 110–23 and reference, see reference and causal contact and spatiality 29–35 as a brute fact 32 as nomological sufficiency 111–15, 122 n. 21, 125 at a distance 31, 32, 214 body‐body 90–2 body‐mind 33, 90, 91 brute vs. rational 608–10 conserved quantity accounts of 91–3 counterfactual accounts of 36, 45, 81–3, 90, 91, 111–12 downward 35, 40, 41, 59, 113, 115, 116, 124 Humean regularity accounts of 45 intentional 82, 83 INUS account of 90 levels of 44 mental 29–52, 102–5, 142 mental‐mental, see causation, mind‐mind mental‐physical, see causation, mind‐body mind‐body 32–7, 90, 91 mind‐mind 32, 90, 91 nomological character of 97, 106 physical 31–4, 38, 39, 43, 90–2 transitivity of 31 cause‐effect pairing 32–5 causes 32, 38, 49 biological 43 individuation of 61 sufficient 39 physical 38, 39, 53–5, 59–61, 79 Chalmers, D. J. 42, 64, 77, 144, 147, 157 n. 6, 159 n., 161 n. 13, 164, 183 n., 211, 225, 231, 256 n., 259 n. 4, 279 n., 281–4, 288, 290, 293 n. 5, 297 n. 20, 298–301, 303 n., 304 n. 32, 306–9, 313,

Page 5 of 37

Index 315–20, 326–9, 332, 363 n. 20, 376–8, 475 n. 3, 477 n. 5, 479, 480 n., 481, 486 n., 487, 497 n. 7, 503, 504 n. 23, 514, 534, 566, 567, 570, 573, 574 n., 666, 753, 754 Chapman, L. J. 688 Cheney, D. 344, 611 Chihara, C. S. 732–5, 737, 739 Child, T. W. 97, 99–102, 107, 434 n. 20 Chinese Room 620–4 Chisholm, R. M. 75, 753 choice 80–2, 339 see also free will Chomsky, N. 184, 356, 612, 734 Christensen, D. 666, 674 Church, A. 614 Church, J. 524 Churchland, P. M. 42 n., 148, 207 n., 391, 408, 714 Churchland, P. S. 391 Clapp, L. 119, 120 n. 12, 122 n. 20 Clark, Andy, 633, 636, 637, 645, 666 Clark, Austen, 268–70, 271–3 Clarke, D. 553, 554 n. Clifford, W. 214 closure, causal 38–45, 53–65, see also causal closure principle evidence for 55–60 of the physical 38–42, 53–65, 78–83, 174, 185, 217 cognitive science 46, 48, 344, 361, 383, 458, 532, 665 coincidence 583–7 commitment 693–5 communication 233, 234 community, linguistic 351–5, 364, 365, 424, 425, 450 computationalism, 48, 625 Cartesian, 614 computational theory of mind, see computationalism conceivability and possibility 78, 79, 173, 284, 314–333 argument against materialism 314 argument for dualism 69–74 strong vs. weak versions 69 clear and distinct 331 ideal 315, 316, 318, 319, 324, 332 positive vs. negative 301 n. 28, 315–19, 324–6, 329 of materialism 332 of disembodiment 69 of dualism 314 of zombies, see zombies, conceivability of prima facie 315–18, 324, 331, 332 primary vs. secondary (1‐ vs. 2‐) 317–19, 324 varieties of 315–19 concepts 227–9, 400, 404, 405, 437–55, 515, 518, 520, 527, 530, 531 acquisition of 227, 441 Page 6 of 37

Index and beliefs 229, 232–4 and compositionality 611–16, 620, 625–8 (p. 800)

and non‐conceptual content, see content, conceptual vs. non‐conceptual and predicates 294 n. 10, 297 and rationality 441–45 and reference 294–9, 446–8 and representation 296–8, 440–3, 448–50 and teleosemantics 308, 396, see also teleosemantics and truth 441–5 as abstract objects 439–43 as cognitive structures 227 as particulars 440 as pleonastic 440, 441, 451–4 as ways of thinking 438, 439, 448, 452 attributions of, see attribution of mental concepts biosemantic account of, see biosemantics changes in 354–6 characterization problem for 438, 448 descriptive 295, 304–6 empty 373, 374 extension of 353–6 general vs. singular 369, 379 individuation of 297, 351, 356, 362, 363, 439–53 Frege’s Principle for 439, 441 logical 444, 452, 453 mental 131, 134, 136–9 natural kind 351–4, 356, 578 object‐dependent 440 of substances 578–86 open questions about 437–54 phenomenal 235–7, 289–311, see also phenomenal‐concept strategy acquisition of 295, 299, 304, 305 as constituted by phenomenal experiences 306–9 direct reference account of 304, 305 information‐theoretic account of 304, 305 modes of presentation of 305–9 quotational account of 308 recognitional account of, see concepts, recognitional reference of 304–9 semantic stability of 299–301, 307 transparency of 294, 299 possession conditions of 437–55, 458, 468–70 property‐dependent 440 psychological 297, 398, 713–25, see also folk psychology recognitional 251, 303–7 sensory, see concepts, phenomenal singular 294 n. 10, 297 Page 7 of 37

Index subjective 292 connectionism 626–8, 665, 666 consciousness 30, 35, 36, 41, 42 n. 15, 132, 139–49, 173, 313, 314, 320–4, 328, 332 and experiences 243–5, 281–90, 494–509, 513–33 and introspection, see introspection and consciousness and non‐conscious thought, see thought, non‐conscious and personal identity, see identity, personal and reference 648–62 and self 669, 670 and what it’s like 211, 243, 247–50, 269, 270, 276, 283–90, 292–4, 300, 495, 496, 503 as a three‐place relation 657–9 as fiction 207 n. 2 as glow 648–54 co‐ 566 creature vs. state 239, 244 n. 6 degrees of 144 disorders of 570–3 hard problem of 281, 534 higher‐order theories of, see HOT (higher‐order thought) in matter 191–8 inner sense view of 241–3, 246, 250, 753–60 locus of 554–61 phenomenal 77, 225, 236, see also qualia relational vs. intrinsic 287 representationalist theories of, see representationalism sameness of 581–3 stream of 227, 573 unity of 565–76 pathologies of the 570–2 content 244–50, 262–6, 351–65, 457–72 and epistemic norms 450, 451 and language 458, 459, 468–70 and self‐knowledge 743–54, 757–62, see also self‐knowledge and the perspectival constraint 461–3 attribution of, see attribution of content broad, see content, wide conceptual vs. non‐conceptual 257–9, 296, 438, 448, 449, 457–72, 478–88, 650, 665, 666 definiteness of, see content, determinacy of determinacy of 515, 526, 530, 531, 632, 635, 640, 643 disjunctivism about 506 externalism vs. internalism about 351–6, 476, 477, 504–6, 672–4, 767–78, see also content, narrow; content, wide fixing of 141 grain of, see grain of representational content grasping of 460 inferential role 100 (p. 801)

linguistic 352–4, 357 Page 8 of 37

Index narrow 227–9, 351–65, 367–80 arguments for 370–4 naturalistic theories of 529 of perceptual experience 224, 226, 494–509 of speech acts 224 phenomenological 479, 500–7 psychological 356, 362, 363 scenario 462, 463 social 355 teleological theories of 308, 396, see also teleosemantics two‐factor theories of 369, 374, 375 vague, see content, determinacy of wide 351–65, 369, 373, 504, see also content, externalism vs. internalism about arguments against 352–6 arguments for 351, 352 context, intensional vs. extensional 104, 522, 528–31, 613 context‐sensitivity of content 351–7, 364 of terms 422 contextualism 775 Conway, M. 663, 723 Cooper, W. E. 210 cooperation 397, 398, 401–4, 718–22, 791 Corabi, J. 87 Corpus Callosum 570 counterfactuals 195, see also causation, counterfactual accounts of Craig, W. L. 194 n. Craik, K. 639 Crane, T. 49, 57, 67, 184, 353, 354, 356 n. 8, 474, 478, 482 n. 11, 483, 485 n., 488 n., 490 n., 497 n. 7, 503, 613 n. 4 Crisp, T. 114 Crook, S. 179 n. Cummins, R. 134 Currie, G. 715 Cussins, A. 461 n. Dainton, B. 514 n. 5, 516, 565, 566, 570, 574 Daly, C. 184 Damasio, A. 557 n. 37, 560, 561, 682, 687, 688 danglers, causal 64 Danzinger, K. 642 n. Darwin, C. 214, 682 Davidson, D. 36, 37, 95–107, 111–13, 134, 185 n. 25, 345, 368, 391, 408, 409, 415, 426 n. 10, 428, 431, 446, 477 n. 5, 574, 633–6, 692, 694 n. 9 & 10, 698–705, 729 n. 4, 736 n. 15, 739, 743, 746–9, 751, 763 n. 21, 787 Davies, M. 467 n. 7, 767, 773, 774 Davis, L. 692, 704 Davis, W. 174 Dawkins, R. 544 n. 8 Page 9 of 37

Index Dawson, M. 572 Debellis, M. 458 decision, see also choice; free will making of 678, 687, 688 Democritus, 152, 208 Demos, R. 782, 783 demonstratives in concepts 444, 445 in experiences 231 in judgments 352 denial, see self‐deception and denial Dennett, D. C. 42 n., 88, 131, 133, 140–5, 148, 174 n. 2, 207 n., 295, 305 n., 339, 344–8, 377 n. 10, 391, 408, 409, 475, 483, 515 n., 527–35, 560 n. 49, 562, 568, 574, 666, 714 dependence 111, 177, 178, 181, 184–6 and emergence 212, 213 and supervenience, see supervenience and dependence causal 86, 89–93 constitutional account of 123 counterfactual 90 n., 111, 775, see also causation, counterfactual accounts of of the mental on the physical, 40, 105, 106, 110, 123 DeRose, K. 775 Descartes, R. 29–37, 55, 56, 68, 69, 72, 85, 177, 206, 208, 240, 283, 293 n. 4, 316, 333 n., 525, 528, 529, 541, 550–6, 569, 607–16, 619, 620, 625, 626, 678, 680, 728–31, 735 n., 736 n. 15, 739, 742, 743, 753 designator non‐rigid 321 rigid 162, 166, 170 design stance 340–4 desire 67, 68, 85, 95, 96, 100, 117, 118, 129–33, 227, 242, 243, 339–49, 375, 376, 382, 386, 401–5, 428, 469, 475–7, 521, 523, 572, 688, 692–4, 698–702, 713–22, 741 determinism 39, 217 and quantum mechanics 54, 59 deviance, causal 703–5 Deutsch, H. 579 n. 1 Deutscher, M. 665 Dewey, J. 499 n. 10 Díez, J. 410 n. Diogenes 208 directly reductive narrow functionalism (DRNF) 375, 376 discrimination, perceptual, see perception and discrimination disjunction problem 387–9 disjunctivism, see content, disjunctivism about dispositionalism normative vs. non‐normative 429–35 pure 195 (p. 802) dispositions 194–7, 203, 215, 218, 293 n. 5, 322, 347, 622, 646 and higher‐order thought theories 247, 248 and sensible qualities 276–8 Page 10 of 37

Index and holism 429–31 behavioural 129, 354, 412, 424–6, 533, 651, 687, 717, 785, 786 grounding of 196–8 normative 424–35 pure 195 regress of 191–4 dissociative identity disorder (DID) 571 Dokic, J. 668 Dorr, C. 559 Dowe, P. 44 Dowell, J. 177 n. 9 Dray, W. 98 dream 519, 530, 551, 553, 561, 601–3, see also imagination Dretske, F. 146, 241, 256 n., 260 n., 261, 266, 287, 288, 381, 383, 389, 390 n., 392, 400–3, 458, 475 n. 2 & 3, 480, 481, 489, 491, 514 n. 2, 524, 530, 568, 625 n. 16, 701 n. 20, 757–60, 763 dualism 29–35, 38–41, 66–85, 86, 93,206–8, 293, 300–9 Cartesian 110, 174–7, 569, 607–16 of causes 61 conceivability argument for, see conceivability argument for dualism neo‐cartesian argument for 69 non‐cartesian 68, 69, 74–7, 80–3 property 38–41, 61, 66–8, 76–8, 307, 313–33 qualia‐based arguments for 77, 78 replacement argument for 74–6 substance 29–35, 61, 66–81 unity argument for 74–6 Duclos, S. E. 682 Dummett, M. 469, 664 dysexecutive syndrome 572, 573 Eddington, A. 215 Eddy, T. 721 Egan, F. 351, 357 n. 11, 359 n. 13, 360 n. 15, 625 n. 17 eliminativism 42 and materialism 207 n. 2 of the mental 42, 294 n. 6 ELIZA 618, 619 emergence, see emergentism emergentism 48, 156–9, 169, 207–17, see also British emergentists and downward causation 35, 41 as emergent vitalism 156 epistemological forms of 211–13 emotions 678–88 cognitivism concerning 678–82 non‐cognitivism concerning 682–6 and self‐deception 781, 787, 788, 793 empiricism 612, 626–8 Enc, B. 390 Engel, S. 667 Page 11 of 37

Index entities, fundamental 206–18, 314 epiphenomenalism 35–8, 85–95, 103, 104, 107, 111, 113, 142–8, 212, 217, 324, 390–2 and causation 85, 86, 89–92 and dependency of mind on body 92 and physicalism 42 arguments against 87, 88, 93 conceptions of 85, 90–3 token vs. type 37, 103 epistemology, see knowledge essence 422, 423 Evans, G. 276, 277, 278 n., 352, 369, 432 n., 457, 464, 465 n., 467, 488, 499, 507 n. 26, 508, 509, 614, 649–51, 665, 666, 741 n. 2, 757, 758 events as a fundamental category 66 mental 36–40 evolution 134, 343–9, 395, 396 and emergentism 212–4, 217 and teleofunctionalism 134 argument against epiphenomenalism 87, 88 Ewing, A. C. 204 n. existence of non‐causal entities 63, 64 of the phenomenal 496, 501–5 experience 223–6, 268–79 see also experiences; consciousness apparent continuity of 557 and attention 229–35 and information 224, 225, 229, 234 content of, see content of perceptual experience features of 282, 289 parts of 574 perceptual 463–6, 494–509, 648, 651 and causal relations 494–509 matching view of 508, 509 properties of 269–71 subject of 67, 68, 73–6, 541–62 veridicality of 495–7, 504–8 experiences as brain events 235–8 as representational, see representationalism feel of 224–6, see also qualia intrinsic feature or quality of 226, 227, 232, 652, 653, 660, see also qualia phenomenology of 258–62, 495–7, 503, see also qualia (p. 803)

qualitative, see qualia subjectively indistinguishable 495, 505–8 unified 568, 574, 575, see also consciousness, unity of explanation causal 38, 278, see also causation Page 12 of 37

Index levels of 110–20 physical 113 psychological 335–63, 374–6, 441 reductive 155–60, 300 and causal role 154, 155, 160, 169 in science 154, 159, 166–70 vs. identity 152–5, 157–60, 206 n. 1, 210 semantic 391, 392 explanatory gap 77, 82, 88, 169, 231, 270, 281–90, 300–5, 313, 529, 534, see also mind‐body problem expressivism about norms 423 extension 353, 354 determination of 429–31 externalism, see also content, externalism vs. internalism about and self‐knowledge, see self‐knowledge and externalism facts abstract 201 natural 64 epistemology of non‐physical 64 Fain, H. 32 n. Fair, D. 44 Falvey, K. 771 Fara, M. 430 Farkas, K. 477 n. 6 Feigl, H. 225, 237 Festinger, L. 723 Fichte, J. G. 546, 555 Field, H. 364, 408, 446 Fine, K. 330, 422 n. 4 Fingarette, H. 792 first‐person access 288, 298 first‐person perspective 289, 294, 295, see also subjectivity fission, see identity, personal Flanagan, O. 514 n. 5, 516, 518, 550 Fodor, J. 43 n., 49, 99, 111, 112, 143, 185, 288, 296 n. 14, 297, 357, 360 n. 16, 361 n. 19, 369–73, 377 n. 10, 381, 387, 388, 392, 408, 409, 414, 416, 431, 458, 467 n. 6, 611–16, 625–8, 631, 637, 640, 732–9 folk psychology 96, 99, 132, 133, 142, 339, 342, 349, 361, 362, 373, 713–25 and categories of mental states 717–21 and simulation 715–8 and theory 713, 714, 720 Foster, J. 32 n., 68, 198 n., 505 n., 506, 507 four‐dimensionalism, see identity, personal Frankfurt, H. 693, 707 Frankish, K. 332 free will 85, 140, 208, 214, 223, 224 Frege, G. 153 n. 1, 163, 257, 259, 439–41, 444, 448, 452, 506, 614 n., 627, 654, 655, 658 Frege dictionary 163 n. 16 Page 13 of 37

Index Fregean sense 369, 408, see also mode of presentation neo‐Fregean 439 Freud, S. 782 Fricker, E. 424 Friedrich, J. 790 Frijda, N. H. 680, 687 function 128, 130–3 and levels 282, 285 and meaning 385–91 and organization 285, 289 and teleology 133 biological 395 cooperative 398 computational 132, 134, 137, 141, 146–8 cooperative 398, 402–4 natural 386, 387 vs. structure 130, 131, 134, 139 functionalism 46–8, 128–51, 160, 286, 375, 615, 622 analytical 136, 137, 169, 286, 302 and cognitive psychology 130 and information‐processing 131, 133, 141, 147, 149 and multiple realizability 43, 47 and psychofunctionalism 132, 286 and the software‐hardware metaphor 130–3 and the type‐type identity theory 129–31, 138, 142 arguments for and against 138–49 as a pragmatic thesis 134, 137, 140 narrow vs. wide causal role versions of 133–7, 141 history of 128–31 varieties of 131–8 Gallistel, C. R. 616 Gallois, A. 747, 775, 776 Garber, D. 31 n. 2 Garon, J. 628 Garrett, B. J. 46, 588 n. Geach, P. T. 579 n. 1, 584 n. 15 Gendler, T. S. 70, 578, 587 n. 26 Gennaro, R. J. 248, 249 Georgalis, N. 514–17 Gertler, B. 743 n. 4, 753, 757 Gibbard, A. 423 n. 6 Gibbons, J. 769, 770 Gibson, E. 545 Gibson, J. J. 269, 499 n. 10 Gigerenzer, G. 789 (p. 804) Gilhooly, K. 672 Gillett, C. 43, 179 n. Ginet, C. 694 n. 9, 695, 701 n. 20, 702 Page 14 of 37

Index given, the 464, 497–506 goal 343, 422, 427, 609, 610, 680, 681, 688 God 29, 56, 62, 185, 189, 190, 208, 209, 314, 325, 328–34, 343, 735, 736 Goel, V. 683 Goffman, A. 792 Gopnik, A. 471 n. 9, 723, 724 Goldberg, S. 771 Goldie, P. 490 n. Goldman, A. 514 n. 5, 518, 526, 694 n. 9, 702, 705, 716, 724, 772 Gordon, R. 715 Gould, S. 88 Graham, G. 512, 515, 531, 533 Grahek, N. 488 n. grain of representational content 460, 464, 468 the problem of 389, 390 Grandy, R. 429 Green, K. 664 Greene, B. 541 n. Greenspan, P. 679 Grice, H. P. 129, 382, 735 Griffin, D. 210 Griffin, R. 344 Griffiths, P. E. 684 grounding of dispositions, see dispositions, grounding of of knowledge, see knowledge, grounding of of meaning, see meaning, grounding of Gurwitsch, A. 502 Güzeldere, G. 304 Hacker, P. 344 Hacking, I. 667 Haggard, P. 246 Haldane, E. 29 n., 177 Hales, S. D. 785 Hall, L. 227 n. 6 Hall, N. 45 n., 92 hallucination 597, 601, see also imagination Hardcastle, V. 567, 568 n. 2, 572 Hardin, C. 146 Hare, R. D. 688 Harman, G. 146, 256 n., 277 n., 296, 299 n., 302 n. 31, 375, 446, 482, 504, 625 n. 16, 652, 692, 695, 697, 699, 703 Harnish, R. M. 615 n. 7 Harré, R. 191, 196, 197 Hartshorne, C. 217 Hawthorne, J. 70, 324, 327, 579 n. 1, 775, 776 Hayek, F. A. 272, 273 Page 15 of 37

Index Heal, J. 98, 715, 716, 724, 769 Healey, R. 176 Heck, R. 459 Hegel, G. W. F. 190, 203, 204 Heidegger, M. 231, 499 n. 10, 513 Heil, J. 110, 113, 625 n. 17, 631, 633, 743, 769 Hellie, B. 475 n. 3, 486 Hellman, G. 178, 179 Hempel, C. G. 57, 129, 153, 178–84 Hempel’s dilemma 178–84 higher‐order global state (HOGS) 144 Hilbert, D. R. 660 Hill, C. 157 n. 7, 158, 162, 163, 249 n. 11, 284, 288, 306, 307, 333, 570 Hinton, J.M. 271 history and function 396, 401 and meaning 386, 387, 391 Hobbes, T. 178, 554, 729 Hoerl, C. 665 Hohwy, J. 775 Holland, J. 207 Holton, R. 791 Horgan, T. 97, 111, 181 n. 18, 486 n., 496 n., 512, 515, 524, 525, 531, 533 Hornsby, J. 97, 345, 704 Horwich, P. 427, 446 HOT (higher‐order thought) 144, 476, 633–6 as a theory of consciousness 239–52, 482 n. 12, 745 n. 5, 755 with intrinsic higher‐order contents 248–50 holism of the mental 100 Hudson, H. 588 n. human beings, see also animals, human as physical objects 541, 547–9, 559 considered as wholes 542–5, 549–51, 555, 560–2 Hume, D. 45, 177, 191–4, 224, 231, 232, 243, 272, 273, 552, 561, 56–9, 596, 597, 626, 627, 643, 678, 683, 782 Humphreys, P. 41 Hurley, S. 428 n., 566, 569 n. 3, 570, 573 Hursthouse, R. 699 Husserl, E. 476 n., 477 n. 5, 499, 513 Huxley, T. H. 35, 36, 85 Hyslop, A. 727, 728, 731, 732, 739 icons, see representation, descriptive vs. iconic idealism 189–205, 210 and imagination 198, 199 and mind‐independence 198, 199, 204 history of 210 Kantian 190, 197, 203, 204 Moore’s refutation of 653 Page 16 of 37

Index ideas 223–31 identity 163, see also individuation conditions for 73–6, 158 of causes 61–3 (p. 805)

of entities 588, 589 of indiscernibles 33 n. 5, 34 of living things 579–80 of mental phenomena 95–7, 102, 129–39, 152–71 of mind and body, see physicalism of properties 152–71 personal 578–90, 667, 671 and analogical reasoning 727, 728 and consciousness 579–81 and fission 585, 586 and four‐dimensionalism 589, 590 and teletransportation 585 diachronic 579 n. 3, 588, 589 extrinsically vs. intrinsically determined 587 judgments about 578–81 practical importance of 578–82, 588 imagery, pictorial 642, 643 images 516–25, 637–46, see also imagination and Hume 596, 597 and Kant 596 intentional content of 596 phenomenology of 595, 596, 599 vs. percepts 595–605 imaginability, see conceivability imagination 316–9, 326, 332, 595–605 and belief 595, 603, 604 and idealism, see idealism and imagination and hallucination, see hallucination and knowledge 598–600, 604 and observational attitude 598–602 and possibility 595–604 and philosophical counter‐examples 595, 602 and that‐clauses 595, see also that‐clauses and the will 597, 600–3 as active 596, 597, 601, 602 cognitive 595, 603–5 imagism vs. sententialism 642, 643 immediacy 516–34 self‐presentational 518–20, 530–4 implementation, see realization impressions 224, 269–72 indeterminacy, phenomenal 264, 265 indeterminism, quantum mechanical 54, 59 Page 17 of 37

Index indexicals 378 indicator semantics, see semantics, information‐theoretic individualism, see also content, narrow anti‐ 227, 749, 771 individuation of concepts, see concepts, individuation of of objects 34 of properties 47 of propositional attitude types, see attitudes, propositional sortal‐relative 578–86 inexistence, intentional 521, 522, see also intentionality and non‐existent objects inference 397–405, see also reasoning and memory, see memory and inference information 382–4, 528, 533 and quantum mechanics 214 processing 285–9, 466, 467, 614–26, 651 ‐theoretic semantics, see semantics, information‐theoretic instrumentalism 346 intelligence 132, 140, 348, 395, 608–10, 617–20 intension 379 epistemic 376–8 primary vs. secondary 318, 320–26, 328, 331 intention 109 n. 1, 124, 691–708 ‐dependent properties 117–19, 124 of a speaker 353, 354 intentionalism 474–91, see also representationalism pure vs. impure 479–90 intentionality 30, 48, 67, 139–42, 144, 149, 190, 199–202, 207 n. 2, 214, 394–406, 414, 417, 418, 512–35, 609–13, 621–5 and content 244–50, 477, 478, 497, 498 and mode 475–8 and non‐existent objects 476 and normativity, see norms and phenomenology, 512–35, see also separatism as self‐transcendence 476 as the mark of the mental 474, 490 intrinsic 632, 642, see also intentionality, original vs. derived objects of 474–90 of conscious states 482, 486–90 of moods 487–90 of perceptual and emotional states 486–90 of sensations 487–90 original vs. derived 343–6, 621, 625, see also meaning, original vs. derived phenomenal 512–35 realism about 531 intentional stance 339–49 in evolutionary biology 347–9 objections to the 346–8 Page 18 of 37

Index intentional systems theory 339–49 and first‐order vs. second‐order intentional systems 344, 345 interactionism 35 interests, practical vs. theoretical 355, 358, 363 internalism about content, see content, externalism vs. internalism about interpreted logical forms (ILF) 408, 415 interpreted utterance forms (IUF) 415 (p. 806) introspection 741–64, see also self‐knowledge and consciousness 209, 247–9, 258–61, 292, 393, 304–7 INUS, see causation, INUS account of inverted earth, see qualia and inverted earth inverted spectrum, see qualia and inverted spectrum Ismael, J. 324 Israel, D. 229, 381 Jackson, F. 58, 64, 87–9, 93 n. 7, 157 n. 6, 159 n., 160 n. 9, 161–4, 181, 223, 235, 256 n., 262, 265 n., 274 n., 284, 299 n., 300, 302, 315, 328, 329, 475 n. 3, 480 n., 638, 702, 727, 731 Jacob, P. 49 James, W. 210, 214–17, 555–60, 561 n. 52, 562, 566, 569, 574, 575, 682–7 Johnson, M. K. 672 Johnson‐Laird, P. N. 639 Johnston, M. 446, 482, 587 n. 26, 660, 783–6 judgment 679–87 Kahneman, D. 789 Kalke, W. 138 Kandel, E. 663 Kane, R. 693 Kant, I. 190, 197, 203, 241 n. 2, 545 n. 11, 548, 549, 555, 557 n. 39, 558, 559, 565–70, 596, 653, 755 Kaplan, D. 649 Kaufman, A. 693 Keeley, B. 530 Kenny, A. 542, 543, 685 Kierkegaard, S. 782 Kim, J. 29, 32 n., 35 n. 7, 37 n. 12, 40 n., 41–4, 47 n., 62, 66, 72, 79, 91, 99–101, 105, 106, 109–11, 113–120, 121 n. 16, 124, 125, 142, 147, 149, 160, 165, 168, 170, 206 n., 211, 217, 392, 513, 514, 517 Kind, A. 475 n. 3, 479 kinds, see also properties fundamental 66, 71 mental 37, 38, 128, 131–7, 143, 148, natural 166, 167, 351–6, 424, see also concepts, natural kind Kirk, R. 256 n., 302 n. 30, 324 Kistler, M. 92 Knobe, J. 695, 696, 698, 700–1 knowledge 608, 609, 613, 618 and acquaintance 648–51 grounding of 651 Page 19 of 37

Index of reference 654–7, 660, see also revelation of self, see self‐knowledge of truths 648–51, 657, 660 propositional 661 knowledge argument 174, 185, 233–7, 295, 296, 313, 323 Kornblith, H. 120 n. 12, 122 n. 21, 123 n., 666, 674, 723 Kosslyn, S. 599 n. 8, 642 Kratzer, A. 422 Kriegel, U. 248, 290, 293 n. 5, 502 n. 19, 514 n. 5, 519 Kripke, S. A. 77, 163 n. 16, 165, 166, 170, 281, 283, 284, 300, 314, 316, 320, 324–8, 330, 333 n., 377 n. 9, 425 n. 8, 426 n. 11, 429–31, 450, 504 n. 22 Kripke test 166, 170 Kusch, M. 717 Lachs, J. 90 Laird, J. D. 682 La Mettrie, J. O. de, 178 Lange, C. G. 682 Langsam, H. 753, 754 n. language and concept possession, see concepts, possession conditions of and non‐linguistic creatures, see concepts, possession conditions of and thought 631–46 as a tool 641 of thought 296, 297, 361 n. 19, 386, 408, 418, 616, 631, 632, 637, 674, 755, see also Men­ talese philosophy of 421 productivity of 612 public 356 n. 9, 408, 430 systematicity of 611–21 understanding of 458, 463, 467 Larson, R. 408, 413, 415 n. Latham, N. 101 Lawlor, K. 663, 672, 674 laws 36, 37, 44–7 and counterfactuals 97, 103 bridge‐, see bridge laws causal 45 conservation 45, 55–7, 91, 92, 208 ceteris paribus 36, 97, 98, 430 deterministic 57, 97, 98 exceptionless 36, 96–8 natural 45, 284, 322 n. 1, 329–31 of special sciences 38, 39, 43–8, 98, 99 physical 36, 37, 44, 63, 103, 340–2 see also physics psychological 36, 37, see also anomalism psychophysical 36, 79, 80, 96, 97, see also anomalism strict 36, 37, 97, 98 Lazarus, R. S. 680 Page 20 of 37

Index learning 395–8, 404 LeDoux, J. E. 681 (p. 807) Leibniz, G. W. 29, 56, 190, 209, 210, 216, 217, 237, 441, 445, 555, 569 Lepore, E. 37 n. 12, 99, 103, 111, 467 n. 6 Leslie, A. 344 Lettvin, J. 527 Levenson, R.W. 682 Levin, J. 304, 305 n. Levine, J. 77, 88, 119, 154, 155 n., 157, 158, 185, 249, 270–2, 274, 281, 284, 288, 290, 300, 309, 534 Lewis, D. 90 n., 91 n., 110, 111, 131, 132, 135, 136, 160, 164 n., 184 n. 23, 286, 302, 426 n. 10, 586, 661, 775 Lewontin, R. 88 Libet, B. 81, 246, Lieberman, A. 790 Lindsay, P. 131 Loar, B. 288, 289, 296, 303, 305, 306, 333, 355, 356, 362–4, 370, 374, 377 n. 10, 514 n. 5 Locke, J. 199, 224, 240, 241, 273, 276, 353, 579–89, 612, 626, 633, 643, 731, 755 Lockwood, M. 197, 214, 566, 570, 574 Loewer, B. 37 n. 12, 44, 45, 99, 103, 111, 114, 181 Loftus, E. 723 Logie, R. H. 672 look‐up table 347, 348, 434 n. 19, 618, 620, 623 Lowe, E. J. 59, 66–8, 71–83, 588 n., 695 luck 699–701 Ludlow, P. 408, 415 n., 673, 769, 770, 772 luminosity 294 Lurie, Y. 97 Lycan,W. 135, 139, 140, 144, 177, 180, 241, 242, 256 n., 269, 287, 288, 480 n., 745 n., 755, 756, 760 Lynch, M. 324 Macdonald, C. 741, 760 machines 608–11, 614–24, 627 Mackie, J. 90, 582 n. 11 magnetosomes 400, 403 Malcolm, N. 234, 732 Malebranche, N. 29, 730, 731, 737 manner, see mode many‐property problem 262 maps cognitive 465 mental 638, 639 Marañon, G. 682 Marcel, A. J. 244, 245, 570 Marcus, E. 324 Marcus, R. B. 163 n. 16 Marks, C. 570 Marr, D. 357, 458, 467 Page 21 of 37

Index Martin, C. B. 195, 196, 642, 644–6, 665 Martin, M. G. F. 461 n., 482–6, 495 n. 3, 507, 666–8 Martin, N. 673 Martin, R. 588 n. Marton, P. 332 Marx, K. 782 Mary thought experiment, see Knowledge Argument materialism 95, 96, 105, 290, 584–6, 612, see also monism; naturalism; physicalism about phenomenal consciousness 256 non‐reductive (NRM) 109–28 two‐dimensionalist arguments against 313–34 matter and extension 31, 37 and identity 579–85 as mind‐independent 189, 204 causal powers of 191–8 concept of 191, 194 dispositional notion of 195–7 Matthen, M. 381 Matthews, R. J. 407–10, 415, 419 Maxwell, G. 197 McCann, H. 692, 693, 697–8, 705 McClelland, J. L. 628, 666 McCormack, T. 665, 669 McCracken, C. J. 731 McCulloch, G. 486 n. McDowell, J. 99, 256 n., 369, 458, 460 n., 463–8, 494, 507 n. 26, 508, 509, 666, 744, 750, 751, 754 n. McGee, V. 560 n. 48 McGeer, V. 746 McGeever, J. 217 McGinn, C. 264 n. 12, 368, 507, 508, 514 n. 5, 519, 534, 595, 597 n. 4 & 5, 599 n. 8 & 10, 600 n. 12, 602 n., 604 n. 16, 704, 738, 742, 772 McKinsey, M. 772, 773 McKitrick, J. 120 n. 13 McKoon, G. 666 McLaughlin, B. 37, 57, 97, 99, 101–4, 106, 158, 162, 163, 181–4, 207, 210, 279, 284, 288, 306, 307, 333, 479, 480 n., 560 n. 48, 628, 741 n. 1, 773, 774, 776, 784, 786 McNally, P. 783 Mead, G. H. 545 meaning 48, 352, 356, 367, 368, 373, 381–92, see also content; intentionality and history, see history and meaning and necessary and sufficient conditions 165 as normative 421–35 individuation of 368, 373 in language 610–14, 623 grounding of 381, 387 natural vs. non‐natural 382–90 Page 22 of 37

Index of mental predicates 153, 162, 164–9, 339 (p. 808)

original vs. derived 382, see also intentionality, original vs. derived and synonymy 153, 154 and use 424–32 measurement‐theory numerical 410, 411 and propositional attitudes 407–19 measure predicate 408–15 mechanisms cognitive 537–63 computational 537–63 semantic interpretation of 538–61 Meehl, P. E. 212 n. Meixner, U. 69, 79 Melden, A. 706 Mele, A. R. 113, 625 n. 17, 691, 692–708, 782, 787–90 Mellor, D. H. 46, 57, 67, 184 Melnyk, A. 175 n. 4, 178 n. 10, 179–81, 184 n. 23, 284 Meltzoff, M. 471 n. 9, 724 memory 48, 141, 142, 254, 435, 572, 596, 598, 605, 663–75, 723, 750 and agency, see agency and memory and inference 672–4 and realism about the past 664, 665 and representation 665–7 and the self 555, 562, 582, 627, 667–71 episodic 663, 665, 667–74 short term 557, n. 40 Mentalese 297, 346, 616, see also language of thought Menzies, P. 46 Merricks, T. 69, 584, 588 n. Mill, J. S. 257, 626, 701 n. 20, 728, 731 n. 7 Miller, A. 467 n. 7 Millikan, R. G. 133, 134, 373, 382, 394–6, 401–6, 625 n. 16, 673 Mills, E. 46 mind as a fundamental natural kind 177, 180–6 disembodiment of 69, 74, 333 n. 2, 679 immaterial 38 mind‐body problem 29, 41, 109, 130, 138, 139, 142, 160, 180–6, 207, 293 n. 5, 303 n. 33 and reductive explanation 160 mind‐reading 305, see also folk psychology misrepresentation 249, 387, 388, 487 Mitchell, K. J. 672 mode of existing 549, 554 intentional 488–91, 498, 503 vs. content 477, 488, 489 Page 23 of 37

Index of presentation 480 n. 8, 506–9 object‐dependent 507 object‐involving 508 of phenomenal concepts, see concepts, phenomenal model, mental, see maps, mental Moll, J. 683 Molnar, G. 195, 196 Montague, M. 478, 494 Montero, B. 173, 174 n. 3, 185 n. 24 Moore, G. E. 21, 261 n. 7, 273–5, 501, 652–6 monism, see also materialism; naturalism; physicalism anomalous, see anomalous monism causal argument for, see physicalism, causal argument for physical vs. phenomenal 37 Russellian 322, 323 morality, see action, intentional Moran, D. 474 n., 749 Morgan, C. 210 Morris, M. 423 n. 7 Morton, A. 713, 714, 716, 723 Moscovitch, M. 669 Moser, P. 703–5 motivation 678–89, 692, 693, 698, 699 intrinsic 698, 699 Mourelatos, A. 208 Mumford, S. 194, 195 Nagel, E. 110 n., 134 Nagel, T. 183, 211, 212, 218, 225, 281, 300, 307, 516, 570, 573, 706, 727 n. 2 narratives 667, 671, see also self, narrative Natsoulas, T. 249 naturalism 53, 60, 96, 218, 547, see also materialism; monism; physicalism methodological vs. ontological 60, 61 regarding intentionality 394–6, 424 nature, hidden 353, 354 underlying physical 60 Neander, K. 249 n. 9, 404 necessity 313, 316, 318–33 Newton, I. 56, 445 Newtonian physics 56, 57, 191, 192 Nichols, S. 348, 714 Nida‐Rümelin, M. 300, 301 n. 27 Nietzsche, F. 546, 782 Nisbett, R. E. 243, 723, 789 Noonan, H. 582 n. 10, 584 Noordhof, P. 43, 125 n. 25 Norman, D. 131 normativity of the intentional, see norms norms 99 Page 24 of 37

Index expressivism about, see expressivism about norms of the intentional 421–35 reductive account of 423–5 truth‐conditional account of 422, 423, 427 (p. 809) Nozick, R. 555 Nuccitelli, S. 673 Nussbaum, M. C. 679 objects 31–5, 43 abstract 201, 439, 440, 443, 444 and propertiedness 546, 548 n. 17, 549, 551 as bearers of properties 66–8, 72 individuation of, see individuation of objects intentional 476–8, 488–90, see also intentionality, objects of mind‐independent 497, 503, 504 problem of coincident 34 of intentionality, see intentionality, objects of tracking properties of 470 O’Connor, T. 41, 701 n. 20 O’Dea, J. 475 n. 3, 480 n. 8 Öhman, A. 679 Olson, E. T. 72, 543, 582 n. 10, 584 n. 16 & 17, 586 n. 22, 588, 589 ordinary‐language philosophy 201 O’Shaughnessy, B. 597 n. 4, 699 other minds 89, 714, 727–39 argument from 88, 89 existence of vs. contents of 727–9 scepticism about 733–5 overdetermination 46, 79, 125, 174 acceptable vs. unacceptable 62, 113 and causal exclusion 39 argument 114 problem of 38 strong vs. weak 63, 64 Owens, J. 771 pain 270, 276–8, 286–9, 480, 487–9, see also experience; experiences; qualia and behaviour 728–39 pairing problem, see cause‐effect pairing panpsychism 177, 180, 206–18 history of, 207–11 arguments for 211–16 arguments against 216–18 Papineau, D. 45, 46, 53, 57, 77, 157, 158, 162, 163, 184 n. 23, 185, 294 n. 8 &10, 296 n. 13, 298 n., 305–9, 333, 382 Parfit, D. 566, 569 n. 4, 570, 587 n. 25 Pargetter, R. 728 Parsons, T. 476 particulars abstract 408, 409, 412 Page 25 of 37

Index past, see memory Patterson, S. 356 n. 8 Peacocke, C. 199, 264 n. 12, 274, 275, 279, 297 n. 19, 346, 348, 425 n. 8, 430 n., 437, 458, 460 n., 462–71, 494, 664, 665, 699 Pears, D. 692 n. 3 Pepper, C. 212 n. percept 595–605 perception 223–33, 268–79, 444, 445, 448–50, 457–71 active vs. passive 224 and discrimination 463–5, 468–70 and experience, see experience, perceptual and thought, see thought and perception factivity or veridicality of 225 n. 1 higher‐order 144, 242, 243, 502 indirect 518 non‐conscious 526, 527 particularity account of 507, 508 somatosensory 480, 481, 496, 561 Pereboom, D. 114, 119, 120 n. 12, 122 n. 20 & 21, 123 n. Perner, J. 719 Perry, J. 223, 229, 233 n., 234 n., 304, 324, 381, 582 n. 11, 669, 670 persistence conditions 73, 74, 582, 588 personhood, see identity, personal persons, see identity, personal perspectival constraint 461–3 Pettit, P. 58, 93 n. 7, 702 phantom pains 75, 230, 489, 524 phenomenal‐concept strategy 302–9 phenomenology 512–35 and intentionality, see intentionality and phenomenology of agency 525 of attitude content 525 of attitude type 525 cognitive 496–509 of experience, see experiences, phenomenology of, see also qualia Phillips, J. 545 Phillips, M. L. 688 physicalism 30, 31, 36–42, 45–8, 173–89, 281–5, 302–9, 475, 486, 546–8, 551, 558, 562, see also materialism; monism; naturalism about properties 152–73 and ghosts 175–8 and mind‐body identity theory 102, 281–8 and physics 154, 173–87 a priori vs. a posteriori 157 n. 6, 158, 159 n. 8, 162–4 arguments against 300–2 as a scientific hypothesis 179, 180 causal argument for 37, 174 non‐reductive 39–43, 47, 48, 62, see also materialism, non‐reductive (NRM) Page 26 of 37

Index substances vs. properties 152 physics 44, 110, 111, 173–87, 272 and fundamental categories 43, 44, 57, 58, 180–6 complete / furture 178, 181–4 (p. 810)

current 44, 178–84 language of 191 naïve 471 scope of 175, 182–3 Pietroski, P. M. 405 Pink, T. 693 Pitcher, G. 685 Pitt, D. 496 n., 514 n. 5 Place, U. T. 129, 154, 211 Planck, M. 272–3 Plato, 152, 782 Poland, J. 176, 178, 181 n. 17, 184 n. 23 Polger, T. 43 n. Pomerantz, J. R. 642 Popper, K. 87 possession conditions of concepts; see concepts, possession conditions of possibility and conceivability, see conceivability and possibility and imagination; see imagination and possibility epistemic 70 metaphysical 70, 316–24, 326–8, 330 of zombies, see zombies, possibility of primary vs. secondary (1‐ vs. 2‐) 318–24, 328–32 Povinelli, D. 721 powers, see dispositions; capacities, causal planning, see reasoning, practical predicates for natural kinds 166, 167, 351–3, 368, 378 and properties 153–71 as rigid designators 162, 166–70 Premack, D. 345 priming effects 245, 249 principle of charity 428, 429 principle of causal interaction 97 Prinz, J. 678, 682, 686 Pritchard, D. 773 private language argument 298, 732 processing cognitive 418 visual 357 productivity of symbol system 398, 412, 612 properties Carnap’s notion of 153 Page 27 of 37

Index causally relevant 391 constitution of 120–5 dispositional 18, 215 dualism, see dualism, property functional 63, 117, 118 identity of, see identity of properties intrinsic 32–5, 351–3 levels of 155, 156 n. 5, 158, 168 levels of vs. orders of 47, 116–18 mental 30, 37–43, 46, 47, 95, 96, 100–6 intrinsic vs. extrinsic 31, 32, 148, 149 micro vs. macro 112 n. 6, 116–19 phenomenal, see qualia physical vs. non‐physical 38, 152–73, see also physicalism about properties as requiring identity 152–5 as requiring reductive explanation 155–7 as requiring supervenience 160, 161 pluralism of 38 n. 13, see also dualism, property relational 32, 33, 368–72 semantic 163, 227 propositions, Russellian 408 protolanguage 644, 645 protophenomenal 197, 293 n. 4, 322 Pryor, J. 773 psychofunctionalism 286 psychology of animals 339, 342–5 autonomy of 48 cognitive 130, 419 commonsense 355, 356, 358, 361–4, see also folk psychology computational 132, 419, 450 experimental 243–6 folk theories of, see folk psychology gestalt 570 introspective 273 scientific 210, 211, 370–3 purpose, see also goal biological 395–8, 402–5 Putnam, H. 46, 106, 111, 112, 129–33, 135, 160 n. 11, 165, 173, 184, 285, 351–3, 356, 367–9, 373, 375, 379, 450, 477 n. 6, 504 n. 22, 615, 714, 749, 768, 775, 776 Pylyshyn, Z. 611, 612, 628, 642 qualia 42, 43, 77, 78, 169, 270, 271 absent 145–8 and inverted earth 255, 264–6 and inverted spectrum 145–8, 255, 256, 263–6 and phenomenal aspects / properties 225, 314, 315, 320–3, 514 n. 2 and phenomenal character 211, 213, 254–65, 268, 479–90 and phenomenal consciousness 253–8, 266, 313–34, 513–24, see also consciousness Page 28 of 37

Index and purely qualitative states 517 and the distinctiveness problem 480 and qualia‐based arguments for dualism, see dualism, qualia‐based arguments for and verification procedures 145 as supervening on representational content 502 dancing 327 (p. 811)

epistemic relation to 292–4, 299–301, 307–9 experiential 132, 143, 144, 225, 235 representationalist theories of, see representationalism subjective character of 225 qualities, see also properties sensory 268–76, 279, 628 mind‐dependent 203 primary and secondary 191, 200, 208, 761 sensible 271–9 quantum mechanics 210, 212, 217, 549 and indeterminism 54, 59, 214 Quine, W. V. 44, 182, 409, 440, 476, 529, 531, 533, 713 Quinn, W. 699 Raffman, D. 515 n. Ramsey, W. 628 Ratcliff, R. 666 rationalism 612 rationality 100–2, 339–49, see also action, rational and rational agents 132, 137, 139, 140, 339–49 and rational coherence 133 and rational intentions 697 and self‐deception, see belief and rationalization Raymont, P. 46, 565, 567 Rea, M. 584 n. 15 realism about the mental 42, 179, 423 about qualia 293–6 and relativism 179 about the physical 198–204 direct 498–507 naïve 191 reality fundamental 202 levels of 212–4 realizability, see realization realization 62–4, 92, 93, 137, 138, 142, 285, 431 and levels 135, 136, 139 multiple 62–4, 130–5, 138–43, 158, 160, 165, see also functionalism and multiple realizability and functions 139, 149 ultimate 143, 144 reasoning 424–7, 431–5, 608, 610, 616 Page 29 of 37

Index defeasible 433 practical 339, 399, 401, 404, 433, 562, 692, 722, 784 reasons acting for 694, 695, 699–702, 707 recognition 224, 232–5 reducibility, see reduction reduction 39, 42–4, 86, 93, 206, 210–12, 217, see also supervenience and identity 506 of folk psychology to physics 96 reductionism, see monism; naturalism; physicalism reference 352–6, 368, 369, 377, 446–8, 685, 686 and causal contact 648, 649 and consciousness, see consciousness and reference by causation 685 by description, 685, 686 fixing of 356, 650–3 knowledge of, see knowledge of reference of phenomenal concepts, see concepts, phenomenal reflex action 609, 610 Reid, T. 273 n., 276, 501 n. 14, 504, 569, 581 n. 6, 731, 732, 736, 737 relations 190, 200–4 reportability of mental states 243, 247, see also introspection representation 48, 381–92, 394–406, 457–71, 475–90, 494–509, 609–26 analogue 296, 305, 308, 644 and content, see content descriptive vs. iconic 396–406 explicit 345 false, see misrepresentation higher‐order, see HOT (higher‐order thought) in language vs. pictures, see imagism vs. sententialism pictorial, 632, 636–8, see also imagery, pictorial pushmi‐pullyu 396–8, 401, 402, 405, 406 vehicles of 294 n. 8, 297, 306, 637–43 representationalism 502–4, 524, 525, see also intentionalism and phenomenal consciousness 144–9, 253–67, 287, 288 and the representational theory of mind (RTM) 296, 297, 416 arguments for 260–5 externalist vs. internalist 257 Fregean 257–9 reductive vs. non‐reductive 257–9 strong vs. weak 256, 257 revelation 659–61 Revonsuo, A. 567 Rey, G. 294 n. 6, 785, 786 Richard, M. 408, 413 Ridge, M. 692 Rips, L. 639 Rives, B. 43 Page 30 of 37

Index Robins, R. W. 683 (p. 812) Robinson, J. 682 Robinson, H. 189, 191 n. 1, 192 n., 194, 198 n., 302, 505 n. Robinson, W. S. 78, 87 robots 132, 146, 160, 339, 343, 622 intelligent, 285, 286 non‐conscious 495 role conceptual 141, 623–5 functional 131, 132, 137, 145–7 and content 375, 376 of perception vs. beliefs 460 Rollins, M. 642, 646 n. Roseman, I. 680 Rosen, G. 422 n. 5, 423 n. 6 & 7 Rosenberg, G. 215 Rosenthal, D. 144, 147, 239, 242–6, 249 n. 10, 250, 273 n., 287, 293 n. 5, 482 n. 12, 502 n. 17, 568, 755, 756 Ross, D. 344 Ross, G. H. T. 29 n., 177 Ross, L. 723, 789 Rovane, C. 588, 589 Ruddick, W. 792 Rumelhart, D. E. 628, 666 Rumfitt, I. 445 Russell, B. 176, 183 n., 197, 215, 275, 290, 292 n. 3, 322, 643, 648–51, 656, 659–61, 664, 753 Ryle, G. 129, 194, 702, 728, 742, 745, 746 Sabates, M. 46 Sainsbury, M. 650 Salmon, N. 369, 478 Sanfey, A. G. 683 Sanford, D.H. 791 Sartre, J. P. 513, 598 n. 6, 782, 792 Sawyer, S. 772, 774 Scanlon, T. 694 n. 10, 699 Schacter, D. 663–8, 672 Schaffer, J. 125 Scherer, K. R. 680 Schiffer, S. 327, 364, 440, 446, 451, 452, 478, 497 n. 8 schizophrenia 571–3 Schnall, S. 682 Schütte, M. 167 n. 22 sciences, special, see laws, of special sciences Scott‐Kakures, D. 787, 789, 790 Scruton, R. 73, 600 n. 13 Seager, W. 206, 208, 217, 520, 524 Searle, J. R. 48, 148, 226 n. 2, 243, 264 n. 12, 421, 467 n. 6, 477 n. 5, 480, 487, 488 n., 499, 514, 524, 526, 530, 575, 620–2, 625, 692, 693, 701 n. 20, 703, 705 Page 31 of 37

Index Sedivy, S. 460 n. Segal, G. 49, 125 n. 25, 166 n., 353–8, 367, 372, 373 n., 374–6, 379, 413, 415 n., 504 n.23 Sehon, S. 702 selection, natural, see evolution self 67–76, 81, 82, 223–8, 236, 541–63 and memory, see memory and the self and personality 545, 547, 562 as subject of experience, see experience, subject of as transient 550, 551 awareness of 144, 243 Buddhist conception of 555, 560 ecological 545 identity and persistence 67–82, 560–2, see also identity, personal illusion of 223 narrative 545, 560 n. 49, 562 reality and existence of 541, 545–9, 554, 559–60 social 545 transparency of 741, 744 self‐deception and denial 781–3 and dispositional belief, see belief, dispositional vs. occurrent and emotions, see emotions and self‐deception and rationalization, see belief and rationalization deflationary approaches to 784–7 twisted 787, 788 self‐knowledge 729, 730, 739, see also introspection and externalism 767–78 and transparency, see self, transparency of as incorrigible 741, 744 as privileged 741, 744, 745 Sellars, W. 85, 212 n., 246, 713 Selten, R. 789 semantics 48, 611, 625 n. 17, 626, see also biosemantics; teleosemantics conceptual role 381 consumer 382 formal 407, 413, 422 information‐theoretic 381–92 naturalized 389 possible world 462 procedural 381 two‐dimensional 313–33 objections to 324–7 sense data 263, 268, 274, 275 Fregean, see Fregean sense impressions 269, 272 sententialism, see imagism vs. sententialism separatism and inseparatism 514–36 Page 32 of 37

Index Seyfarth, R. 344, 611 (p. 813) Shapiro, L. A. 43 n. Shoemaker, S. 92 n., 119, 120, 145–7, 246, 256 n., 259 n. 5, 322 n., 329, 330, 566, 574, 582 n. 11, 583 n. 12 & 13, 584 n. 16, 586 n. 21 & 24, 672, 741 n. 2, 754, 756 Sidelle, A. 330 Sider, T. 543 n. 7, 584, 589 Siegel, S. 499 Siegler, F. A. 783 Siewert, C. 475 n. 3, 482, 486 n., 496 n., 514, 522 sign, natural 275–9, 401–4 Silins, N. 773 simultagnosia 572, 573 skepticism about other minds, see other minds, skepticism about about phenomenal content 525 Skrbina, D. 208, 211 Slater, A. 471 n. 9 Smart, J. J. C. 129, 154, 174, 175, 180, 211, 274 Smith, B. 570 Smith, C. 680 Smith, D. 496 n., 502 n.19 Smith, M. 692 n. 2 Smith, Q. 194 n. Smolensky, P. 628 Snowdon, P. 177, 495 n. 2 Soames, S. 324, 369, 478 Sober, E. 49, 125 n. 25 solipsism 625, 728, 730, 731, 735–7 Solomon, R. 679 Sosa, E. 37 n. 12, 587 n. 26, 745 soul 40, 72, 110, 152, 174, 283, 347, 544–8, 553, 559, 608, 731, see also dualism, substance and spatio‐temporal location 31–4 Sousa, R. de, 680 Spelke, E. S. 471 n. 9, 561 n. 51, 616 Sperry, R. W. 36, 41 Spinoza, B. 29, 208–10, 678–80 Sprigge, T. 200, 204 n. 7 Squire, R. 663 Stalnaker, R. 156 n., 158, 159, 162, 163, 165, 324, 328, 408, 462, 666 Stampe, D. 381 state abstract, higher‐order 285–8 cognitive 67, 227–9, 235 computational 458 information‐processing 466 inherently conscious 253, 254 of affairs 199–203 psychological 352, 362–4, 367–75 Page 33 of 37

Index narrow vs. wide, see content, narrow; content, wide subpersonal vs. personal‐level states 458 Statman, D. 792 Sterelney, K. 721 Stich, S. 42 n., 133, 348, 373, 628, 685, 714 stimuli, sensory 224, 230 recognition and interpretation of, see recognition Stoljar, D. 197, 301 n. 29, 303 n. 35, 324, 475 n. 3, 482 Stoutland, F. 37 n. 11 Strawson, G. 176 n. 7, 177 n. 9, 212, 215, 496 n., 514 n. 5, 516, 517, 526, 532, 533, 541, 543 n. 3, 549 n. 20, 551, 552 n. 24, 555, 560 n. 48, 562 Strawson, P. F. 75, 199, 484, 569 n. 3, 570, 595 n., 596 n. 3, 713, 732 Stuart, M. 273 Sturgeon, S. 303 n. 33, 332 subject, see self subjectivity 223–8, 254–8, 260, 263, 264, 292, 294–6, 309, see also first‐person perspective definition of 229 epistemology of 229, 230 substance 29–34 dualism, see dualism, substance immaterial 31–3 material 30–3 mental, see substance, immaterial supervenience 38–46, 62–4, 92, 96, 105–7, 110, 117, 118, 121–5, 160, 161, 174, 177, 185 and anomalous monism, see anomalous monism and supervenience and dependence 105, 106, 110 and necessity 40 and type‐identity 62 argument 38–46 of phenomenal character on representational content 479–86, 502–4 of properties 62 weak vs. strong vs. global 105, 106, 111 Suppes, P. 408 n., 411 Sutton, J. 666 Sverdlik, S. 695, 700 n. Swamp Mary 295 Swampman 134, 391, 530 Swinburne, R. 68, 183, 584 Swoyer, C. 408 n., 410 symbol‐world relation 381, 399, 400 symbols 381–92 syntax 611 Taliaferro, C. 183 Taylor, S. E. 793 teleosemantics 308, 396, 759 n. teletransportation, see identity, personal terms, singular 352 (p. 814) Thalberg, L. 692 n. 5, 694 n. 9, 703, 705 Page 34 of 37

Index Thales of Milet, 208, 214 that‐clauses 355, 356, 362–5, 407–15, 438, 439, 449–51, 595 Thau, M. 475 n. 3 theory of mind 719, see also folk psychology theory‐theory, see folk psychology and theory thinking 607–28, see also thought as a two‐place relation 497 third‐person perspective 183, 287, 288 Thomas, N. J. T. 324, 642 n. Thomasson, A. 114, 502 n.19 Thomson, J. 694 n. 9 thought 640–2 and language, see language and thought and perception 681–6 contents vs. feels 226 expression of 640, 641 higher‐order, see HOT (higher‐order thought) non‐conscious 645, 646 object‐involving 352 reflexive 668–71 Tienson, J. 486 n., 496 n., 512, 515 n., 524, 531 Tiffany, E. C. 101, 102 time 665–73 Tracy, J. L. 683 transparency as an argument for representationalism 260–2, 503 of experience 294, 299, 482–4, 501, 502, 568, 575, 651–5 of phenomenal concepts, see concepts, phenomenal of the self, see self, transparency of of thought 741, 744, 750 semantic 633 Trefil, J. 543 Trevarthen, C. 570, 572 n. Trope, Y. 790 truth 354–7, 446–8 bearers 202 conditions 226, 446, 453 correspondence theory of 199 normative 422, 423, 427, 428 truth‐maker theory 202, 203 Tulving, E. 663, 668–71 Turing, A. M. 612, 614–17, 621 Turing machine 132, 614, 615 Turing test 347,348, 434 n. 19, 617–19 Twin Earth 317, 318, 325, 352, 355–7, 367–79, 389, 673, 749–51, 760, 768–72, 775 two‐dimensionalism, see semantics, two‐dimensional; materialism, two‐dimensional arguments against two‐factor theories of content, see content, two‐factor theories of Page 35 of 37

Index Tye, M. 97, 144, 149, 253, 256 n., 259, 261 n. 8, 275 n., 287, 288, 293 n. 5, 296, 299 n., 302 n. 31, 304, 458, 461, 475 n. 3, 479–83, 487, 488, 504, 514 n. 2, 524, 530, 566–8, 574 n., 575, 642, 769, 776 Unger, P. 176 n. 7, 183 n., 582 n. 11, 584 n. 15, 585 n. 19, 586 n. 20 understanding functional 131, 134, 137, 139, 140 of concepts 522, 770, 777 of words 516, 620–4 unity argument for dualism 74, 76 of consciousness, see consciousness, unity of of the mind 512–35, see also separatism of the world, 144, 168, 169 uniqueness theorem 411, 412, 415, 417 universals 201 Urmson, J. 732 use vs. mention, 623, 624 Vahind, H. 770, 772 Valins, S. 682 Vartanian, O. 683 Van Cleve, J. 653 Van Fraassen, B. 182 Van Gulick, R. 43, 111, 116 n. 7, 128, 133, 143, 144, 148, 249 n. 11 Van Inwagen, P. 76, 551 n. 21, 584 n. 17 Velleman, J. D. 264 n. 12, 671, 692 n. 3, 702, 706, 707 verificationism 153, 298, 640, 664 Von Eckart, B. 357 Vonnegut, K. 640 n. 8 Wallace, R.J. 702 Walter, S. 85, 91, 93 n. 7, 290 Warfield, T. 114, 685, 772, 774 water and H2O 129, 154, 158, 159, 162–7, 173, 286–8, 300, 316–20, 325, 326, 352, 353, 367–9, 373, 377, 389, 673, 749, 761, 776, 777 vs. twater and XYZ 368, 371, 372, 375, 768–72, 775 Watson, R. A. 30 Webb, S. 348 Wedgwood, R. 421, 422 n. 2 Weizenbaum, J. 618, 619 Wellman, H. 719 Wheeler, M. 669 Whisner, W. N. 785 White, P. A. 243 White, S. 300, 301 n. 27, 307, 377 n. 10, 570, 760 Whitehead, A. 210, 214, 217, 546 (p. 815) Whiten, A. 344, 721 Wimmer, H. 719 Wiggins, D. 579 n. 1, 584 n. 17, 585 n. 19, 586 Wigner, E. 214 Page 36 of 37

Index Williamson, T. 372, 495 n. 3 Wilson, G. 692 n. 1, 701 n. 19, 702, 704 Wilson, R. 515 n., 534 Wilson, T. 243, 723 Wimsatt, W. 180 n. 13 Wittgenstein, L. 145, 276–8, 298, 302, 597, 598 n. 6, 599 n. 10, 631, 632, 634 n. 3, 640, 702, 732– 9, 749 Wollheim, R. 600 n. 13 Wong, H. J. 41 Wood, A. W. 786 Woodward, J. 45 Woodworth, R. S. 642 n. Woolhouse, R. 56 world, physical 173–89 as mind‐independent 189–99, 204 facts 160–4, 174, 181, 185, see also facts complete knowledge of 156, 163 n. 17, 164 notions of the 58, 181–6 as objective and not subjective 183 as relational and not intrinsic 181–3 Wright, C. 743, 744, 749, 754, 761 n. 20, 773 Wright, L. 134 Wundt, W. 19, 210, 561 n. 52, 568 Yablo, S. 41 n. 14, 49, 93 n. 7, 327, 331 Yalowitz, S. 102 Yoo, J. 95 Zahavi, D. 499 n. 11, 502 n. 19 zero‐crossing 257, 458 Zimmerman, D. 584 Zinnes, J. 408 n., 411 zombies 185, 314, 391, 727 n. 2 conceivability of 300–9, 317, 322–9 functional 145–7 possibility of 64, 173, 174, 487 (p. 816)

Page 37 of 37