Sein und Schein: Explorations in Existential Semiotics 9781614516354, 9781614517511

Existential semiotics is a new paradigm in the studies of signs, signification and communication. This book develops its

234 24 6MB

English Pages 478 Year 2015

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Polecaj historie

Sein und Schein: Explorations in Existential Semiotics
 9781614516354, 9781614517511

Table of contents :
Preface to Sein und Schein
Contents
Part I Philosophy: Varieties of Being
1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing)
1.1 Introduction
1.2 A return to basic ideas
1.3 Modalities
1.4 Dasein and transcendence
1.5 Turn-around of Dasein
1.6 Values
1.7 New types of signs
1.8 More on transcendence
1.9 Mimesis
1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING
1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING
1.11.1 Consequences of our varieties of subjectivity
2 On the appearance or the present structure and existential digressions of the subject
2.1 Introduction
2.2 More on vertical appearance
2.3 More on horizontal appearance
3 Representation in Semiotics
3.1 The relation of representation in semiotics
3.2 Mapping representation
3.3 Nöth’s handbook
3.4 Representation in philosophy – John Deely
3.5 Peirce
3.6 Model theory
3.7 From cybernetics to cultural semiotics
3.8 Representation as function
3.9 The archaeology of Foucault
3.10 Existential semiotic interpretation
4 The concept of genre: In general and in music
4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general ...
4.2 ... and inmusic
4.2.1 Before genres
4.2.2 Major genre categories: Art music and popular music
4.2.3 Norms and varieties of music
4.2.4 Genre in musical communication
4.2.5 Transgressing genres
4.2.6 Crises of genres
4.2.7 Cultural reflections
4.2.8 Classics
4.2.9 National versus universal
4.2.10 Social classification and functions
4.2.11 Genre as classification
4.2.12 Recent theories
5 The world and its interpretation
5.1 World and worlds
5.1.1 Philosophers
5.1.2 Artists
5.1.3 Semioticians
5.2 Closing thoughts
6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape
6.1 Introduction
6.2 Milieu – Taine
6.3 Surrounding/surrounded
6.4 New models of communication
6.5 Umwelt and Uexküll
6.6 Dasein . . .
6.7 ... and transcendence
6.8 Semiosphere, Lotman and Ruskin
6.9 Heidegger’s view
6.10 Subject and environment
Part II Doing: Society and Culture
7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation: Towards a new theory of collective and individual subjectivity
7.1 Introduction
7.2 The lesson of semiocrises
7.3 Collective subjectivity or identity as a world view
7.4 Individual subjectivity or the fight between two manners of ‘being’ in the world
8 Ideologies manifesting axiologies
8.1 Introduction
9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs
9.1 Globalization and transcendence
9.2 Globalization as the new civilization: Some signs of the time
9.3 Aesthetics of resistance
9.3.1 Forces of resistance I: Being
9.3.2 Forces of resistance II: Memory
9.3.3 Forces of resistance III: History
9.4 What are we resisting?
10 Culture and transcendence
10.1 The theory in brief
10.2 Transculturality
10.3 Criticism of British cultural studies
10.4 Language games
10.5 Articulation
10.6 Subject positions
10.7 What Foucault said
10.8 Action
10.9 Cultivating
10.10 Content and Speculation
10.11 The organism
10.12 Generation
10.13 Nature
10.14 Rhizome
10.15 Zemic/Zetic
10.16 Transfer
10.17 Alien-psychic
10.18 Conclusion
Part III Lesser Arts
11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts
11.1 General observations
11.1.1 Skill
11.1.2 Theory
11.1.3 Time
11.1.4 Emotions
11.1.5 Intentional body
11.1.6 Unpredictability
11.1.7 Schein
11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance
11.3 Performance in various arts
11.3.1 Performance of the text
11.3.2 Film performance-analysis
11.3.3 Varieties of actor/actress, musician, dancer
12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking
12.1 Introduction
12.2 Two historical perspectives
12.3 Semiotic questions about food
12.4 Cooking as a generative course
12.5 An application: cooking in Paris according to Ville Vallgren, Finnish sculptor and gourmet
12.6 Conclusion
Part IV Heimat
13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism
13.A.1 Introduction
13.A.2 What semioticians say about nature
13.A.3 Auguste Comte
13.A.4 German thinkers from Kant to Schiller
13.A.5 Différance
13.A.6 In biosemiotics
13.A.7 Semiogerms
13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music
13.B.1 On the musically “organic”
13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic”
13.B.3 Organic narrativity
14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician
14.1 Introduction
Part V Precursors
15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce (1855–1916), the American classic between Hegel and Peirce
15.1 Josiah Royce as a historical figure
15.2 Why Hegel?
15.3 Back to Royce
15.4 Toward the world of interpretation
15.5 The moral burden of the individual
15.6 Royce’s metaphysics and last insights on interpretation
16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by Susan Petrilli
16.1 Introduction
16.2 The challenge of originality
16.3 The idea of “three”
16.4 Royce as Lady Welby’s contemporary
16.5 Welby’s independence as a scholar
16.6 Who is a significian?
16.7 Problematic language
16.8 Metaphors
16.9 How to educate our expressive powers
16.10 Transcendence
17 Vladimir Solovyov
17.1 Background
17.2 Moral philosophy
17.3 Sophia and the World Soul
18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch
18.1 Introduction
18.2 Wassily Kandinsky
18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music
18.4 Lev Karsavin (1892–1952)
18.5 Wilhelm Sesemann
18.6 Vladimir Propp
18.7 Mikhail Bakhtin
19 Wilhelm Sesemann in the context of semiotics
19.1 Introduction
20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music
21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics
22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez
Part VI Practice
23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period
23.1 Introduction
23.2 Beginning: Lévi-Strauss, Greimas ... and Paris
23.3 The Impact of Thomas A. Sebeok
23.4 Semiotics expands
23.5 Imatra starts: Founding of the ISI
23.6 IASS Continues
23.7 The World Congress in Finland
23.8 From Italy to Bulgaria and Estonia
23.9 The Finnish Network University of Semiotics as an experiment
23.10 SEMKNOW
23.11 What do we want?
Literature
Index

Citation preview

Eero Tarasti Sein und Schein

Eero Tarasti

Sein und Schein

| Explorations in Existential Semiotics

ISBN 978-1-61451-751-1 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-1-61451-635-4 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-1-5015-0116-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 Walter de Gruyter Inc., Berlin/Boston Cover image: Alain Benainous/Gamma-Rapho/gettyimages Typesetting: PTP-Berlin, Protago-TEX-Production GmbH, Berlin Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com

Preface to Sein und Schein I have the feeling that the title of this book, once conceived in a talk with Anke Beck, my publisher, should indeed correspond to the contents. What is namely proposed here is that I start with rather philosophical reflections on what could be called ‘ontologico-transcendental’ issues of existential semiotics. So this is certainly about ‘Being’. Yet, what follows is, chapter by chapter, more about ‘Appearance’, i.e., the empirical world in which we live, from cultural case studies to performance and even such ‘lesser arts’ as gastronomy. The Reader may ask what the unifying factor behind such diversity then is. The answer is: the new phase of the existential semiotics, this paradigm of sign studies which I launched as early as 2000, with the first monograph published in English by Indiana University Press. It was followed by expanded and deepened versions in different languages in which the original theory was elaborated on in many directions. These were Fondements de la sémiotique existentielle 2009 (Paris: L’Harmattan) and Fondamenti di semiotica esistenziale 2009 (Roma, Bari: Giuseppe Laterza); moreover, they also appeared in these years in Bulgarian and Chinese; and translations into Turkish and Farsi are in process. In this avenue towards renewal of already existing ‘classical’ approaches to semiotics, my theory is growing from the roots of European semiotics, and particularly the so-called Paris school of semiotics, once created by A. J. Greimas. In this path, a.o., the semiotic square became a ‘Z-model’, and likewise many elements were changed. However, in this situation of ‘neosemiotics’ as I have called it, one can also continue to be Greimassian, Lotmanian, Peircean without worries – the classical theories do not lose their validity in the study of our Dasein. However, the new theory offers perhaps a broader context, or it is like Greimas put it ‘englobant’, surrounding. On the other hand, existential semiotics stems from the continental philosophy of the line from Kant, Hegel, and Kierkegaard to Heidegger, Jaspers, Arendt, Sartre, Marcel, and Wahl. What the word ‘existential’ immediately evokes to most is of course existentialism. Nevertheless, this is by no means to be understood as any kind of return to existentialism. We never go back, we are in 2015 now, and the theory written now has to reflect its particular conditions. What emerges is perhaps an effort to understand basic issues of the contemporary world, its ethical and axiological problems, even to propose a theory of resistance, answering to the same question once proposed by Lev Tolstoi: What do we have to do? Yet, my conviction is that a sermon does not help; we must have a theory if we want to get some more lasting effects.

vi | Preface to Sein und Schein So we are here on the way to a synthesis of both semiotic and philosophical tradition. It is obvious that we are moving towards the social issues, psychology of culture; although semiotics is never the same as psychology, its metalanguage is conceptual. Anyway, issues like Bakhtin’s dialogism, criticism of some cultural theories are the direction of these reflections. All this without forgetting the radical consequences which such difficult notions as ‘transcendence’ can bring to semiotics. However, and after all, is it not true that the whole semiotics is a transcendental art? Every act of communication is the effort of Mr. A to reach the ‘alien psychic’ (Fremdseelig) consciousness of Mr. B, to paraphrase a little de Saussure. And every sign, is it not referring to something absent, i.e., transcendental? Theories grow from other theories and from the works of other scholars. This is taken into account here with a panorama of precursors of existential semiotics, where rather amazing names may appear in this context. And all the work of semioticians has been made possible by certain organizing and institutional activities, which have made this esoteric science something experiential and concrete. This fact is recalled by the concluding chapter of the book, Can Semiotics Be Organized. My very special thanks go to all those scholars and institutions with whom I have been working in these years, from the ISI to the IASS. I am indebted about this constant dialogue to my colleagues as well as students in many countries and continents. Rick Littlefield has edited the majority of these chapters. Paul Forsell has been my irreplaceable help not only in the editorial work but in all my scholarly life. I warmly thank Kim Keskiivari for the proofreading. I dedicate this book to my wife, Eila, who has followed and supported it in all of its phases. My publisher Mouton de Gruyter I thank for a many years’ long, inspiring and pleasant cooperation. Helsinki, January 2015

Eero Tarasti

Contents Preface to Sein und Schein | v

Part I

Philosophy: Varieties of Being

1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) | 3 1.1 Introduction | 3 1.2 A return to basic ideas | 4 1.3 Modalities | 4 1.4 Dasein and transcendence | 5 1.5 Turn-around of Dasein | 8 1.6 Values | 10 1.7 New types of signs | 14 1.8 More on transcendence | 16 1.9 Mimesis | 18 1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING | 21 1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING | 28 1.11.1 Consequences of our varieties of subjectivity | 29 2 2.1 2.2 2.3

On the appearance or the present structure and existential digressions of the subject | 39 Introduction | 39 More on vertical appearance | 42 More on horizontal appearance | 50

3 3.1 3.2 3.3 3.4 3.5 3.6 3.7 3.8 3.9 3.10

Representation in Semiotics | 54 The relation of representation in semiotics | 54 Mapping representation | 55 Nöth’s handbook | 57 Representation in philosophy – John Deely | 58 Peirce | 59 Model theory | 60 From cybernetics to cultural semiotics | 61 Representation as function | 63 The archaeology of Foucault | 64 Existential semiotic interpretation | 66

viii | Contents 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music | 70 4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . . | 70 4.2 . . . and in music | 83 4.2.1 Before genres | 83 4.2.2 Major genre categories: Art music and popular music | 86 4.2.3 Norms and varieties of music | 88 4.2.4 Genre in musical communication | 89 4.2.5 Transgressing genres | 90 4.2.6 Crises of genres | 91 4.2.7 Cultural reflections | 92 4.2.8 Classics | 93 4.2.9 National versus universal | 93 4.2.10 Social classification and functions | 95 4.2.11 Genre as classification | 97 4.2.12 Recent theories | 98 5 5.1 5.1.1 5.1.2 5.1.3 5.2

The world and its interpretation | 100 World and worlds | 100 Philosophers | 101 Artists | 106 Semioticians | 109 Closing thoughts | 111

6 6.1 6.2 6.3 6.4 6.5 6.6 6.7 6.8 6.9 6.10

Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape | 113 Introduction | 113 Milieu – Taine | 113 Surrounding/surrounded | 115 New models of communication | 117 Umwelt and Uexküll | 118 Dasein . . . | 120 . . . and transcendence | 122 Semiosphere, Lotman and Ruskin | 124 Heidegger’s view | 125 Subject and environment | 128

Part II 7 7.1

Doing: Society and Culture Semio-crises in the era of globalisation: Towards a new theory of collective and individual subjectivity | 133 Introduction | 133

Contents |

7.2 7.3 7.4

The lesson of semiocrises | 134 Collective subjectivity or identity as a world view | 137 Individual subjectivity or the fight between two manners of ‘being’ in the world | 141

8 8.1

Ideologies manifesting axiologies | 144 Introduction | 144

9

9.3 9.3.1 9.3.2 9.3.3 9.4

Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs | 152 Globalization and transcendence | 152 Globalization as the new civilization: Some signs of the time | 154 Aesthetics of resistance | 158 Forces of resistance I: Being | 162 Forces of resistance II: Memory | 167 Forces of resistance III: History | 177 What are we resisting? | 180

10 10.1 10.2 10.3 10.4 10.5 10.6 10.7 10.8 10.9 10.10 10.11 10.12 10.13 10.14 10.15 10.16 10.17 10.18

Culture and transcendence | 182 The theory in brief | 184 Transculturality | 185 Criticism of British cultural studies | 187 Language games | 189 Articulation | 190 Subject positions | 192 What Foucault said | 193 Action | 195 Cultivating | 196 Content and Speculation | 198 The organism | 200 Generation | 201 Nature | 202 Rhizome | 203 Zemic/Zetic | 205 Transfer | 206 Alien-psychic | 208 Conclusion | 209

9.1 9.2

ix

x | Contents

Lesser Arts

Part III

11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts | 213 11.1 General observations | 213 11.1.1 Skill | 214 11.1.2 Theory | 214 11.1.3 Time | 218 11.1.4 Emotions | 221 11.1.5 Intentional body | 221 11.1.6 Unpredictability | 223 11.1.7 Schein | 223 11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance | 227 11.3 Performance in various arts | 233 11.3.1 Performance of the text | 233 11.3.2 Film performance-analysis | 235 11.3.3 Varieties of actor/actress, musician, dancer | 237 12 12.1 12.2 12.3 12.4 12.5 12.6

On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking | 249 Introduction | 249 Two historical perspectives | 251 Semiotic questions about food | 253 Cooking as a generative course | 256 An application: cooking in Paris according to Ville Vallgren, Finnish sculptor and gourmet | 261 Conclusion | 265

Part IV

Heimat

13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism | 269 13.A.1 Introduction | 269 13.A.2 What semioticians say about nature | 269 13.A.3 Auguste Comte | 271 13.A.4 German thinkers from Kant to Schiller | 272 13.A.5 Différance | 276 13.A.6 In biosemiotics | 279 13.A.7 Semiogerms | 282

Contents |

13.B

Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music | 283 13.B.1 On the musically “organic” | 283 13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic” | 294 13.B.3 Organic narrativity | 302 14 14.1

Part V 15 15.1 15.2 15.3 15.4 15.5 15.6 16

Finland in the eyes of a semiotician | 306 Introduction | 306

Precursors From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce (1855–1916), the American classic between Hegel and Peirce | 321 Josiah Royce as a historical figure | 321 Why Hegel? | 325 Back to Royce | 330 Toward the world of interpretation | 331 The moral burden of the individual | 334 Royce’s metaphysics and last insights on interpretation | 339

16.1 16.2 16.3 16.4 16.5 16.6 16.7 16.8 16.9 16.10

Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by Susan Petrilli | 342 Introduction | 342 The challenge of originality | 343 The idea of “three” | 344 Royce as Lady Welby’s contemporary | 345 Welby’s independence as a scholar | 346 Who is a significian? | 348 Problematic language | 349 Metaphors | 351 How to educate our expressive powers | 351 Transcendence | 352

17 17.1 17.2 17.3

Vladimir Solovyov | 354 Background | 354 Moral philosophy | 357 Sophia and the World Soul | 362

xi

xii | Contents 18 18.1 18.2 18.3 18.4 18.5 18.6 18.7

Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch | 367 Introduction | 367 Wassily Kandinsky | 369 Its key concepts are metaphors from music | 371 Lev Karsavin (1892–1952) | 378 Wilhelm Sesemann | 382 Vladimir Propp | 384 Mikhail Bakhtin | 388

19 19.1

Wilhelm Sesemann in the context of semiotics | 392 Introduction | 392

20

Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music | 398

21

The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics | 406

22

São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez | 413

Part VI 23 23.1 23.2 23.3 23.4 23.5 23.6 23.7 23.8 23.9 23.10 23.11

Practice

Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period | 423 Introduction | 423 Beginning: Lévi-Strauss, Greimas . . . and Paris | 424 The Impact of Thomas A. Sebeok | 425 Semiotics expands | 427 Imatra starts: Founding of the ISI | 428 IASS Continues | 431 The World Congress in Finland | 433 From Italy to Bulgaria and Estonia | 435 The Finnish Network University of Semiotics as an experiment | 436 SEMKNOW | 438 What do we want? | 439

Literature | 441 Index | 455

| Part I: Philosophy: Varieties of Being

Chapter 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) 1.1 Introduction Most readers of this book probably know existential semiotics as a relatively new “school” or approach to general semiotics and philosophy. It is intended to renew the epistemic foundations of the theory of signs by rereading the classics of continental philosophy in the line of Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Jaspers, Arendt, and Sartre. Its most salient aspect is the revalorization of subject and subjectivity, from which it launches new notions such as transcendence, Dasein, modalities, values, Moi/Soi, and other issues soon to be discussed. It constitutes a kind of ontological semiotics starting from the modality of Being and shifting toward Doing and Appearing, as well. Those who have followed the unfolding of existential semiotics may find the latter of these modalities – Appearing – to be a more recent addition to our line of thought, at least as expounded with the thoroughness it receives here. To prepare for its exposition, let us begin with the most important aspects of existential semiotics. The mere notion of an “existential” semiotics evokes many issues in the history of ideas and the study of signs¹. As such, it is a new theory of studies of communication and signification, as Eco has defined the scope of semiotics (Eco 1979: 8). But beyond that, the attribute “existential” calls on a certain psychological dimension – namely, existential philosophy and even existentialism. As such, the theory involves the phenomenon of transcendence, which may bring to mind American Transcendentalist philosophers, such as Ralph Waldo Emerson, the writer Henry David Thoreau; certainly these and others can be considered kinds of pre-existentialist thinkers. On the other hand, it certainly carries a philo-

1 Some twenty years ago I began my attempts to renew the so-called “classical” semiotic approach and to rethink its epistemological bases. My first publication in this vein was entitled Existential Semiotics (Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 2000). Translated, modified and extended versions of this text have recently appeared: Fondements de la sémiotique existentielle, trans. Jean-Laurent Csinidis (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2009); and Fondamenti di semiotica esistenziale, trans. Massimo Berruti (Bari: Laterza Editore, 2009). Moreover, the Belgian review DEGRES published in 2003 a special issue on Sémiotique existentielle, which features some international reactions to these new theories. Július Fuják edited proceedings from a symposium on Convergences and Divergences of Existential Semiotics (Nitra 2007). Moreover, JeanMarie Jacono arranged seminars on existential semiotics in the University of Aix en Provence.

4 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) sophical tinge that takes us back to German speculative philosophy, to the time of Kant, Schelling, Hegel, and thereafter the existentialist line in the proper sense (i.e., Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Jaspers, Sartre, de Beauvoir, Arendt, Wahl, Gabriel Marcel, etc.). Yet, while the present theory draws inspiration from these classical sources, one cannot return to any earlier historic phase. The theoretical thought of 2015 is definitely philosophy in the present time, and in our case it is enriched by the development of semiotics, particularly throughout the twentieth century.

1.2 A return to basic ideas The present theoretical and philosophical reflections start from the hypothesis that semiotics cannot forever remain focused on the classics from Peirce and Saussure to Greimas, Lotman, Sebeok, and others. Semiosis is in flux and reflects new epistemic choices in the situation of sciences in the 2000s. Hence my own “return” to existentialism is not bound to classical Hegel, Kierkegaard, Sartre, or Heidegger, but rather it draws inspiration from them and, most of all, situates their ideas within a semiotics of the present. Existential semiotics explores the life of signs from within. Unlike most previous semiotics, which investigates only the conditions of particular meanings, existential semiotics studies phenomena in their uniqueness. It studies signs in movement and flux, that is, as signs becoming signs, and defined as pre-signs, act-signs and post-signs (Tarasti 2000: 33). Signs are viewed as transiting back and forth between Dasein – Being-There, our world with its subjects and objects – and transcendence. Completely new sign categories emerge in the tension between reality, as Dasein, and whatever lies beyond it. Completely new sign categories emerge. We have to make a new list of categories in the side of that once done by Peirce. Such new signs so far discovered are, among others, trans-signs, endoand exo-signs, quasi-signs (or as-if-signs), and pheno- and geno-signs.

1.3 Modalities In my earlier theory of musical semiotics (Tarasti 1994: 27, 38–43), I concluded that music signifies most importantly by means of its modalities, in the Greimassian sense. Greimas started with his Sémantique structurale (1966), which stemmed from phenomenology, semantics, Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology, and LéviStraussian structural anthropology, not to mention Saussure and Hjelmslev. He launched new concepts such as semanalysis, the actantial model, isotopies, and so forth. In the late 1970s he put his thought into a generative model (“generative

1.4 Dasein and transcendence |

5

course”), which proved both powerful and fashionable at that time (Greimas 1979: 157–164). The most radical of his innovations, however, was the discovery of modalities, to which he referred as the “third semiotic revolution” (the first being the invention of semantics by Bréal, and second, the structural linguistics of Saussure). Modalities are the ways in which a speaker animates and colors his/her speech by providing it with wishes, hopes, certainties, uncertainties, duties, emotions, and so forth. Larousse’s French Dictionary defines modality: Psychic activity that the speaker projects into what he is saying. A thought is not content with a simple presentation, but demands active participation by the thinking subject, activity which in the expression forms the soul of the sentence, without which the sentence does not exist.

Modalities appear in the grammar of some languages as modal or special subjunctive verb forms. For instance, in French: when one says, “I have to go to the bank”, the sentence is rendered “Il faut que j’aille à la banque”, the verb form indicating the modality of obligation or duty – “must” (devoir) – instilled in the communication by the locution “Il faut” (it is necessary). The “plain”, unmodalized form would be simply “je vais”, you go. Italian and German are two other modern languages that feature the subjunctive mood (modality). The fundamental modalities are Being and Doing. We further distinguish a third modality, Becoming, which refers to the normal temporal course of events in our Dasein or life-world (discussed below). Other modalities, in turn, are Will, Can, Know, Must, and Believe. Here the modalities are to be understood as processual concepts. They are the element of “classical semiotics” that remains valid in the new existential semiotics, precisely because of their dynamic nature.

1.4 Dasein and transcendence The modalities aptly portray what happens inside what I call Dasein in the model shown in Figure 1.1 (from Tarasti 2000: 10). The concept of Dasein, a term that literally means “being-there”, has been borrowed from German philosophy, especially that of Heidegger and Jaspers (see Jaspers 1948: 6–11, 57–66, 295). Unlike in Heidegger, for whom Dasein refers primarily to my existence, here it does not refer only to one subject, Me, but also to Others, and likewise to the objects of our desire.

6 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) Beyond Dasein, beyond the concrete reality in which we live, there is transcendence. The simplest definition of this intriguing notion might be the following: The transcendent is anything that is absent in actuality, but present in our minds.

Figure 1.1: The Model of Dasein

The model also introduces an element crucial to any existential theory: the subject. This subject, dwelling in Dasein, feels it to be somehow deficient or otherwise unsatisfactory, and so negates it. This is what Jean-Paul Sartre called néantisation (Sartre 1943: 44–45). A lack in his/her existence forces the subject to search for both something more and something different. There are two transcendental acts in the model, first negation and then affirmation. With this we have the existential “move” in Dasein (x). First our subject finds himself amid the objective signs of Dasein. Then the subject recognizes the emptiness and Nothingness surrounding the existence from which he has come – that which precedes him and comes after him. The subject then takes a leap into Nothingness, into the realm of le Néant, described by Sartre. From here, all of his earlier Dasein seems to have lost its foundation: it appears to be senseless. This constitutes the first act of transcendence: negation. The subject does not stop here, but there follows the second act of transcendence, when he encounters the opposite pole of Nothingness: a universe that takes on meaning in some supra-individual way, independently of his own act of signification. This act, affirmation, results in the subject finding what Peirce called the Ground. It was at first difficult to find a suitable concept to portray this state. Upon reading the Russian philosopher Vladimir Solovyov (1965: 348– 349), it became clear that affirmation is what in Gnostic philosophy was called pleroma or plenitude. This in turn evoked Emerson’s notion of the “Oversoul” and Schelling’s Weltseele, world soul. The latter, a kind of anima mundi, refers to the

1.4 Dasein and transcendence |

7

unified inner nature of the world, understood as a living being with the capacity to desire, conceive, and feel. In short, the world soul constitutes a “modal” entity, to use our Greimassian vocabulary (Greimas 1979: 230–232). It must be emphasized that the present model is of a conceptual nature, not an empirical one. This does not of course exclude it from subsequent psychological, anthropological, or theological applications. One person has proposed that “transcendental journey” means “a psychedelic trip”; others have compared it to the act of a shaman in which his soul, after he has eaten hallucinogenic mushrooms, makes a trans-mundane journey to other realities; and so forth. Our scheme, however, is philosophical and deals with what Kant called the transzendental rather than the transzendent (Kant 1787 [1968]: 379). We can provide the logical operations of affirmation and negation with psychological content and distinguish more subtle nuances of these acts: Negation, for example, may mean the following: Abandonment, giving up: One is in a situation in which x appears; the subject has taken it into its possession but now abandons it, i.e., becomes “disjuncted” from it (formalized as S V O, in Greimassian semiotics; see Greimas 1979: 108). Passing by: x appears but the subject passes it by. Forgetting: x appeared, but it is forgotten; it no longer has any impact. Counter-argument: x appears, but something totally different follows: y; or x appears and is followed by its negation (inversion, contrast, opposition, etc.). This corresponds to Greimas’s semiotic square and its categories s1 and s2, and non-s1 and non-s2 (ibid.: 29–33). Rejection: x appears, but it is rejected. Prevention: x is going to appear, but is prevented from doing so. Removal of relational attributes: x appears, but one eliminates its semes x . . . xn , whereafter it becomes acceptable. Destruction: x appears, but is destroyed. Collapse, disappearance: x appears but disappears on its own accord, without our being able to influence it. Concealment: the appearance of x is hidden, but it nevertheless “is” on a certain level. Parody: x appears, but it is not taken seriously, or is taken as an “as-if”. Mockery: x appears, but one trifles with it; it is ironized, made grotesque. Dissolution: x appears, but it is reduced to smaller parts; when its total phenomenal quality is lost, one “cannot tell the forest from the trees”. In Adorno’s words: “When one scrutinizes art works very closely, even the most objective works turn into confusion, texts into words [. . . ] the particular element of

8 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) the work vanishes; its abridgment evaporates under the microscopic gaze” (Adorno 2006: 209, translation mine). Misunderstanding: x appears, but it is not interpreted as x, but as something else. Affirmation, in turn, may mean the following: Acceptance: x appears and we accept it without intervening in it; for example, when we rejoice in others’ success. Helping: We may contribute to the fact that x appears. Enlightenment: We see x in a favorable light. Revelation of the truth and disappearance of the lie: x appears, and it is recognized as Schein (mere appearance, a lie); conversely, we act in such a way that allows x󸀠 to appear. Initiation: We start to strive; we undertake an act so that some positive, euphoric x appears. Duration: We attempt to maintain x; for example, by teaching someone. Completion: x appears as the final result of a process, as the reward of pain; Schein, now in the sense of “shine” or brilliance, has been attained by labor. We say more about this later, concerning the modality of Appearing (apparence). Organic vitality: x erupts; it appears in consequence of an organic process, as having abandoned itself to the process, as if “riding atop a wave”. Transfiguration: x radiates something that stems from the background, not from its own power, but as the effulgence of an invisible reality. For example, take the bodies in El Greco’s paintings. First we encounter the negation – a body portrayed as suffering – but behind it a hopeful luminosity. Victory: x appears as the end of a long struggle; for example, the brilliant C major at the end of Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony in C minor. Opening: the appearance of x means a gateway to possibilities; new worlds open to us. Liberation: the appearance of x signifies a breaking of the chains of y or x󸀠 .

1.5 Turn-around of Dasein Two other aspects of this model relate to how our psyche adapts to his/her existential situation and journeys. The first of these is evoked by viewing negation as a kind of alienation or estrangement: when a subject temporarily exits his Dasein in his transcendental act, the journey can last for whatsoever time span, be it hours, days, weeks, even years. And it can happen that when he returns to the world of his Dasein, he finds it changed. Like a spinning globe, it has continued moving

1.5 Turn-around of Dasein

|

9

on its own and completely apart from our subject; it has perhaps turned in such a direction that, when our subject returns, it is no longer the same world. One may find in our model the solipsism that Dasein exists only for one subject and that it changes its shape because of his/her existential experiences. But not only so. For during the transcendental journey, the world may have in the meantime developed in a new direction. The subject does not return “home” but to a quite different world from the one that he left. Insofar as we take Dasein as a collective entity, which consists of subjects and objects, of Others, we encounter the community and the autonomous development of the collectivity, the changes brought by history. Our subject can either accept this change and try to adapt to it, or he may deny it. From the latter case emerges a special opportunity for semiotics of resistance (discussed in a later chapter). As shown in Figure 1.2, progress does not mean just going along with the normal course of a journey, but also looking at alternatives, at what might have happened or have been possible (see Tarasti 2009c: 51, 61–65).

Figure 1.2: The turn-around of Dasein

Second, there is an aspect of our model that opens new avenues after the previous one. Namely, the arrows can go backward as well. Our subject recalls how Dasein was before, and returns to it on the basis of his memory, which retains some images and ideas from those previous worlds and their phases, as illustrated in Figure 1.3. Some of them he may have already forgotten, and similarly the Dasein may have forgotten him. There is a risk indeed that, if he dwells too long in his position of resistance and outside the Dasein, then he is forgotten – like a text discarded and ignored by the collective memory of a culture. This leads to the strong social

10 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing)

Figure 1.3: The counter-current of Dasein

implications of our theory. Real thinkers of resistance are always forgotten and suppressed. If they were accepted, they would not be what they wanted to be. Thus, in our model the arrows also go backwards.

1.6 Values As mentioned earlier, existential semiotics conceives of signs to be in constant movement between transcendence and Dasein. Depending on their proximity to Dasein, whether they are approaching it or departing from it, one gets new types of signs. We have already mentioned pre-signs – ideas or values that have not yet become concrete signs. Such signs are virtual. When they become manifest as a sign “vehicle” or an act, they become act-signs. When they make an impact on receivers, they become post-signs. In their virtual, potential state as transcendental entities, they can be called trans-signs. These phases correspond to three activities of the human mind: virtualizing, actualizing, and realizing (notions used by both Greimas and by Roman Ingarden). Ultimately, there is an axiological problem with the existence of values. In the Saussurean tradition values are relative; they are determined only in their context, as opposed to other values by the linguistic community (Saussure [1916] 1995: 116). In my theory, by contrast, values are transcendental but become signs via the activities of the subject. In the field of aesthetics, such a view is of course problematic. How is it possible, say, that the value of a Beethoven sonata existed before its creation? Was it somewhere waiting for its actualization in Dasein? To this we may reply that transcendental values do not become a manifest reality without an agent who actualizes them. When actualization occurs, signs may be

1.6 Values |

11

different from what they were thought to be earlier, when mere pre-signs (Tarasti 2000: 33). Without the help of other modalities – Know, Can, Must, and Will – they never become concrete. Signs can also be classified into endo- and exo-signs – either internal or external, respectively, to our subject’s world (ibid.: 37–55). Let us scrutinize this problem in terms of moral values. The following diagram summarizes our discussion thus far: values



modalities



signs

The movement proceeds from left to right, when in semiosis an abstract idea is formulated and eventually crystallizes as a sign (see Tarasti 2004: 39). But can we call this process semiosis? To some philosophers, to say that something is a “sign” is not any recommendation. But on what grounds could we reason that, just because something has the characteristics of a sign, then it is less “real” or less valuable? To Peirce’s way of thinking, to become conscious of a sign is a Second. The French writer Le Clézio says that when we are reading a novel and exclaim, “Oh this was well said!”, that that is a kind of sign, and it no longer functions. The functionality of signs has become almost an aesthetic slogan in recent years. But this is the same as stated above – namely, the value-reality escapes our grasp, and everything becomes mere technical problems of functionality. Some may say this is the semioticians’ fault. They taught us that everything is sign and semiosis: there can be disturbances in their functioning, but such flaws can be corrected with the technical knowledge we have of the functioning of text. Thus, values remain completely external, and transcendental, and one does not need to believe in their existence: There are only opinions, language, discourse, but no transcendental categories. As Greimas said: “Il n’y a pas de vérité, il n’y a que véridiction” – There is no truth, there are only statements about truth. All moral philosophers have to deal with Hume, who proposed that no values can be inferred from facts. From the state of how things are, we cannot logically infer how they should be. In my existential semiotics, I defend the idea that values can be transcendental ideas alongside other values that exist outside Dasein. Still, in some cases and under certain circumstances, they start to exercise their influence within the Dasein, when a living subject – individual or collective – therein feels such a value as his own, experiences it as moving him/her into something, and finally realizes this value as a sign. The British philosopher John Mackie, in his Inventing Right and Wrong (1977), represents the extreme of value-nominalism. Different cultures view right and wrong in different ways, such that no independent value facts exist. All moral statements are thus untrue. Mackie argues that all objective moral theories make a mistake when they say that one cannot step outside or above morals if he/she wants to do so. In his view, morality is a special form of social life, which man and his community create and choose. (This already

12 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) sounds rather existential.) Mackie argues that, if moralizing leads to quarrels and disputes, then morals ought to be forgotten. Even so, if we insist on the point that moral values exist in transcendence, it remains up to the person of Dasein to believe this and to allow them to have an impact on his/her acts. This idea probably provides us with the key to the problem of how to fit values into modalities and furthermore into signs – that is, how to act. I offer you now such a proposal. No one can say, “I pursue such and such an act because a transcendental value x requires me to do so”. When I select value x as my ideal, it is always my own choice, for which I am responsible. This is my main rebuttal to the argument most often used against value-realists. And that argument is: What guarantees that a person will not adopt a completely foolish transcendental value and even imagine himself to be right? When I have picked value x, it falls into the field of the modalities and passions of our Dasein, amidst our Wants, Obligations, Abilities, and Knowledge. Then I do the act, x or non-x; that is, I either fulfil an act following this value or I give it up. I do something against it, negating the value by my act (see Figure 1.4). Hence, the signified of the act is the transcendental value, but only insofar as our subject has the proper competence in the code whereby he/she can connect such an act to the transcendental value in question.

Figure 1.4: The enactment of values

At the same time, this act triggers other acts, which either affirm or negate the act x/non-x. Consequently, we can infer the crucial imperative for any moral activity: If act /x → non-x/ causes in its Umwelt other negative acts, which are negative in relation to other transcendental values, then such an act should not be committed. We might, for example, imagine that we have the transcendental value of hon-

1.6 Values |

13

esty or of keeping promises. However, somebody does something contrary (e.g., breaks a contract). This negative act, in its social environment, prompts reactions or other acts that can likewise be negative: non-y punishing, non-p abandonment, exclusion from the community, non-q hatred. All these reactive value-acts are, in turn, negations of some transcendental values, such as indulgence, benevolence, abstention from violence, charity, and so forth (see Figure 1.5).

Figure 1.5: Reaction to a value-act

In other words, if the correction of a negative value-act causes more negative acts in its Umwelt than the original negative act did, then one has to give up such a correction, give up being morally “right.” As in any fulfilment of a value, two kinds of modalities function in such a moral value-act: (1) modalities that regulate the acts and behaviors of their agents in the Dasein, and (2) modalities that regulate the relationships of value-acts to their transcendental values. This is a double movement: (a) It manifests and actualizes values, by the process in which a virtual act changes and may even become real. (b) We return to the value as it is in transcendence and compare the “actualized” value to the virtual value. In this way, the transcendental value serves as the source of the actualized value in Dasein. These two acts of meta-modalization presuppose a particular value competency. If our subjects do not possess the right codes by which to connect a potential, virtual value to an act that concretizes it, and if they cannot decode from an act its value content and compare it to the “encyclopaedia” of values, then the reality of values is not fulfilled at all. This model should likewise fit with other values, such as truth or epistemic values or beauty and aesthetic values. In any case, the subject of Dasein is completely responsible for his value choices, that is to say, the values that he metamodalizes from the (virtual) encyclopaedia of values. Naturally, when he is devoid of some value because of, say, a lack of education, one may also

14 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) hold his community responsible; e.g., his “senders” in narratological terms (school, parents, teachers). Still, he remains existentially responsible for which transcendental values he selects, how he modalizes them into value acts, and the kinds of value acts and modalities that they bring about. The intermediate phase of modalities is indispensable in making values and signs compatible. It also explains why some originally right value can, when transformed into a value act, get distorted into a caricature of itself: It is caused by modalization, in the transformation of the phase of actualization when the human passions intervene. This explains the nature of metamodalities, mentioned above. If they are altogether the activities of a subject, then how do metamodalities distinguish themselves from ordinary modalities? The answer is: They contribute to the particular act of signification in which a value is connected to a physical act or object of the sign vehicle. This implies the following kinds of modalities: 1. Want (vouloir): I want to connect value x to the signified of act x. Should the subject not want it, this value could not manifest. A concern is whether such a wanting or desire differs from that by which subjects of Dasein look after each other or various value objects. Not even a psychoanalyst would presume that Freudian desire can explain, for example, artistic activity, ethical choice, or scientific research. Rather, a special form of human wanting is involved. 2. Know (savoir): I know that value x exists; without such knowledge I cannot even want to concretize it in my value act. This kind of knowing is not that of familiarity or acquaintance. Rather, it is more like the kind of knowledge we receive in our Dasein, the kind of knowledge that information theory tries to embody in its concepts of entropy and redundancy. 3. Can (pouvoir): I am able to (can) connect a value x to an act x. For example, I want to help sick people, but to be capable of doing so I must master medicine; I want to help the poor, but unless I am able give them something, I cannot do it; I want to transmit artistic experiences, but if I do not master the proper techniques, then I cannot produce any such emotions; and so forth. 4. Must (devoir): Denoting obligation or duty, must requires the internalization of values such that we can experience the sense that a value obligates us to act (or not) in a certain way. But even here, the metamodality of Must is our own existential choice.

1.7 New types of signs The traffic between these instances of signs – that is to say, between transcendence and existence – is taken care of by metamodalities. Altogether, signs have their situations, which is an aspect essential to the existential approach. If we

1.7 New types of signs

| 15

take that traffic as a narrative structure portraying human life, it radically differs from classical story schemes, which are symmetrical. Any narrative starts with a situation in which we are hic, nunc, ego – Here, Now, Me – but then something happens that causes a “disengagement” from this primal state, to Elsewhere, Then, Others. Yet, normally in a classical story, we return to the initial state; we are “engaged” with it, hence the syntagmatic line becomes symmetrical. By contrast, in existential semiosis there is no return – what happens next is always unknown and unpredictable. Another new scientific paradigm that has entered into existential semiotics – perhaps paradoxically to some minds – is biosemiotics. Biosemiotics is one of the new pursuits that have emerged in the last 20 years within general semiotics, thanks to the writings of Thomas A. Sebeok (see, e.g., Sebeok 2001: 31–44), and above all to the original doctrine advanced by the Estonian Jakob v. Uexküll (Uexküll 1940). Biosemiotics does not argue that semiotic and symbolic processes and forms are reducible to something biological, as do some sociobiological theories that say society is ultimately nothing but biology. Rather, it is the other way round: biology and vital processes are shown to be semioses. Jakob’s son, Thure v. Uexküll, claims his father’s doctrine is particularly compatible with Peircean semiotics (T. Uexküll et al. 1993), but nothing prevents us from using it in other conceptual frameworks as well. To illustrate how such semiosis functions within an organism, Uexküll uses musical metaphors; he says that every organism surrounded by its Umwelt possesses its codes or something like a musical score, which determines what signs it either accepts or rejects from the Umwelt. This principle is called Ich-Ton, Me-Tone². Uexküll calls the process of signs intruding into the organism and functioning therein endosemiosis. On this basis, we speak of two kinds of signs: endo-signs and exo-signs, signs that are either inside or outside the object (Tarasti 2000: 37–56). I have tried to bring this idea back to music and art by arguing that every composer, every composition, every artwork has a Me-Tone that determines its characteristics. In this new framework of existential semiotics, and its fundamental notions of Dasein and transcendence, we give it a Kantian interpretation, such that the Ich-Ton appears through Kantian categories of subject (actor)-time-space, whenever some transcendental idea is filtered into Dasein. We can further distinguish as-if signs; these are signs that must not be taken quite literally in the Dasein, but rather as kinds of metaphors. All signs of artistic representation are of this nature; for example, many signs in cinema and theater that should never be confused with reality. I also distinguish between pheno- and

2 On the Ich-Ton principle in music, see Tarasti 2002: 98, 109.

16 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) geno-signs³. Pheno-signs are traditional signs that refer to or stand for something else. When referring to or standing for something, the sign remains what it is; it is only a tool, a window into the world of the signified. By contrast, in the case of geno-sign, the entire process of signs becoming signs is included: the whole generation of the sign through various phases is vividly evoked by the appearance of such a sign. For example, when we listen to the overture to Wagner’s Parsifal we first hear a motif rising from the depths, solemn, sad, longing for something. At this point it is a pheno-sign, which by its mere musical qualities evokes certain modal content (Will, Can, etc.). A dedicated Wagnerian may recognize it as the Abendmahl motif, referring to Amfortas. However, by the time it is heard six hours later at the end of the opera, it has become a geno-sign. We feel that it contains the entire life-story of Parsifal, who from a young and foolish fellow has grown into the redeemer of the Grail knights. The motif carries the whole story within itself. Here again we see an essential point: signs are never fixed; they are always in the process of becoming something else. Next I want to scrutinize some new issues and concepts whereby existential semiotics tries to contribute to semiotics and to the humanities in general. These will be discussed under the headings of Transcendence, Subject, Being, Doing, and Appearing.

1.8 More on transcendence Transcendence is not a concept that we are used to encountering in the semiotic context. Dictionaries, encyclopaedias and handbooks from Greimas and Sebeok as well as Posner, Nöth, and Bouissac simply exclude it from semiotic discussion. Still, no one can deny its cogency and centrality to German philosophy from Kant to Heidegger. As this philosophical tradition, its idealist nature rejected by most semioticians, becomes to be seen more and more as nourishment to contemporary semiotics – witness the turn to phenomenology and hermeneutics in the European context and to deconstruction in the USA – we can no longer ignore its existence. In existential semiotics, the life of signs is situated in their movement and traffic between transcendence and Dasein. To some, the mere mention of a notion like transcendence has mystical or theological overtones. If we go in this direction – which would also be very Heideg-

3 The terms pheno- and geno-text, as used here, have nothing to do with Julia Kristeva’s usage of the same terms (Kristeva 1969), nor with Barthes’s “pheno-” and “geno-song” (Barthes 1977: 182).

1.8 More on transcendence | 17

gerian as far as he considered the ultimate goal of every being and Dasein to be its disappearance, Sein zum Tod – we find that within existential semiotics we can deal with even such profound and serious issues. In this framework, death means the disappearance of the boundaries of the Dasein and the merging of a subject with transcendence. The juxtaposition of the temporality of Dasein and atemporality of transcendence – time/non-time – is reconciled. According to certain processes of narrativity and dynamism, everything that happened in Dasein has accumulated into the acts of this subject. They are signs left by him that fuse together with acts by other subjects who have already moved into transcendence. This process is irreversible; no longer can the events therein be changed. They can of course be re-narrativized, rendered part of the pseudo-narrativity and temporality of history writing. In such a case, a subject has the ability to “re-modalize” them, and they are again subjected to communication processes. Transcendence, however, represents pure signification without narrativization. Hence when the boundaries of the Dasein become blurry or vanish altogether, then the real semiosis starts, without narrativity. There is narrativity only in Dasein. In turn, when a transcendental idea intrudes into the Dasein of a subject, it becomes a sign and it participates in communication. One is led to ask what force makes a transcendental idea manifest in communication or incarnate into a sign. Signs have a certain imperishable part. Goethe certainly referred to this when he said, Kein Wesen kann zu nichts zerfallen (no being can disappear). Signs also have a perishable, temporal, spatial, and actorial part. From the viewpoint of a subject, this involves the manifestation of content in the physical appearance of the sign vehicle. Essential here is thus the concept of a boundary: in order to become a sign, a transcendental idea must transgress a limit. Altogether, we can say that semiotics, in its deepest essence, is a transcendental discipline. If it consists, following Umberto Eco, of two areas: communication and signification, one can easily notice how they both refer to something transcendental. For the first, every communication act is a transcendental event in which Mr. A tries to reach Mr. B with his message. Yet, Mr. B always remain a ‘transcendental’ entity to Mr. A, or what is called in philosophy ‘alien psychic’. Assuming the phenomenological standpoint the only certain thing to Mr. A is his own stream of consciousness. What happens in the mind of Mr. B is a hypothesis that it is something similar to what happens in the mind of Mr. A. Therefore every act of communication contains a true risk of misunderstanding. On the other hand, as said, in every sign – in the Saussurean sense – the signified, the meaning looms behind the signifier, the sign vehicle and so the sense or signification is as well something ‘transcendental’.

18 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing)

Figure 1.6: Communication according to de Saussure. In fact, it is a transcendental act between two subjects

1.9 Mimesis We might, then, refer to the incarnation of transcendence as a sign its “first mimesis”, the latter as defined by Ricoeur (1983: 85–129). In other words, the Dasein of a subject can mimic or simulate transcendence: man by his act(s) wishes to change his Dasein according to some idea. Every action is founded on the contradiction between an idea and the reality of Dasein. The subject wants to intervene in the course of events. Existentially he can do so – that is to say, he is free to do so, even if at the same time he might be incapable of it. Ricoeur describes two more kinds of mimesis. When a subject in his Dasein creates something that serves as a model of that Dasein (for example, “art imitating life”), then the second mimesis occurs. In Ricoeur’s theory, mimesis essentially follows the course of communication: mimesis1 = production of sign, and mimesis2 = the manner in which a sign simulates or portrays the living world (Dasein). Mimesis3, then, would be the same as aesthesis, the reception or interpretation of a sign. In our model, however, mimesis does not take place horizontally, in a syntagmatic or linear way as a kind of narrative course from sender to receiver, but vertically as a movement from transcendence or a subject’s inner consciousness, from a transcendental subject toward his living world, that is, Dasein (by transcendental subject, we understand a subject who, by thought, tries to conceive of transcendence). In this light, a slight correction is necessary to our earlier model of transcendence. There are not two different transcendences, one an empty and anguishing nothingness (le Néant), and the other a rich and overwhelming plenitude. There is only one transcendence, which the subject experiences as nothingness in his act of negation, when he clings to his Dasein for fear of transgressing the boundaries of his existence. This is caused by his unwillingness to give up the merits, achievements, and signs he has won or otherwise obtained in the phases of

1.9 Mimesis |

19

his Dasein. In front of the unknown atemporal and anti-narrative transcendence, he experiences anguish, and he feels that nothingness threatens the significations he has made in his Dasein, which he believes to have created himself. Any and all statements about the fact that his life has gone down the drain, that all his plans have come to naught in the processes of Dasein – these all result from a metaphysical attitude. Yet, when the boundaries of Dasein become blurred, the subject sees the connection of his signs and acts to their proper, timeless transcendence and real signification. The subject has the liberty to pursue affirmation and negation, as stated above. This means that he/she can reject the processes of mimesis1 through mimesis3. When a subject opposes mimesis1, he does not want to listen to the voice of the transcendental subject within himself and does not transform transcendental ideas into signs. His existence does not reach the level of sign; it remains a series of detached moments in the process of communication but without real content. Models that remain within Dasein and emphasize its immanency, which claim that the only reality is Dasein itself, that the body and society are a continuous process and that nothing else exists – such models are based on the rejection of mimesis1. A subject can also reject mimesis2, which is the idea that he can create intentional objects in the course of Dasein. He may not realize that he can, by his acts and signs (act-signs), imitate and simulate aspects of Dasein. An artist creates copies and models his Dasein, in which, however, that artist can try to see the existential in the narration of his/her own life. Music serves as such a narration on a high level of abstraction. In turn, mimesis3 may also be rejected. In this case, the subject rejects giving up the positions and signs he has gained during processes of communication. Yet, if he does not know to make the limits of his Dasein vis-à-vis transcendence more transparent and thus experience the plenitude of transcendence – which is nothing else but the encyclopaedia of acts and ideas in the totality of the transcendent – he remains without this essential, decisive, and positive experience, which can also change his attitude toward death and the vanishing of his Dasein. In fact, in every temporal artwork such disappearance already takes place, but still the subject seeks after such a mini-narration transfigured, because he has mirrored the imperishable, transcendental entities of his life-world in the aforementioned model and has become aware of them. In any case, there is only one transcendence, but the individual who clings to the communication processes of his Dasein, as rich as they may be, is blinded to its contents, to the true semiosis of ideas and acts and significations, and hence believes transcendence to be empty. Therefore, only when he abandons the boundaries of his Dasein, or via some act of conception is able to step over this bor-

20 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) derline, does he realize the true plenitude of transcendence. This experience is connected with the existential one: that he is already expected on the other side of the boundary. All that is positive or negative, which he has left in his life, waits for him in transcendence. Thus mimesis3 means transgressing the boundary, striving and succeeding in getting beyond oneself. The continuous crossing of limits of transcendence and Dasein constitutes one of the most profound problems of existential semiotics. It manifests as many sub-problems of the communication processes of Dasein. For example, it is not enough for a subject to hear within himself the voice of a transcendental subject, which guides him to the right aesthetic resolution or ethical choice; he must also manifest this voice to others in the world of communication; this involves encountering a subject who is an alien-psychic entity. Such an encounter of the alien-psychic is again essentially an event of mimesis2. That is to say, our subject creates his model of “mini-Dasein” not to himself but in dialogue with someone else, another, who influences it essentially. Our subject strives to anticipate such a transcendence of the other – for example, to please him, to get his message understood. But why is this so important? Why does our subject want to communicate? Communication is always a crossing over the boundary, and in this sense it is a model of both mimesis1 and mimesis2. The subject wants to show through communicating that his message goes beyond the boundary, that it is supported by the authority of transcendence. But he also wants by this communicative act to abandon his own boundaries and taste in advance what the complete disappearance of such borderlines would mean. Communication on this level of transference, as shifts of values and modalities, means just such a fusion with the Other. It is anticipating the final blending with the totally Other, that is, with transcendence in the proper sense. In fact, the forces of semiosis operate in two directions: vertically and horizontally. The vertical force leads to the fulfilment of ideas of transcendence, to mimesis in Dasein, in such a manner that they first become noemata (ideas, conceptions) of a subject. Thereafter the vertical movement continues within the Dasein, modelling and simulating the latter in various texts and narratives. This represents the second degree of mimesis. The third phase is in fact a kind of demimesis, the return of ideas back to the transcendence with which they blend. Narrativity is a special kind of syntagmatic form, which appears first in the life-world of the Dasein and then in the world of text. In other words, the ideas are at once modalized and syntagmatized so as to participate in processes of communication. This is the horizontal direction of semiosis, its temporalization. Both the horizontal and the vertical forces are ultimately of a transcendental nature. This is true of communication – every act of communication is an encounter with the Other, the alien psyche, a leap toward the unknown. And true of

1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING | 21

signification – by signs we talk about things that are not present, that are already transcendent. Therefore, the two essentials for a semiotics – communication and signification – represent the transcendental for existential semiotics. When in Saussure’s picture of a dialogue, Mr. A sends signs to Mr. B, the latter is a transcendental entity to the former. There is a gap between them, but in human communication the gap is not empty: it is filled by modalities and modalizations by these subjects, both destinator and destinatee. The signs used and emitted here are transcendental entities, because they are aliquid stat pro aliquo – something standing for something, as goes the oldest Scholastic definition of sign.

1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING In the structuralist phase of semiotics, the subject was eliminated in favor of systems and grammars that were internalized in us, as Lacan postulated: Ça parle. In poststructuralist and postmodern theories the subject re-entered. As noted at the beginning of this chapter, one may interpret existential semiotics as one of these new revalorizations of subjectivity in the history of ideas, but it is no longer a “post-”phenomenon, but rather a part of “neosemiotics”. This paradigm sets forth something radically new, borrowing what it needs from classical semiotics, and combining these ideas with the most inspirational speculative philosophy from Kant and Hegel to Sartre and Marcel. Neosemiotics never considers only the text but all its conditions, its whole Umwelt, its process of becoming a text, the whole act of enunciation. There has been much talk about subjects and subjectivity in many neighboring areas of semiotics, such as psychoanalysis, gender theories, and cultural theories. Without a more articulated vision of how a subject appears in the enunciation and in our semiotic activities in general, however, such theoretical efforts remain short of their goals, as laudable as their efforts might be. To re-evaluate the subject requires a short excursion to the roots of existential semiotics, which means going back to Hegel and his logic. For some semioticians, Hegel is mere conceptual poetry, to others he becomes acceptable only after a Marxist turn-around, but to some, like Hannah Arendt, he stands as the central thinker of Western philosophy. He compiled phenomena of nature and history into a homogeneous construction; it is hard to tell, however, whether that edifice is a prison or a palace (Arendt 2000: 111). To Arendt, Hegel was the last word in Western philosophy. All that came after him either imitated him or rebelled against him. Present schools of thought – in Arendt’s case, Husserl, Heidegger, and Jaspers – were epigones of Hegel; they all tried to reconstruct the unity of thinking and being without reaching a balance at which they either privileged matter (materialism) or mind (idealism).

22 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) Arendt might have been right. Even the semiotic thought is indebted to Hegel, whose traces we can follow both in Peirce and Royce (discussed in separate chapters, below) as well as in the French structuralists, the Tartu cultural semioticians – and particularly in existential semiotics. Hence I take as my starting point a principle from Hegelian logic, by which we construct further our theory of subject – namely, his categories of an-sich-sein (Being-in-itself) and für-sich-sein (Being-for-itself) (Inwood 1992: 133–136). Hegel used the terms an sich and für sich in their ordinary senses but also provided them with contrasting meanings. As finite, a thing has a determinate nature only by virtue of its relation to other things: in negation of, and by, them. This is true not only of items in the world but also of Kant’s thing-in-itself, since it, too, is cut off from our cognition. Thus, a thing as it is an sich has no overtly determinate character; at most, it has potential character that will be actualized only by its relations to other things. An infant, for example, is an sich rational potentially, not actually. A tailor is a tailor an sich in the sense of having certain internal skills that suit him for this role and of having certain overt features that distinguish him from, say, a sailor. Being a tailor, or musician, thus involves an interplay between being an sich and being for another. But a person is not simply a role occupant. He is also an individual “I” and as such can distance himself from his role and think of himself just as me or I.When he does this, he is no longer for others but for himself. For example, a bus driver has already left a stop, but notices one person still running to catch the bus. Against the rules, he stops and takes on the passenger because he feels compassion for him. Although his selfconsciousness may presuppose recognition by others, an “I” is not one of a system of contrasting roles: Everyone is an I. The idea that if something is for itself, if it is aware of itself, leads to the idea that an entity may have in itself certain characteristics that are not for itself. A slave is, as a man, free in himself, but he may not be free for himself. The student may be a future doctor and professor, but he does not yet know it. Finally, the terms an sich and für sich, as signifying potentiality and actuality, may be applied to a subject’s development. When a person becomes for himself what he is in himself, he usually recognizes his identity: he becomes meaningful to himself. But before we make an existential-semiotic turn-around of Hegel, let us see what Kierkegaard did with the notions of an sich and für sich. In his thought, these notions turn into subjective and objective being. In the chapter, “Becoming a Subject” in his Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Kierkegaard speaks about an individual who is said to be a subject, an individual who is what he is simply because he has become that (Kierkegaard 1993 [1846]). The transformation of a subject from an sich being to für sich being corresponds to his becoming a sign to himself, or the emergence of his identity. Kierkegaard says

1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING |

23

the task of the subject is to shed more and more of his subjectivity and become more and more objective. The objective being is the same when observing as when being observed. But in his theory, this observation has to be of an ethical nature. The next careful reader of Hegel (and of Kierkegaard) was Jean-Paul Sartre, whose L’Être et le néant (1943) was, to a great extent, based on the Hegelian concepts of an sich and für sich (être-en-soi and être-pour-soi). According to Sartre, Being simply is and cannot help but be. But Being has as its potentiality the fact that it becomes aware of itself via an act of negation. In Kierkegaardian terms, the being becomes an observer of itself, and hence is shifted into Being-for-itself. This is precisely transcending. The pour-soi as the outburst of negation forms the basis for identity. It appears as a lack. According to Sartre, this is the beginning of transcendence. As said above of narrativity: human reality strives for something that it lacks (Sartre 1943: 124–125). Man starts to exist when he realizes the incompleteness of its being. Via this effort, value enters human life. Value is that to which one aspires. Being-in-itself precedes every consciousness; Being-in-itself is the same as what Being-for-itself was earlier. The essential change in Sartre’s theory regarding Hegel is the movement between these two categories, and a kind of subjectivization of them in view of existence. Another modernization of Hegel and his categories has been offered by Jacques Fontanille in his study Soma et séma: Figures du corps (Fontanille 2004). In the book he deals with corporeal semiotics and presents the distinction between categories of Moi and Soi in a fresh manner. As a Greimassian semiotician, Fontanille starts from the actant and his/her body. He distinguishes between body and form. We speak of body as such or flesh (chair), which is the center of everything, as the material resistance to or impulse toward semiotic processes. The body is the sensorial motor fulcrum of semiotic experience (ibid.: 22). On the other hand, there is another body, which constitutes the identity and directional principle of the flesh. This body is the carrier of the “me” (Moi), whereas the literal body supports the “self” (Soi) (ibid.: 22–23). The Soi constructs itself in discursive activity. The Soi is that part of ourselves which the me, Moi, extends beyond itself so as to create itself in its activity. The Moi is that part of ourselves to which the Soi refers when establishing itself. The Moi provides the Soi with impulse and resistance whereby it can become something. In turn, the Soi furnishes the Moi with the reflexivity that it needs to stay within its limits when it changes. The Moi resists and forces the Soi to meet its own alterity. Hence the two are inseparable. Although Fontanille is a semiotician, his reasoning fits well with the aforementioned Hegelian categories. This involves a new interpretation of an sich and für sich, the first corresponding to bodily ego and the latter to its stability, identity, and aspiration outward (Sartrean negation). The Soi functions as a kind of mem-

24 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) ory of the body, or Moi; it gives form to those traces of tensions and needs that have place in the flesh of the Moi. In the light of Fontanille’s concepts, we could change the Hegelian Being-initself and Being-for-itself (an-sich-sein and für-sich-sein) to an-mir-sein and fürmich-sein – Being-in-myself and Being-for-myself. Before we ponder the consequences this may have for our existential semiotics, we shall first examine the principles of Moi and Soi as such. Anything belonging to the category of mich, me, concerns the subject as an individual entity; whereas the concept of sich has to be reserved for the social aspect of this subject. In terms of Uexküll’s principle of Ich-Ton, which determines the identity and individuality of an organism, we can distinguish in it two aspects: Moi and Soi. In “me” the subject appears as such, as a bundle of sensations; in the “self” the subject appears as observed by others, as socially determined. These constitute the existential and social aspects of the subject, or rather, its individual and communal sides. Here we put together most important ideas presented above. My intention was to specify the category of Being by providing this basic modality with new aspects drawn from Kant and Hegel, and to follow the phases of this concept further, from Kierkegaard to Sartre and Fontanille. When one aims for more subtle tools in semiotics, one can still find basic innovations in classics of the philosophy. Being-in-itself and Being-for-itself were turned into Being-in-and-for-myself in existential semiotics. When these notions are combined in the Greimassian semiotic square, one gets the cases shown in Figure 1.7.

Figure 1.7: Moi/Soi

1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING | 25

The figure may be interpreted as follows: 1. Being-in-myself represents our bodily ego, which appears as kinetic energy, “khora”, desire, gestures, intonations, Peirce’s Firstness. Our ego is not yet conscious of itself in any way, but rests in the naïve Firstness of its Being. Modality: endotactic Will. 2. Being-for-myself corresponds to Kierkegaard’s attitude of an “observer”. It is Sartre’s negation, in which the mere being shifts to transcendence, notes the lack in its own existence, and thus becomes aware of itself and transcendence. The mere being of the subject becomes existing. This corresponds to the transcendental acts of my previous model: negation and affirmation. The ego discovers its identity, reaches a certain stability, a permanent corporeality via habit. Modality: endotactic Can. 3. Being-in-itself is a transcendental category. It refers to norms, ideas, and values, which are purely conceptual and virtual; they are the potentialities of a subject, which he can either actualize or not actualize. Abstract units and categories are involved. Modality: exotactic, Must. 4. Being-for-itself means the aforementioned norms, ideas, and values as realized by the conduct of our subject in his Dasein. Those abstract entities appear here as distinctions, applied values, choices, and realizations that often will be far away from original transcendental entities. Modality: exotactic, Know. The essential aspect of the model is that it combines the spheres of Moi and Soi, the individual and collective subjectivities. It portrays semiosis not only as a movement of the collective Hegelian spirit, but also Being-in-and-for-itself – the presence of a subject – via Being-in-and-for-myself. Not only is the distinction of these four logical cases crucial, but so is the movement among them, which is the transformation of a chaotic corporeal ego into its identity, the transforming of ego into a sign to itself. We must further take into account the impact of such a stable and completely responsible “transcendental” ego on the actualization of transcendental values, in which the ego becomes a sign to other subjects. In this phase, the Being-in-and-for-myself meets the You, or Being-in-and-for-yourself, Others. Behind a thus-created social field looms the realm of transcendental and virtual values and norms, signs that have not yet become signs to anyone. Hence our model portrays the varieties of our individual and social being within the mind of a subject. It shows how the social intrudes into our innermost being and makes us social “animals”. In the classical sense, the semiotic sphere consists only of fields of Being-for-myself and Being-for-itself. The extremities of the semiotic square are the field of pre-signs, which surround from two sides the semiosis in the proper sense. In this semiosis, however, the process of act-signs cannot be understood

26 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) without going outside of it, to transcendence. The existential analysis hence becomes a Kantian transcendental analytics in these two phases. We can elaborate this a-chronic structure further. Strictly speaking, it is no longer a Greimassian semiotic square with its rigorous logical relations of contrariety, contradiction, and implication. In what follows, I move even further from the idea of a static square, toward a more dynamic and flexible model in which everything is in motion – a fundamental thesis of existential semiotics since its beginning. We can now improve the model and make it still simpler by indicating those four cases of Being on the semiotic square, using the following signs: M1, M2, M3, M4; and S1, S2, S3, S4:

Figure 1.8: Moi and Soi on the semiotic square

When these cases overlap, they appear as in Figure 1.8. They are almost the same as above but are now seen from the standpoint of our semiotic subject in general and not as his acts embodied in texts or signs. There are two directions in the model. One starts from pure corporeality and sensibility (M1; le sensible), moves to a permanent, stable body (M2), and further to the social representation of the body in social roles and professions (M3), and finally to abstract values and norms of a society (M4; l’intelligible, l’abstrait). Conversely, there is a movement from abstract norms to their exemplifications or representations in certain social institutions, further to their enactment via the suitable personalities that these institutes recruit for their purposes, and ultimately to certain corporeal entities. Hence in every form of the square, at the upper side of the Moi (as we call that part of the “me” in the model), there is a tiny trace of the social; correspondingly, in even the most abstract social norms, there is a tiny trace of pure corporeality. The model itself takes place within the mind of a subject, explaining how the social is internalized in it, and thus why we behave socially (i.e., obeying laws and norms).

1.10 The subject reconsidered: BEING | 27

Figure 1.9: Moi and soi, overlapping

It explains how society keeps us in its grasp. In Adorno’s terms, it is the juxtaposition of Ich und Gesellschaft. As a Greimassian semiotic square, I have in previous studies made efforts to temporalize it by viewing movements among its members. Now I would rather call it the “zemic” or Z-model, in view of its inner (emic) motions. The model seems apt for describing almost any possible theory or approach to human reality, depending on which aspect of subjectivity – psychological, individual, or collective – it emphasizes. For example, L’esprit des lois by Montesquieu (S1); Culture in Minds and Societies by Jaan Valsiner (2007; all M cases in the light of the S’s); Philosophy of Flesh by Mark Johnson (M1); Dictionnaire du corps (CNRS Editions 2008; all varieties of M); Characters by La Bruyère (M2); Goethe’s Wilhelm Meisters Lehrjahre, as well as the Bildungsroman in general, in its shift from M1 to S1. We can also situate other central concepts of existential semiotics into these positions: dialogue, representation, and so forth. I leave transcendence out at this point, because the model is still completely immanent – that is, it deals with phenomena of our empirical or phenomenal world, that is to say, Dasein. Transcendence becomes a crucial addendum later. The model calls for further elaboration. As it stands, it concerns four stable moments of Being. But what if we consider the modality of Doing? In that case, do the four movements represent a kind of “organic” growth from pure body to social norms? If yes, does this development take place by itself or by acts and activities of our subject? Is he/she able to promote or resist it – that is, affirm or deny it? As Schelling put it: either we are only looking at and observing this process (i.e., we are in a state of Schauen), or we can influence or cause it (i.e., we act via Handeln). How does the dialogue take place as an autocommunication among those instances of subject? Which signs and texts represent each moment? And what kinds of questions does our subject encounter in each stage?

28 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing)

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING In the foregoing scheme, man poses questions; in the cases of M, these questions are individual, whereas in cases of S they are collective. This is very typical of existential semiotics, which always tries to imagine and portray the life of signs from within – how it “feels” to be in the position of S1 or S2, and so forth. (1) In the case of M1, we might ask, Who am I in my body, perceived in its chaotic and fleshly Firstness? Answers being, for example, “I wake up in the morning, I breathe, I feel no pain, I exist, this is wonderful”. Avicenna imagined a man floating in the air without any external stimuli, yet still being sure of his existence; this would equal the state of M1. Yet, even his primary being has been soon modalized, with euphoric or dysphoric “thymic” values as follows: which properties I have, what I am capable of, what I am good at – that is, what is involved is my sensibility, my Sinnlichkeit. In Lévi-Strauss’s terms, this is the “concrete”, le sensible, the case of being in archaic societies, such as the Suyá Indians in Mato Grosso. These have a corporeal existence, but are in direct touch with myths – beliefs in the case of S1 (see Anthony Seeger 2004). (2) How can I develop my capacities so that I become a personality, so that I assume an identity? This is Snellman’s (1806–1881) notion of personality, the Goethean schöner Geist. By what training can I sublimate my physical essence into a man/woman with a certain competence? (3) How can I obtain a job, position, role in a social institute that would suit my personality, skills, and inclinations? How can I become this or that businessman, artist, politician, administrator, teacher, professor, officer, priest, and so forth? How do I obtain work that is equal to my capacities? How can I act in the community so that I become accepted by it and gain appreciation and success? (4) Can I accept the dominant values and norms of my community and society? If yes, then how can I, on this level of “Fourthness”, bring them to their brilliance and efficiency? If no (since we can always either affirm or deny), then how can I become a dissident, up to extreme negation and refusal? How can I withdraw from values that I find unacceptable and become an extreme pacifist, ecologist, and so forth? We are dealing here with quite concrete cases and positions of our subject, not only with theoretical ontological varieties of different kinds of “being”. From the standpoint of the society, however, its members, individual Mois, are but carriers or vehicles of the Soi, its tools and implementations. Hence we may from the point of view of Soi ask the following collective questions of Moi: (1) How does the latter instantiate the voice of the society, its ideology and axiology, which appear in sanctified texts and myths? That is, how does Moi represent the society as a virtual belief system?

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING |

29

(2) Here, norms and principles are shifted into manifest laws, rules, and institutions. How are the activities of individual members of the society regulated, dominated, and ruled by norms and social practices? How are such laws and rules channelled into acceptable forms and genres of behavior? This is the same as Bourdieu’s notion of habitus. (3) To what extent can individual personal properties and characteristics serve the society? Which types of persons are the proper material for its institutions? How are persons recruited into these practices? Interviews in job-hunting, for example. (4) How does the society penetrate even to the physical-sensible behavior of an individual? How are gender distinctions partly constructed? Here, we encounter those modalities whereby a Soi enacts its commitments and those passions that make it real in the innermost core of the individual, by emotions and feelings of guilt, shame, glory, duty, and their quasi-physical counterparts of behavior. Involved here is the realization of Moi and Soi via four phases in two opposed directions, in the Dasein. Issue here is linked to this movement and its goal-directness, Kantian Zweckmässigkeit (1790 [1974]: 322–325), hence this constitutes the Schellingian action, Handeln. Yet each phase also has its existential side. That is, each phase can stop, can cease moving automatically or organically forward by stepping into transcendence, by reflecting on each developmental stage from the viewpoint of its essence – that “idea” or “value” which tells us how things should be. We know, however, that from being itself we cannot infer in any way how it should be.

1.11.1 Consequences of our varieties of subjectivity Let us advance these consequences in the form of 17 theses: (1) Every sign or text stems from its being or from a certain being behind it: ontological foundation. Hence, the basis of this theory lies in the modality of Being, the philosophical category of Sein. In this sense, the theory proposed here is “realist” and not nominalist. The latter would mean taking into account only what is in the discourse, the textual level; whereas here we postulate an agent, a subject from whom these texts and signs originate. This means that we can somehow scrutinize every species and form of sign in this framework, and can in this context also interpret every scientific theory and discourse about human life. (2) Each sign or text is made by a subject in a given state of being, or emerges “organically” from it. This is one of the fundamental issues of any semiotic theory: whether signs are just pragmatic, changeable, and variable tools

30 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) that are continuously analyzed and improved upon by the agents using them, or whether they exist objectively and independent of the choices and acts of a semiotic subject. (3) One mode of being changes into another. Hence, the shift from M1 to M4 can also be interpreted as the psychological development of a subject from childhood to adult. As such, it represents a subject’s generative course. We should note that no achieved stage disappears from one’s life when he or she reaches a new state; rather, one is constructed as a multilevel psyche in the course of life. Even in the body, M1 changes physically as it ages; for example, persons, old and young, may become anguished at noticing these changes, and as a result must remodalize him/herself (Darrault-Harris and Klein 2007). On the other hand, within a subjective microtime, such as a day, one must dedicate a part of it to corporeal existence; i.e., to M1: eat, sleep, etc. Another part goes to personal hobbies in M2, another part for salaried work in M3. And a part may be devoted to general interests, to public life, social associations for universal values; i.e., to M4 = S1. Bertrand Russell recommended that with age the last part should become more and more prominent, when M3 action is completed with retirement. This is valid in much of Western society, of course; but in archaic communities the division of daily routine is different, as it is in postmodern, post-industrial society. One who is unemployed may be deprived of levels M3 and M4, but can focus on his M1 and M2. Different profiles of lifestyles, can thus be sketched on the basis of our Z-model. (4) Different modes of being are in dialogue with each other. So far existential semiotics has mostly dealt with only a single, solipsistic subject, living its life in his/her Dasein and pursuing his/her “transcendental journeys”. Yet, a subject is formed and constituted by his/her communication with other subjects as much as by personal choices. John Dewey said that mere communication as such is educative. Some scholars have even argued that such a dialogue is the primary issue; in other words, communication and mediation – all our ideas, concepts, and values – are nothing but absolutizations of these experiences of dialogue. The best-known theory in this regard is that by Mikhail Bakhtin. An entire school of psychology has been elaborated on his theory by Hubert J. M. Hermans, who speaks about the dialogical self as a “society of mind”. To Hermans, this notion was inspired by William James in his classic distinction of “I” and “Me” (as also with George Herbert Mead) and by Bakhtin in his theory of the polyphonic novel. Thus for Hermans “Self and society both function as a polyphony of consonant and dissonant voices” (Hermans 2002: 148). The issue here is whether we consider the dialogue as a disturbing element (“noise”) in our Z-model, which seems to be a relatively closed and autotelic process. Or do we take dialogue as the precondition of any such process and shift

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING |

31

from one phase to the other? If we take the phenomenological position, then the only certain thing is our own stream of consciousness; anything that happens in another’s mind is only our hypothesis, and it is a constant source of frustration in our lives when these others do not behave as we expected. Dialogue always constitutes the unpredictable element in our Dasein; it serves as the Freudian reality principle, correcting our otherwise random and sometimes wild fantasies and concepts. The other external issue that provides us with standards and suasive forces is transcendence. (5) What does it mean that one mode of being changes into another? This is the principle of “unfolding” development, of history both in individuals and societies. There are two major narratives of such metamorphoses, one stemming from M1 and moving toward S1, the other from S1 and ultimately reaching M1. The Finnish psychiatrist and writer Oscar Parland wrote a novel, Förvandlingar (Changes), in which he, with astonishment, scrutinized transformations of human life, such that new identities could emerge under the cover of a gastropod shell and a brilliant butterfly emerge (Parland 1945 [1966]). Or, as in Turgenev’s novels, a person is portrayed in heartbreaking and incurable sorrow at one moment, and in the next moment appears years later, talking and laughing cheerfully with others. (6) Every mode of being has its history: the memory of what it was, and the expectations of what it will be. This means that the paradigms of memory and expectation are open at each moment of the process of the horizontal appearance, but in the existential sense we are not bound to them. In his speech at the La Coruña world congress of the International Association for Semiotic Studies, Salman Rushdie asked whether or not we are bound to our history. Expectation is in turn based on the modality of “believe” (Greimas) or the principle of hope (Ernst Bloch 1985). These in turn are closely related to the modality of “knowing”. Some would say that hope is based on ignorance, the fact that we probably do not know what will happen. Life is a determined semiosis in many respects; however, there is that improbabilité infinie, which can happen, which in fact really does happen, and which causes huge empires to collapse. A person can achieve something against all odds and evaluations (Arendt 1972: 221). If all signs obtain their power in reference to the past by the functioning of involuntary memory (Henri Bergson), they also can be re-articulated, first by reflection and thought in our present, and then in our textual and discursive activities, whereby these intuitions are communicated to others. Hence what was at first totally private, unique, and mental, becomes public, common, and ultimately a semiotic force in reshaping our Dasein. (7) Every sign is considered an appearance with regard to its Being; thus, Being constitutes its truth. Does the Z-model, then, describe the essence

32 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) of the world, understood as what and how life really is in our Dasein, as a kind of ontological depth that then manifests as our semiotic-symbolic activities? The whole theory of Schein is extremely important here, where we speak of “vertical appearance”. To say that truth is always conditioned by history would mean to deny this type of Schein. In the words of Kant: “. . . so kann man nicht vermeiden, dass nicht alles dadurch in blossen Schein verwandelt werde” (1787 [1968]: 116). (8) Dialogue between two subjects, or how modes take place in different “levels” or modes. Who speaks in a dialogue? A subject who consists of various portions or degrees of the principles M and S. Dialogue is a mutual transference that is aided or blocked by similarity, identity, or difference between the Moi and Soi. A dialogue exists (a) when within the same Dasein Moi A and Moi B, share the same Soi; or (b) when they share the same S and M; e.g., M = gender and S = values, and these two actors, x and y, in communication both have their own variants of M1, M2, M3 . . . and S1, S2, S3 . . . . In the case of (a), the Italian scholars Gino Stefani and Stefania Guerra Lisi, in their pathbreaking treatise on art therapy, Globality of Languages in Art and in Life (2006), elaborate the principle of contact in all communication. How we get in contact with other persons is certainly a fundamental issue in our Dasein, and negatively so if a lecturer or performer feels he did not gain contact with his audience, or a teacher with his pupils. Now the following questions arise: (1) How does the dialogue intervene in and influence our becoming and growth from M1 to S1? (2) How does the dialogue intervene in our transformation from the social man into an individual who has a unique destiny in the world, and who distinguishes him-/herself not only socially (Bourdieu) but also existentially? In the first case, our subject-actor externalizes him-/herself, becomes manifest; he/she explains himself by getting involved in broader and broader circles and contexts. In the latter case, it is the society, S, that understands itself by becoming more and more substantial and concrete. How does the subject in its state of M1 reach toward S1 in its efforts to succeed in social life, and in its desire to become accepted? On the other hand, how is M1 manipulated by S1 and S2 via its formation process, Bildung, Erscheinen, development? Communication is a special type of appearance, Erscheinen. We have there, in an ideal case, two subjects, X and Y (Saussure’s Mr. A and Mr. B) in a dialogue. X sends a sign from his/her M1 and Y answers from the position of his/her M2. For example, a young artist or student, full of enthusiasm but without techniques, displays something he has written chaotically by his intuition, and the receiver answers from his/her S3: Do not try, you should first work and learn a lot! But the answer can also derive from the receiver’s S2: You must first be a professionally recognized artist. Or from S1: Your expression has no aesthetic value whatsoever! Contact is not established unless the subjects talk on the same levels of their M/S modes. This is one source of misunderstanding among individuals and collective

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING |

33

actors. In society, we listen to the signs of S. If signs of M and S come into conflict, how do we judge? The situation is analogous to Husserl’s distinction of two types of sign: Bedeutungszeichen and Ausdruckszeichen – that is, symbolic, conventional exo-signs as signs of S, and expressive endo-signs, often iconic, organic signs of M. The third type of sign is transcendental, leading us beyond both Moi and Soi. By transcendental signs we reflect on those of M/S. They form a kind of metalanguage whereby we talk about our situation in Dasein and transcend it. (9) The real semiotic forces in the universe occur in the two opposite directions: from body to values, that is, from concrete to abstract (M1–S1), or from values and norms to “khora” (S1–M1). The essential issue leading us toward semiotics of action, toward what Habermas called “kommunikatives Handeln” (Habermas 1987), is whether we can trust that these forces function organically, and watch only to see if something goes wrong so as to correct the Z process, or if we are we required to do something, perform a special semiotic act, with every shift from M1 to M2 to M3 = S2, and so forth. If yes, then what is the nature of such an act whereby we intervene in the course of the events? Should it be studied according to a logic of action, as in considering how p becomes q? Or should we adopt the Heideggerian principle of Gelassenheit, the principle of letting things happen, as put forth by Morris (1956)? (10) The encounter between Moi and Soi – i.e., body and society – takes place between M2 and S2. Hence the essential shift is from social practices to individual or already half-socialized identities and personalities. Yet this “bridge” from M to S or from S to M cannot be separated from the encounter as a whole. We might say that there are two concepts that crystallize this encounter. One is “gesture”, which characterizes the cases M1 and M2. In M1 “gesture” is still only on the level of behavior. Yet gesture can become intentional in M2 when it is done by a person with an identity, and then we reach the phase of “acting” or Handeln. The other important notion here is the one of “genre”, or Gattung, as a special type of social practice both in action and text. All genre scholars admit that it is essentially a social notion, based on a collective agreement, and that it presupposes a proper audience, a receiver community. For example, TV, cinema, and mass media genres have been formed for special types of public, as Cobley has emphasized (2001: 192). In literature it is constituted by readers; in music it is constituted by listeners. Therefore, the encounter of Me and Society, Moi and Soi, takes place as the conjunction, either blending together or conflicting, between gesture and genre. As Adorno has said, gestures that cannot be developed, only repeated and intensified (Adorno 1974: 32). They must be put into expressive genres in order to be influential in the cultural sense, and not remain on merely the psychological, individual level. Sometimes the “me” wants to impose its own new Soi; as regarding avant-garde works of art, it is said that they create their own audience. This

34 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) can prove difficult, however, because communication is possible only by means of an accepted language, grammar as a social agreement and construction. A single Moi cannot decide this, unless he/she wants to speak an idiolectic language understood by only one person. On the other hand, genres need to be attractive to individuals, to M2s, so as to serve their purposes. In this sense, genre involves making an impact (Wirken) according to a certain plan, or semiotically speaking, narrative program. Using Brémond’s (1973) terms, we can describe the narrative phases leading our subject (internally) from one mode or phase to the others: the shift from S1 to S2 = virtuality; from S2 to S3 (M2) = passage to an act; and from S3 (M2) to S4 (M1). We may ask, How does this relate to the demand of existentiality? Is existentiality present in phases M1 and M2, thereafter giving place for something “social”, the Soi, which would then be the origin of semiosis? If so, then a semiotic act would be essentially of a social nature, and we would from those phenomenological adventures return to the Saussurean basis. However, if we conceive the semiotic act existentially as a transcendental act, we would rather think that our subject was able to take some distance from all those four modes of being, and from the operations connecting them and putting them into a developmental scheme from M1 to S1 or vice versa, so to step outside of this process, in which case the real leap is based precisely on the liberty of the subject to scrutinize his/her Dasein from a transcendental viewpoint and thus pursue what we earlier called a “transcendental journey”. (11) In the analysis of subjects (of Being and Doing) and their representations (appearing), the four modes can exist simultaneously. Valsiner (2007) quotes Lewin’s comparison between American and German personality spheres and how easily their borderlines can be crossed. The structure of intrapsychological borderline systems is involved here. Layer 5 is the utmost subjective, deeply intrapersonal level. In the American U-type personality, this layer is protected by resistance boundaries to outsiders’ penetration, whereas the other layers (1–4) can be crossed in the interpersonal domain with relative ease. In the German G-type only, the outermost layer is easily crossed; in other layers one is more protected (Figure 1.10). Valsiner has concluded that people create their own personal-cultural structure of self-boundaries and rules for entry into the various layers of one’s self (ibid.: 247). We could say the same about crossing the boundaries from M1 through S1 (Figure 1.11). The boundaries between the modes are not necessarily fixed, but vary according to different situations of dialogue with other persons in the community. Signs are used to mark these spheres; for example, clothes, such as uniforms, can signify the protection of M1 and M2 in the social role of a priest, soldier, businessmen.

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING |

35

Figure 1.10: Kurt Lewin’s comparison of social relations in (a) America and (b) Germany (Valsiner 2007: 247)

Figure 1.11: Boundaries of the self, according to Valsiner (2007)

On an airplane, passengers quickly mark their spheres by placing things around themselves. Though one person lets another intrude into his/her M2 or even M1, this may not hold true with a different person. Marshal Mannerheim could toast with a young solder at an evening party, but the next day found him again in his high position. The dialogical-self model questions the idea of a fixed core, if one assumes that, as Hermans defines it, “The dialogical self is conceived as social – not in the sense that a self-contained individual enters into social interactions with other outside people, but in the sense that other people occupy positions in the multivoiced self. The self is not only ‘here’ but also ‘there’, and because of the power of imagination the person can act as if he or she were the other” (Valsiner 2007: 149).” This was evident as early as in the early works of Bakhtin, when he discovered the dialogical nature of any communication. This dialogical principle is organized

36 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) into an imaginary landscape in which “I” has the possibility to move as in space, which is exactly what Proust said about music and its capacity to teach people to see unknown realities through others’ eyes. (12) Among the modes, there exists a process of learning (“knowing”) from a subject’s inner point of view or of educating (“making known”). Learning and teaching are essentially dialogue, but the problem for every individual M1 is to become M2 and M3, and so forth, whereas from the viewpoint of culture, it is crucial that its values of S1 are adopted, assimilated, maintained, and renewed by institutions, personalities, and ultimately living and experiencing human subjects. So, for example, if S1 = love for fatherland (Heimat), then S2 may = army, S3 = M2 = soldier, and then S4 = M1 = a certain combination of qualities. Another example: S1 = love for beauty in communication; S2 = theater, M2 = actor, M1 = certain physiopsychic qualities; or S1 = love for beauty in sounds; S2 = orchestra, S3 = M2 = musician, M1 = certain ability to hear and body to play. Whether teaching occurs as a dialogue between a master with high competence and a younger pupil imitating him/her, or as a self-teaching process in a dialogical group or club is an interesting educational issue. On one hand, culture decides which texts and modalities are to be preserved and further transmitted to younger generations and which are to be forgotten. Ultimately, the distinction between “culture” and “civilization” (see Elias 1997) concerns putting the emphasis either on S1 – as internal, interoceptive – or on M1, as exteroceptive, sensuality, pleasure. (13) Every mode of Being and Doing as well as Becoming has its own ambiance, atmosphere, Stimmung, how they feel in their positions. Such an emotional atmosphere emerges from the isotopies, which are the basis of any action or decision-making. The existential project emphasizes this inner view of things. (14) At every stage or mode, possibilities are open for reflection (Schauen), dissociation, alienation, and existentiality, which means a shift to a metalevel, “meta-being” via affirmation/negation. Hence, the possibility of freedom opens on the side of necessity. Here, we have to ponder how the transcendence appears and manifests in the Dasein; often, it occurs as a noise or disturbance in the communication. Let us think of such a value as goodness. How can we explain that such things as goodness are a reality? Those who do good acts most often have to suffer and even become martyrs from their consequences, not merely in the sense of ingratitude from the side of the objects of goodness, but even their hostility. Arendt said that good acts have to be concealed; they can never be made public. That, however, cannot always be avoided. How can goodness make people worse and not better? Because goodness means strength, and by helping others, one shows he/she is stronger than the other, a form of subordination that people consider unbearable. On the other hand, goodness

1.11 Questions by a subject: From BEING to DOING |

37

makes evil appear, and when it is foregrounded, it can be more easily attacked and conquered. Goodness may thus seem an anomaly and disturbance. Very often transcendence is felt in such a way. (15) One mode of Being can compensate or sublimate another. In the process of civilization, certain basic qualities are, via training and education, elevated from their merely physical qualities to the most spiritual, Thirdness-level phenomena and sign actions. Yet there are limits: the lack of certain M1 properties cannot be compensated for by a strong belief in certain values and cultural goals. A young person may hear in an entrance examination: “You will never become this and that”. Prophecies often realize themselves but also cause counterreactions that make an individual cross over his normal boundaries. (16) Each mode of Being is an actuality, but in a dialogue with others it becomes reality; yet, these modes originate from and aim for virtualities. Virtuality here is the same as transcendence, hence the problem is, How do we communicate with such an entity as transcendence? Is transcendental movement opposed to a dialogue in Dasein? Dialogue can strengthen or weaken the development of Moi. In fact, Moi is constituted by and in dialogue only, but how can we be sure that there is a transcendental dimension to our whole existence? What we consider the voice of transcendence may be nothing but the impact of another subject on us, and via him/her the S1 what our surrounding community takes as transcendental: it is true and absolute under all circumstances. What is the difference and how do we distinguish between truth in Dasein and truth in a transcendental sense? How do we talk with transcendence? Via meta-modalities? If I want something in Dasein, how does that differ from wanting and striving for something transcendental? Does the latter mean an elevation of something into a general and universal principle for all others as well? Or if I know something in Dasein, how do I know in transcendence? The latter may seem irrational or absurd in the light of the former. (17) Every mode of being has one dominant modality that organizes and subordinates the others. Thus, in M1 the modality of Will is the most important; everything is in a state of wanting/willing to be actualized. In M2, Can organizes all the other modalities, which find their place in harmony or disharmony with that modality; involved here is what one realistically Can do with one’s modalities, their capacity to be actualized. In M3, Know gives further possibilities for enacting, actualizing, realizing modalities; the knowledge (Wissen) accumulated in social institutions provides persons with their proper position in that society. In M4, Must dominates; it evaluates, orders, commands, subordinates, tests previous modes, either approving or disapproving them. It seems that the modalities, in their order of development, are built one upon the other, so that they accumulate into a more or less firm foundation. So essen-

38 | 1 Existential semiotics today: Sein (Being) and Schein (Appearing) tially the Must of S1 would never have any power over subjects until they have first internalized it in their own Will (cf. Jaspers 1948: 423–435). Thanks to Will, the Dasein is not closed within its own world but reaches beyond it. There is illusion and reality. Will tries to make illusions concrete realities. Thanks to Will, the Dasein steps into history. With the energy of Will, we strive in our imaginary directive of interiority toward real situations. So Jaspers conceives the energy and power of Will as a kind of streaming force so that connects the various modes of being, our M1–M2–M3–M4. Will “is not satisfied with satisfaction at one moment but constitutes the ‘destiny’ and basis for the continuity of our existence” (ibid.: 425). On the other hand, Will is at the origin of our semiotic acts. It is, as Jaspers well observes (ibid.), “Duration as the continuity of sense” (Sie ist Dauer als Kontinuität des Sinns). The first sign of the functioning of a will is bodily movement, which should be seen as a continuation of our psychic events as they appear at a given moment (Augenblick). For Jaspers, this is a truly magical moment because there the spiritual directly intervenes in the psychic and physical world and causes a change in our Dasein. Therefore, “will” is the moment that recruits all the other modalities for its fulfilment. It is the counterforce to the merely occurring, organic, or automatic course from M1 to S1. So on one hand we have growth and becoming, fulfilment and force; on the other hand, we have doing and goals (ibid.: 429). In this aspect, Will might even seem to be something uncreative; it can only desire such things that are given in that automatic process and set its goals according to the Know of S2 and Must of S1.

Chapter 2 On the appearance or the present structure and existential digressions of the subject Motto: Die Zeit ist die formale Bedingung a priori aller Erscheinungen überhaupt (Kant 1787/1986: 98)

2.1 Introduction One does not need to know much history of semiotics in order to recognize the background of my title. It is of course a paraphrase of Umberto Eco’s classic Struttura assente (1968), whose outcome was one of the milestones in the history of European semiotics. At that moment, everything had turned into ‘structural’. LéviStrauss had already published his Anthropologie structurale (1962) – but why was structure absent in Eco? The thought reveals something quite essential in the history of structuralism and the way of reasoning to which a grand part of semiotics has stayed faithful – namely that the ‘true’ reality was not the one to be seen, heard and felt, but the structure behind it, which causes it. The surface of the reality was only, as Greimas said ‘effet du sens’, i.e., a meaning effect. In one word, the reality was only Schein, like as early as Schiller and Kant taught, or appearance, or illusion. What is involved is a kind of reductionism like as early as Mireille MarcLipiansky remarked about Lévi-Strauss: réductionnisme qui cherche à ramener le supérieur à l’inférieur (Marc-Lipiansky 1973: 136); in the same study, under the title ‘antihumanism’, she distinguished among four different phases: the reduction of the individual into the collective, the reduction of the conscious to unconscious categories, the reduction of consciousness into an unconscious combinatory, which eliminates the creative activity of a subject and the historicity, and the reduction of freedom into necessity. One could not in a better way resume the issue. Without any doubt has this world view won when we look at the world around us. Yet, it is the aim of this essay to attempt to show that there is an alternative. There no phenomenon is reduced into anything else, but both the individual, conscious, the phenomena of consciousness, creativity, historicity, subject and freedom are possible – at least in theory. In order to convey the idea in terms of the old-fashioned German humanism – which the Germans themselves have tried to forget since Adorno and Benjamin: Den Sinnen hast

40 | 2 On the appearance Du dann zu trauen, kein falsches lassen sie dich schauen, wenn dein Verständnis dich wach erhält (Trust then in your senses, they do not betray you when your understanding keeps you awake). On the other hand, existentiality has reached former Paris school scholars of semiotics. In his new theories (a.o. Présences de l’autre , Landowski 1997), the social semiotician Eric Landowski has scrutinized semiotics of the life itself, even if it were leading us to intuitive knowledge and a kind of ‘light’ semiotics. It is close to phenomenology, to the notion of situation by Sartre, which Landowski admits having used for a long time; in the end, what one encounters here is the semiotics of experience and ‘being in the world’ (être au monde). It is essential that in this new semiotics the crucial things are the digressions from a programmed behaviour. According to Landowski, a bee and a housewife are programmed entities: “Where did you put my apples”, she asks when arranging things. They have to be always in the same place, for instance at the piano. It would be senseless to ask why it has to be so. The program entitles itself. But the existential behaviour is irregular and breaks the ‘normal’ course. Therefore, we cannot presume, that it would follow same laws as ‘programmed’, ‘natural world’. Existentiality is hence a deviation from structure. One does not need to search far from the artistic representation of this problem as it is the central theme in the trilogy by the Finnish movies director Aki Kaurismäki in his films Drifting Clouds, The Man Without a Past and Lights in the Dusk – particularly in the last mentioned (from 2006), in the most cogent but also gloomiest and most apocalyptic manner. The structure of the society is mostly there, it is not shown, it is ‘somewhere’ there, but its affirmative pressure has been denied by cinematic means, or as Adorno put it: “The revolt against the appearance, the unsatisfied state of art about itself, has been the recurrent motif in the request for truth in art . . . Art has always strived for dissonance . . . the affirmative drive of society, with which the aesthetic illusion has allied, has subordinated this aspiration” (Adorno 2006: 226). In the Lights of the Suburb only the consequences are shown in the existential vicissitudes of subjects, in their violence. The cinematographic Schein is at the same time fascinating, but it serves the cause of uncovering ‘the truth of being’. Accordingly, it does not remain mere ‘shine’, brilliance without foundation, or lie, something which appears but is not. Hence existentiality and structure meet each other and one always discovers subjects whose conduct is deviation from structure, a challenge to it. When Kaurismäki was asked: “Are you an existentialist?” he responded: “ I do not know. Perhaps not, since then it would prove that Sartre was not . . . .” (1988) (cited from v. Bagh 2006: 74). However, the principle of hope by Ernst Bloch is realized still in the closing words of the movie: “Do not

2.1 Introduction |

41

go – stay here/Do not die/I shall not die of this” (ibid.: 210). It is hard to get rid of the scheme: structure and its appearance. Yet in sociology we are taught that structures are constructions in order to explain man’s behaviour. The Phenomenology of Everyday Life by Alfred Schütz and Thomas Luckmann investigates structures and discovers there even three kinds of transcendences: a. minor everyday transcendences of type “I open the closet and take the coffee cup from its familiar place”, i.e., I presume that it is there although I did not perceive it; b. middle: I encounter another person whom I suppose to be to some extent similar to myself; c. major: I return via a novel or a film to ancient Rome, or I am shifted to the past, i.e., absent time, or to the future. But altogether, when the structure has been ‘revealed’ or made manifest, it is said that it dominates man’s actions, manifests in them, and hence it is reified as something Yuri Lotman called ‘a generator of structurality’. Then how seriously do we have to take the concept of Schein, illusion? Many persons living in the contemporary world – those whom the ‘understanding’ still keeps awake – have noticed that there is more and more Schein in the society, the reality has been made a spectacle, it has been ‘aestheticised’ (Wolfgang Welsch), it has been polished, but we cannot take it seriously, albeit we live amidst it. The finer, the more glittering, the more colorful letter drops into our mail box, the more probably we classify it as an ‘ad’ and throw it to trashes. So senders have set forth to imitate ‘ authentic’ message and we can receive a letter reminding misleadingly of a handwritten letter – where we are offered a.o. better conditions of insurance. The more visually impressive a power point presentation is, the more we doubt whether its author has, in fact, anything important to say. If the label of a wine bottle is very bright and tempting, we leave the bottle on the shelf and grasp another one with an old-fashioned text. On stage, more shocking than virtuoso acrobacy and physicality can be a calm reading of a text in a darkened room. Even the corporeality can be Schein in the sense of a betrayal, illusion. When the body is too gegenständlich (thinglike) it loses its credibility and more impressive can be after all a transfigured body like in El Greco’s paintings. Thus we can distinguish between what I have called ‘act-sign’ and ‘quasisign’. But on which basis? By which quality do we recognize the Schein character of a sign in our contemporary world of electronic communication? Doubtless must there be in a sign some extra- or additional signs which provide us with a hint. What are they? How can they be found? How do we find the right avenue amidst the temptations of Schein?

42 | 2 On the appearance

2.2 More on vertical appearance The idea of the appearance of the Schein is not quite a new finding; it dates back to German philosophy. Kant spoke about it in his Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1787/1969), Friedrich Schiller in his Briefe über ästhetische Erziehung (1795/2000). Kant pondered over Schein in Critique of Pure Reason, in the chapter ‘Transcendental aesthetics’. He argues how space and time determine all our perception concerning both external objects and our own states of mind. Later on, Greimas coined the terms interoceptive/exteroceptive (it is altogether not difficult to turn Kant into semiotics in the framework of the Paris School). But then what is involved is how the external and the internal world appear to our senses. From this, one cannot yet reason that they were mere Schein (ein blosser Schein). As early as this nuance represents the attitude that Schein is something less real than objects as such. Nevertheless, it would be our own fault, according to Kant, if we started solely on this ground to consider the entire objective reality a Schein, in the sense of an illusion. Kant inquires: what is truth? Is it coincidence of perception with its object? No, since perception is filtered by a priori categories. On the other hand, formal logic is not the same as the logic of these perceptual categories; by formal logic we cannot say anything about objective reality. One needs a particular logic of Schein which Kant calls dialectic in order to talk about how Schein, illusion, is related to reality – in other words, the program is the same as the one which Thomas A. Sebeok declared two hundred years later as the objective of semiotics: to study our illusions about reality, its various alternative models, not reality as such. In any case, in Kant the term Schein always appears in the context of bloss, but he does not deny that it is also ‘real’ (Kant, op. cit.: 114–116). Adorno took this view directly from Kant, Schein was illusion, phantasmagoria, which art paradoxically has to deny and abolish by its own Schein. Schiller became familiar with Kant’s thought immediately, and as one result we have his famous letters about aesthetic education. Yet, the radical difference from Kant was that he referred to the joy of Schein. The savage men became humans when they were detached from reality, when they started to take it as a play and as a Schein, which could be appreciated as such. The dissolution from interests of the reality towards the world of Schein was a decisive step of progress for mankind. We see by means of our eyes, we hear by means of our ears, but it is an entirely different thing to feel with eyes and to experience the rhythm of the surrounding world. As long as man is savage, he feels his emotions only with his senses but as soon as he starts to enjoy what his eyes see and furnishes what he sees with its own value, he is aesthetically free and the ‘play desire’ develops in him. Finally,

2.2 More on vertical appearance

| 43

such a right and sincere Schein was to Schiller’s mind also moral, insofar as it did not attempt to represent the reality, nor even when the reality used it as its own representation. To strive for independent Schein more freedom of heart and energy of will were needed than in order to dominate the reality. Undeniably the sphere of morality also belonged to the universe of Schein; it included two world views – we could continue from Schiller: either, a being is basically good and evilness mere Schein, or, goodness is apparent and evilness real. In literature we encounter representatives of both directions: see, for instance, the latter point dominant in novels by Céline, Camus, Sartre, while the former is evident in Brontë, Tolstoi, Gide. If the evil is basically veiled sacred, then how far can we live resorting to this ad hoc hypothesis? How far can the Schein of the evil go, that we still believe in the goodness of being looming behind it? According to another theory, the evilness of a society falls upon an individual, causing the disillusionment, the cynic view – or as Jean Cocteau put it: the society is a machine infernale in order to annihilate the mortal – it is a kind of cruel play of the Gods. Even this theory certainly gets evidence for its support. Consequently, we have two basic theories of Schein: one that maintains it as false, as illusion, betrayal; and the other one that considers it an independent, autonomous reality of its own, a great step of progress of humanity. How these theories have been inherited by later discussion about Schein will be seen soon. Likewise, the French phenomenologist Étienne Souriau, who also had an impact upon early semiotic structuralism, like Sémantique structurale by Greimas, and whose monumental knowledge of the whole 20th century was gathered in a collective work Vocabulaire d’esthétique, gives new meanings to the terms of apparence and apparition. The term apparence is defined by Souriau as an aspect whereby an object manifests, insofar as this representation then distinguishes itself from the object thus becoming manifest. From this definition, furthermore three different nuances open, which are: 1. the mere appearance of something to our senses, i.e., a phenomenon; 2. precisely the illusory appearance or illusion; 3. the appearance which presupposes some kind of judgement, i.e., is the same as vraisemblance, verisimilitude. As far as what is involved is an illusion, we speak for instance about the illusion of reality in painting or theater. The ‘truth’ of theater is based upon three kinds of illusions: representation of emotions of men, the illusion of time and place or diegesis and presentation of natural or supernatural phenomena in order to provoke strong emotions in spectator or in order to increase the credibility of the events on stage in general. The latter

44 | 2 On the appearance case also leads to the term apparition which thus means appearance of something surprising to the spectator. What appears can be a real person who indeed appears at a right moment on stage, for instance the masked subscriber of Requiem in the movie Amadeus by Forman; but it can also be a real person who is imagined to be present; or it can be in reality a supernatural being – like Il commandatore at the end of Don Giovanni. It is evident that apparence corresponds to the German notion of Schein and apparition to Erscheinung. Altogether, these cases deal with Schein as a vertical phenomenon, in depth: it is something, somewhere – which, then, so to say, is elevated to the surface of reality and manifests itself. Greimas’s theory of paraître is also of this kind. In his well-known so-called veridictory square we act by categories of être and paraître, being and appearing. When they are negated we get four cases; being, not-being, appearing, not-appearing. When they are situated in the square, we get four meaning effects: truth, untruth, lie and secret, always according to what the relationship of these categories is: truth is what appears and is what it appears; lie is what appears but is not that; secret is something which is but does not appear in any way and untruth is something which neither is nor appears.

Figure 2.1: Greimas’s veridictory square

In fact it is already on this basis that we can sketch a theory of vertical Schein. We notice how many topical problems of culture, art and philosophy find their proper place in this framework. Regarding existential semiotics what is involved is a theory of Dasein of course. Otto Lehto has proposed that Dasein is characterized by its particular Da-signs. But to which extent are they in reality Da-shine in the sense of brilliance, virtuosity and bravura of this term? Even though in shine there is always the same danger as with Schein or it is always under certain conditions the same as fake and illusions, the lie: All that glitters is not gold. Without love the words are empty as the Bible says. Thus, one has to distinguish between Pseudo-shine which belongs to the category of vanity, and the authentic shine or brilliance, which is always based on

2.2 More on vertical appearance | 45

the ‘truth of being’. What is involved can be shine which has been gained by work according to the protestant ethics. We accept richness if it has been obtained by striving or overwhelming talents, but doubt nouveaux riches. On the symbolic level, in a symphony, the law of thematic elaboration prevails: the victory finale of the end has to be gained by the struggle of thematic actorial forces in music, in their Durchführung and in the whole structure; if in music there is shine without this work, it is entertainment, lower level shimmer. Yet, there is also brilliance which is like gift of nature, proof of vitality, overwhelming energy, like in the case of Australian aboriginal handicraft studied by Anne Hénault. The problem of shine remains in the aforementioned distinction: from which signs can we distinguish between pseudo-shine and real, ‘good’ shine? In order to do this we need to compare Schein to Sein – to continue our playing with words. Appearance and being manifest in many forms and variations in the history of ideas. First, we have a pair of concepts referring to this: structure and ornament. One thinks that structure ‘is’ (i.e., it is real, it is something permanent), whereas its decoration is merely the quality of surface. It is required for a good work of art to contain a well-planned structure, which can be deliberately decorated, but without such a structure one does not reach a substantial impact. In music this is evident. The finale of the Quartet opus 30 by Ernest Chausson is real shine, brilliance, which for performers is a remarkable technical challenge – but it turns out to be easier when one distinguishes in music what is structure and what is figuration, ornamentation. In general, this means to distinguish the important, pertinent elements from the less important, i.e., between what is foregrounded and what is pushed towards the background. In this case, we put in the background the brilliant figuration and in the foreground there comes the structure, the substance. The very moment this cognitive operation articulates the text in the performer’s mind, he makes it his/her ‘own’, which leads to the right interpretation. For instance, the last pages of the Chausson work are quasi-unplayable, namely, if one approaches it such as that all has to be played with the same vigour. But when one notices that the octaves of the pianist’s left hand actually duplicate the cello and alto theme in unison – which is nothing else but the return of a variant of the ‘Parsifal’ theme from the slow movement in this narrative climax (‘the return of the hero’), but now as euphoric and brilliant – whereas the right hands of the pianist and of the violinist play mere ornamentation to this structure, then the riddle of these pages is solved. What is involved is authentic shine, which is based upon ‘truth of being’, i.e., the return of the theme. Moreover, the whole theory of simulacra, copies of reality as Schein, belongs to this category. The doctrines of Jean Baudrillard get here a new dimension, just as Eco’s theory of forgery. The problem of a forgery is not only in comparison of two

46 | 2 On the appearance objects on the same level but in the shift of levels: in the dialectics of appearance and being, in the Kantian sense. Likewise, the theory of dreams represents the illusory nature of the oneiric reality compared to being, to which we always wake up. Yet, the problem remains like in the Chinese anecdote; there was a Chinese man who dreamed to be a butterfly; when he woke up he thought: am I now a Chinese who dreams to be a butterfly or am I a butterfly who dreams to be a Chinese? Ingmar Bergman spoke about a particular ‘moment of wolf’, which one experiences in the night, when the entire daylight existence collapses as Schein and behind it the true reality is revealed, which evokes one’s deepest values. One does not need to do anything any longer, the lack has been liquidated. A respective mirror relationship appears between the classical concepts of subject and object. Does the subject represent the ‘true’ being and the objects the world of ‘appearances’ as Kierkegaard supposedly thought, or is the world of objects real and the world of subjects Schein? The answer naturally depends on epistemology, i.e., whether we adopt the idealist or realist attitude. In the sphere of society one can ask: Is the ‘I’ the only certain thing and the ‘Other’ or ‘you’ Schein, which we can always reach only fragmentarily and hypothetically by presuming that what occurs in ‘you’ is something similar as in ‘me’? This was the basic problem of the phenomenological sociology of Alfred Schütz and Thomas Luckmann. On the level of culture and society Norbert Elias has spoken about the difference between culture and civilisation, where culture is spirit, depth, values – i.e., the German culture – and civilisation sensuality, superficiality, matter – i.e., Italian-French culture. All trends of fashion of modern contemporary culture would be thus put to the latter case. But behind fashion there looms style, or as a French classic already said: the style is the man. We could specify: man’s more stable essence, his identity. Style manifests – or appears – in its variability as fashions, fashion elevates the style to its shine. Harri Veivo has analysed the case of printing the name of Proust on a T-shirt. It is of course a blasphemy, iconoclasm regarding the authentic style represented by Proust. How the ‘Proustian’ body sits at a chair in a stylish and almost ‘transcendental’ manner: a photo of Reynaldo Hahn. This is still style, identity, which appears as corporeal signs (Veivo 2006: 40–41). Furthermore, from this we can infer the dichotomy mind/matter or spirit and body. Even the earth spirit and matter (one young Tartu semiotician studies the semiotics of the ‘Earth spirit’ manifest in certain ancient woods in Estonia). Ultimately: transcendence and Dasein, where the true being is transcendental and being-there only metaphor and, finally, as already said, Da-shine. The dichotomy of spirit and body constitutes a particular field of semiotic problems of its own, which crystallizes in the opposition verbal/non-verbal. The non-verbal in communication is, of course, gesturality. The Moscow linguist Nat-

2.2 More on vertical appearance | 47

alia Sukhova has divided the communication act into two aspects: the prosodic nucleus or structure of the sentence, and its kinetic, gestural enactment. The gesticulation is, thus, ‘appearance’ of communication, its visible side, its Schein. Yet, the aforementioned two aspects go hand in hand: i.e., when a human being speaks he/she gesticulates and mimics in order to make his/her speech persuasive. Fully gestureless or expressionless speech act would not guarantee the understanding of the message, i.e., solely the prosodic nucleus is not sufficient. In fact, this theory is close to the distinction of semiotics into signification (= prosodic nucleus) and communication (= kinetic gestures). True, a communication act without gestures, Schein, can be used as an artistic device, like Aki Kaurismäki in his movies. There famous, gestureless, overgrammatical dialogue is either a special quasi-humoristic priem, artistic method, or one sign of social reification. It can also be taken as a sign of total lack of modalisation which belongs to any ‘normal’ human communication, and leads into an immobile narrativity. For instance: Man (M): What about electricity? Anttila: Is included in the rent. M: When can I move? Anttila: As soon as I turn my back. M: What about the keys? Anttila: Do you see a lock anywhere? M: I do not. Anttila: Do not make sophistry or I take even the door with me. The cash is the rent of one month. M: You will get the money already tomorrow if God allows. Anttila: His paths are unknown to me, but if you do not pay I shall send my killer dog to bite your nose away. M: Fine, it is making me only harm . . .

Particularly when one follows the filmic realisation of the scene the immobility between the two subjects Mr. A and Mr. B (remember the diagram by Saussure!), the emptiness of the modal space between them is strongly foregrounded. However, any communication normally starts from the fact that we want to say something and that this intention appears as a phrase and/or gesture. However, there are two alternative theories: either we think that intention is the signified, which has two parallel signifiers – the prosodic nucleus or the sentence AND the gestures. These signifiers are either compatible or not (see Figure 2.2). Or then we think that the core of the communicational act is the intention, which then appears as a movement outwards, towards the Other, first as a sentence – and then as a gesture. The gestures are, so to say, the utmost cover, the surface of the fulfilment of the intention, its Schein (see Figure 2.3).

48 | 2 On the appearance

prosodic nucleus 1st signifier

gestures 2nd signifier

intention signified

Figure 2.2: Intention as signified with two signifiers

kinetic gesturality prosodic nucleus (sentence) intention

Figure 2.3: Intention as the core of communication

Both theories would have musical implications: in music we first have likewise the ‘prosodic nucleus’, i.e., the musical phrase which has as a syntacticomorphological structure. But thereafter such a musical phrase is provided with ‘gestures’ which, so to say, ‘encrusts’ it. Accordingly, gestures could not be thought in music without the nucleus phrase, gestures do not have their autonomous existence, they are totally dependent on the nucleus phrase. Adorno said: gestures cannot be developed, the development is only a quality of the musico-syntactic nucleus phrase. Even in other respects of the Adornian theory, the opposed pole of Schein is ‘expression’,

2.2 More on vertical appearance | 49

Figure 2.4: Categories around being and appearance, and their empirical exemplifications

50 | 2 On the appearance which is the only guarantee for the authenticity of communication. In fact, what is involved is Husserl’s sign distinction: Ausdruckszeichen and Bedeutungszeichen and its application, just as Alfred Schütz used it in sociology with the concepts of Anzeichen and bedeutsame Zeichen (Schütz 1974: 166). Yet, how is this related to my own theory of subject, in which Moi and Soi struggle with each other so that Moi is the first mere gesture and then gradually transforms into syntax when it meets the level of the social norms, topics, techniques and styles of the Soi? According to this, is there anything like pure gesturality, which is the origin of music? The gestures and kinetics are the sphere of being-in-myself and being-formyself. But what is the status of gesture as a notion: Is it, so to say, a bridge from an organism to its Umwelt, or are the gestures, after all, always directed towards something, or intentional? Then, even the being-in-myself were intentional and would manifest a movement out of me. In any case, the world of the Moi would then represent authenticity and the one of the Soi, the Schein.

2.3 More on horizontal appearance Nevertheless, in the aforementioned dictionary by Souriau there is a passage which opens a different view. Namely, we find the following definition for the term apparence: “Certain art works never appear to the spectator entirely and by all parts simultaneously. The temporal arts like music, theatre and cinema, are all based upon successive appearance” (Souriau 1990: 140). Hence, when we join the idea of temporality – of succession, linearity, syntagmaticity, seriality, unfolding, developing – to such a static concept like Schein or being, we are led to a radically new theory. A naïve fact is that we can live our lives only one moment at a time. So the reality all the time appears to us temporarily, it has a certain rhythm, which we can, however, either decelerate or accelerate, but which altogether proceeds irrefutably. We are all the time going towards something unknown and unpredictable – we are all the time transgressing some boundary – or moving towards transcendence. Just such an idea of borderline did Schütz and Luckmann consider essential with transcendence. The thought could be resumed in one phrase: the appearance (Erscheinen) is becoming of transcendence (Werden der Transzendenz). Yet, not whatsoever becoming is an ‘existential’ revelation or realisation of the transcendence, i.e., existential choice. There is also ‘blind’ becoming, without any chosen direction, the principle of laisser-aller, which means throwing and abandoning into the power of uncertain future, perhaps its ‘narrative’ course leading assumingly into ‘good’. The situation could be illustrated with the following scheme:

2.3 More on horizontal appearance |

51

Figure 2.5: Appearance as becoming of transcendence

The modalities of existential appearance are: becoming (necessity) and doing (freedom) and their alternation or balance. One could say that the existential appearance is directed only by the IchTon, the identity of a subject (the concept has been borrowed from v. Uexküll’s biosemiotics), but for which we cannot know in advance how it reacts in each situation. Therefore, the Schein, which manifests the ‘truth of being’ as a kind of figuration of a structure, its ornamentation, is not yet existential Schein in this new sense. Similarly, the brilliance of the appearance, which is realisation of the structure of being, is, of course, a kind of brilliance, but one has to distinguish from it the shine which takes place in the choice at every moment, and the fact that we are truly free to choose and not predetermined by any structural or ontological principle. Mozart’s music precisely fulfils this kind of idea of a continuous appearing and play (Erscheinung und Spiel): we can never anticipate to which direction he goes at each time. Therefore his music is always maximally informative – and existential. On the other hand, the brilliance presupposes one kind of modality, namely the decisiveness. The hesitation cannot lead to brilliance – albeit hesitation is an important category leading our subject from one Dasein to the other, as Pärttyli Rinne has shown. Namely, hesitation is a sign of the fact that the subject is aware of his/her being in a situation of choice, i.e., that he/she can choose. Without such a freedom of choice, there would be no hesitation either, otherwise than as a resistance to what happens in any case. Therefore existentiality cannot be but a digression from the normal ‘appearance’ of a structure. For instance a work which blindly follows some narrative scheme, actant model, or generative course is not existential appearance, since there is nothing surprising, stopping; it just occurs ‘organically’ (like the Schenkerian Urlinie 5–4–3–2–1 of tonal music). A philosopher who has managed to portray this process very well is Karl Jaspers in his Die Philosophie (Jaspers 1948). He first remarks that there is no sense to speak about appearance when some being, thing appears in the world.

52 | 2 On the appearance What is involved is not the ‘mere’ appearance of a ready object. In the appearance we always face the appearance of some non-existing or transcendent to the consciousness (Jaspers op. cit.: 43). Without transcendence the existence would lose its proper being-in-myself and its orientation towards the world, its depth. Man is possible existence, who via consciousness orients itself to the world and establishes via the world a relationship to the transcendence (Jaspers op. cit.: 45). Jaspers refers to v. Uexküll, but rejects his theory with the remark that man is not the same as biological Dasein. The mere fact that he as a biologist investigates it from his own point of view, shows that he is not only his own physical Dasein but understands even other Daseins. Man is thus a ‘transcending’ animal one could resume. (It seems that Jaspers did not yet realize the essence of Uexküllian doctrine which , by no means, represents any reductionism in favour of anything ‘biological’ – on the contrary, in this theory even biology becomes communication and semiosis.) From the viewpoint of transcendence this world is not only Dasein but appearance. Insofar as man is not only a part of the world but can be freely himself, he is possible existence. Transcendence opens to him expressly as a possible existence. If the possible is interpreted as ‘virtual’ what is involved is the realisation of certain possibilities (Jaspers op. cit.: 71). Existence and transcendence ‘are’ therefore not as things ‘are’ in the world (this has been likewise emphasized by John Deely in his semiotic philosophy, like in his Four Ages of Understanding). They exist also for others. Dasein as being lives and vanishes. Yet, existence does not recognize death. Dasein is empirically there, existence only as a freedom. Dasein is completely temporal, but existence is in time more than time. One would be attempted to add here the Lithuanian-Russian philosopher Lev Karsavin (who was Greimas’s great idol, see Greimas 2001) and the term invented by him: omnitemporality, which means a multidimensional virtual time. It is analogous to the concept of plenitude by existential semiotics, whose opposed pole, nothingness, would be just characterized by achronicity. Therefore we cannot take it as granted that transcendence would somehow be a sphere devoid of time; instead, one has to distinguish therein these two aspects. World and existence are always in mutual tension, they can either be united or separated. Existence is never general, but always particular. The objective reality of the world and the existential reality both appear in time. The objective reality has its own rules, like in history the law of cause and consequence. Instead, the origin of the existential reality is just in time, in which it appears and is free. Substances are in the objective reality a factor obstructing the time and follow their causal laws. Compared to them the communication between existencies is something quite different. The necessities of objective reality are opposed by the time realized in a moment. Time in general is something measurable, objective

2.3 More on horizontal appearance |

53

and real, and valid for all; the actualized existential time is based upon depth and freedom. In the existential appearance one selects and decides just about some particular time. Existence has just its own time, and not time in general. Existential temporality and appearance are characterized by leaps and transformation (Jaspers, op. cit.: 309). These starting points have immediate consequences even to such far-seeming theory as semiotics. Namely, when in semiotics communication is the only properly dynamic temporal process in the mediation of message from destinator to destinatee, we have here found a completely new deeper epistemic level: appearance. Appearance as the existentiality of subjects and appearance in general is a still more fundamental category than communication. Which kind of semiotics might emerge if we took this principle of horizontal appearance as our fulcrum? Which kind of theory, which methods, which analyses? I already referred a.o. to the new research program of Eric Landowski, ‘the semiotics of life’ and irregularities, which are analogous to existential semiotics. But also new approaches may emanate. As such, there are no difficulties to bring the notion of transcendence into semiotics. Semiotics as a study of signification and communication is, when we think of it more closely, a completely transcendental discipline. Communication: every act of communication is a leap to the unknown. When Mr. A says something to Mr. B in the model by Saussure, he pursues a transcendental act, he cannot know what will happen, he transgresses a borderline, he encounters the Other, the unknown, of which he can only have presumptions, abductions but never certain knowledge. Signification: if we take as our basis the oldest medieval definition of it: aliquid stat pro aliquo sign is something which represents something absent, by signs we can talk about the absent, the transcendental. The signified is always transcendental – every word, gesture, tone fulfils the minor transcendence of Schütz and Luckmann. But when we moreover take into account that transcendence in fact ‘is’ not but is always becoming via the appearance, many of our traditional concepts are brought to a new light. Transcendence as nothingness is just such in which the appearance has stopped, the time has been finished, one is in a totally achronic state and nothing more anguishing could one even imagine for a subject. Instead, transcendence as a plenitude means the virtuality of innumerable possibilities, omnitemporality, which only artists have been able to conceive and simulate: Wagner in the networks of his leitmotifs in his operas and Proust by the time dimensions going to all direction in his novels. These simulacra, i.e., models, are Schein which corresponds to the ‘truth of being’. Their modus is appearance, linear and horizontal.

Chapter 3 Representation in Semiotics 3.1 The relation of representation in semiotics The notion of “representation” does not come up so frequently in encyclopaedias and dictionaries of semiotics – least, not at first sight, although it is the basis of the entire discipline. To signify, to express, to convey, and more; all these semiotic mechanisms rely on representation in the sense of one thing standing for another. It concerns not only the supposition of becoming detached from the meta-level of reality, but also the demand for faithful (re)presentation so as to effect iconicity. The epistemic level, according to Kant, has to do with the filtering of external reality into our consciousness via categories. A modern version of this theory is biosemiotics, according to which the so-called external reality does not exist as an objective entity; there are only signs picked up from the environment (Umwelt) by an organism. These are discerned, or “marked”, according to the capacities of sense organs, and reacted to in certain activities (Wirken). In this we arrive at the classical problem which occupied structuralists and post-structuralists: Is there a reality beyond signs or “texts”? If so, can it be reduced to representation? Correspondingly, deconstructionists in the wake of Derrida believed that text was everything; all was in text and in “writing”. Yet the Paris school semioticians, as pupils of Greimas, were fascinated by the problem of how to create an illusion of reference, by which textual mechanisms one could bring about the impression of a discourse realistically portraying reality, as in the natural sciences. Accordingly, representation can be conceived as a kind of similarity or correspondence between sign and reality. We speak of “representative” and “non-representative” arts, and also of prescriptive and descriptive representations, discussed later in this chapter. By the former we can reproduce the represented object; for instance in music by notes, in drama by dialogue, and so on. In the latter we aim to portray the reality more or less adequately, but in a less rigorous way. However, representation can be also interpreted as a process as in existential semiotics, where it occurs as the change of a pre-sign into an act-sign and further into a post-sign. In this chain of signs becoming something, the act-sign can be considered a representation of the pre-sign, when we can accept as a pre-sign any virtual idea, value, or intention. Here we may ask, for instance, At what point does a pre-sign become “ripe” or mature enough to be represented? If we presume that the everyday reality of our Dasein is surrounded by transcendence, then next we must ask how transcendence is represented in our world.

3.2 Mapping representation | 55

According to Solomon Marcus, transcendence appears to us only as metaphors, whose origin is corporeal. On this view, an art work is thus a representation of an aesthetic idea or intention. A moral act is a representation of an ethical value, which brings it from a virtual mode of being into the actual. If we articulate subjective reality by categories of Being and Appearing, it is clear that the capacity of Appearance (Schein) to represent Being varies. Misrepresentation or under-representation may occur, when the Schein of Appearance becomes mere shine or brilliance.

3.2 Mapping representation Representation necessitates a shift from the universe of things to their signs, or as Peirce called them, their “representamina”. Some, like Peirce, wanted to preserve the original idea of representation by using the Greek word, representamen, instead of “sign”. Both Anglo-analytic philosophy and the human sciences in general take seriously the idea of representation, such that we no longer speak about things themselves but about their linguistic signs: in a two-place relationship of representation, the first term, the one which represents, becomes more important than the second, that is to say, that which is represented, the reality itself. As early as in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason the thing itself, the reality an sich, became a transcendental entity, about which we could know only via its representations by categories of time, place, and subject. The crisis of representation was already there. It was argued that, if the basic idea of representation was a kind of correspondence between the sign and its object, then one could know nothing about the object without a certain mediation supplied by structures, mechanisms of discourse, and other linguistic means. To say that something represents something implies a very strong presumption that the representation hits its target with precision. But if I say that something only signifies or conveys or expresses something, then the relationship between x and y, representamen and object, is taken to be less precise, “softer”. Altogether, the problem of representation is to a great extent the same as the contrast between realism and nominalism: representation is clearly on the side of a realist epistemology; the essential matter is not the relationship – nor word – as in nominalism. The history of semiotics can be roughly simplified as the fight between these two principles. On the one side are the realists, beginning with the Scholastics, who took an achronic, paradigmatic, vertical view of representation: the sign is set “above” its object, but temporally at the same point, a kind of “now” moment in which representation takes place. On the other side, in nominalism we pay attention to the horizontal dimension: a word refers to a word, a sign to a sign,

56 | 3 Representation in Semiotics one unfolding from the other in a process, referencing each other in an endless series. Thomas A. Sebeok saw one side of semiotics – this kind of interminable chain of dictionary definitions. If we ask what the word “pupil” means, it refers to the word “to learn”, then to “teacher”, then to “school”, to “education”, and on and on. We end up with endless semiosis operating by a chain of signs. The other side of semiotics is a dynamic and mobile notion, which designates the transmission of signs from sender to receiver. We should add, however, that even signification can be conceived as a process, and not necessarily an endless one. Nevertheless, one can say in principle that American pragmatist semiotics starts from realism, the position consciously adopted by Charles S. Peirce, who in his correspondence with Victoria Lady Welby mocked the nominalists as “scholars” on the level of wine tasters. By contrast, the European branch of semiotics (or “semiology”) has clearly proved more nominalist, a trait culminating with the declaration, “Il n’y a pas d’hors texte!” Yet this distinction is truly rough, and immediately we encounter contradictions. Structuralists were on the latter side. But let us recall the debate waged in the 1960s between ontological and methodological structuralism. Eco criticized Lévi-Strauss for the aforementioned metaphysical view that structures exist only as an algebra of the human brain, a claim LéviStrauss made in his argument about mythical thought. Eco put much energy into establishing realist semiotics as an empirical science, and also into dismantling pseudo-realism, in his famous critiques of iconicity. To the European school of semiotics, insofar as we think of it beginning with Saussure, representation seemed to be no problem: to represent was always arbitrary, or conventional, with some exceptions, such as motivated signs or iconographies, as in onomatopoeia and similar. It is interesting to note how circular figures were in fashion. Saussure represented linguistic signs with a drawing of a tree, while at the same time the Czech composer Leoš Janáček represented musical meanings likewise, with a circle model, as Tiina Vainiomäki (2012: 210 and 269) (see Figure 3.1). There are two species of representation: vertical and horizontal, achronic and diachronic, paradigmatic and syntagmatic. In principle this dichotomy seems to coincide with that of realism and nominalism. For instance, such trends in semiotics as Derrida’s “deconstruction” represent the latter, in which writing is crucial and concepts, which refer to each other in endless discourse, are overlooked. His source of inspiration was Heidegger’s philosophy, of which von Wright said that its difficulty – or profundity – lodged upon the fact that everything said referred to what had been said and what was going to be said. One can almost see something cultural in this dichotomy: Anglo-Saxon scientists are easily positivists and behaviorists who search for the ultimate interpretant of all symbols in the brain

3.3 Nöth’s handbook

| 57

Figure 3.1: The models by the Czech composer Leoš Janáček on a) word and ‘center’ of consciousness (1923) and b) the structure of the expressive-rhythmic figure, scasovka (1927); the diagram by Saussure (1916)

and genes; whereas those in Latin and Roman culture produce endless discourse around an issue, consider it barbaric to name it directly. The very history of semiotics turns on the issue of representation and its articulation, and deserves a proper position in the encyclopaedia of our knowledge. Next I present some cases of the latter, paying special attention to the shifts and overlapping among categories of representation.

3.3 Nöth’s handbook An excellent overall presentation of representation in semiotics can be found in Winfried Nöth’s Handbook of Semiotics (2000 [1994]). He properly views it as one of the key concepts of semiotics since the Scholastics and also as a central issue in cognitive semiotics. Nöth also mentions the broad field of meanings linked to social representations; for example, in political-juridical semiotics, referring to representatives in elections and to the art-word “representations” which courts use to designate witnesses’ testimonies. The notion of representation appears in the history of semiotics often as a synonym for sign, beginning with John Locke (Nöth 2000: 162). Representation often refers to the object to be represented and by this means also to the referent. Hence we find such concepts in German philosophy as Darstellung and Vorstellung. Then it is conceived often as a phenomenon opposed to that of communication. For instance, Husserl’s “inner monologue” does not convey anything in the communicative sense, but doubtless represents something to the subject itself. In existential semiotics this can be interpreted as a relation or phenomenon whereby the subject maintains inner dialogue between Moi/Soi. Finally, Nöth mentions a nuance that occurs as early as with William Occam, which refers to the fact that at the same time as when one re-presents, or makes some-

58 | 3 Representation in Semiotics thing present again, one also “re-calls” something, a phenomenon not unrelated to the existential-semiotic underscoring of the importance of memory. Are there signs that represent nothing? Nelson Goodman developed a philosophical theory of representation in his work Languages of Art (1976), by which he means the closest visual representation. Among others, his term “exemplification” evokes this meaning: a tailor makes a proof example of a dress, by which one gets to the idea of a model. In the background, of course, stand Peirce’s conceptual pair: type and token. The latter an occurrence, an exemplification, of some type; for instance, a sonata by Beethoven or Mozart is an exemplification of sonata form, the type. Generally speaking, this involves a relationship to some more or less stable and fixed point of departure, the object that is “represented”; of course, the intentions of emotional expression lie beyond this relationship. Husserl, however, distinguished Bedeutungszeichen, which names and represents things, from Ausdruckszeichen, which contains intention and expression. Nöth also speaks about the “crisis of representation”. The latter was precipitated by Michel Foucault, who showed that in the classical age (seventeenth century) there occurred a transfer from iconic similarity between sign and world, to a dyadic, arbitrary, and conventional representation, which climaxed of with Saussure. From this emerged the so-called classical representation model, in which the linguistic order determined the “order of things”, the title of one of Foucault’s books. The classical model fell into crisis when at the beginning of the nineteenth century emerged a historical view of the inner development of things, which had its own logic. Nowadays “crisis of representation” has come to designate the postmodern notion that signs have no fixed and stable referent, that world has dissolved into various discourses and habits, which constitute their own rhizomatic mass. No model of representation can be seen as privileged over any other. In semiotics, among other fields, this meant a rejection of the generative model, that is, the idea that surface signs can either derive from a single deep structure or be reduced to one. In consequence, all manners of representation have become acceptable and exist together, side by side. We may illustrate this situation with John Cage who, when asked if he liked the symphonies of Beethoven, replied, Yes, if they are played all at the same time.

3.4 Representation in philosophy – John Deely John Deely’s monumental work Four Ages of Understanding (2001) is a total presentation of the history of Western philosophy in the light of the notion of sign. In it a central role is assumed by the concept of representation in different ages. Deely considers the progress of philosophy in view of the fact that things

3.5 Peirce

| 59

are discussed as signs and not as ideas. Representation as a concept is something definite, determined, fixed. He argues that words signify, but only concepts represent. What is problematic in defining the field of representation is that it can only refer to the structure of our sense data; that is, the information that comes to our senses “represents” external reality to us, but of this reality we can know nothing. Kant, of course, took this view, but it occurs as early as in Leibniz’s “monads”. Though each monad represents external reality in its own peculiar manner, there prevails however considerable equality and consensus among different individuals about how that reality is represented to us. This is possible, thinks Leibniz, thanks to a harmoniousness among men that was pre-established by God. On the God-idea, Deely writes: “Leibniz . . . explained communication ultimately through the hookup of the individual monads with the Divine Monad, the great communication satellite in the sky that made ‘my representations’ correspond with yours and so on for every other creature forming and projecting its own private representations” (Deely 1990: 10). For Deely, the essential task is to distinguish between sign and representation, and therefore signification and representation. Confusion enters via the fact that every sign must be a representation, not every representation needs to be a sign. In other words, a sign is always a representation of some type. Here Deely thinks realistically that every sign has an object, and that behind it is the dynamic object, a real thing. In our view, representation can be purely transcendental as a relationship: a sign is always also an ontological relationship. Even in transcendental relationships there is a distinction between object and sign.

3.5 Peirce The best-known theory of representation in Anglo-analytic philosophy is the triadic model by Charles S. Peirce, in which the representamen is able to represent some object only because a secondary signum, the interpretant, connects them. In Peirce’s model the object of representation is already a “semiotic” entity, but behind it looms the “dynamic object”, which is a real entity. As Eco says, it “kicks off” the semiosis. Likewise, behind the interpretant is the “dynamic interpretant”. Peirce’s model is based upon his phenomenal categories of Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness. From this model follow nine different sign categories, and moreover an endless number of their combinations. European semioticians have criticized the model, using the argument of Occam’s razor, that Peirce’s conception of sign is unnecessarily broad. Nevertheless, Peirce’s model has been developed further and applied to practical semiotic analyses, according to the principles of pragmaticism, and “-ism” which he himself founded.

60 | 3 Representation in Semiotics One variation of Peirce is found with the Danish literary semiotician Jørgen Dines Johansen, who has elaborated his own so-called pyramid model. The latter combines two semiotic subjects, author and reader – the author insofar as there is always someone who produces the sign, and the reader since someone always receives and interprets it. In the same way as Peirce distinguished between the immediate object and the interpretant, Johansen differentiates the empirical and the modeling author and reader. This idea stems from the classical notion in literary semiotics of implied author and implied reader. Johansen believes this interpretation to exist immanently in Peirce’s model, but he provides it with new dimensions by explicating this immanent or “hidden” nominalism. Peirce was himself a natural scientist who aspired to reveal objective rules of the sign as a kind of natural law. Our introduction of the subject, however, changes the situation and in fact distances our model from realism. The process of representation is not at all unequivocal, definite, or fixed. For example, the implied author/reader and empirical author/reader are realities of different degrees, and this makes misunderstandings possible. The semiosis can go wrong, say, if the empirical author uses in his representamen certain rhetoric by which he wishes to affect the empirical reader, but addresses his speeches incorrectly to the wrong implied reader. Such rhetoric does not serve him properly, because he has an errant view of his own implied reader. Another problem with Peirce’s model is how the dynamic object can produce a direct object. Does this take place as a kind of causal relation, as organic development, or as transformation? The weakest aspect of this kind semiotics is that, even though it emphasizes the processual and the dynamic, it remains completely immanent; it cannot be used for critical evaluation or judgment of phenomena. True, it portrays quite efficiently the functioning of a phenomenon, but remains on that phenomenon’s level. In this way, Peircean or Peirce-based semiotics preserves some neutrality, but it is an easy target to those critics who accuse semiotic analyses to be purely of technical interest.

3.6 Model theory The phenomenon of representation is closely linked also to scientific modeling and to the notion of model in general. The scientist who elaborates and develops models to portray certain phenomena also produces their representations as kinds of artefacts. Tarja Knuuttila, in her dissertation Models as Epistemic Artefacts: Toward a Non-Representationalist Account of Scientific Representation (2005), collected her observations into four main points, two of which follow here.

3.7 From cybernetics to cultural semiotics

|

61

(1) It is not necessary to deal with the whole philosophical field of representation, since models can represent but also misrepresent. (2) It is often unclear what scientific models represent; it is better rather to talk about how models “render” or “translate” instead of how they represent. Above all, models can have many uses other than representations. For instance models are often situated in some intermediate terrain between representing and experimenting. On the other hand, the ways in which models are constructed amount to more than “representing something”. This point in turn emphasizes the materiality of the model. Ronald Giere, a professor of philosophy at the University of Minnesota, and Knuuttila together discussed the notion of model and its relation to representation. Giere noticed that representation had been pondered in the history of philosophy in three ages: in antiquity, the Middle Ages, and in the twentieth century. He referred to the studies by Hintikka and v. Wright. But when Knuuttila brought under the same roof such different orientations as logic, semiotics, technology, and literature, the pragmatic aspect was underlined, but was it carried too far? Models are something by which one does something. In most pragmatic cases, models are used to produce certain things, whereas scientific models are without exception abstract, and none of them corresponds to the reality. Here the semiotic approach offers the answer: models are material symbols, but they refer to abstract entities. For instance, economic models do not have a concrete object such as “the economy”. Models are not representations but interactive units. In semiotics we meet with different kinds of signs, some are about material objects, others about immaterial objects, but signs themselves always have a material aspect.

3.7 From cybernetics to cultural semiotics The issues and definitions above reflect in every point some broader problems connected to models. For the first, the concept of model is central in cybernetics, which has fed into many other disciplines since the latter half of the twentieth century, not the least of which is semiotics. Georg Klaus, in his dictionary of cybernetics, speaks about his method of modeling. He distinguishes between two types of model: models as tools to acquire knowledge, and models to regulate dynamic systems and their functioning. Klaus’s view of models is completely pragmatic, as representations, can be either ideal or material formations. Hence one may build models of purely semiotic abstract sign systems, as is the case with mathematical and logical models. But they can also be real in a certain material-energetic sense. Hence they can be artificial or natural. Klaus describes the building of models as an interactive process between model and object (reality), in which the subject of the model (man) makes models

62 | 3 Representation in Semiotics on the basis of his knowledge of objects, both their material and ideal aspects, and by applying analogies – as iconic and indexical sign relations – between both realms. The model has to represent the original. Yet by influencing the model and observing the results one can gather more information about both the model and its object. A model can always be improved. On the basis of test results, analogies between model and object can be strengthened. The process continues until the model is a satisfactory image (icon) of the original. Results are achieved gradually by correcting the model and by presenting several versions of it. The cybernetic model, a kind of gradually developing representation of the reality, is under perpetual correction. On this view, representation is far from a fixed relationship, but rather a constantly changing process. Cybernetics was one of the background influences on semiotics in the 1960s, particularly in the USSR. There the so-called Tartu-Moscow school of cultural semiotics drew from like information theory, computer studies, and cybernetics. The famous distinction between primary and secondary modeling systems emerged from this context. Thomas A. Sebeok, in his A Sign Is Just A Sign (1991), asked in what sense language would be a “primary modeling system”; for his answer, he quoted the classical definition by Yuri Lotman: . . . a set of elements and rules of their combination which has a keen analogy with the whole field forming the object of the study. Therefore modeling systems can be taken as language and systems which utilize natural language as their basis and thus create additional superstructures, can be called correspondingly secondary modeling systems. (Lotman, quoted in Sebeok 1991: 50)

As Sebeok proposes, Lotman’s definition is “cybernetic” as opposed to stemming from Uexküll’s. Lotman’s primary modeling system, or natural language, is a kind of representation of reality. He is strongly structuralist when he takes natural language as the basis of other, secondary sign systems. Some have argued that the talk about primary and secondary modeling systems was an euphemism in the USSR of the 1960s. There official Marxist theory prevailed, and spoke of a superstructure which causally reflected the substructure. However that may be, only in the light of representation can we understand the thesis that Sebeok often declared, namely that language did not emerge for communication but for modeling or representing reality. Sebeok argues that language developed as an adaptation; speech was born as a derivative phenomenon of language over the course of two million years. Language consisted of a set of traits, which were created for the purpose of cognitive function of modeling, and not at all for communication, that is, the transmission of messages (Sebeok refers to Chomsky and Popper to support his thesis). For communication, nonverbal transmission emerged in all animal

3.8 Representation as function |

63

species, and it continues to function in all human interaction. To Sebeok’s mind, language is in the first place a representational system, not a communicative one (Sebeok 1991: 56).

3.8 Representation as function Eco in his earlier semiotic output pondered upon a special kind of representation, namely iconicity, the relations of sign and object based upon similarity. He took pains to show that iconicity is ultimately nothing but a “natural” category. In this respect he stands in the line of European semiotics, such that via analyses one aims to show that many semiotic entities taken as natural and given are basically conceptual constructions and social practices – which could therefore be otherwise. In this respect Eco heads in the same direction as the Paris School and Roland Barthes. He proposes that the iconic relation be seen rather as a relation of description between two universes, which consist of a certain amount of elements. Universe A is an iconic sign of Universe B, a representation, if those two universes have a sufficient number of common elements. What is involved is a transformation between two worlds and shapes. As a continuation of this theory, Eco developed his theory of fakes and forgeries, which questions under what conditions A is not the same as B, although someone claims that it is. This is a case of failed or unsuccessful representation, of apparent or quasi-representation. In the end, such a misuse of representation in order to cheat is reduced to the Greimassian categories of Being and Appearing. Something that first is is then compared to something that appears to be what it really is not. Representation is always Appearance, paraître. In his newer theories of semiotics, Eco underlines the role of the Dynamic Object (Peirce) in representation. He has come to this position through viewing in new ways the category of Being. We noted in the preceding chapter that, as a realist semiotician Eco (1997), argues that Being exists before one speaks about it. Being precedes our discourse, and it is something to which our speech is compared if we want to clarify whether it is true or not. We also noted that Eco’s view is in principle the same as Peirce’s: that behind the objects of signs lies the so-called dynamic object, which is and which precipitates the semiosis. Eco had in his earlier work Les limites d’interprétation (Eco 1992: 59–61) written of Heidegger as a kind of hermetic mystic who supposed that behind all signs and words there was some real Being which only the elect or “called” could attain. Now Eco allots positive attention to him. Yet in Heidegger, being always turns on the fact that being, Seiende, appears in Dasein most readily as my being-there, and

64 | 3 Representation in Semiotics therefore we cannot talk about being other than by talking about ourselves. With this, as we pointed out in Chapter Three, the category of subject is introduced.

3.9 The archaeology of Foucault In French philosophy, even before Eco, one finds reflections on similar issues, in both structuralist and phenomenological schools. Michel Foucault’s Les mots et les choses (1970) dealt expressly with the problem of representation in European culture. He started from the genuinely structuralist hypothesis that the true reality was not the one which was seen (unlike in empiricism), nor the one which a subject believed to be reality (unlike in existentialism, although Sartre had argued that consciousness was always consciousness of something). Rather, reality was hidden in its own universal archaeological level. From this perspective, all the various historical phases with their discontinuities proved to be illusory in their differences. What this involves, basically, is the question of how, in that cultural deep level, the categories of similarity and difference in representation were already determined. Foucault wants to concentrate on the level which precedes that of phenomenal perception, which in fact decides even our most naïve, everyday experience. For Foucault, nothing is more empirical and practical than the way things are set in “order”. Moreover, Foucault situates this order in the things themselves as their inner law, a concealed network which also establishes the manner in which they relate to each other. This order also manifests in such networks as that of the glance, research, language. These networks, or “basic codes”, rule over a culture’s language, perceptual frames, values, and practices, and also form the empirical order by which one operates and in which one feels comfortable. He speaks here about the level of representation of the reality as preceding everyday experience, which at the same time articulates the reality. At the other extreme, of course, there are abstract scientific theories and philosophical interpretation which explain why a certain order exists altogether. It is interesting that Foucault postulates between these two spheres of representation a third sphere, in which culture deviates, unnoticed, from the order of primary codes, which are none other than Lotman’s primary modeling systems, though Foucault does not mention them. This third sphere differs from them; it abandons the invisible forces represented by primary codes, and once liberated from them, may notice that that “order of things” is perhaps not the only possible one, nor the best. For Foucault, here lies the possibility of change in culture, and the existence of this level explains the epistemic crises in European culture. Between the “coded eye” (or ear we might add!) and reflexive knowledge is a

3.9 The archaeology of Foucault | 65

middle sphere, which deliberates the order itself. The Foucauldian man takes his position here, as a subject who is only a recent discovery. Foucault illustrates with an analysis of Vélasquez’s painting Infanta, in which the viewer of the painting – the subject – is drawn into its particular system of representation. We, as subjects, look at the picture of a place in which the painter in turn looks at us. In his analysis Foucault excludes all contextual knowledge, such as proper names like Philip II, Marguerita, and other known figures. We must stand before the painting as if we did not know who is reflected in the depths of the mirror, and we have to study this reflection by means of its own concepts. On the one hand, Foucault’s analysis is hermeneutic – not without reason did he study the Swiss Heideggerian Binswanger. That is to say, he starts from a certain pre-understanding of the painting. Yet at the same time he denies the naïve representational pre-understanding in the form of historical facts, and encourages us to scrutinize only a structural-visual composition of the painting, which has been set up to serve his analysis of the relationship of representation. Such a hypothetical, zero-point of research is far from, say, the American “Grounded-theory method”, which operates on the belief that research can “objectively” reveal all of its object, by allowing the empirical object to speak and organize itself. The psychoanalyst Medard Boss (1953) claims, for instance, that the emergence of perspective grew out of profound epistemic concepts. The masterworks of Japanese painting were without perspective. The spirit of Eastern culture was oriented toward abandoning any tension of I/not-I – an opposition that is central to Vélasquez’s painting. The notion of perspective was also alien to the ancient Greeks. For them the essential phenomenon was ergon, the beings of the world and their inherent energies. Man began more and more to believe that it was he who, as a thinking and imagining entity, provided the world with sense. More and more people started to take the essential content of things to be the result of human activity. This standpoint culminated in the Cartesian res cogitans, which seated the subject on its chair of honor; and from this also emerged perspective in painting. One might add to this the principle of “tonality”: in music there grew the idea of one tonal center, the Being of the tonic as the basic musical actor and subject, from which everything departs and to which everything returns. Foucauldian reasoning on cultural archaeology and representation runs along the same lines as that of Boss (1953): No science can appear without the prescientific leading thread of its thought . . . . Never has man lived amidst a senseless chaos, to which only scientific scholar would bring their sense without any prejudice. Always there is rather somewhere some weak and unexplainable view on the essence, a certain although completely unconscious metaphysics, a general idea of the true nature of things . . . Therefore all scientific explanations are only clean explanations and distinctions of a certain prescientific world understanding.

66 | 3 Representation in Semiotics It is astounding that biosemiotics, a new branch of the discipline, supports this view. Jakob v. Uexküll’s Umwelt model tells that an organism receives signs from its environment on the basis of codes typical of its species, which thus serve as a kind of representational filter between it and the reality. As discussed earlier, he called this filter the Ich-Ton, which as a kind of “score” determines those stimuli from the external world that are allowed to “play” in the organism. His view, epistemically, was completely Kantian – as was all structuralist thinking, even Foucault’s. Thure v. Uexküll completed his father’s theories by the notion of the so-called endo-genic signs. Inside the organism communication takes place, of which the organism is not conscious at all; paradoxically, the organism is conscious only of exo-genic signs, those coming from outside. In the interaction of endo- and exo-genic signs emerges the reality of an organism; nothing like objective reality exists in this theory. Representation as the passive registration of external signs is totally alien to biosemiotics. It is therefore anything but the reduction of semiosis to biology. On the contrary, it is proving biology to be semiotics.

3.10 Existential semiotic interpretation Essential to the theory of existential semiotics is the idea of the becoming of signs, their constant motion and change. Also crucial is the journey between two domains or worlds, between Dasein, the empirical reality, and transcendence which lies outside it, in absentia, but present in our minds. How something absent can be present of course leads to issues of representation. In addressing this matter, we must also note that, in semiotics, there is no abrupt borderline between Dasein and transcendence. Rather, the idea of transcendence and the material signs represent the two extremes of the same continuum; somewhere in-between lies the limit whose transgression means the act of representation. Every culture determines this borderline: where “reality” stops and “representation” begins. Representation is altogether the filter which selects the transcendence and lets it manifest in the Dasein. If one thinks of an organism or subject in his Umwelt, one should distinguish two kinds of representation. (1) The first representation takes place in the subject’s concrete milieu regulated by the Ich-Ton of the organism. (2) The second representation occurs when the virtual ideas of transcendence area actualized and realized in the Dasein. It is clear that representation is also a modal concept. In Greimas’s theory it returns to the relationship of Being and Appearing: representation is how Being manifests in Appearing. Yet, if we are dealing with a subjective reality, it is already as such modal by its nature. On the basis of the Greimassian category of being (être), I have tried to make the notion more subtle, and using the notion of an-mir-

3.10 Existential semiotic interpretation |

67

sein to an-sich-sein, develop a theory of the existential semiotic subject, which lives in an interaction of four instances and dialectics. To review: these are the categories of an-mir-sein and für-mich-sein or what can be called, the Moi, me, which develops from its primal kinetic-physical state into a personality. On the other side are the categories für-sich-sein and an-sich-sein, which represent the socially determined side of the subject, the Soi. It is in the movement of Moi towards Soi where a shift occurs, from abstract codes to social practices and their representatives in various professions and societal roles. Correspondingly, the Soi diminishes in its movement towards Moi, such that concrete social practices retreat into representations and “ideas” projected within the Moi. It is clear that the pertinent action in this model takes place among these four instances via particular kinds of signs, by which we are transported from modes of Being to modes of action via signs, we may even say, via representational models. We must also take care to note how the subject represents to itself these phases when we are dealing with signs intended for self-reflection and introspection. Schelling’s distinction of two kinds of action, Handeln and Schauen, are precisely equivalent to our distinction. In the earliest version of my model, the modes of Being were on the one hand Hegelian and on the other hand Greimassian, as represented by static categories on the “semiotic square”. Since then the Z-model has developed, as discussed in Chapter One, to depict the essential movement from Moi to Soi, from pure corporeality (M1) to a stable body or personality (M2). From there onward the motion is toward the representation of the body in social roles and professions (M3), up to the abstract norms and values of a society (M4). In addition, the motion may be from Soi to Moi, from norms (S1) to their “exemplifications” or representations in social institutions and practices (S2), further to their functioning via recruiting suitable persons S3, and finally to the impact of norms on the body (S4). Thus corporeality always contains at least some Soi and correspondingly, in the most abstract social norms there is a trace of body, or Moi. The model itself describes the world of Dasein, which lives in constant tension between me and society. The model also portrays events and representations within the subjective mind. All four instances, from M1 to S1, function as internalized in our minds; hence the Z-model explains why we are more than mere corporeality, mere biology, and it examines why and how society has penetrated into us, making us social. The proper and explicitly semiotic question is: How is this process of Dasein represented by signs and texts? All of this is illustrated in Figure 3.2 where the broken-line circle of Dasein serves as the representation of the primal Dasein. Representation is not unilinear in its signifying. There are at least seven subcategories: (1) spherisation (after Valsiner), concerning the spheres of the social Me; (2) simultanisation, the simultaneously superimposed presence of all mo-

68 | 3 Representation in Semiotics

Moi M1 (S4)

M2 (S3)

M1 (S4)

M2 (S3)

S2 (M3)

S1 (M4)

S2 (M3)

S1 (M4)

Soi

Figure 3.2: Representation of the Dasein

ments; (3) localization refers to the fact that, in the representing text, the modes of Being are localized to certain places; (4) temporalisation, such that the modes appear as a time continuum; (5) Widerspiegelung, a Marxist term, here indicating that the text reflects the original Dasein, mirroring and imitating it iconically; (6) fragmentation, such that the modes of Being appear in signs and texts only occasionally, incompletely, and fragmentarily; and (7) self-reflective, or arbitrary: the text has no iconic or indexical relation to the original Dasein; rather, the representation is entirely constructed and conventional (see Figure 3.3, p. 69). If our subject is culture itself, then the essential matter is how it represents to itself those various instances in its continuous process of development. Here we recall Lotman’s famous declaration in his Thesis 9.0.2: “The central mechanism which combines various levels of culture and systems is the model of a culture of itself, the myth of a culture of itself, which appears in a given phase of it. It is realized in the manner in which a culture represents itself for itself . . . and thus regulates actively the shaping of its own whole.” Both individuals and entire cultures and communities make for themselves two types of representations; descriptive, which are intended for self-reflection, and prescriptive, which are meant for action. For instance, the Bible, for a priest, may be a descriptive representation of God’s announcements; whereas the handbook of a Mass serves as a prescriptive representation of a religious ceremony. Physiologie du goût by Brillat-Savarin is a descriptive representation of cooking, whereas Éloges de la cuisine française by Édouard Nignon (1995) is partly prescriptive. Altogether, the problem of representation is omnipresent, wherever a subject lives, moves, feels, and reflects upon itself. To return to where we began: Representation is certainly not in a crisis, in the sense that, as a pertinent idea, it has become unnecessary. Rather, it covers more and more subtle phenomena, and its purport is becoming richer and richer in the present phase of neosemiotics, the phase in which we are now living.

3.10 Existential semiotic interpretation |

S1 S2 M2

a.

spherisation

M1

b.

c 1.

M1

M1 M2 S2 S1

simultanisation

M1

S1

S1

M2

localisation

M2 c 2. M1→M2→S2→S1 temporalisation

S2

S1 d. Widerspiegelung

e.

M1

S1

f.

Figure 3.3: Different kinds of representation

M2

fragmentation

S2

autoriflessivo arbitrarity

69

Chapter 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music 4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . . The notion of genre (Gattung) belongs to the central vocabulary and concepts of semiotics. Nevertheless, it is less than overwhelmingly present in encyclopaedias and dictionaries of the discipline. One problem is that it easily blends together with other terms such as discourse, type, function, class, style, text, form, and so on. And in trying to define genre in semiotics, we naturally have to ask, Which semiotics? There is not one semiotics, but as many as there are semioticians. In fact, semiotics has so thoroughly infiltrated other fields that it is now articulated by many other discourses and terminologies. As we have noted, in the broadest sense semiotics consists of two parts: signification, the study of meaning, and communication, the study of the transmission of messages and signs. Genres can “signify” as such: the receiver of the message turns to the TV channel which offers the “genre” he wishes to consume, and which as such already represents something to him, whatever the content of the program might be – news, cinema, soap opera, conversation, concerts, weather, medical program, ceremony, or detective story. A listener selects a concert to attend because he wants to hear a certain kind of music; one goes to the movies to see a certain kind of film, say a “romantic comedy” or “thriller”. Used in this way, such genre designations already provide material to be taken as significations. In communication, genre involves structures which the sender and receiver of a message have to accept mutually to some extent, if one wants to communicate anything. Hence genre is a super-code, or “overcode” in Umberto Eco’s terms, whose rules an individual cannot decide upon alone. In Saussure’s classical distinction of langue/parole, genre no doubt belongs to the first mentioned principle, which is essentially a collective agreement. When Eco in his early work La struttura assente (1968) wrote about the “automatisms” of codes which guide our speech and acts, he in fact portrayed one aspect of genre: “We have to ask whether man is free to express what he really intends, or whether he is guided by some code . . . correspondingly we can doubt that a sender of a message speaks in reality under the influence of some code. The mechanisms and automatisms of language force the speaker to say certain things and leave certain things unsaid . . . ” (Eco 1968 [1971]: 60). Hence what a speaker “means” belongs to the domain of signification, and how he says it belongs to communication. Genre as a semiotic formation pertains to the latter, that is, to the social sphere.

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

|

71

To understand the birth of genre in a subject, we have to scrutinize how and why one selects a genre, and likewise one’s efforts to change genre, to break its norms – which often happens in the arts – and finally, how one completely abandons a genre. Genre concerns all the social behaviors of man. The verstehende Soziologie of Alfred Schütz and Thomas Luckmann comes close to the concept of semiotic action. The authors distinguish the concepts of Verhalten (behavior), Handeln (action), and Wirken (influence). Whether my conduct is an action, I know best myself. On the other hand: . . . my fellows, others, essentially determine – on the basis of socially objectified rules concerning typical behavior and gathered in a social store of information – the manifested or non-manifested goals of my action. . . . This causes my own conduct to be directed according to a certain predetermined intention, which is the basic precondition of any communication. . . . On this basis we are also able to correct and improve our behavior, what is valuable for the practices of our daily life. (Schütz and Luckmann 1994: 18–19)

As semiotic subjects, we fit our behavior and expression into some genre in order to crystallize our thoughts and emotions as members of a certain community and, on the other hand, in order to please others. The semiotic basis of genre is thus to be seen as an oscillation between our two principles of Moi and Soi, self and society. In the historical sense, definitions of genre appear either deductively, from given theoretical assumptions, or inductively, by the gathering of various cases of genre. For the latter, Ducrot and Todorov (1972: 196) recommend the concept of “type” instead of genre. (This should not be confused with “type” in Peircean semiotics, where it is identified with a particular category of signs from which one may produce single signs, or “tokens”.) On the other hand, there have been many semiotic attempts to define genre, each with its own model. Such attempts reveal the extreme diversity of the phenomenon. One starting-point of European semiotics was Russian Formalism in the early twentieth century. When the latter was discovered in the west in the 1960s, from it grew a particular sub-genre of semiotics: narratology. In fact, a good many genre studies examine the various narrative devices and structures used by genres. Vladimir Propp, in his landmark Morphology of the Folktale (1928), created a structural definition for this genre of Russian folklore on the basis of textual properties: a folktale consisted of 31 functions or actions whose order was always the same, and which constituted a kind of ideal genre repertoire from which particular folktales picked their own versions. No specific folktale was obliged to fulfil all the functions. Greimas later completed Propp’s model by adding the “actants” of a story, which he reduced to six ideal types: destinator and destinatee,

72 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music subject and object, helper and opponent; this was called the “mythical actant model”. This model was generalized in application to all stories, regardless of their social contexts. As early as here we see the effort of semiotics to clarify the (presumably) universal processes of meaning and communication, understood as the production mechanisms behind specific semiotic entities. Most theories aim to explain genre using this vocabulary and metalanguage. Another Russian formalist, Mikhail Bakhtin, developed a genre theory whose starting-point was communication, the speech act or act of utterance; it was based on a dialogical principle, which he considered decisive. He believed that no concept, or “ideologeme”, exists that did not first occur in a dialogue, as enunciated by someone. In Finland, Erkki Peuranen studied the semiotics of socalled “disputes” as the origin of Bakhtinian dialogism, these having taken place in Nääveli in 1918. The idea of dialogism transforms various genres into dynamic units, in the sense that the end result of a dialogue cannot be anticipated. The starting point here is the notion of a speaking subject, which has tremendous impact on our everyday life. At every step we can hear someone talking about someone else. In colloquial speech, we mostly speak about what others speak. When listening to fragments of dialogue on the street, in a crowd, in waiting rooms and so on, one hears frequently repeated: “He said so and so, he spoke, he stated. . . . Information is seldom conveyed directly, but always by a reference to an indefinite general source: ‘I have heard . . . it is said . . . people think . . . believe . . . .” (Bakhtin 1979: 158). These are primary speech genres, which Monika Fludernik calls “natural narratology”; from them more complex types of genre are launched, such as various species of literature. Altogether, the speech of others was for Bakhtin the same as the “alien word”, authoritarian speech, which tries to persuade us with its truthfulness. The authoritarian word demands that we recognize and adopt it; it inserts itself, without regard for whether we consider it innately convincing. The alien word comes to us as ready-made, pre-existent. Bakhtin thus joins the concept of genre to the concept of power and ideologies: someone has the power to determine the genre (ibid.: 162–163). From this developed the postcolonial theory of genre, in which the “dominant” subject dictates to the “dominated” the rules of the genre, its langue (Tarasti 2000: 137–151). From the notions of dominant/dominated came the idea of primary and secondary genres, as seen in the Tartu-Moscow School’s (Yuri Lotman and others) notion of primary and secondary modeling systems, which we have already mentioned. What is crucial to communication is its persuasive, conative function, as another formalist, Roman Jakobson, described it. Genres are necessary, and their rules must be accepted if one wants to convince a destinatee and to insure his understanding of a message. What is involved here is the credibility and truth value of a discourse. In Germany, André Jolles elaborated his own theory of folk-

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

|

73

lore genres in the 1930s in his study Einfache Formen (1930). Legends, such as biographies of saints, are incredible, doubtful, and in the end untrue, from the viewpoint of history. In legends, which tell the story of an either extremely good or extremely bad person, the miracle plays a central role. Correspondingly, other genres, such as myth, fairy tale and saga (die Sage), differ from a history and thus, according to Jacob Grimm, are untrue. In his Deutsche Mythologie (1835) Grimm describes these genres: History never repeats itself, but is everywhere fresh and new; a saga in turn is always reborn . . . the winged saga rises and sinks, its remaining descent [obtains in the fact that it] does not arrive in every nation. Where distant events have disappeared in the darkness of time, there a saga joins itself to them . . . when a myth weakens and is going to dissolve, then history rushes to help. But where myth and history encounter each other, there epos weaves its texture . . . .

Basically, genres have to do with man’s desire for knowledge, his world view, and his efforts to understand: a subject faces the world and asks, he demands, that phenomena and the world become familiar to him. And he gets the answer: namely, his own words. Myth and oracle belong together as a genre: they both prophesy. Yet the spiritual activity of a myth has an authority, cogency, and independence different from those of legend and saga, and therefore as linguistic expression has a coherence, competence, and authority higher than that of legend and saga. The riddle-myth is an answer that includes a question that is hiding the answer. In myth man asks about the quality of the world and phenomena, and the world answers. In a riddle, man is asked the question, in order to determine if the asked person possesses a certain value. Accordingly, genres were articulated in archaic societies via certain functions and means of sense production. Literary critic Northrop Frye developed a genre theory that may be seen as a continuation of Jolles’s work and his definitions of riddles. Narrative modes, in such genres as myth, which determine realistic stories and comedy, are based on the relationship between a protagonist and a reader or destinatee: if the characters in a story are on a higher level than we are, then myth is involved. If they are on the same level, it is a realistic mode, and if they behave worse than we do, then it is a comedic mode. Genre thus emerges, in these theories, from the generally human processes of signification and communication. By crossing different categories we get different definitions of genre, just as in Frye, where the mixing of categories intellectual/personal intention and introvert/extrovert results in four cases: testimony, romance, analysis, and novel. According to Todorov, genres emerge internally: a literary genre is not born from reality but from literature itself. Poems can be written only by its point of departure from other poems, literature from other lit-

74 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music erature (Todorov 1972: 14–15). Literature does not represent our everyday life but rather itself, which unavoidably leads to a kind of tautology: literature signifies only itself; that is, literature and poetry are languages of their own. Such a language does not constitute any truth, but expresses several possible truths. Via the concept of genre, a literary work is set into a relationship with all other literature (ibid.: 12). This argument surely holds true for other arts as well: pictures emerge from other pictures, music from other music¹. Genre can thus be defined ontologically starting from the social functions and historical situations that create and maintain them. Or nominalistically, we may suppose genres to be like Wittgenstein’s language games, which grow and tumble one into the next, like dominoes: Genre 1 = ABCD, genre 2 = BCDE, genre 3 = CDEF, genre 4 = DEFG, where the first and last texts in this family relationship have no common traits, but still develop from the same series. Such is how Danish literary scholar Jørgen Dines Johansen advises examination of the concept of genre and its transformations (Johansen 2002: 4). It is true that genres presuppose memory, as collective memoranda of a culture (Asafiev). Yet, Theodor Adorno, who always underlined the dialectical and negative aspect, states that art always tries to break free of the straightjacket of the generic, and strive for the particular: “There is no aesthetic progress without oblivion; every advancement also includes regression” (Adorno 2006: 404). Adorno interprets art in relation to society and dares to utilize the concept of progress: Art is in its innermost essence bound with the ever stronger historic movement of contrasts. It has just as much or as little progress as society . . . since no progress has yet taken place in the world, there has yet to be progress in art: il faut continuer . . . art remains totally blended with what Hegel calls the world spirit . . . . Art works that dwell in brotherly union with the world spirit are indebted to it for their breath, vitality, and everything by which they can transgress the Always-the-same. (ibid.: 401)

One might ask, then, Who determines which genres follow the movement of the world spirit, and which do not? Adorno presupposes that the continuity of art genres is based upon historic events and upon generic correspondences with static social structures, which show the limitations of genre history. For with abrupt structural changes, “as when the position of the bourgeois class ascended

1 The notion of music deriving from previous music should be distinguished from the case of Musik über Musik, as in the manner of Igor Stravinsky’s parodies of earlier style periods; for instance, in the “Devil’s Chorale” in L’histoire du soldat, which was commonly considered to be “Bach harmonized with ‘wrong’ bass notes”.

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

|

75

in the nineteenth century, genres and styles change just as unexpectedly” (ibid.: 402). And yet, genres may obstinately continue to live through periods of crisis (discussed below). Adorno brings us to the crux of a central problem: the mutation of genres. Almost all scholars nowadays emphasize this aspect of change, in contrast to the normativity of genres. Adorno juxtaposes genre concepts with convention and style. The nominalist school showed that all artistic genres and their demands were set from the outside, hence fragile, dead, and formal. Nevertheless, conventions become tempting when they lose their power, when they become play. Conventions serve as masks when they become functionless, and masks are the forefathers of art. Accordingly, Adorno on one hand connects art genres to society, but on the other shows how genres detach themselves from its practices. The advent of conventions-cum-formal principles fortified them internally and made them resistant to imitating outer reality. The stronger a subject becomes, and the weaker categories of social order get, the more difficult it is to reconcile the relationship of subject and conventions. It is precisely this ever-growing gap between inner and outer, the cleft between the Moi and the Soi, that leads to the breakdown of conventions and, with that, to a change of genres. In any case, the context of Adornian theory is the European society of what I call the “sociosemiotic” phase – along with which the genre theory of someone like Georges Dumézil, scholar of Indo-European mythology, already seems outmoded. He posited three species of mythologies and actants: (1) amidst the play of the gods: the warrior-hero; (2) amidst gods and demons: the shaman; and (3) amidst the gods and men: the king. Similarly, Claude Lévi-Strauss’s view of genre-shifts, even between cultures, can be explained on the basis of his ontological structuralism. That is to say, categories of the human spirit are essentially the same in all ages and everywhere, which explains for instance the fascinating thesis he proposes in the last volume of his Mythologiques; namely, that South American Indians had for millennia used the structure of a fugue, this particular “genre”, in their myths, even before it was discovered in Europe. In the seventeenth century, when the Cartesian spirit had expelled myth from science, one finds it did not become extinct at all; and of course it could not become extinct, being a universal property of the human mind – a Kantian “transcendental”; rather, its heritage was shared by two genres. Literature inherited the content of myth, and hence the novel emerged². Music, on

2 Here Lévi-Strauss had in mind a novel like Don Quixote, but I would rather exemplify this with a novel by Madeleine de Scudéry, written during the French Baroque period, namely her novel Le Grand Cyrus, the longest novel ever written, amounting to some 10,000 pages – truly a neverending tale.

76 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music its part, inherited from myth its structure and so the fugue emerged as a particular musical technique, which Adorno described in this way: Fugue is an organizational form of completely rationalized and tonalized polyphony; in this sense it extends as a form much further than its individual realizations, although it cannot exist without them. Therefore emancipation from the scheme already has been written universally in the concept of the scheme itself. (Adorno 2006: 386–387)

Here Adorno adds to genre a new concept, namely genre as a “scheme”. As did Lévi-Strauss, Michel Foucault, in his structuralist period, touched on the problem of genre in his work Les mots et les choses (Foucault 1970). As we saw in the preceding chapter, his view was based on the idea of an epistemic, archaeological level of culture, which determines the criteria of similarity and difference for each epoch. On this basis emerged an archaeology of knowledge about genres such as grammar, natural history, economy, linguistics, philosophy, and so forth. The subject for whom these genres represented Being was, however, still invisible; according to Foucault he did not even exist two hundred years ago. The natural sciences treated man as a genre. The semiotic subject is not the entity that decides about genre; rather, genre occurs, takes place, is “generated”, in a kind of internal and organic process of sense production. As Yuri Lotman argued, culture is the generator of such “structurality”; genres are formations guaranteeing the continuity of the universe of signs, or “semiosphere” in Lotman’s terms. Later, Jaan Valsiner, in his book Culture in Minds and Societies, pondered varieties of deductive, inductive, and abductive reasoning in the formation of social concepts (Valsiner 2007: 279), and his results hold true also for the theory of genres. Very close to such thoughts come theories that identify the concept of genre with discourse (Morris 1971: 205). The best-known representative of this theory is perhaps the American semiotician Charles Morris, who classified genres of discourse on the basis of their usage and modes; in use they were informative, evaluative, incitive, and systemic; their modes were signifying, appreciative, prescriptive, and formative. He ended up with 16 different genres of discourse (see Figure 4.1). Morris states that each of the 16 classes of discourse can be studied only by scrutinizing documents and statements that are generally recognized as belonging to each genre. Hence in Morris’s view, one needs to do empirical research in poetry, fiction, law, religion and other languages. For instance, “religious discourse” is manifested in documents that some consider religious, but which do not belong to the determinative, initiating genre of holy writ. Like Morris, the Paris school of semiotics and its leader A. J. Greimas approached the concept of genre deductively. In his famous Sémiotique: Dictionnaire

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

Usage

|

informative

valuative

incitive

systemic

designative

scientific

fictional

judicial

cosmological

appraisive

mythic

poetic

moral

critical

prescriptive

technological

political

religious

propagandist

formative

logic-mathematical

retoric

grammatical

metaphysical

Mode

77

Figure 4.1: Morris’s genres of discourse

raisonnée de la théorie du langage (Saussure and Courtés 1979: 164), Greimas gives three definitions of genre. According to him, “genre” denotes a class of discourses which can be identified by sociolectal criteria. These in turn are due to the implicit classifications; in oral traditions these are based upon a particular categorization of the world or “theory of genres”, which in many societies appears in the form of explicit, essentially non-scientific classification. Such a genre theory, however, has nothing to do with a typology of discourses like Morris’s, which is rather based on the recognition of special formal features. Genre theory, for Greimas, is obviously a cultural relativism and stems from hidden ideological presumptions. For Greimas it proves interesting only if it reveals the concealed axiologies of a culture. Doubtless just such genre research has been done in many domains of the Paris school. On the other hand, in the context of European culture, modern genre theory takes shape along the axis of two poles: (a) “classical” theory, which is based upon the unscientific distinction between form and content in certain literary discourses (comedy, tragedy, etc.); and (b) “postclassical” theory, which consists of a certain vision of reality, of references whereby one can distinguish various “possible worlds” that are more or less hidden narrative manifestations of norms (e.g., fantastic or miraculous tales, surrealist stories, etc.). As the third point Greimas says that the same cultural framework that produces literary genres can also carry religious genres, among others. Another dictionary following the Paris school is the Vocabulaire des études sémiotiques et sémiologiques (Aldriss et al.: 2009). In it genre is viewed more as a component than as an individual phenomenon; great discourses (literature, philosophy, science, etc.) in general consist of various genres. Literary discourse is compounded from genres such as the novel, short story, prose poem and so on, and each of these can be further split into subgenres: travel log, detective story, and so on. The author of the definition, Jean-François Bordron, interestingly states that the understanding of a text cannot be separated from its placement in some genre; genre forms the background out of which the specificity of a text emerges.

78 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music Genre can be taken as a set of complex norms that is renewed through history. To write a novel means to write like writers of novels, where the mimetic aspect of genre is central. These norms have to be distinguished from linguistic schemes, just as they are from different uses of language. It would be erroneous to take genres as perpetual entities. In this definition genre thus appears akin to the Greimassian notion of isotopy. Isotopy indicates that level of meaning of a text, or part thereof, which guarantees that we can read it as a coherent whole. Isotopy is not so much an empirical as a cognitive category, which enables us to grasp the profound meaning of a text. The Belgian scholar Jean-Marie Klinkenberg states the same when he remarks that we can directly classify phrases we encounter into different genres. For instance, consider phrases such as “Il pleut à Paris”, “Il pleut dans mon cœur”, and “Put a tiger in your tank”. We immediately notice that the former belongs to the genre of reportage, the second to “poetry”, and the latter to the “advertisement” genre. One can thus suppose that in a text representing a genre there must be some index pointing to which generic isotopy it belongs. Naturally, the mere title of a work evokes its genre. If the word “novel” appears on a book cover, the reader knows what to expect; if on a musical score one reads the title “symphony” or “sonata”, then a listener knows how to listen. A constant source of mistakes is the choice of the wrong genre. For instance, in a social situation in which only politeness codes rule, the truth code is suppressed. No one begins a dinner table conversation with, “I heard your doctoral thesis was rejected” or “Your book received bad reviews”, even if these things are true. Finally, we must remember that semiotic genre theory does not only concern literary, visual, or auditive objects. Behaviors, too, are “texts” that are classifiable into genres: seminars, interviews, coffee parties, ceremonial speeches, lessons, meetings, musical performances, sporting events, and many more. The concept of genre undeniably has a normative dimension. The illustrious aesthetician of the Prague school, Jan Mukařovský, considered genres above all as meeting places of aesthetic norms. Genre represented for him the technical norms of art-work production, by which he understood certain manners, petrified residues of the long development of the arts; they stand, so to speak, in the lobby through which one enters an art work. Conventions like poetic meters, musical forms and the like were necessary norms when they developed, and they included just certain regularities of genres (Mukařovský 1978: 53). Even though genres are normative, they are also to a certain extent arbitrary. Philippe Lejeune (1975) has developed a theory of autobiographical contract (pacte autobiographique). In studying autobiographies Lejeune noticed how such texts operated on the basis of a kind of implicit agreement, which determined who was to be the narrating ego. He gathered his results into a diagram, in which

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

|

79

Figure 4.2: Lejeune’s comparison of autobiography to general biography

the genre of autobiography is juxtaposed with the biographic genre in general (Figure 4.2). In addition to autobiography Lejeune advances the notion of a novelistic contract, an important genre principle that (in addition to fictionality) requires that the narration not be based upon identity; that is, the author and the main protagonist are different entities. The issue of representation arises again, in that genres can imitate each other, as did certain biographies of the eighteenth century that took intimate literary genres as their models; for example, letters (Goethe’s Sufferings of Young Werther or Senancour’s Obermann); memoirs and diaries (Bernanos’s Le journal d’un curé de campagne). Lejeune’s theory may be generalized to include a contract of the cinematic genre, a symphonic agreement (pacte symphonesque), and more. This simply means that when an artist announces, for instance in a title, that a work is a play, performance, or symphony, he is obliged to make good on his promise. Yet the mixing of genres has become habitual in all the arts: as part of an opera performance we may see videos; in music we have crossover phenomena among genres and cultures, for instance between erudite and popular genres, of which collage, among others, is a special form. Genres are no longer fixed codes but dynamic processes in which everyone in a communicative act can participate. Günther Kress (Kress & van Leeuwen 2001: 191) has emphasized that a genre corresponds to the changing social structures that it enacts. Genres carve out various positions for those who participate in them – interviewer and the one interviewed, for instance – which one may either accept or reject. This theory underlines that a genre contract is only a modest proposal, the actual functions of which are conditioned by all partners in a communication. In current theories, particularly in the visual fields of cinema and TV, genre operates primarily as a semiotic process of production. For instance, the film institution relies on genre as one of its main ingredients, its function being to regulate

80 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music production and consumption of movies. When a film, even as early the production phase, is situated in a certain genre, this creates anticipations in the spectator. Because cinematic genre types are based on production and consumption, it is hard to find any common generic criteria for all of them. In existential semiotic terms, a genre is a virtual pre-sign: a concept, model, or type which is realized either well or badly in an act-sign, that is, in some text, and which is then, as a post-sign, put by receivers into the correct genre. But this “correct” genre need not necessarily be the same as the one as that of the virtual idea as it awaits actualization. Göran Sonesson ponders such issues in his book Bildbetydelser (1992), but scarcely mentions the concept of genre. He speaks instead about images or pictures, which are only one type of visual signification. For socially pertinent pictures he distinguishes the following criteria, which constitute a kind of genre analysis in the visual domain: First is the principle of construction, how a pictorial sign is built; for instance, those aspects that distinguish a photograph from a painting. Then there is the socially intentional effect, impact or functions; these are the effects which the picture is intended to have on a certain community. An advertisement, for instance, is presumed to “sell”, a satire to poke fun, a documentary to provoke thought, and so forth. The social distribution channel disseminates the picture in a society such that it reaches its intended receivers. For instance, an advertisement differs from a newspaper picture; a landscape postcard differs from a poster, and so on (Sonesson 1992: 266). Sonesson uses as an example the classical analysis by Roland Barthes of a Panzani ad: it is a photograph (principle of construction), which serves as an advertisement (socially intentional effect), that occurs as a newspaper announcement (channel of distribution). Roland Barthes traced the most varied behaviors and textual genres to one archetype: the modern myth. Genre analysis thus involves the revelation of hidden ideology. In his famous inaugural lecture to the French Academy, Barthes examined the normative character of language, which he provocatively declared to be “fascist”, and from which the only escape was by literature, which as a secondary language plays with and breaks the rules of genre. Genre theories of the 1990s and 2000s start more and more from the viewpoint of the consumer. The empirical material comes from the world of media or multimedia, from advertising, TV or cinema. Paul Cobley (1996, 2002), for example, argues that consumers know, at least roughly, what “genre” means, in that they take it as a classification which determines whether some text corresponds to their previous experience with similar texts. Genres in the marketing world have received special attention by Italian semioticians, almost all of whom seem to follow the methodology of the Paris school (except for Eco and Ponzio). Gianfranco Marrone (2007), in his research on the semiotics of labels and brands,

4.1 A semiotic approach to genre in general . . .

|

81

views genres as based upon certain general impacts of sociability on our behavior, production, and interpretation, whereas individuality is based upon style. Brand names and other company emblems run by a system that exploits genres of communication, as was said above in connection with Charles Morris. In Marrone’s view, genres have long served as prescriptive rules, aesthetic norms from which one can produce literary and artistic works and against which idealistic, Romantic artists once struggled as limitations to their creative freedom (Marrone 2007: 183–184). Gradually the descriptive perspective has come to predominate in anthropology, linguistics, and aesthetics. From this angle, genre appears as a concept which can be better interpreted, the more it stands out from other, similar phenomena. Genre does not manifest via only one text. Rather seldom is some thriller, sonnet, document, talk show, novel and so on defined as its own particular genre only by virtue of its own contents. Most often it contains other texts – paratexts – and the genres to which they in turn belong. Genre is therefore a non-empirical, mediated reality, something translated and intertextual, and as such it is a determining entity of human and social signification (ibid.: 183). Between text and genre occurs a particular dialectics, since on the one hand every text becomes interpreted and understood by a certain genre, and on the other hand, a text simultaneously renews, destroys, and creates that genre. On this basis Marrone presents four genres of advertising as a semiotic square. It originates from the two main ideologies of advertising distinguished by J. M. Floch: referentiality, which foregrounds the inner substance of the producer, or construction, which focuses on the destinator (utterer, producer) of the ad. Advertising genres are thus referential, mythical, substantial, and indirect (ibid.: 188). We should add that brand names and labels are kinds of “marked” signs (Martinet), which arise out of a continuum of signs, the “semiosphere” (Lotman), or out of some deep-level isotopy (Greimas). The very notion of “brand” or “branding” brings with it such an identificational aspect. Cobley’s (ibid.) theory of genre also deals with electronic media, but emphasizes the other side of the equation, the receiver, thus emphasizing genre as a set of expectations rather than a textual unit. Such analysis takes genres as part of the public sphere rather than as textual phenomena. From this it follows that generic features cannot be strict rules. In Rick Altman’s (1999) theory of cinematic genres, they consist of “building blocks” on the one hand, and on the other, of the structure into which they are inserted. Thus we have semantics and syntax. On this ground one can map which textual field the reader’s expectations can influence. Nevertheless, as a comment valid for all genre theories this hypothesis remains incomplete, given that a genre employs all semiotic mechanisms. Rather, genre is a dominant, a principle traversing all levels

82 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music of a text, as the Formalists defined it, or a “semantic gesture” as the Prague structuralists claimed. If some case of genre consists of various discourses, then the reader (listener, spectator) decides which of these to follow as a syntactic clue to the work (Marrone 2007: 25). Narratological concepts help us to shape the reality of genre. For instance, the real reader of a genre is not its “implied reader”, in other words, the one which was in the mind of the producer of the genre. Also, some cases of genre can open a new genre, in a kind of type/token relationship. For instance, after Beethoven’s Eroica Symphony all the Allegro movements of symphonies written in E flat major were heard in the atmosphere or Stimmung which it created; hence E flat major emerged as a “heroic” key. Genre innovations can thus be realized via individual creations. Even though a genre is bound to history by its semantic blocks, it is likewise true that genres can survive even during great periods of crisis, when, according to Asafiev, a culture’s store of “intonations”, internalized musical “givens”, is forced to change. The concept of genre can be located in a certain position in existential semiotics, as one case of its modes of Being. These, as we know, produce four cases: being-in-myself (an-mir-sein), being-for-myself (für-mich-sein), being-foroneself (für-sich-sein), and being-in-oneself (an-sich-sein). The M-cases (Moi) on our Z-model, as elaborated in Chapter One, indicate the “Me”, as modes of subjective being; the S-cases indicate “Society” (Soi). The Z-model, reproduced in Figure 4.3, thus portrays individual and social aspects of the human mind, especially how the social intrudes into man’s essence, and on the other hand, how corporeality passes through even the most abstract norms and values of a society. The cases correspond to the following phases of human development: body as a chaotic, kinetic, energetic, and desiring entity; body as organized into a person (identity). On the other hand, in the bottom right corner of the figure are shown norms, ideas, values as abstract categories, and the values in question as actualized into social practices and institutions. For reasons of economy I number these phases M1, M2, M3, M4 and S1, S2, S3, S4. The Z-model depicts two semiotic forces, one going from body to social norms, and the other from social norms to body. Does this occur according to an “Adornian” process, such that the body, step by step, becomes socialized as it passes through these four cases? Or is society embodied, corporealized? Whatever the case, it is clear where genres belong in this model: S2 (social practices). These are encountered by, say, a painter, who from this meeting finds renewed inspiration and resources for his actions. Genre is thus guided by these two forces, and since it is situated at their crossing point, always a space of tension, its reality is always moving and changing. This explains also the observation made as early as by Tynianov (1924/1977: 235), that a genre shifts; not all forms or manifestations of a genre can be covered by a single, static definition. Evolution takes place in a

4.2 . . . and in music

| 83

Figure 4.3: The Z-model of Moi/Soi

broken, fragmented way, not in a direct line. Hence, as mentioned earlier, genre is not a perpetual and immutable system.

4.2 . . . and in music In music the concept of genre is more complicated than in all the other arts. Since the musical reality itself is so diverse – both anthropologically, from culture to culture, and historically, with respect to changes within a single culture – it seems futile to try and put all definitions of musical genres into one theoretical model. I borrow from ethnomusicology the terms “emic” and “etic”; the former describes a culture’s internal ideas about itself, the latter, those characteristics of a culture as seen from the outside. From these we get two basic approaches to musical genres. The emic, or inner, way starts from a musical subject (composer, performer, listener) and scrutinizes genre with respect to its participants in human communication. The etic approach, in turn, examines musical phenomena so that they can be classified, typified, and analyzed.

4.2.1 Before genres Other theories study the states that come before the concept of genre, the grounds on which genres originate. One such theory is that of the Czech musicologist Vladimir Karbusický, concerning archetypes or Urformen, of which he distinguishes five: (1) endless production, repetition, impulsive variation; (2) additivetectonic devices, the building of musical space by addition; (3) cyclic “eternal” return, circular movement, (4) departure-development-return; (5) four-part dram-

84 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music aturgy, as in cyclic sonata form, featuring the dialectical dramatization of development (Karbusický 1992: 91). These are shown in Figure 4.4. Class 4 is quite similar to many other foundations of musical form, such as introductory, developing, and terminating “functions”; or as Boris Asafiev put it, initium-motus-terminus in his intonation theory. In general narratology we have the categories of virtuality – passage to act/non-passage to the act – achievement/ non-achievement (Brémond 1973); or inchoativity, durativity, terminativity (Greimas and Courtés 1979: 22, 111, 185, 389). The Italian semioticians Gino Stefani and Stefania Guerra Lisi, in turn, have developed a theory of seven prenatal style features: (1) Concentric-pulsating style, centering on one point, pulsation, vibration line, ostinato, drone, protomelody; as in Beethoven’s “Moonlight” Sonata, Wagner’s Rhinegold overture, or Ligeti’s Atmosphères. (2) Balancing, wave-like motion, swaying, rocking, tensionrelaxation, sliding and gliding, as in Bach’s C major Prelude from Das Wohltemperierte Klavier or Palestrina Masses. (3) Melodic, continuous movement, linear, upward and downward, ease, happiness, tenderness, experience of flight, dream, arabesque, legato, fluid-like “arch form”, cantabile phrasing, as in Bellini’s Casta diva, Schumann’s Träumerei. (4) Turning, circular movement, pirouette, circling, spiral, whirling, being swept away by passion, Viennese waltz, baroque: elliptical, spiral orbits, poetics of wonder, astonishment, spiral staircases of Bernini, Caravaggio, and Borromini. (5) Rhythmic-staccato, movement to and fro, activation of the center, points, strokes, Schumann’s Rasch style (as Barthes called it), African drumming, two-pulse musics, hymns, marches, tarantellas, samba, tango, Berio’s Circles. (6) Image-Action, chaos, loss of control, anxiety, tendency to trance, Scriabin’s music, Stravinsky’s Sacre, Stockhausen’s Gesang der Jünglinge. (7) Cathartic: changes of stimuli, chaos of timbres, surprise, crescendo, acceleration, intensification, vital forces, syncopated rhythmic style, arrival, Rossini’s crescendos, ecstasy, catharsis of Beethoven’s symphonies. Stefani’s theory traces kinetic states of music before the appearance of genres, and on this universal basis can be shifted from one art to another. The theory uses the epistemic level as the starting point, and its application to different arts – say, a principle such as ornamentation, as in the Baroque style, which category also appears in literary genres such as the novel, as well as in painting and in music. As Couperin famously stated, “Nous écrivons différemment de ce que nous exécutons.” The Swiss music psychologist Ernst Kurth believed European art music to have two basic stylistic genres that preceded musical genres in the proper sense; namely, polyphonic linear art and movement – as in Palestrina-type vocal works – and classicism or corporeal, rhythmic style, which appears in marches, dances, and melodies. If the first-mentioned was based upon transcendental movement toward the heights, the latter was more earthly and based upon joi de vivre and

4.2 . . . and in music

Figure 4.4: Karbusický’s urformen

| 85

86 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music bodily energy. Later, the American musicologist Leonard B. Meyer searched for melodic archetypes looming behind formal and generic principles, such as triadic, axis type, scale type, gap and fill, and more. In sum: musical genres in such theories are articulated on an ontological foundation that already has its own order and hierarchy, from which different genres then adopt categories and devices.

4.2.2 Major genre categories: Art music and popular music Also problematic for attempts to define musical genre is that one can make both broad generalizations and tiny distinctions within the framework of some formal entities. For instance, we may speak about art and popular music, but also of genres in between, which Carlos Vega (1967) calls “mesomusic”, referring to music that is simultaneously both or neither, as is often the case in Latin American music. We also find this, for instance, in the case of Viennese operetta and Spanish zarzuela. German musicologists created the category of Trivialmusik (Dahlhaus 1973), in reference to music which, starting in the nineteenth century, served purely social goals; for example, character pieces and dance tunes in salons. A special subgenre of trivial music was a degraded genre of art music, whose criteria were again inside the music. The criteria determining the distinction between “artistic” and “popular” prove difficult to determine, because that distinction is always to some extent ideological. Adherents of art music state that only art music is multilevel, as is its basic Western manifestation in so-called Classical music and style. The success of the Classical style, in the line of Haydn–Mozart–Beethoven, relied however upon the sociological fact that it offered to all Viennese social classes something of their own, something familiar to listen to. Popular cultural elements became internalized in art music as particular “topics”, such as Ländlers, waltzes, musettes, hunting signals, folk tunes, and more. Popular music is said to be based upon immediate sensual enjoyment, corporeality, music in which the gestural has not been sublimated into expression. Ethnomusicologists in turn claim that the internal quality and interiority attributed to art music is an illusory category: all music is internal; musical experience is an experience plain and simple, and different experiences cannot be set into any order of values. What this involves is always a cultural distinction. This dichotomy parallels the one outlined by Norbert Elias in his distinction between “culture” and “civilization”. The former is the same as the German Geist, Innigkeit, seriousness, the Sublime; and the latter is the material aspect of culture, enjoyment, sensual pleasure, Beauty, melody, cantabile, Italian and French styles, popularity. Concerning modern society, Pierre Bourdieu created a theory of simultaneous musical genres together with other “genres” of life style, where

4.2 . . . and in music

| 87

the choice of music, like that of food, reveals the class to which one belongs. This may hold true for traditional class society, as in Paris with its arrondissements, or in youth cultures; but in the age of electronic communication, all musical genres are available to everyone. Carl Dahlhaus has said that genre in music is always linked with tradition. Tradition, in turn, functions most efficiently when its existence is not made conscious, when it unobtrusively guides man’s behavior. Living tradition is invisible. Tradition, so to say, “offers” musical genres as something ready-made. And yet, in the postmodern age people no longer live in a society of one tradition, but of several and perhaps conflicting traditions. From this point of view musical genres engage in a struggle for existence. Defenders of art music have good reason to worry that the culture, behavior, and concepts which that genre represents may be disappearing, or at least blending and mixing with genres strongly favored by communications media. Gino Stefani, in his early theory of musical competence, refers to the dichotomy of erudite/popular. The most important art music obtains at the level of individual opus or composition; in popular music, anthropological codes and schemes are the most essential ingredients. Dahlhaus (1973), too, says that in Western art music the meaning of genre diminishes radically from the nineteenth century on, with the individual art work distinguishing itself from others as the crucial point. Guido Adler called the extreme case of this style-genre the “academic” style. The term “mediocre” was applied to lower class music, unlike in the age of the Baroque or Classicism, when following a genre type was more important than aesthetic novelty. Lieber langweilig aber im Stil remained a principle in Germany, but in France Hector Berlioz wrote the following in 1830, in his essay, Sur la musique classique et la musique romantique: On a voulu très longtemps et quelques personnes voudraient encore retenir la symphonie dans le cadre étroit qui lui fût tracé par Haydn. Mozart ne fit pas la moindre tentative pour en sortir. C’était toujours, pour lui comme pour Haydn, le même plan, le même ordre d’idées, la même succession d’impressions, toujours allegro suivi d’un andante, d’un menuet et d’un finale . . . vif, et dans ces quatre mouvements jamais autre chose qu’un enchaînement plus ou moins habilé de jolies phrases, de petites coquetteries mélodiques . . . ces compositions n’avaient pour but que de divertir l’oreille . . . . Jamais on n’y remarque à moindre tendance vers cet ordre d’idées qu’on appelle poétique . . . les compositeurs romantiques au contraire ont écrit sur leur banniére: Inspiration libre, le prémier qui brisa les chaines scolastiques et s’affranchit du jeu plus pesant encore de la routine fût Gluck. Il innova presque dans tout . . . . (quoted in Condé 1981: 95–96) (We have for a very long time wanted, and some people still do, to restrain the symphony within the narrow framework which was traced by Haydn. Mozart did not make the slightest attempt to escape. It was always for him and Haydn the same plan, the same ideas, the same succession of impressions, always followed by an allegro, andante, a minuet and a lively finale . . . and in four movements anything except a succession of more or less skilful pretty

88 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music phrases, small melodic flirtations . . . these compositions were intended only to entertain the ear . . . . Never will one notice the trend we call poetic . . . Instead, Romantic composers have written on their banner: “Free Inspiration!” Nevertheless the first to break the chains of scholasticism and advance toward something beyond the routine, was Gluck. He was an innovator in almost everything . . . .) [Translation mine]

4.2.3 Norms and varieties of music It is common for almost any musical phenomenon to be called a genre. One hears of “genres” of piano music, wind music, string music and so on, referring to the instrument(s) producing the music (the musical channels and Jakobson’s phatic function). Yet, likewise there is talk about genres such as “sonata”, “symphony”, “concerto”, “oratorio” and the like, when a category of musical form is taken in mind. Also musical texture is experienced as a genre (e.g., fugue). Then we have military music, church music, chamber music, advertising music, cinema music, mood music – all of which function in primarily a social sense. The theory of musical topics grows from this basis (Ratner, Monelle), such as the military and pastoral entities stemming from those socially codified types of music. Altogether, it is impossible to fix genre into a single musical category. Many general genre-theoretical issues also apply to music, although in musicology they have not yet received much attention. As a normative scheme or framework, genre is a mold into which a composer imparts his own musical ideas. Genre is like a vow made by the composer, to which he refers in the title of his work, and which in turn makes the listener expect something particular. A composer may of course also break such a vow or play with it, but these attitudes are negative sides of the primary, normative idea of a genre contract. Genres may die by being forgotten, which Adorno mentions in his aesthetics; but they can also emerge from an individual creation when a single work rises to such a significantly normative position that is then imitated by all others. The normativity of genre can ultimately be codified into rules so strict that they can be described by a generative grammar, similar to how language is formalized into a grammar and inserted into a computer. Musical rules, too, can be formalized for such purposes, and as we know, such experiments are plentiful. Finally, genres can also blend together, into fusions and crossover cases, as we have seen. And genres can migrate, like the famous case of the chaconne, stemming from the Mexican dance, chacona amulatada. We have also the case of multiculturalism in music, leading to fascinating genre fusions, as in the case of Ligeti and the Finnish avant-gardist Erik Bergman.

4.2 . . . and in music

| 89

4.2.4 Genre in musical communication In music, as in other sign systems and discourses, a subject wants to communicate something to a community. A Moi aspires to touch the world of Soi (Tarasti 2005: 234–246). A composer wants to express some idea, create some signification that he seeks to transmit. Music is the speech of one man to another, or as conductor Nikolaus Harnoncourt calls it, Musik als Klangrede. The composer must take into account the expectations of his public and use devices, structures, and tools to convey those of his ideas which have also been mastered by his audience. A composer must to some extent share the same codes as his listeners, and here genre helps him. Genre crystallizes sociologically the anticipations of receivers and consumers of a musical message; genres represent structures of communication, of langue, which a speaker must abide by if he wants to be understood (Tarasti 1994: 16). Hence what is mediated to listeners are precisely musical significations. Of course this semiotic theory can also be interpreted as a certain developmental phase of Western erudite music, as Carl Dahlhaus presumes when he speaks about musical genre and form. One may consider, for instance, sonata to be something like an outer framework, a scheme into which the content is put in order for it to appear. In this sense genre merges with norms: Genre is a sub-concept of norms, and from norms one can make aesthetic judgments. The work that neglects rules cannot manifest individuality either . . . . Art works came to be taken as individuals, whose genre characteristics were secondary and aesthetically even negligible. This view coincided with Romantic-genius aesthetics, which for originality and expression abandoned authoritarian norms and schemes as alien to real art. All this was based upon a philosophy of art inherited from the eighteenth century, which claimed that contemplation, plunging without concepts into the individual and particular, was the core of aesthetics. (Dahlhaus 1973: 889–890)

When Umberto Eco says that the aesthetic moment appears above all as a breaking of norms, even here perhaps the Romantic model looms in the background. In any case, in the light of our theory of Moi/Soi, an individual composer who reaches out to the world of the Soi needs the help of genre to attain it. From the viewpoint of Soi, genres render individual composers as raw material for the maintenance of a tradition. On the other hand, as Dahlhaus says: “Genre traditions are at their strongest where they are unconscious, and belong to those conditions which are set for music, instead of developing by themselves from it. Tradition is – to summarize – that which is understood from itself” (ibid.: 891). From this Hegelian point of view, then, composers are victims of a cunning historical intellect, where genres exist to recruit them as agents of music history. Yet Adorno

90 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music emphasized that Moi is always in contradiction with society; and it had to be, since for him progressive music lived in the conflict and constant negation of tradition. He accuses Wagner of school-like four part harmony and Beethoven of inappropriate “gesturality” in the pompous second theme of the slow movement of the Fifth Symphony. Genre deeply impacts musical structures and principles. As noted above, Ernst Kurth saw two great manifestations of the Classical style in the history of Western art music; the first, polyphonic linear art, the second, lied, march and dance tunes of the Viennese classical period: Classical style was prepared historically by the growing penetration of folk and dance elements into music. Just as the lied-like classical form principle was based upon dance, so the polyphonic line was historically reduced into the chorale and most closely to the Protestant chorale, the artistic nature of which pervades the polyphony of Bach’s music. Yet the linear form principle goes still further back, into Gregorian chant, accordingly to the time when no external meters dominated. (Kurth 1922: 9)

With this last statement Kurth means lied-like, symmetrical, periodic phrases, in groups of 2 + 2, 2 + 2; whereas linear polyphony constituted a continuous line. In other words, principles of musical formation emerged precisely from the penetration of certain genres – chorale, Gregorian chant, and dance – into general musical consciousness. This process can be well illustrated by J. S. Bach’s and G. Fr. Handel’s instrumental works. For instance, The Well-Tempered Clavier, Book I: D major prelude, essentially a French ouverture (opera in clavichord music); G minor prelude: vocal techniques and dotted rhythms; E flat major prelude: linear, Gregorian chant; F minor fugue: theme as chorale; Prelude to the G major partita: orchestral effects, basso continuo; Gigue as fugue; etc. And in Handel: F minor fugue, the outburst of bel canto melodiousness; D minor prelude: pure linearity, with no bar lines!

4.2.5 Transgressing genres On the other hand, a musical work of art can exceed its borderlines; a composition may start from a genre type, then transcend it. This takes place in almost all great art. Bach’s St. Matthew Passion can be taken as the climax of functional music of its time; that is to say, of the Protestant chorale, polyphony, and counterpoint, as well as of Baroque opera, with its arias, recitatives, and orchestral ritornellos – the Passion brings to completion and surpasses all of these. It is the same with the Wagnerian Gesamtkunstwerk, which blends various arts together and produces something more than mere opera. Therefore Wagner called his last work, Parsifal,

4.2 . . . and in music |

91

by the genre title Bühnenweihfestspiel, where a single art work became a genre of its own, itself being the only exemplification of that genre. A genre tradition culminates in works that form their own genre. In this sense genres can serve as utopias. Granted, a genre must have an audience to receive it with their expectations; nevertheless, some musical compositions create their own audiences. According to Marcel Proust, the late string quartets of Beethoven are such works. And Alexander Scriabin, in his last phase, ended up with a new art form which he called an acte préalable, an almost untranslatable term meaning an act prior to the formation of a contract or promise, i.e., genre. For him this meant a thing of mystery, a work that had to include tones, colors, dance, choirs, perfumes, and which could only be realized in India. This was of course a post-Wagnerian dream, and yet the whole aesthetics of avant-garde music is based to a large extent precisely upon such a view of genre as a utopia.

4.2.6 Crises of genres Genres can of course emerge from previous genres, but likewise they can originate when changes in a culture’s intonations occur, when old intonations no longer correspond to the emotional moods of new periods, that is to say, when genres fall into crisis. When Pierre Boulez first struck out at opera as a genre, he proposed that opera houses be burnt. Genre can thus be experienced as a harmful obstacle, something we must get rid of in the name of progress. And yet, genres persist as a challenge to composers, as a kind of world of ideals and norms which they strive for in order to gain acceptance by their community. Genres come to act as a kind of sanctified code, which cannot be changed. Whoever intervenes in the codes of this genre must fall outside the community, as has in fact happened in some countries. Take Sibelius for instance, who sought only to renew the genre of the symphony, but whose “profound musical logic” Adorno, the norm-giver of the German musical world, could not understand, neither aesthetically nor musictheoretically. Instead, Sibelius’s gradual processes of change came to be accepted as a precursor of minimalism! This shows that an earlier misunderstood work can suddenly become acceptable to a new musical genre and conceived as a pioneer of the latter. For instance, the symphony is still, even after Sibelius, a genre for which almost all composers in Finnish music culture aspire; to write effectively in this genre has become a rite of initiation, the proof of being a true composer. Accordingly, composers are born in a certain culture and environment and must live under its norms. But this does not change the principal fact that genres are constructs and ultimately choices and commitments of composers. As a bundle of norms, genre represents the “necessity” of the musical communication;

92 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music as a choice, they constitute “freedom”. There are also composers who change their communities and, like chameleons, adapt to the social orders of different contexts. Igor Stravinsky became a model example of the nomadic composer identity. He launched his career in turn of the century Russia when, thanks to Diaghilev, ballet was the central genre. For this Stravinsky created the Firebird, Petrushka, and Rite of Spring. Then he moved to Switzerland and France, where he wrote completely new chamber music genres for small ensembles. Finally he moved to the USA, and again adapted to new markets and genres.

4.2.7 Cultural reflections An interesting phenomenon is why certain musical genres are so strongly rooted in certain cultures, while alien to others. According to the German view, in European erudite music there are two main genres. The first is German instrumental music, so-called “absolute music”, with the symphony its highest manifestation. On the other hand, there is Italian vocal art with all its manifestations, beginning from bel canto and its arch-genre and culmination, opera. Alles Andere bleibt am Rande (Everything else remains on the periphery), as Hans Georg Eggebrecht claims in his history of Western music. With the possible exception of Martucci, Italian composers did not write many symphonies. Similarly, in France symphonies have been avoided, being considered too Nordic and heavy. There the most important genres have been ballet, opera, and mélodie. Genres are thus also entities of discoursive power; to define a genre, to teach it, to adopt it – all this constitutes the use of power. Who has the right to change a genre? Do genres have a center and periphery? In the market economy they serve also as economic powers. In copyright offices, which secure reimbursements, one criterion for the price of music is precisely its genre, because various genres are accorded different values. All musical genres live via time, place, and actors, even though they are in a constant historic process of change, developing on the one hand according to their own laws, and on the other hand according to their functions in a society. Genres are cultural units linked with certain places and functions: church music is listened to in a church, military music in a parade, chamber music at home, and so on. Finally, it comes down to individuals, who either have certain genres thrust upon them, or choose genres for themselves. Musicians have their own special genres, those in which their person and style, their Moi, are best displayed. Italian bel canto tenors are not perhaps very good at performing Wagner; Glenn Gould is splendid at playing Bach, but out of his comfort zone when performing Romantic music.

4.2 . . . and in music

| 93

4.2.8 Classics One has to ask also if there are such things as national music genres. The question can be formulated this way: Can universal music be national? Rising to this challenge, the German musicologist Hermann Danuser edited an anthology whose title alone is revealing: Gattungen der Musik und Ihre Klassiker (Danuser 1988). In this work he chooses certain genres of art music and for each genre indicates its “classic” representative; in this context, the term “classic” means exemplary or ideal. Any artist whose work ranks among the top achievements in his art may be called “classical” (ibid.: 13). In defining central musical genres, Danuser defers to Ludwig Finscher, a specialist in string quartet literature. Finscher, in turn, argues that in all of the central musical genres – from Gregorian chant to symphony – classicality appears as an evaluative norm. By their essence and structure they have become highly differentiated and manifest themselves as exemplary, and moreover have enough historical longevity to have reached maturity. Danuser categorizes art music as represented by its most central genres and composers (Figure 4.5).

Catholic church music Evangelical church music I Evangelical church music II Oratorio Musical tragedy Musical comedy Solo concerto String quartet Piano sonata Symphony Lied Lyrical piano piece Music drama

Palestrina Schütz J. S. Bach Handel Gluck Mozart Mozart Haydn Beethoven Beethoven Schubert Schumann Wagner

Figure 4.5: Danuser’s list of central genres and their representative composers

4.2.9 National versus universal It is a striking fact that “opera” is not listed among the genres in Danuser’s list – perhaps because it would require considering the role of Italian opera, which is avoided, as is the symphonic poem. Danuser admits that the national dimension of classicality is of great importance, but that great difficulties present themselves

94 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music in dealing with it. The problem lies in the relationship of the national (as in Italian opera and symphonic poem) to the universal. He is aware of the Germano-centricism of the list and admits that one might ask, Why Schütz and not Monteverdi? Why Gluck and not Rameau? Why Schumann and not Chopin? Yet he says that nationalities foreground composers who have national meaning, but carry no weight outside their nation (Danuser 1988: 14). On the other hand, all nations have, notwithstanding chauvinist emphases, their own value and legitimacy without any hierarchies. Hence one could justifiably take Chopin as the classic of the lyrical piano piece. Still, we may ask how the national be pondered in respect of classicality. Is the “national” an advantage or disadvantage? Danuser omits telling the reader that his entire reasoning starts from the hypothesis that, on the one hand, there is Music which is universal – all of whose representatives happen to be German – and on the other, music that is “national”. This would mean that his “classic” composers, in addition to being German, are automatically universal as well. This calls to mind a cartoon in which a Swede under a starry sky says, “Isn’t it wonderful that we Swedes are the only people who are not foreigners!” Or the fact that in Russian conservatories and universities, music history has been divided into two classes: “Music History” (= Russian music) and “Foreign Music History” (= Bach, Mozart, Beethoven, and all the rest). Do distinctly national musical genres exist? From the moment the national category became a significant cultural element, they most surely do. Chopin wrote mazurkas and polonaises, but in his piano works they are no longer the dances of Polish folklore; in 1839 he wrote to his parents from Paris, remarking that no one could actually dance to them. In his late mature works, such as the F minor Ballade, G minor Fantasy, and Fantasy-Polonaise, Chopin created a synthetic style characterized by the blending together of these genres. For instance, in the introduction to the Andante spianato there suddenly occurs the reminiscence of a mazurka and the accent typical of Kujawiak dance (accent on the second beat of the bar). Chopin also transferred genre features of Italian bel canto to his piano music, for instance in his Nocturnes and Études. He did not move scenes from Bellini’s operas directly into his piano pieces, but rather imitated generic traits of bel canto. Many composers conceived as national did the same. That is to say, they did not directly quote folk music, but mimicked the features of folk genres in a deeper and less recognizable manner. From Hungarian folk music Bartók adopted the style of parlando rubato. Dvořák wrote instrumental “dumkas”. Latin American music is filled with new, folk-based musical genres, such as the Choros by Heitor Villa-Lobos (a musical genre played by street musicians of Rio de Janeiro) and more. In all these cases, the original folk genres are transcended, which results in a new genre that goes beyond the previous ones. What from a European

4.2 . . . and in music

| 95

viewpoint is “exotic” is, to these composers, completely natural – as natural as the four-part choral Satz is for Germans.

4.2.10 Social classification and functions The concept of genre in music can also serve as a criterion of classification. For instance, the aforementioned category of “classical music” may emerge originally from a certain historical style or genre. Viennese classicism expanded to cover also the Baroque and Renaissance, and was provided with the aesthetic evaluation that, in it, form and content coincided, whereas in Romanticism the content determined the form. When canonized, the classical style started to cover the entire field of Western art music, and came to receive even more universal definitions, such that it was music that all people in the world wanted to hear and perform, again and again, from China and Korea to Venezuela. Ultimately, the generic label of “classical” has come to cover all the art music available on recordings. Even radically new music, which denies the pertinence of such labels, falls into this category and ends up on the “classical” shelves of every music store. The concept of genre has become more and more viewed as a sociological entity corresponding to developments in other fields and other arts. This concern with commercial and social conditions of production was manifested early on. As said above, there emerged a particular genre in bourgeois music culture which Germans called Trivialmusik. In the broad sense this referred to everyday music which was played on social occasions, at home or for public entertainment. It comes close to the concept of musical kitsch, denoting inauthentic pathos, sentimentality without a musical basis. Dahlhaus’s example of kitsch is the horn melody from the Andante cantabile of Tchaikovsky’s Fifth Symphony: a tension occurs on the dominant-seventh chord and its resolution into tonic, but this selfevident event is made “tragic” and its impact is banal. Here one might ask, Why then are the huge dominant-seventh formations of Bruckner’s symphonies not kitsch? For Vladimir Jankélévitch, a French music philosopher, Sibelius’s Pelléas was shallow “casino” music (1992). For Adorno, Sibelius’s references to folk music indicated helplessness, but quite similar devices in Mahler were “progressive representations” of the voice of the suppressed classes. Genre terms are therefore used in music criticism, but often in a hypocritical manner. Subjective aesthetic judgments and propagandizing ideologies often wear the garb of genre concepts.

96 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music 4.2.10.1 Piano music as the genre of women The development of piano music serves well as an example of the close connection between social context and its inherent values. The expansion of the piano in European cultural history coincides with the growth of the bourgeois class. Unlike the nobility, the bourgeoisie could not afford to hire musicians and orchestras; thus, home music was essentially chamber music. What had not been written for piano was arranged for it, and new subgenres emerged; for example, four-hand versions of symphonies, piano scores of operas, and the like. The practice of arranging grew out of salon music, which was defined by Robert Schumann in 1840 such that it referred to the place of music-making, and not to its musical genre. The piano symbolically represented the power of the modern bourgeois class, and was at the same time an industrial product and an elegant home furnishing. Since the salon was the realm of women, while the men were influential outside the home, piano music was written precisely for women. Carl Czerny said in 1842 that the piano was particularly suitable for the more beautiful gender. Woman at the piano became the center of family and social life. Young girls of all social classes received piano lessons. In America, such a person was called a “piano girl”. It was clear that these social conditions also influenced the genre itself: piano music. The most popular piece in the nineteenth century was the Prayer of the Maiden by Tekla Bądarzewska, which appeared in Warsaw in 1856. It consisted of only two pages of music, only one motif, no development, clear harmonic cadences, figurations and crossing of hands, all of which gave the impression of virtuosity, when it was in fact a simple texture. All this was later considered by “feminist musicology” as a type of gendered musical genre. The musical genre-representation of women was therefore the lyrical character piece for piano, an arbitrary structure that could easily have been defined differently in another social context. Yet this rule of the supposed “femininity” of women’s music has brilliant exceptions, such as Fanny Hensel, Teresa Carreño (the Venezuelan piano virtuoso), and Clara Schumann, who enjoyed success in writing “male” genres and playing outside the home, on public concert stages. Correspondingly, the lyrical character piece started to lose its signification when record players and radios replaced the piano; it was then that the piano and piano music as a particularly feminine genre of expression lost its meaning. Altogether, this shows the close connection between musical genres and changes in their social functions. Modern computer technology has enabled quite new musical genres and revolutionized in general the social role of composers, since the tools of composing are available to all. A similar case of genre transformation was the melodrama, widely popular in early Romanticism; called declamatorium (recitations accompanied by music), the genre was used by Mozart, Beethoven, Carl Maria von Weber, and in Finland by Friedrich Pacius (e.g., in his Die Weihe der

4.2 . . . and in music |

97

Töne). It disappeared as a genre, then was reborn as non-diegetic cinema music, that is, music not part of the plot itself. What else is cinema music, playing behind actors who are speaking on screen, if not a subgenre of melodrama?

4.2.11 Genre as classification Wolfgang Marx, in his extensive study Klassifikation und Gattungsbegriff in der Musikwissenchaft (2004), approaches the concept of genre above all as a principle of classification, whereby we can conceptualize the course of music history and its various cases. Alongside “genre” appear many other concepts, such as type, group, class, category, form, style, genus, species. Friedrich Blume stressed that concepts like genre, style, and form are very close to each other. In fact, in the first edition of Musik in Geschichte und Gegenwart, the word Gattung (genre) does not appear at all, any observations about it being made with regard to the word “form”. Similarly, Walter Wiora sought to distinguish genre history from the analysis of form. The characteristics of genre can vary greatly according to various criteria, to which belong social context or function, formal structure (sonata, rondo, etc.), and performance forces (orchestral, piano, woodwinds, choral, etc.). Still, the concept of genre serves as a classificatory criterion, almost as in biology where one classifies animal or plant species. Therefore the genre “art music” can be further classified: secular vs. sacred (where secular music = instrumental music), vocal music vs. instrumental music, and so on. However, the difference between this and natural-science classification lies in the fact that for music there are no universally valid criteria for classification. A problem of its own is the understanding of genres either by the model of an organism or that of development. Genre, understood as an organism, causes us to think of it has having a birth, climax, and decline or disappearance. According to the development model, genre likewise has its emergent moment, continuous change of horizon, then vanishing or blending together with other genres. Genre has also been scrutinized as an ontological entity where, according to Dahlhaus, some are inclined to idealize it in the Platonic tradition, the opposing view being either realist or nominalist. Historians and sociologists find metaphysical genre theories strange, although the concept of genre is itself an abstraction, in our terms, a transcendental unit. Genre also plays into the field of aesthetics, in which one may distinguish four periods: (1) speculative music theory until 1300, where we have genres like musica naturalis or artificialis, and in the first case, musica mundana and musica humana; (2) the period of composed music, c. 1300–1800; (3) the period of art music, beginning from 1800; (4) modern times, when all sounding forms are accepted as

98 | 4 The concept of genre: In general and in music music: art music, popular music, and folk music. In Athanasius Kircher’s Musurgia universalis (1650) the classification of music is extremely diverse, even absurd to contemporary minds. In the mid-eighteenth century the so-called aesthetics of autonomy was born, which viewed art music as completely detached from everyday life. The musical work was conceived as the entirely unique creation of a composer, and one which followed its own rules. In the Romantic period, to follow the rules of genre was a sign of mediocrity.

4.2.12 Recent theories Newer genre theoreticians have rejected many theses and assumptions of the German Gattung theory. Chopin scholar Jeffrey Kallberg has studied the rhetorics of genre. Kallberg denies Dahlhaus’s normative view of genre, and particularly the notion that, from about the year 1830 on, genre lost its meaning, because compositions had to be unique and individual masterworks. When the function of music changed to an autonomy aesthetics, Dahlhaus presumes that communication between composer and listener weakened. Semiotically speaking, this means that if genre terms are structures of communication, as I claim above, then composers would have had less need for them from that moment on. According to Kallberg, the Romantics’ emphasis on individuality was rather a counter-reaction to the normative view of what was then Neoclassicism. When the Romantics stressed individuality, they did not at all abandon the universal value of art. Yet when we arrive at the twentieth century, genre comes to be identified, says Dahlhaus, with the title of the work. But this claim cannot be supported. After all, when composers call their works Prisms, Figures, Structures, Transformations, and such, these titles do not make the genre disappear. Worse is that Dahlhaus neglects the communicational and persuasive value of genres. Genre is for Kallberg a persuasive force that guides the listener’s response. The choice of genre and its recognition constitute the framework for musical communication. A kind of genre agreement occurs between composer and listener. As we have repeated several times: The composer agrees to use certain forms, shapes, and gestures, and the listener agrees to interpret the work in this context. Agreements can be broken, however, or simply misunderstood, as occurs with marginal works. Counter-genres or antigenres emerge, including synthetic genres (like Chopin’s late works) and at the extreme such counter-genres as John Cage’s 4󸀠 33󸀠󸀠 which defies all generic expectations. In a word, genre serves as a rhetorical technique. It aids in making an impact upon the listener. Jim Samson, along the same lines, speaks about genre markers in a composition. For him genre is the most powerful code binding composer and listener.

4.2 . . . and in music

| 99

Works often have a “host genre” and “visiting genres”. These may constitute a “counterpoint” of genres, or one of them may control the other(s). Another wellknown theoretician, Franco Fabbri (1973), views genres as does Eco, as “cultural units”. He does not accept the archetype theory of genre, according to which they are determined outside of time and place. Rather, he views genre as set of musical events, real or possible, the course of which is determined by societal rules, demands, and tastes. Fabbri allows that by means of genre we can understand musical events, but above all we can talk about them. In other words, genres pertain to the meta-linguistic aspect of music. In sum, we would do well to recall that nowadays genres have to do mostly with the receiver (consumer). The unrestrained capitalism of the “global” economy sees to that genre, along with many other of what we would call transcendental entities, becomes a commodity, one that feeds the tastes and desires of the largest world-markets possible. Setting aside such issues as sales and consumption, in the next chapter I address the issue of globality from a different perspective, with some thoughts on the world and how it has come to be interpreted.

Chapter 5 The world and its interpretation 5.1 World and worlds Thinkers have devised various theories not only about the world, but about “worlds”, be they Popper’s “three world entities”, theories of “possible worlds”, and others. All of these involve semiotics, which, operative in the given world, should also prove pertinent to possible, impossible, and totally transcendental worlds. It becomes fashionable to ponder “world views” from time to time, discussed as early as in Karl Jaspers’s Psychologie der Weltanschauungen (1919). Most recently on the topic we have Anne Cauquelin’s book, À l’angle des mondes possibles (2010). Cauquelin, editor-in-chief of the journal Nouvelle revue d’esthétique, starts with Aristotle’s claim that everything centers around the earth (Terra), which circulates around fire, together with nine other planets. So that the “perfect” number ten would be filled, the ancient Greeks imagined that there was also an invisible anti-earth (Anti-Terra). In doing so, they were already postulating the logical or semiotic structure of S and non-S (here, S does not refer to Soi, but simply to logical positions). Aristotle further argued for a virtual existence before action (dunamis), which was transformed into entelechy or actualization. Similarly, if one wants to move (kinesis), one must have the potentiality (energeia) to do so. For both subject and material to be able to act, they need potentiality. The potentiality of stone might be to become a wall, but a sculptor can make a statue of it. Leibniz defined this virtuality as a “monad”, a self-contained, self-maintaining entity. From this it was a small step to the idea that we live in only one world. To this vision Cauquelin adds one more element: fiction. Through art and poetry we can imagine possible worlds. For instance, a novel creates a world, which is not quite the same as our real world, but close enough so that we can identify with it. Aesthetics is a way in which we can penetrate into possible worlds. Cauquelin’s crucial thesis is that of the plurality of worlds. The earth on which we live is a place from which we can depart for other territories, even to “extra-territories”, as Adorno reasoned. To Cauquelin’s mind, both “semiologists” and analytic philosophers conceive the opening and unfolding of the world as occurring horizontally, in linear fashion, whereas in phenomenology it is understood vertically, in depth. Just as verticality exists in the visible world, so does it also in the invisible one. In our opening chapter, we argued that transcendence opens precisely into this invisible, vertical nothingness. Heidegger, too, spoke of the opening of the ground, of depth. Hence

5.1 World and worlds

|

101

Cauquelin is certain that transcendence exists in art. From this we arrive at Eco’s concept of the “open work”, from there to ontologies, and finally to Being in the “second life” as avatars. We may end our introduction with the notion of utopia, that Baconian world that does not exist, and to Ernst Bloch’s principle of “hope”. What is involved here is the category of noch nicht, not yet . . . but perhaps in the future. Its opposite category is the loss of the hope: . . . auch ich war einmal . . . even I was once hopeful, but after many unfruitful years, I abandoned hope. It is easy to see how, without hope, one can easily develop a cynical view of the world. We have seen, even in this brief introduction, great diversity in thought about “worlds”. In what follows I look at some world-views more closely, grouping them under the categories of philosophers, artists, and semioticians.

5.1.1 Philosophers First is the little-known Avicenna (Ibn-Sina), a Persian philosopher, medical doctor, logician, psychologist, theologian and poet, who lived in c. 980–1037. A child prodigy, as his autobiography testifies, he went on to write about his world and about how one became a scholar. What was needed were good libraries and the ability to remember by heart. At the age of only ten years, he had already read the Qur’an and much other literature. He proved to be much more skilful than his teachers and also became familiar with logic and law, as well as with the mathematical and natural sciences of Euclid and Ptolemy. He wrote books about the physical sciences and metaphysics, and then about medicine, which he studied empirically by visiting sick people. At the age of sixteen he declared, “During all that time I never slept a night, and all my days I spent in studies. I made notebooks for myself, in which I gathered all the premises into classes with their syllogisms. I would long ponder the premises of each problem until the issue became clear to me (quoted in Avicenna & al-Ghazali 2001: 22). Avicenna then took on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, “without, however, understanding its contents”. Altogether, he read the book forty times and memorized all of its contents. As an adult Avicenna spent a migratory life visiting various courts, and was even appointed to high state posts. His pupil Abu Ubaid continued his biography and assembled, among other things, a catalogue of Avicenna’s works. Avicenna went on to become one of the most important scholars to mediate the heritage of ancient philosophy to Europe. Some thought-experiments by Avicenna in psychology, metaphysics, and logic have had longstanding impact on European philosophy. The best-known of these experiments is his proof of the existence of the soul:

102 | 5 The world and its interpretation When you are in good health, or rather in a normal state, such that you can comprehend matters properly, are you ever forgetful of your own existence . . . ? . . . then imagine that you are suspended in space for an instant, in such a way that you do not see the parts of your body, and the members of it do not touch one another, you will find that you are unaware of everything about yourself except the fact that you are – that you exist. With what do you perceive yourself in such a state, or before or after it? (Quoted in Afnan 1958: 150)

Thereafter Avicenna reasons that the answer is not the body, nor any sense organ: “So what you perceive is something other than these things which you do not perceive while you are perceiving yourself . . . . Thus that self which you perceive does not belong to the order of things that you perceive through the senses in any way whatsoever, or through what resembles the senses” (ibid.). Neither do I perceive it by my action, since floating in such a state one is separated from one’s acts. Such an act should thus have an absolute agent. It is easy to see how this idea of Avicenna was duplicated many philosophers later, among them St. Augustine, and particularly Descartes with his principle of cogito ergo sum. Persian thought, one of Avicenna’s influences, contains the core of the IndoEuropean world view, namely the dualist principle, especially the division of the world into Good and Evil; for example, Zoroaster separated Ahuramazda, the good god, from Ahriman, the evil one. At the same time, east of Persia another type of thinking prevailed, which in contrast emphasized unity. Hence the visions of Avicenna are central if we wish to understand more about the birth of our European heritage. His famous poem on the soul displays the same vision as above, only in fictional form. Avicenna portrays the soul as a bird that has been imprisoned in a cage in the world. It remembers its previous situation, and wonders why it had to come here down: “Out of her lofty home she hath come down / upon thee, this white dove in all the pride / Of her reluctant beauty . . . unwillingly she came”. Then Avicenna asks in the poem: “Why then was she cast down from her high peak/to this degrading depth?” This happened “. . . for a purpose wise, that is concealed / E’en from the keenest mind and liveliest wit”. But when the time arrives she is ready to return. We may thus say that Avicenna portrays the journey of the soul from transcendence to Dasein, and back to transcendence. All classical philosophers over the centuries have conceived of their own “worlds”. We have already mentioned one of the best-known of these, Leibniz, who spoke about windowless monads, which function together because God has set them into an harmonia praestabilita, a pre-established harmony. Leibniz’s idea that we are living in the best possible world was ironized by Voltaire in his Zadig, in which he reports on the victims of the Lisboan earthquake and asks if

5.1 World and worlds |

103

we really do live in the best possible world. By opposing theory and fact one can easily unravel any system of thought. In the discussion of vertical Appearance, in Chapter Two, we noted that Immanuel Kant solved the conflict by distinguishing between the “transcendental” and the “transcendent”. The first-mentioned refers to the limits of life in general and to the idea of that which lies beyond existence. The latter, in turn, relates to the epistemic fact that we can never know what reality is as such, the famous Ding an sich, since it is filtered to us always through our sense categories, via time, space, and subject. In both cases, transcendental and transcendent, the experienced reality is mere Appearance, or Schein. It is easy to see how several later philosophies of the world stem from this distinction, as did all structuralism: the perceived world is mere surface; the real reality lies behind it. The distinction holds even in biosemiotics, such that the organism lives in its own reality according to its Ich-Ton. Hence there is no such thing as a world common to all, a universal Umwelt. Uexküll, a biologist and the initiator of biosemiotics, even admitted that this view represents a kind of metaphysics. Yet, among the German speculative philosophers it was perhaps Hegel who suffered most from attacks concerning any system’s blindness to the empirical world. Even to Kierkegaard, his contemporary, Hegel’s system appeared ridiculous, a place where the subject had to build himself a magnificent palace, so to speak, but himself live behind it in a little doghouse. Anglo-analytic philosophy and empirical science as a whole have taken a negative attitude toward Hegel. Bertrand Russell, for example, put in his ironic comment on “John”: if we want to know him we do not need to know all his relatives, social connections, hobbies, and so on. The criticism is directed precisely toward what Russell called the Hegelian “pudding world”: if you touch one edge of it, the whole thing vibrates. In opposition to this system stands logical empiricism, the atomistic world of separate entities. Another criticism of Hegel has been ideological. John Deely, however, in dealing with Hegel’s concepts of absolute spirit, argues that they ought not be directly paralleled to German doctrines in the 1930s, as little as Marx should be accused of the crimes of communism (Deely 2001: 573). For her part, Hannah Arendt considered Hegel the last great philosopher, to whom all subsequent thinkers are indebted. And of course the socially radical Frankfurt School was eminently Hegelian. For example, Theodor W. Adorno’s reasoning is incomprehensible without knowledge of Hegel. The latter’s system had the reputation of snaring anyone who started it. It was said in Finland, for instance, that one nineteenth-century docent needed ten years to get familiar with Hegel, then another ten other years to get rid of him. Finland’s Johan Vilhelm Snellman (1806–1881) was remarkable as a

104 | 5 The world and its interpretation statesman precisely because he adopted the Hegelian perspective in his political action as well as his thought. Another criticism against Hegel is discoursive or deconstructive. The linguist Roland Posner has argued that Hegel represents conceptual poetry, not serious philosophy. Despite the criticisms and (mis)uses of Hegel’s thought, his view of the world as Becoming remains a fascinating concept. Seen in this way, the world stems from the “immanent emergence of contradictions” and “necessary connections” – although David Hume had taken great pains to prove that no necessary connections exist. In his widely known Essay concerning Human Understanding, Hume writes the following: “There are no ideas which occur in metaphysics more obscure and uncertain than those of ‘power’, ‘force’, ‘energy’, or ‘necessary connections’ ” (Hume 1748 [1955]: 73). Furthermore, the “scenes of the universe are continually shifting, and one object follows another in an uninterrupted succession; but the power or force which actuates the whole machine is entirely concealed from us” (ibid.: 75). And: “All events seem entirely loose and separate. One event follows another, but we never can observe any tie between them. They seem conjoined, but never connected” (ibid.: 85). Hegel’s view was totally different. Alongside Being there is always Not-Being, and the Becoming emerges from their conflict. For Hegel, the truth of Being is its essence (Wesen). In the German language, this word originates from the perfect participle of the verb to be: gewesen. For Hegel, knowledge wants to clarify the truth about what is Being-in-oneself and for-oneself, and thus penetrates the surface of things into the background that constitutes the truth of the Being. From this it follows that Being is in fact Appearance, Schein, and that Appearance is mere reflection of itself. Hegel describes the Becoming in Being as a movement from nothingness to nothingness and, from there, back to itself. This is the origin of such notions as difference, contradiction, and opposition. Furthermore, the essence determines itself as the Ground, which can be absolute. The essence must manifest, must appear. The Being into which the essence becomes is essential Being, or existence. Finally one arrives at the concept of reality: the Being is not yet real, and reality is higher than existence. Hence the real is Appearance; it manifests and, in its exteriority, “is” itself. Moreover, the real, as such, is also possible. Hegel also distinguishes between the concepts of real necessity and absolute necessity. He then ponders the relationship of physical-organic life to spiritual life in history. It is customary to say that, from small causes, great effects emerge in history. A mere anecdote, for instance, can precipitate an event. According to Hegel, what is involved is thus only the motivation, an external stimulus, which the inner spirit of the event would not have needed, and in which role it could and would have exploited numerous other motives in order to manifest itself. Who, however,

5.1 World and worlds |

105

knows the laws of real and absolute necessity and possibility? Without doubt only a philosopher who has the ability to analyze them. Here we get close to the solipsism criticized by Deely. According to him, Kant showed that what the mind first knows is the representation which the mind itself makes. Hence, Deely argues, if we take it that some ideas as such guide this representation from the outside, as an “absolute spirit”, we arrive at a dead end (see Deely 2000: 553–572). To which group Hegel belongs is hard to say, since in his philosophy the representation of reality becomes a self-reflexive, discoursive process, whose supposed origin in the Absolute Spirit ultimately remains in the background. The metalanguage whereby the “reality” is portrayed becomes autonomous, a discourse of its own. The same phenomenon takes place in Kierkegaard, in his Closing Unscientific Post-Script. There he engages in a kind of “minimalist” conceptual play, in which the terms are mirrored, and in which one proceeds very, very slowly, step by step, with only slight changes. The method is quite the same as in Hegel, although Kierkegaard intended it to negate Hegelianism. Thus, in both Hegel and Kierkegaard, the world disappears under its interpretation. The “worlds” of later philosophers are articulated on this basis. Schopenhauer elevated the modality of the “will” to a central position. Later, Karl Jaspers gave it a more precise definition: Wille ist Kontinuität im Dauer des Sinnes (The will is continuity in the duration of the sense). This of course means that, unlike in Hegel’s system, the sense needs to be carried and supported by a human subject and his modalities. In the arts, for instance, the musician or actor is required, during performance, to maintain and temporalize the “sense” as a chain of signs. Otherwise it dissolves into fragments (we say more about this in the chapter below, on performance). For Schelling the essence of the world was in its soul, die Weltseele, which was a feeling, living, and thus, semiotically speaking, modal entity. Ralph Waldo Emerson’s idea of Oversoul stemmed from this source. Its continuity was emphasized by the energeticist philosophers of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, most notably by Henri Bergson, for whom the essence of the world was temporality divided into two categories: the physically measurable time of temps d’espace, and the experienced, inner time, temps de durée, or duration (see Bankov 2000). From there it was not a large step to phenomenology and to Edmund Husserl, whose reflections began with inner time-consciousness. To what extent the semiotic philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, and his triadic models, can be derived from Hegel has been discussed by Max H. Fisch, among others (see Fisch 1986: 261–282). Another American philosopher of Peirce’s time, Josiah Royce, was overtly Hegelian in his theory of the world of interpretation, which for him always had three members, A, B and C, of which B was the most important because of its mediation between A and C. Peirce was himself aware of the “Hegelian” nature of his categories of First, Second, and Third, but said that

106 | 5 The world and its interpretation he had not studied much Hegel at all. He wrote to his friend Royce in May 1902 and invited him to spend the summer at his home in Arisbe, Delaware, where: “. . . you and I could pitch into the logical problems and I am sure I could make it well spent time for you, while with all you should teach me of Hegel etc. I am equally sure it would tremendously benefit my own work” (cited in Fisch 1986: 262). For Peirce the world was a signic process, or semiosis, but its rules were to him as objective as natural laws. We shall return to both Peirce and Royce, in later chapters dedicated to these philosophers (see later in this book more on Royce). For now we return Europe, where existential philosophy, with all its variants, turned Hegel upside-down. In Heidegger’s ontology, the world was a place of alienation, characterized by a sinking into to das Man Sein, average being. The incompleteness and deficiency of Dasein drive us to the idea of transcendence, toward which we aspire, according to Jean-Paul Sartre, in the dialectics between being and nothingness. Even Jaspers thought the world to find its Archimedean fulcrum in transcendence, to which we compare our reality. To Hannah Arendt, a pupil of both Heidegger and Jaspers, the world was ruled by compelling causality, or necessity. Yet it was also a place where something “infinitely improbable”, such as freedom, could take place. For Emmanuel Lévinas, in turn, the world is always going toward the infinite or the unknown, and thus never returns to the same place, unlike in most narrative models, where one returns to the beginning, now transformed, and creating an overall symmetrical arch.

5.1.2 Artists What did modernism and postmodernism inherit from the great humanist ages of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries? Many would reply, nothing positive, only guilt. They see nothing helpful about such principles as the intentional fallacy, which is the erroneous claim to know what the author intends, though his output is something quite different. Or Ruskin’s pathetic fallacy, according to which we project onto nature our own feelings, for example when we refer to a “melancholic” landscape or a “laughing” brook; not to mention the argumentum ad hominem, a type of false reasoning by which one evaluates the person rather than his or her argument. Goethe represented German neo-humanism, which some have questioned in the light of twentieth-century history. He supposed the worlds of both plants and humans to be characterized by the principle of organic growth, from which entire ecological philosophies have sprung. Goethe’s Young Werther launched the first youth culture in Europe, and with his Faust created an artistic figure which historian Oswald Spengler later promoted as a basic myth of the Western mind. This all was material for Wilhelm Humboldt, who coined the

5.1 World and worlds

|

107

idea of Bildung, cultivation, which he claimed should prevail in the university in the form of three kinds of freedom: freedom to teach (Lehrfreiheit), freedom to learn (Lernfreiheit), and freedom to live (Lebensfreiheit). Nevertheless, the artist who, in our time, has perhaps suffered most from the weight of the past was Richard Wagner (1813–1883). Many a scholar has made a career, at least in the USA, by declaring Wagner’s operas to be models of anti-Semitic fantasy, of personal chauvinism, and more. To do so, they must ignore the simple fact that Wagner never put any such thing in his art works. Wagner was thoroughly a theater man. If he had wanted to stage the ideologies of his quasi-philosophical writings, he could and would have done so. In addition, the leading motif of all his aesthetics was, under the influence of Schopenhauer and Buddhism, the principle of Mitleid, compassion, which comes quite close to Bloch’s leading principle of Hoffnung, which we mentioned in the introduction to this chapter. Nor did Wagner put Buddhism visibly on stage, as did Harry Kupfer in his production of Parsifal. Wagner became a victim of complete misunderstandings only after his time, when his art was subordinated to the propaganda of opposing ideologies. In fact, the Nibelungen Ring constitutes an eminently relevant analysis of the contemporary world of globalization, of climate crisis, and of the ecological catastrophe which will necessarily follow unless mankind makes a complete turn around and gives up the “ring”, that is to say, the will to power. Rhinegold symbolizes the misuse of natural resources. Wagner raises up mythical figures to pronounce warnings, but his protagonists do not listen to their voices. Erda, mother of the Earth, appears twice, singing, “Mein Schlaf is Träumen, mein Träumen ist Sinnen, mein Sinnen Walten des Wissens” (My sleep is dreaming, my dreaming is reflection, my reflection is power of knowledge). But she is not believed, and the consequences are catastrophic. Wagner was a great visionary, whose musico-mythical world is at once a model, simulacrum, and prophecy. To be fair, we should consider the example of a contrary type of artist. Leo Tolstoi was initially anti-Wagnerian, but in the end came to hold somewhat similar views as Wagner’s. In Vladimir Chertkov’s book, The Last Days of Tolstoi (1922) we can read fragments of the great author’s diaries. In them Tolstoi speaks of growth being impossible in a life that knows no suffering, that without tribulations, mankind would end up every badly. Chertkov recalls an instance in 1909, when Tolstoi returned from his usual solitary walk in the woods, his face beaming with joy: “I have been thinking much and I am satisfied with the result. It has become quite clear to me, standing now at the crossroad, without knowing what to do, that one must always take the decision that brings more self-denial.” Later, pragmatist Georg Henrik v. Wright did not much appreciate this kind of moralizing philosophy, and historically speaking, we can say that Tolstoi’s thought paved the

108 | 5 The world and its interpretation way for communism. In any case, Tolstoi’s world was essentially an axiological universe of moral choices. Of course, the writer who best transmitted the world of humanism from the ancien régime to contemporary times, and who was at the same time completely “modern”, was Marcel Proust. André Maurois once said that the Proustian world is based on two principles: time which destroys, and memory which preserves. The Proustian novel represents impressionist aesthetics in the sense that one phrase or one minute detail prove more valuable than a long, logical development or narrative structure. The Proustian world was that of la belle époque, a time essentially euphoric and hedonistic, but from this shallow ground he plumbs metaphysical depths, qualities that cannot be explained away as literary-historical fact. In contrast to these humanists, we have writers who remained uncommitted to any philosophies or systems. Tolstoi’s opposite may be Anton Chekhov, a pair which Russian literary scholar Vladimir Lakshin portrays as a clash of two world views. Adding to the disillusioned views of Chekhov we have the Persian writer and the cult figure of Farsi literature, Sadeq Hedayat (1903–1951). His discovery in Finland must be credited to Henri Broms, who edited Hedayat’s novel, The Blind Owl, and in his introduction analyzes the author’s cultural background and position in world literature. Influenced by Edgar Allan Poe, Franz Kafka, and Omar Khayam, Hedayat studied in Paris, but traveled in India for two years (1936–1937), where he wrote the Blind Owl. The novel features complex, surrealistic characters, and it portrays events that are often nightmarish and full of anguish. The novel opens: “There are pains in life which bother us silently in loneliness, like a cancer. This anguish cannot be told to anyone, since in general these incomprehensible aches have been considered incredible or rare phenomena. If someone speaks or writes about them, one normally takes him with doubts and scornful smiles.” Later the narrator ponders: “Am I an individual and personal being? I do not know, but when I just looked in the mirror, I did not recognize myself. That previous ego was dead, dissolved, but there is no separating obstacle or gap between the past and the present. I have to write a story about myself but I do not know where to start. My whole life is mere fairytale and story. I have pressed a bundle of grapes and pour the juice, little by little, into the dry throat of an old shadow.” Some might say that Hedayat was existentialist as even before Sartre’s Nausée. Hedayat’s personality is thoroughly explored by his pupil M. F. Farzaneh, in his memoirs, Rencontres avec Sadegh Hedayat (1993). The two had conversations in the cafes of Tehran and finally in Paris. On the one hand, Hedayat takes an attitude of rejection toward his pupil and admirer, and sometimes disappears completely; at other times, he gives him lessons on how to be a writer. Hedayat admits to greatly admire Gogol and E. T. A. Hoffmann, particularly the latter’s Tomcat Murr. He says: “If one avoids reading others in the desire to keep oneself unique, if one

5.1 World and worlds |

109

does not read and study, one is lost. But on the very day when you start to write, you have to be yourself. You become a true writer on the same day when you forget your sources.” He goes on to note, however, that originality for originality’s sake amounts to mere eccentricity. The book is a fascinating report on a writer’s destiny, until its end in a lonely Parisian hotel room.

5.1.3 Semioticians The writer’s world is much based upon talk about the world, and therefore upon language. In this sense, for instance, Marcel Proust can be considered a great semiotician, although he does not use that word himself. According to Saussure, the chaos of the world, and particularly linguistic reality, takes on a kind of order when one distinguishes between langue and parole. As we know, the first is a set of conventional rules, which the individual has no power over, but can only to adopt if one wants to communicate. The latter is an individual realization of the former. This hypothesis was later elevated into a general principle articulating the world. It was, for example, the starting point for Lévi-Strauss’s theory that the world of cultures was dominated by the algebra (langue) of the human brain, which could be expressed in short formulas, as done by Köngäs-Maranda in his Structural Models in Folklore (1962). The world of Michel Foucault was ruled by epistemes of the “archaeological” level. The founder of the Paris school of semiotics, A. J. Greimas (1967), first considered the deepest level of meanings to be isotopies, from which significations started. Later he underlined the cogency of modalities (Being, Doing, and others; see Chapter One). With these he had already stepped outside structuralism. The only French theorist to turn Saussure’s thesis around was Julia Kristeva, for whom the deepest semiotic level was the khora, the place of desires, kinetic energies, and pulsations. In her view, langue was the patriarchal order, with all its emphasis on domination. Most of the French semioticians were nominalists, who viewed significations as looming in the language itself. But none of them, as far as I know, has spoken about one of their predecessors, one of the founders of Parisian salons in the seventeenth century, Madeleine de Scudéry, another semiotician malgré lui, who, similar to Umberto Eco, came to the realization that signs are created so as to enable us to lie. A plethora of literary salons emerged in Paris in the mid-seventeenth century, and their keepers considered themselves to belong to a community of the precious (Les Précieuses). lived in a fictive, novelesque world, in which they created literary portraits, but hiding them behind pseudonyms borrowed from ancient mythology. The precious had their own codes of behavior. They said, for instance, that in the

110 | 5 The world and its interpretation production of enjoyment, imagination means more than reality. When one sins only in one’s fantasies, one does not commit sin in reality. One could convey one’s emotions only to those who knew how to appreciate them. A thought had no worth if everyone understood it. A true “precious” had to speak differently from other people, so that his thoughts would be understood only by his equals. Henrick Schück, the Swedish literary historian, has picked up some metaphors used by the precious: les enfants de l’air, children of the air, meant sighs; les chers souffrants, dear sufferers, meant feet. Chairs were called les commodités de la conversation. With such private language, criticisms could be made milder. For instance, if one wanted to say, “There is nothing good about this book”, one could say instead, “L’on ne trouve point de quoi s’arrester dans ce livre” (We find little to dwell on in this book). An ugly girl might be called une belle à faire peur (a beauty who frightens one). Some of the metaphors they invented have remained in general use; for instance, “His forehead became clouded” and “to mask one’s thoughts” (Schück 1961: 104). The precious became so famous that Molière wrote his comedy Les Précieuses ridicules in order to parodize them. In this play one finds the following scene, which takes place in a theater loge: Magdeon: Apprenez, sotte, à vous énoncer moins vulgairement. Dites: “Voila un nécessaire, qui demande si vous êtes en commodité d’être visible.” Marotte: Dame! Je n’entends point de latin et je n’ai pas appris, comme vous la filofie dans le Grand Cyre. (Magdeon, pointing to indicating the loge: Learn, stupid, to express yourself less vulgarly. Say instead: “Oh there is the necessity which demands that you permit the commodity to be visible.” Marotte: Dear lady! I cannot at all understand Latin, and unlike you I have not learned the beautiful language of the Great Cyrus.”)

Marotte is referring to the gigantic novel by Madeleine de Scudéry, Le Grand Cyrus, which takes place in the ancient Persia, but whose protagonists were in fact members of the “precious” literary salons of Paris, and were based upon their literary portraits. The precious particularly admired the Queen of Sweden, whose literary interests had made a strong impact on Parisians. Not only was Scudéry’s novel enchanting to the precious, it also holds the world record for being the longest novel ever written, consisting of about 10,000 pages in its original form. Today Le Grande Cyrus is available on the internet, as well as in edited book form. Highly readable, even with its Baroque nuances in orthography, the novel’s plot is not so fanciful as one might first imagine. Why do we return to such a world? Because Madeleine de Scudéry represents another precursor of the semiotic movement. What is semiotics if not everyday phenomena described in special terms and conceptual metalanguage, which only

5.2 Closing thoughts | 111

the initiated can understand? Semiotics prides itself on being an international language of scholars, whether from Europe, Africa, China, or Persia. Those who identify themselves as Peirceans, Greimassians, Lotmanians, or existential semioticians – they always understand each other. Whether others understand them is another matter, and one that is perhaps not so important. Umberto Eco said that semiotics is a method whereby simple things can be made complex. This, indeed, was the goal of Les Précieuses! From this premise, several variants later developed. For Mikhail Bakhtin the world was a dialogue. No concept was valid as such, but only as it belonged to a dialogue, where it represented either familiar or alien speech. From this it follows that concepts are ultimately unpredictable; hence the end result of a dialogue cannot be known by anyone in advance. Bakhtin took as his model the “polyphonic” novel by Dostoevsky, which constituted a kind of interplay of consciousnesses. Another variant of this view is that the world is a constant translation from one language to another, and not only from language, but from one culture to another. Peeter Torop, in his theory of translation, combines Bakhtin’s thought with that of Yuri Lotman, founder of the Tartu-Moscow school of semiotics. For Lotman, the world consisted in the movement between culture and non-culture, and the “translation” of non-culture into culture. The Tartu school presumed that somewhere inside a culture, in its deep level, existed a kind of generator of structurality, from which the semiosphere emerged, the latter being a continuum of signs that enable the social life of humanity, as the biosphere enables its biological life. Another Tartu semiotician, Peet Lepik, has pondered the universality of Lotman’s theory and its connections to the magical-mythical world view. Thomas A. Sebeok, one of the leading semioticians of the twentieth century, introduced the idea that the world is a global semiosis, in which our “semiotic self” lives between illusion and reality. In fact, Sebeok once argued that semiotics does not study the world at all, but rather our illusions about it. Finally, our world is also one of action, which returns us to our early thoughts on the subject’s choices. Augusto Ponzio, in his work on communication, states that we also have the freedom to choose non-functionality, diritto all’infunzionalità, which brings us back to Heidegger’s principle of letting things go, Gelassenheit.

5.2 Closing thoughts I have not yet stated my own world view, but perhaps it has become clear from the reflections above. In my model of the world, I endeavor to create a kind of system that takes its place alongside French nominalism, the Hegelian principle of con-

112 | 5 The world and its interpretation tinuity, and the world of the body. My vision is much like what Lévi-Strauss meant by his notion of bricolage. One makes culture of what is at hand and by what man is as a body. Some thinkers would say that everything is body. This, however, almost amounts to a reification of the body. Man is all the time corporeal, true, but he also strives continuously to transcend, to exceed the body’s boundaries; without doing so, he simply cannot stay comfortable in his own skin. Therefore the human mind, the world of one’s Dasein, is based upon the two principles expounded in various places in this book: Me and Society (as internalized), Moi and Soi. A constant tension exists between the two, but there is also liberation from this eternal struggle by transcendence, in the Kantian sense. Semiotics is a doubly transcendental science. On the one hand, by signs we refer to what is not present; signs detach us from the primitive reality, which leads to metaphors, symbols, and allegories. On the other hand, what we do with signs – each act of communication – is a transcendental act, since the object and goal of the communication is a projection from subject A to subject B, a “leap” toward the Other, the unknown, alien-psyche.

Chapter 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape 6.1 Introduction Central scientific and other kinds of problems are often very simple in nature. This holds true for a theme such as “environment”. Yet we must immediately expand the notion a little: a surrounding cannot be thought without the thinking of something that it surrounds. This “something” can be any phenomenon whatsoever that captures our attention: people, work, an act, behavior, an event – anything whatsoever that distinguishes itself something with limits, as the center of something, as something discrete – in a word, as something which has an environment. Let us refer to this center with the term “subject”, evoking at the same time its etymology in English or in French as sujet, which may refer not only to a person, but also to a topic, matter, issue. From this more general, almost naïve standpoint we encounter such universal problems as the relationship of a subject to its environment. Do surrounding conditions determine one’s life? or is the fate of the subject determined by what is within him or her? In other words, Are our activities predestined by genes and biology? or guided by education, culture, society or the environment? Generally, in any theory the emphasis will go to one or the other. Of course what is involved is the dialectics between the inner and outer, between endosemiosis and exosemiosis (as said in the theory of Uexküll), or between the interoceptive and the exteroceptive, as A. J. Greimas put it. The Finnish educational philosopher J. A. Hollo had the idea that man was something between these two entities. Our self is the domain in which we can make choices and decisions which can partly negate or refute, improve or fight against biological determinism and/or change the environment into something more favorable (insofar as it is negative) for the goals, aspirations, growth, intentions and development of this “self”. We have arrived at the domain of the existential, the significance and cogency of which no doubt depend on which factor we stress more, the environment or the subject.

6.2 Milieu – Taine In the philosophy of arts one of the best-known theories of milieu is that by the French aesthetician Hippolyte Taine, one which has continued to have impact

114 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape thought, to greater or lesser degrees, from the nineteenth century to the present. According to Taine, art was necessarily and irrefutably the product of its environment. Such a view was “naturally” understandable amidst the general optimism of la belle époque when the theory was formulated, since it has an inbuilt ideology stemming from the view that Paris was the best possible environment in which to exercise artistic and spiritual-intellectual gifts; during those periods when the city was not like that, an optimism reigned that things could be turned around, and the environment bettered. Taine opens his study: “We have to first admit the fact that an artwork is not a detached or separate phenomenon, and we have to show that connection on which it is dependent and which explains it”. The first such “connection”, environment or paradigm where Taine situates art is in the total output of the author. The second is given by other artists of the same country or period, schools and “artist families”. The third environment is broader still: . . . the world which surrounds it and whose taste is similar to it . . . The state of the customs and spiritual life influences the artist and his audience, and they are not at all separated from other people . . . behind their voices . . . we distinguish so to say a distant murmur, infinite and multiple voice of the people which as a joint choir sings around them . . . .

Illustrations of Taine’s conception of the environment appear in the work of several artists of his time, beginning with writers such as Émile Zola and Gustave Flaubert. Their novels exhibit a naturalist aesthetics as well as protagonists presented as both products and victims of the conditions of their time. Very much like Zola and Taine is our Finnish sculptor Ville Vallgren in the most congenial works of his Parisian period, such as Misère, Désespoir (1893), Malédiction (1899), La Douleur (1917). The dysphoric nature of these works set them apart from Vallgren’s other creations, which generally follow the sunny disposition of la belle époque, with its cheerful praise of the joys of life. In Vallgren’s works just listed, disaster envelopes people; it surrounds them as a weighty fog, as a crushing, depressing fate. These persons are not responsible for their unhappiness; it is caused, rather, by a harsh environment and unjust society. Hence one can see in such works a social critique of the type of Zola. But at the same time, there is a kind of beauty in them. Vallgren knew Zola personally and certainly read his works, insofar as he read anything at all. In addition, Vallgren’s sculptures extend the heritage of naturalism and of French classicism. This view of environment and subject is, in an interesting way, “modern” in the historic sense of the word, if one thinks of later theoreticians of these subjects. As early as in the 1950’s, the Belgian structuralist Lucien Goldmann, in his book Le dieu caché, was arguing that to explain a work meant inserting it into everexpanding surroundings and circles. For example, to explain Racine’s tragedies

6.3 Surrounding/surrounded

| 115

and Pascal’s Pensées, one has to relate them to the seventeenth-century religious movement called Jansenism, which in turn cannot be analyzed without locating it in the larger structure(s) of French society. And so on. At the same time, explanation works in the other direction as well: inwardly, towards the center, towards understanding. A “burrowing” into these circles, which, at the least, calls for close reading of Racine and Pascal, is indisposable if one wants to understand seventeenth-century French society. At the core of this understanding lies the “text”, with its structures and messages. The theory outlined thus far establishes a clear distinction between environment and “subject”. But is this relation as unambiguous as Taine and Goldmann and many other sociological theorists have claimed? Does knowledge of the environment permit us to infer the kinds of subjects that will inhabit it? Or does such knowledge predict the kinds of works and acts that will take place there? Hardly. For the relation between environment and subject is not one of organic unfolding, but rather one of transformations, ruptures, re-evaluations, re-proportioning, and so on. So many things can take place in one’s environment, that the individual is in no way, nor at all times, at the mercy of his surroundings. The semiotic perspective mostly shares in this view: the sign is an autonomous unit, and although it may take place in the most rudimentary situation of communication (following Jakobson’s model of sender-message-receiver), the sign is also independent of that situation. Sign and art-work are detached from all their surroundings. The relationship is not a causal one between sign and society, or gender, or body, or any external thing whatsoever. Rather, the relationship is strictly semiotic one. We can come back to this problem when pondering the nature of communication, and whether it represents a kind of causal issue or not. The sign-surroundings relationship can be articulated in many ways, which Peirce demonstrated as early as when he distinguished his sign categories of icons, indexes, and symbols. It is thus easy to understand why semiotics, the study of signs, is unpopular in any totalitarian ideology. Semiotics allows for the liberty of sign and subject to work out their own relation with the environment, which can never completely determine that relation as much as some totalitarian, fascist, and other despotic systems of government have tried to do. Still, the will to control and dominate remains the main one of any administrational system, particularly in the present world of technosemiotic and global marketing.

6.3 Surrounding/surrounded For a different view of the problem at hand, I turn now to the founder of the Paris school of semiotics, A. J. Greimas, and to his notions of surrounding/surrounded

116 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape (englobant/englobé). In one of his early works, Sémantique structurale (1967), Greimas theorizes this pair of notions for the first time. This happens in the last chapter of his treatise when he is analyzing a novel by Georges Bernanos, Le journal d’un curée de campagne. As known, that analysis is based upon the functioning of the general category of life/death, which Greimas will later come to consider the fundamental axiological model of an individual. In this case, however, the category serves as a kind of deixis: one can be dead even when alive, or alive when dead. A person’s very existence is based on these categories, which are two contradictory terms that complement and complete each other at the level of one’s noological essence. In a way, this category surrounds all the events of the novel by Bernanos. Greimas claims to have borrowed the notions of englobé/englobant from existentialist philosopher Karl Jaspers, and he prefers them over the similar notions of contenant/contenu. Greimas says that the general category of englobé/englobant is not a particular feature in Bernanos, but rather serves as a bridge whereby “. . . one can move unnoticed from the ‘abstract’ to the figurative by transforming concepts into actants, or ideas into functions.” (Greimas 1966: 226) Greimas then scrutinizes all the semes of the novel in this light, ending with a complete formulation of their taxonomies and a definitive transformational model of the Bernanosian universe. Greimas’s analysis is of interest mainly in its treatment of existential problems; at the same time, it is a completely structuralist project. The main protagonist meets with a tragic end, and the actor of death destroys his body from the inside. The novel as such is a proof of Tainean milieu theory, but here it comes about on the interoceptive axis. The basic problematic of the novel thus restates the irreconcilable and irreducible conflict between the subject and his/her environment. In general, the semiotic view on the central issue of environment/subject or surrounding/surrounded sparked and continues to spark new types of theories, especially in philosophies of anthropology. The structuralist view of course emphasizes the role of the environment. In fact, the subject qua subject ultimately vanishes and is only a product of his surrounding system, an intersection of systems; the subject disappears as soon as our systems of knowledge take on new configurations, as Michel Foucault argued in his influential The Order of Things (1). In this matter, Foucault’s thought agreed with that of Lévi-Strauss, whose basic enterprise in his Structural Anthropology (1963) was to study the categories of nature and culture – both of which were viewed as surrounding man, not representing him. This view argued that no unit, term, lexeme, sign, or subject was significant as such but only as a part of its context, environment, and structure. This fundamental belief was shared by Yuri Lotman and the Tartu-Moscow School, and as such is classic structuralism in its thoroughgoing relativity, and the fact

6.4 New models of communication |

117

that all these authors emphasize that no sign or text can function alone, isolated from other signs. Such a continuum, which both enables one’s social life and surrounds us, was as we know christened the “semiosphere” by Lotman. Furthermore, Lotman and his group argued vigorously that every culture is surrounded by the sphere of disorganisation, which pre-existing cultural groups attempt to conquer and change into a culture. All science starts with the presupposition that any phenomenon under examination is situated in its proper environment. That phenomenon can, for instance, be paradigmatic; that is to say, the phenomenon is seen as one case among all the various alternatives, which either exist alongside this phenomenon or as some of its numerous possibilities. Another scientific point of departure is to situate a given phenomenon within the intertextual network, in the milieu that genetically “causes” or produces this phenomenon as a “subject”. This could be considered a kind of syntagmatic environment, in which the phenomenon is connected, by various relations of metonymy, with its surrounding elements. In the case of biography, one who studies the subject and its environment can embed his subject in a network of two kinds of relations, one “syntagmatic” and the other “paradigmatic”. Let us presume, for example, that we are studying Sibelius. In speaking of his famous biography of the composer, eminent musicologist Erik Tawaststjerna said his method was similar to that of Thomas Mann and Marcel Proust: Sibelius was portrayed via his contemporaries, which included painter Gallen-Kallela, writer Adolf Paul, conductor Robert Kajanus, friend Axel Carpelan, composer Ferruccio Busoni, and others. These all stood in a syntagmatic relation to the Finnish master. On the other hand are “paradigmatic” relations. Regarding Sibelius’s oeuvre, for example, Tawaststjerna compared the composer’s output to that of other actors in the same field, who offered alternative solutions, yet in absentia: Mahler, Strauss, Wagner, Schönberg, Debussy, and so on. There were also subjects (e.g., Busoni) who occupied both syntagmatic and paradigmatic roles; that is to say, people who influenced Sibelius musically, aesthetically, and in other paradigmatic ways, and who were at the same time his contemporaries, sharing in the same “syntagmatic” course of events, which included artistic milieu, historical events, and the like.

6.4 New models of communication But an opposing view is shared by the “new” semiotics, in which, to our surprise, biosemiotics and existential semiotics agree. They share a central claim, namely, that the environment does not dominate the subject but, rather, the other way round: the subject determines the environment. In fact the subject, by virtue of its

118 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape “choices”, “determines” the kind of milieu in which it lives. The theory of social construction plays an in-between role, with its view that each sign, term, text or personality is a construed unit that could also be otherwise. Hence, they are all products of surrounding structures and systems. Yet, since these structures are essentially arbitrary and not dictated by nature, they can be changed, and it is the subject which has the power to change them! On this point – that the subject can make its own possibilities – biosemiotics and existential semiotics agree. In an ordinary communication model, such as that by Jakobson (mentioned above) or the one by Shannon and Weaver, the center is the message, and sometimes the person. But this subject is surrounded by other conditions of communication. Ultimately, the whole communication is framed by external conditions, or “reality”. The decisive factor here is “context”, since it constitutes the environment of communication. At least it is clear that sometimes we may have two superimposed functions or that two aspects can be stressed at the same time; for example, an artist or a politician, when launching new ideas, at the same time creates the environment that is appropriate for them. Wagner creates Bayreuth, functionalists Bauhaus, semioticians Imatra, and so on. But normally, the simultaneous operating of two functions is too much. Just as it is almost impossible to receive both code and message at the same time, it is hard to pay equal attention to both message and context. If the context is underlined, then no attention is given to the message, which then acts as a side-effect. The same holds true for the relation of code/context. If in some situation all of one’s attention goes into the effort to speak correctly or behave in the right manner, then one cannot enjoy the context; for example, a celebration or ceremony. Any element can cease to be pertinent if attention is focused on other elements that surround it. New models can be sketched that augment and improve our own, rather schematic view of communication. I have delineated five new variants which could be taken into account (see Figure 6.1). All of these cases display different ways our subject relates to its “object”, its environment, or even also to another subject.

6.5 Umwelt and Uexküll As a contrast to theories stressing the role of surroundings, semiotic models have emerged which instead emphasize the centrality of the subject as the “surrounded”. A theory of biosemiotics was developed just before the middle of the last century by the Estonian biologist Jakob von Uexküll, though his thought has begun to influence semiotics heavily only during the last decades (with the exception

6.5 Umwelt and Uexküll |

119

Figure 6.1: Models of communication

of Italy, where, according to Ugo Volli, he became known as early as the 1960’s due to his activities in Naples). The fundaments of Uexküll’s thinking were presented in his concise essay, “Bedeutungslehre” (1940). Among other revelations, the essay shows that approaches to biological research have not all been based on a Comtean or “positivistic” sense of determinism, but contrarily, that much biological discourse takes place in argumentation that at times comes to sound rather metaphysical. According to Uexküll, movement in nature is not mechanically causal, but is based upon two meaningful processes: Merken – to signify – and Wirken – to react, to influence. He believed that any object whatsoever can serve as a carrier of meaning (Bedeutungsträger). This means two things: either the object is

120 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape a Merkmalträger (sign carrier) received by a subject, or it is this subject, whom Uexküll calls the “meaning receiver” (Bedeutungsempfänger). A subject must have a special Merkmalorgan in order to receive it. The most important observation by Uexküll is that each organism lives in its own subjective universe of signs, which he calls the Umwelt. Objectively speaking, there is no single Umwelt common to all species. For instance, to one hiking in a meadow, the “meadow” represents completely different realities, depending on whether the hiker is an insect, cow, human being, or even another part of the field itself (say, a plant swaying in the wind). Uexküll compares each organism to a kind of clock mechanism, whose alarm starts to ring when we activate certain mechanisms. Those mechanisms are signs of the Umwelt, which accepts the mechanisms as its Bedeutungsträger. To Uexküll, every organism has its own Ich Ton, its own “me tone”. These tones altogether constitute the Lebenston, the “life-tone” of the organism. The semiotic nature of Jakob v. Uexküll’s theory has been further elucidated by his son, Thure v. Uexküll. As bases for my own reflections, I have tried to use his ideas concerning two kinds of signs, namely, endosigns and exosigns. We are far from the positivists’ thesis of reducibility, i.e., that phii phenomena could without residue be translated into f-phenomena; rather, it is the other way around. We try to solve the problem of what it means when we speak about nature and organism as epistemic categories. Thure von Uexküll thought that his father’s Umweltslehre fitted particularly well together with Peirce’s triadic semiotics. But there is no reason to presume that Peirce’s is the only semiotic theory compatible with the idea of Umwelt. For instance, the notion of Umwelt is doubtless akin to Greimas’s “isotopy” and Lotman’s “semiosphere” (or more specifically, Lotman’s notion of culture). An organism, semiotic actor, or subject can fall, says Uexküll, into an Umwelt or isotopy that might or might not be one of its own. It can fall into the semiosphere of its own or into one outside it. Every culture likewise has its own Ich-Ton by which it recognizes and identifies the signs around it (Merkung) and in turn functions and acts (Wirkung) in the sphere of non-culture which surrounds it. What does not belong to Umwelt, belongs to Otherness.

6.6 Dasein . . . Let’s move now from biosemiotics to existential semiotic views of the concept of surrounding/surrounded. We could take as a motto a scene from the end of Goethe’s Faust II. Faust, now in his old age and gripped by a progressive optimism, has started to turn wild marshes into manageable fields, and launched many other environmental projects which he believes will benefit humankind. He has, among

6.6 Dasein . . .

|

121

other things, ordered the burning of a hut, the home of two old persons (Filemon and Baucis), in order to make space for his projects. But suddenly four sorcerers arrive uninvited at his palace: Sorge, Mangel, Schuld, and Not (Sorrow, Need, Guilt, and Worry). Faust refuses to admit their power, even when Sorrow blows upon him and says, “People are blind all their lives, now you Faust become blind at the end of your way!” Faust loses his sight, but rebuffs Sorrow by taking the loss as a gain: “Die Nacht scheint tiefer tief hereinzudringen / Allein im Innern leuchtet helles Licht.” This scene from Faust foregrounds the problem of surrounding and subject in a new manner. The environment, the surrounding, is dark, gloomy, and evil, but its center, the surrounded, is internally illuminated and good. This is what Jaspers meant by his concepts of Existenzerhellung. Correspondingly, one can imagine a situation in which the surrounded is evil whereas the environment is good. In that way, we bring an ethical value judgement into our distinction. In fact, present here is the whole emergence of semiotics as a part of the project of the “modern”. First of all, man exists prior to the Cartesian question, a part of the predetermined cosmos and its order. Hence there is no difference between both subject and environment experienced as cosmos. But then man becomes aware of himself as a separate being, as a discrete sign, semiotically speaking, along with the principle of the cogito, and as a consequence man tries to rediscover his lost unity with the cosmos. Since he has distinguished himself from his Umwelt, he has to express himself with particular signs and assume that via these signs he will be heard and understood. This is simply the origin of the concept of sign according to existential semiotics: signs are needed in order to mediate between man and his environment. As long as one is a part of cosmos, however, he does not need what Husserl called the Ausdruck, or “expressive”, aspect of signs. In existential semiotics, the subject is surrounded in a double sense; first, by his Dasein, his existence, which includes other subjects and objects. This relationship becomes “narrativized”, which is to say that such models are valid here whose catalyzing force is desire, Trieb; the subject strives for an object and tries to take possession of it. Either he is disjuncted from it, which launches all narration, or he has gained it, become conjuncted with it, and is satisfied, such that the inner movement of the Dasein is at rest and remains mere being. In Greimas’s theory, both subjects and objects are modal and modalized entities. In the subjunctive words of art related to semiotic modalization, they Know, Can, Want, Must (have obligations), and Believe something and in something regarding other subjects. An essential addition to this universe of classical semiotics is the introduction of the notion of transcendence into existential semiotics, which surrounds even the Dasein. The concept of transcendence brings with it

122 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape extremely complex philosophical-conceptual problems, since one can think that values “dwell” in the transcendence in a virtual state and from there exercise their impact on the existence of people. After all, ultimately a major part of humankind’s Dasein takes place as a dialectic between Dasein and transcendence, since it belongs to the mere concept of sign that the physical part of sign, sign as a sign vehicle, refers to and that yields something which is invisible, inaudible, unobservable, which is absent but present at the same time, since it is remembered and can be recalled by the use of a sign. A basic gift of being human is our ability to transcend, to exit in our mind the present deixis, hic nunc ego. Upon this ability is based all imagination, the logic of possible worlds, as well as the capacity to form metalanguage, to agree that with the latter I can transcend my present language, I step outside it, I observe and reflect upon it.

6.7 . . . and transcendence A major part of our existence takes place alongside our imagining of reality and in the dialectics between Dasein and transcendence. Transcendence is therefore not something that surrounds us in the same sense as space surrounds us and the earth, but is present all the time. Transcendence is an aspect of reality, since the ways we conceive it, at every moment, influence our actions, acts, and ways of being in Dasein. Resorting to this fundamental nature of reality and existence, it would be as reasonable to attempt to reduce everything into transcendental concepts, as Plato did, the difference being that they are reduced to sensory data of common-sense experience. What is involved is an epistemic choice. Where is transcendence located? It is most commonly imagined to be an empty space that surrounds Dasein. In existential semiotics, I have so far outlined two ways of viewing transcendence: (1) either as emptiness, le Néant, or (2) as plenitude, fullness. Both views have philosophical kin, both forerunners and in the present: Nothingness or emptiness among the existentialists, and plenitude (kerygma, fullness) among the gnostics. Yet transcendence can also be situated in relation to the temporal axis of human beings or other organisms, in the category of life/death, as the state that both precedes life and that comes after it. The latter alternative leads to the origin of religion as a particular semiotic inference about what happens to the subject after life. Into what kind of “environment” is the subject then shifted? We find a musical “speculation” on this question by Edward Elgar, the British composer, who wrote an oratorio called The Dream of Gerontius, which consists of two parts. The first one, rather short, takes place in the “Dasein”, so to say, and the latter in

6.7 . . . and transcendence |

123

transcendence. Likewise, the main emphasis in Dante’s Divine Comedy is on the latter. Let us assume, however, that transcendence can be inhabited by such entities as values, and that perhaps something remains there after the wanderings of our subject in Dasein – how can this be logically-conceptually thinkable? If life in the environment of Dasein were characterized by modalities, could then “life” in transcendence be represented by something like “metamodalities”? Are, for instance, values waiting there, as ideas to be actualised and realised in Dasein, such that metamodalities would mediate or “control the traffic” between Dasein and transcendence? If we still cannot imagine our subject as such as an entity carrying modalities in transcendence, then is there any sense in extending the discussion so as to speak in this respect of kinds of “metamodalities”? They are of course hypotheses, abductive inferences of the nature of transcendence, which are partly based upon certain observations on certain phenomena in Dasein, which cannot be explained other than as consequences of certain phenomena in transcendence. Such knowledge is naturally very uncertain, since there can be another hypothesis that could explain these phenomena as well. Transcendence would, in the Peircean sense, be an abductive presumption that emerges from such reasoning as follows: 1. a certain phenomenon perceived in the Dasein: an act of kindness, aesthetic experience, revelation of truth . . . . 2. a rule: the notions of goodness, beauty, truth are transcendental, transgressing the boundaries of our Dasein . . . . 3. therefore: these perceived phenomena fulfil transcendence amidst Dasein. One might well imagine a counter-argument, based, say, on such a theory as Platonism: 1. a certain perceived phenomenon as above . . . . 2. rule: under certain circumstances people behave like that . . . . 3. this phenomenon belongs exclusively to the domain of such phenomena, and we do not need a concept such as transcendence in order to explain it. In modern terms: What kind of functional environment plays host to our notions of value, soul, metamodalities, and the like, and forms the environment of “transcendence”? This argument comes close to the so-called “transcendental argument” by Charles Taylor, as Sami Pihlström (2002) has pointed out. Namely, certain human behaviours, especially in the moral and ethical field, cannot be explained by mere “pragmatist” or “natural” criteria without supposing they have a kind of transcendental existence (see Pihlström 2002: 14)

124 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape What kind of Umwelt is it? In his overview of ecosemiotics, in his Handbuch der Semiotik, the section on Kultursemiotische Modelle der Mensch-Umwelt-Beziehung, Winfried Nöth presumes that the view of the omnipresence of sign on all levels of human environment leads to pansemiotics, which explains all phenomena of environment as signs. He distinguishes three subcategories: (1) the properly pansemiotic view, which is not far away from Peirce’s idea that the “. . . whole universe is perfused by signs, unless it right away consists of them”. The philosophy of Peirce’s synechism, moreover, argued that in such a universe all signs would be interdependent. Peirce would not have had any logical difficulties here, although he did not have a theory of subject, which would have been carrying such signs of the universe. He even used the metaphor of evolutionary love or connected such very modal entities to the formation of the universe and the “semiotic web”.

6.8 Semiosphere, Lotman and Ruskin Likewise, Lotman’s idea of semiosphere is such a pansemiotic model. Even he had a theory of a subject carrying the semiosphere, a subject that could as well be a collective unit; and this theory was limited within a speech of culture. But when culture was determined as a group of texts, he never discussed the essential empirical problem that would come to the mind of a sociologist or British anthropologist, namely, which social group or indigenous tribe would produce and use such texts. In the pansemiotic model, signs thus do not have a particular “sender” occupying that spot on the communication model. In this sense, the pansemiotic model means a return to pre-Cartesian, cosmological thinking, albeit without well-founded theological reasoning (cf. Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self ). It was thus not at all naïve when a Lithuanian student once asked Thomas A. Sebeok, Are you a pantheist? Instead, according to Nöth another species of Umwelt thought was the magical model in which the environment also transmits signs, but their manipulator was man and Nature the receiver, in which one wants to produce a certain phenomenon by this activity. (Tzvetan Todorov has studied the discourse of magic in this light.) The third alternative is the mythological model in which the environment is narrativized; it is transformed into a battlefield of agent and acts superior to humankind (Northrop Frye’s mythological mode of storytelling). These stories in turn explain why certain matters have been allowed entry and initiated into the Dasein. Such mythical stories, then – the immediate empirical Dasein of our subject to another environment, namely, that of transcendence – can mediate the relationship between these two surroundings.

6.9 Heidegger’s view

| 125

Accordingly, mythology and mythical stories provide us with an excellent source if we want to clarify whether the semiotic notions of the world of Dasein remain valid in transcendence. Since prehistoric times, they have been kinds of abductive models of the average man about transcendence and its nature, and particularly its impact on Dasein. If one reads, for instance, a handbook of mythology on Antiquity or Kalevala, and observes how certain mythological persons behave in transcendence, one notices that the logic of their sanctions, taboos, modalities and so on are remarkably similar to the ones applied in Dasein. But a great difference remains: they can enact modalities and modalisations which considerably transgress the limits of everyday modalities. Yet, which part of such a mythology is mere mythologism, which is apt as a topic of art yet is no longer believed, and which part is the primary mythicism? John Ruskin warned against projecting one’s emotions and modalities upon nature, and invented the term “pathetic fallacy” to portray such fallacious reasoning. If the landscape seemed melancholic, this was merely a projection of our own, human emotions, a pathetic fallacy. In this view, modalities could not exist beyond our human world of Dasein. An essential question is what kind of theory of subject would be necessary in order for the existential semiotic vision of two Daseins and transcendence to be correct and functional. What is involved is obviously not a theory of empirical self in the line of John Locke, David Hume, Bertrand Russell. It must be another type of subject theory.

6.9 Heidegger’s view In Heidegger’s philosophy we of course meet the concept of Umwelt. He says in his Sein und Zeit: “Die nächste Welt des alltäglichen Dasein ist die Umwelt” (1967: 66). (The closest of world of our daily being-there is environment.) To his mind, “Um-” part of the word “Umwelt” contains a reference to spatiality (Räumlichkeit). He refers to the concept of worldliness. In the background looms the ontology which spatializes the “world”, according to which the world is seen as a kind of res extensa or dimensional space, whose opposition would be res cogitans, or man. In other words, man/subject has separated himself as a discrete cogitans, a conceiving subject in this world. Now we can ask to what extent the existential semiotic concepts of Dasein and transcendence are as such a notion related to Umwelt, or whether in this context they change into something too spatializing. Heidegger believes that Umwelt essentially entails the notion of being-with: we are in an environment in which there are tools and cares, concrete things and practical activities; nature becomes

126 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape concrete, but is not exhausted therein: the plants of the botanist are not the same plants as those growing in a field. Heidegger’s world is not identical with the practical interests of caring or being concerned. It is typical that he introduces his concepts of sign precisely at this moment. His theory is compatible with that of Lotman in the sense that each sign manifests the idea of concreteness and position in the world as a whole, or it is established in its semiosphere or isotopy. Nevertheless, Heidegger does not postulate the ontology of sign by transcendence or with the fact that it is in the essence of a sign to refer to something which is not present. Contrarily, signs and tools always refer to that context to which they belong. This has as its consequence that signs occupy, so to say, their correct and predestined place in the environment. In Heidegger’s world things are in their proper places; they have their own ontology. In his vision the world is revealed or uncovered, and things find their places by themselves. His subject is not the same as the one of existential semiotics, who, as said above, between the environment and biological codes is capable of action and deciding where signs belong and how they are used. In the world of existential semiotics, signs are not automatically in their proper places as part of a kind of “generative” iconicoontological process, as I have dared to characterize the systems of both Heidegger and Greimas. When he speaks of the boundaries of the environment, Heidegger evokes a mode of being best called interiority: “This means that the extensional being is itself closed by some extensional which by its boundaries surrounds it” (Heidegger 1967: 135). Therefore both the interior and the surroundings – or as Greimas more elegantly put it, englobé/englobant – are in space. A tool has, to his “mind”, its place, and it is situated all around: es liegt herum . . . . Place is not here interpreted arbitrarily as something in which things are presented. Place is always a given “there” or “area” to which a tool belongs. This area to which things belong is for Heidegger “the surrounding domain” (Gegend). Quite correctly Heidegger notes that we often become aware of this belonging to a certain place only “when something is encountered that is not in its proper place”, something has fallen into the wrong surroundings. Greimas would say, into a “false isotopy”. It would be erroneous, though, to identify Heidegger’s theory of environment with such objects as signs and tools, since it essentially includes other beings. Being is to be-with. The problem of the “who” of being is resolved by the fact that being-there is always being of myself. It is self-evident to his mind. Thereafter come others of “myself,” or das Man and other public forms of being, in which the “me” relinquishes its being of itself into “das Man”. Now, Heidegger does have a theory of subject. But essential here is that the transcendence surrounding the Dasein cannot be spatialised except with great difficulties. Transcendence rather appears as a certain illumination of the Dasein, as Jaspers thought, or as Heidegger

6.9 Heidegger’s view

| 127

would say: as a mode of being or Stimmung and Befindlichkeit (kinds of a tunement). Physically and spatially we are amidst the Dasein as a certain actor ego, but when we start to exist our being is seen with different eyes and heard with different ears; it becomes significant by the fact that we compare it to the transcendental value or idea. In such a moment of existing, the Dasein experiences either a transascendance, as Jean Wahl put it – it becomes illuminated with the fullness of transcendence and its significance – or it undergoes trans-descendence, a plunge into emptiness. Dasein is filled altogether by the transcendence surrounding it. Our transcendental metamodality can well be in contradiction with the modalities of our Dasein. Our knowing concerns only empirical being; it is mere Wissen; whereas the transcendental knowing would be Kennen to use the terms of the Lithuanian-Finnish philosopher, Wilhelm Sesemann; that is to say, it is something subjectively experienced, something interoceptive, not exteroceptive. Paradoxically, transcendence does not surround us in our Dasein as a physical space, as a kind of space beyond the limits of Dasein. Rather, it opens within us. It is thus a manner by which the surrounded reacts to the surrounding, just as in the closing scene from Faust that I quoted above. Our will strives for desirable objects in the Dasein in order to possess them; it strives for conjunction – which may presuppose the disjunction of those objects from others, since we are living in the world of competency. By contrast, our transcendental meta-will is wanting tinged by the existential experience, for instance, in artistic creation, scientific research, or ethical service (Kundry’s “Dienen, Dienen”). There is truth in what John Cage once told Daniel Charles, namely, that there is poetry as soon as we notice we do not possess anything! The subject does not want anything in a dyadic but triadic relationship. What is involved is not only subject and object, but subject, object AND some presign or postsign, which as an enunciant or as an interpretant filters our experience of act-sign. According to Peirce, the most primitive pragmatic relations of life are dyadic, like the brute facts of desire; they become semiotic only in a triadic sign relationship. This holds true in existential semiotics as well. The third element which enlightens subject and object, ego and its surroundings, or that part of the surroundings which he wants or which serves as the object of his care (Heidegger’s Sorge, Greimas’s vouloir, i.e., will) is precisely the transcendental idea or value, the conceiving of which is a metamodal activity. What then happens in us when we start to exist or experience our Dasein in the light of transcendence? The analysis of our existential moments can help us clarify the nature of transcendence, and the best means for this is certainly art. In existential semiotics, the terms Umwelt and subject adopt a quite new and special meaning. Umwelt is, so to say, purged of its rough empirical content, and in this context the speech of ecosemiotics in a practical sense is perhaps mislead-

128 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape ing. Still, the idea fits well here insofar as ecosemiotics includes the critique of language and use of language or of sign in the negative sense, as a pollutant of environment. A semiosphere can be destroyed or polluted not only by the fact that a culture decides to eliminate certain texts, but also, as Heidegger said, by the fact that our public being in the world sinks into the being of anyone at all in das Man. This is exemplified by average ways of being, by gossiping, and other negative phenomena whereby our environment is polluted. According to Nöth, if our signs were basically anthropomorphic and therefore we were responsible for them, this would lead us into a kind of mental ecology. He says: No one can deny that our semiotic Umwelt would be conceptually and ideologically as distorted and polluted as it is visually and acoustically. So our subject has to admit that the Dasein enlightened by transcendence does not look beautiful at all. How this is the case becomes evident by the growing experience of our subject. But how it should be, becomes clear by how the subject conceives of transcendence and how he can adjust his Dasein according to its measures. At the end of Goethe’s tragedy Faust is an old man, but even though he is blind, he thinks himself progressive. But he errs when he believes that sounds of hooks, by the lemurs and Mephisto, are noises of the labour by which he prepares a place for future generations. There is deep irony in the fact that, in reality, they are digging Faust’s grave. But that is something he does not know, since thereafter the reader or spectator is truly moved into transcendence, in which a choir of mountain spirits – which no longer inhabit any concrete place or environment – closes the drama. Faust believes that he hears within himself the voice of transcendence, but his inner “light” is an illusion – from the viewpoint of Dasein’s modalities, but not in relation to transcendental metamodalities, since the selfish wanting of Faust has been transformed into an eternal striving and aspiration which in the end saves him.

6.10 Subject and environment In closing, I will put together our observations on the environment and subject, the surrounding and the surrounded, and ask if there is a theory that would “surround” and cover all other theories. Greimas once said, when visiting Canada, to an unknown Anglo-analytic philosopher: “Your theory is interesting, but are you aware that you are the surrounded and I am the surrounding?” As a taxonomy, one can distinguish among nine logical cases of the interrelationships of these two categories; they can also be formalized with logical symbols. I use the symbol S to portray the subject (the surrounded, the center) and the symbol O to describe the environment, which could be the same as the

6.10 Subject and environment |

129

Greimassian “object”, insofar as the environment constitutes the object of our subject’s action. O can both mean the Dasein and the transcendence as an environment or the Uexküllian Umwelt, which even he replaces with the term “object”. 1. S ∧ O The subject has been conjuncted with the environment; i.e., there is harmony between them. The subject is a part of its environment and has not yet been separated from it (consider someone that has lived his whole life in a village community characterised by organic solidarity, in which all the subjects and tools are in their proper place, as in a kind of Heideggerian utopia). Or the subject has regained his lost fatherland, patrie perdue, found unity with his environment, and returned into his correct isotopy. 2. S ∨ E The subject has been disjuncted from its environment; the subject is separated from its milieu. Between him and the environment a friction prevails; the surroundings are something else, a disorganisation, an Other, and the subject does not belong to it in any way, like the Arab princes in Montesquieu’s Persian letters in Paris or like a modern building interjected into an historic environment. 3. S → E The subject wants, strives for and towards his environment; he tries to become assimilated with it, become like it. 4. S ↔ E The subject wants to be detached from its environment, to grow free of it, to distinguish itself from it. 5. S ≠ E The subject is indifferent to its surroundings. The subject may have totally abandoned his surroundings or never been a part of them. It wants to live on its own terms and under its own conditions. There is no communication between subject and environment, yet they live side by side, apparently peacefully, like certain minorities in their main culture. 6. S The subject has no environment; it is alone in this world; the environment has been excluded. The subject is viewed as completely disjunct from its connections to any outer contexts; this is like a sender of message without a receiver. The structuralist study of “text” proceeded in this way, believing that in this way one reaches the zero point required by objectivity. But it is hard to imagine such a subject as other than an isolated object in a laboratory; perhaps in a certain mental state an autist subject lies without contact with his environment, as happens with certain patients discussed in clinical cases. 7. E The mere environment, without any center. For instance, network models are like that. They have no central point, but they are omnipresent; an empty space could be thought in this way. 8. S =→ Y The subject tries to dominate its environment, to subordinate the surrounding to its power, to elaborate and mould it according to its modalities. The subject creates a semiosphere suitable for itself. Some rulers even want to

130 | 6 Signs around Us – Umwelt, Semiosphere and Signscape

9.

dominate transcendence; they do this by their mythologies, in which they are represented as protagonists of mythical narration in order to legitimize and absolutize their power, as occurs in Rubens’s paintings of the regime of Maria di Medici. S ←= Y The environment dominates the subject. The subject is subordinated to the dictatorship of conditions, which he feels he has no power to influence or change. Such a case is given by a subject directed from the “outside”, one whom ideologies, propaganda, and other means of manipulation utilize as their target.

| Part II: Doing: Society and Culture

Chapter 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation: Towards a new theory of collective and individual subjectivity 7.1 Introduction It is certainly a truth that the present situation in the world is something much embarrassing any thoughtful mind when we try to make sense of recent developments. This is a challenge for semiotics which has always aspired towards a universal theory. When looking at the human condition particularly in the era of globalization with all its threats and promises we must agree that we are in the Foucaultian sense most obviously in a state of new configuration of our knowledge. We have to note also with ambivalent emotions how well semioticians have prophesized and anticipated what has happened. Do we not have the feeling that with all the time increasing control in every respect of life we are going towards Foucault’s panopticon model? When looking at the internet communication we have to admit how right Jean Baudrillard was for a long time ago, when he spoke about the electronic bubble world, an ecstasy of communication, etc. In the pragmatic sense, it has been proved that semiotics is the theory of our present world and even being always two or three steps in advance to the contemporary. But if this is true then we must not stop our theorizing and efforts to elaborate new structures and models which would help us to understand better the world in which we are living- and when it is going wrong, to improve, correct it. Semiotics has had in all its phases at least hidden an emancipated function. The theme of one of our semiotic events at the ISI in Imatra – Power: visible and invisible – manifests these trends, and we are pondering not only all forms of invisible and symbolic power by which we are dominated, but also how man can be liberated from such dominations. So the question is: If the world has become globalized and all political decisions in daily life are ultimately motivated and justified by the adaptation to global economic and social effects, how can such a global force exercise such a universalized power upon man’s behaviour? It is evident that traditional organisations are shattering: we hear it all the time said that this and that must be changed, it cannot be done any earlier, we have to adapt to new demands of efficiency, there must be more and more control of the quality of the results, more and more results with less and less costs, etc. How are these arguments allowed to exercise their

134 | 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation limitless power? At least many feel we are in a crisis, and I would like to add: we are in a special kind of crisis, which I would call a semiocrisis. Nationalisms seemed to have become at least in the European Union – and in all kinds of nations united, merely what I would call picturesque regional qualities, which can be enjoyed as tourism, but which no longer perplex and agitate our minds seriously. What then about regionalisms or localities? Most agree that Europe is after all nothing but localities which are the cross points and fulcra of identities or collective subjectivities. To be a European is to be local. But one cannot become a European by travelling in all corners of it and trying to adapt via this type of tourism to its various ambiances. So: Marcel Proust was not French but citizen of XIV arrondissement, Boulevard Haussmannian, or Faubourgian. Goethe was not German but Weimarian. Wagner was not German but Rigan, Triebschenian, or Bayreuthian. Dostoevsky was not Russian but Petersburgian. Albeniz was not Spanish but Andalusian, Almerian, Sevillan. Pablo Neruda was not Chilean but Isla Negraan. Peirce was not American but Milfordian. Neither was Sebeok American but Bloomingtonian or ‘Hoosier’ as they say. I do not believe that the local environment from which art works or great thoughts emerge would be indifferent regarding their contents. What I would call ‘ecoform’ of such a work stems from these roots; this means the adaptation of the work to its particular physical and spiritual environment. But if nationalism is thus positively questioned by the emphasis on regionalism, even more both nationalism and regionalism are questioned by globalisation effects. So we are obviously in a crisis.

7.2 The lesson of semiocrises How to determine what is a semiocrisis, what are its symptoms, what is its conceptual basis? Semiocrisis is due to the changes of epistemes in a culture. Epistemes are as Michel Foucault once defined them, depth level mental entities which change very slowly. Hence, when they undergo a transformation they can be metaphorically called earthquakes caused by shifts of continental plateaus. Earthquakes can be to some extent anticipated but, when they take place exactly speaking, no one can tell. The conceptual orientations of a culture’s deep level also move as slowly as continental plateaus. A semiocrisis emerges when these epistemic levels start to move. This becomes manifest when the prevalent discourse in a society does no longer correspond to the epistemic reality. The speech is not equal to man’s situation. Such a discrepancy between man’s speech and the values steering the epistemes at the deep level of a culture, causes

7.2 The lesson of semiocrises

| 135

what can be called intracultural misunderstanding (NOT cross-cultural ones as Walburga v. Raffler-Engel once argued) or what the French philosopher Vladimir Jankélévich called by the term ‘méconnaissance’, miss-knowledge. For instance, even if all the unemployed people would gather to manifestations in millions in front of government houses of various countries, nothing would happen. Their speech is not heard. The values to which they resort seem to have vanished, or the dominant values seem to inhabit elsewhere, unreachable and exercising their power from there. But then suddenly a semiocrisis erupts. In general semiocrisis means that the visible, observable signs of social life do not correspond to its immanent structures. Signs have lost their isotopies, their connections to their true meanings. Benevolent media try to improve the situation, return to the stable good times before the semiocrisis. But this does not help. Even media is powerless in front of this phenomenon. As said, such situations can be forecasted but their exact timing is impossible. Accordingly, when the value isotopies of a culture start to move, they cause semiocrisis. It is as if under the surface of the everyday reality there would loom a kind of sociokinetic energy field, which can combine things in unexpected manners. Just these changes in such a socio-energetic level are recognized as semiocrisis. When old structures falter man is left in a structureless situation in which they are no longer protecting him. This again can have two consequences: either man then becomes aware of him/herself as an existing subject – as it happened in Europe after World War II. Man experiences the Sartrean Nothingness; man unexpectedly encounters the emptiness and becomes conscious of his/her situation, choice and responsibility/solidarity. This is one way to react to the epistemic earthquakes recognized as semiocrisis (may be also my new theory on existential semiotics to which I shall come back later could be explained as a manifestation of the semiocrisis in the 1990s and 2000s). Nevertheless, a more common reaction is to reject the Nothingness and resort to old values until the last moment, by misunderstanding, ignoring the signs of a semiocrisis. Hence a mythological behaviour enormously increases under such times. Mythical longing, nostalgia for perpetual myths, of a nation or tradition are emphasized. When the experience of nothingness under semiocrisis becomes unbearable man creates himself a symbolic surrogate in the media world and its phantasmagorical products. In the Marxist sense, one could say that semiocrises are after all nothing but the phenomena of ‘falsches Bewusstsein’, i.e., the cases in which man’s consciousness does not equal to his reality. But the danger, of course, lies in the problem who has the right to tell to another: your speech represents false consciousness. Or, to put it in a Hegelian manner, who decides which victims of cunningness of the reason are. Theoretically speaking what is involved is the reference of signs,

136 | 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation to which signs and speeches are alluding. If they refer to each other like mostly in the discourse of media – then we reach the reality behind them only in the moments of semiocrisis. In this sense they display a positive aspect: they are like ‘hermeneutic windows’, moments of rupture. One becomes in such a moment aware of the reference of the signs and of the difference between his discourse and epistemes. Therefore semiocrises are excellent lessons of semiotics. This was already noticed by Charles Morris when he said that as we become conscious of our stomach when it does not function normally, in the same manner we become conscious of our signs in their disorder. But we cannot stop here: How can we clarify the situation of semiocrisis? How can we survive it, or What Do We Have to Do, like Leo Tolstoi asked over one century ago? The collective memory of a society or community can help us here. It can reveal and remember previous analogous cases in their history. These help us see what might have happened. Suddenly the important counterpoints of social life become crucial, which under normal conditions remain under the massive roar and rumble of world history. They are found in the marginal, in places where one would least think they would be. They are like answers which in order to he heard need the major theme. But they are never blended with it. Such counterparts can provide kinds of intellectual moments of innovations, revelation. Amidst a semiocrisis which has pursued a leap from nothingness to creation of a new meaning, a new semiotic identity may manifest. Whether such voices and counterparts can ever be made heard via media is a problem of its own. Media of course tries to maintain a critical discourse. It is represented by specialists. They may be right but when their opinion is distributed via global media, the medium becomes message. Whatsoever opinion becomes thus a social power under the conditions of global bubble world, even when the specialist or critic would deny it or withdraw from such influences. Criticism becomes power; not on its own, but upon other criteria no longer under its control. So, here is a short theory of semiocrisis. However, this may still sound rather programmatic like any discourse aiming for improving the world or pointing out which moral responsibilities are tended to sound. Easily such a speech is no longer semiotics, but a sermon. If we want to make a true semioethics, as Ponzio and Petrilli suggest, we have to continue our reflections. Therefore we have to go further and analyze the situation still more in depth. In fact without a theory of subjectivity, to my mind we cannot get very far in our analysis of ‘condition humaine’ of globalized world. Such a theory can evidently have two faces: one looking at collective subjectivity or identity, which we could also nominate with the somewhat outdated concept of world view – and individual identity. In the latter case we can join to the theory I have tried to elaborate

7.3 Collective subjectivity or identity as a world view

| 137

during decades already, existential semiotics. Of course the existential aspects fit well with individual issues; often existential is thought to be a category of one solipsist self or subject. It is true I have not yet expanded my theory very efficiently towards the social realm. But I shall show you later how a door is opened in that direction in some new issues of semiotic identity.

7.3 Collective subjectivity or identity as a world view Is the concept of world view a semiotic one at all? For the first it evokes the Belgian literary scholar, once called a genetic structuralist, Lucien Goldman and his studies in French collective mentalities in the 17th century (I refer to his study Le Dieu caché 1955, on Racine and Pascal). Goldmann studied world views and said that they were determined by three relationships: man’s relation to himself, man’s relation to others and man’s relation to nature. But are his definitions still valid? Man’s relation to himself doubtless leads us to the concept of subjectivity. Without a theory of subject it is impossible to speak about man’s existence. I shall take this issue again later. Man’s relation to others? Can it be studied semiotically? Certainly theories like Greimas’s mythical actant model would be suitable to scrutinize at least stereotypes in the world of social interaction. One can for instance easily imagine various types of communities according to which aspects of such a mythical communication they stress, destinator; destinatee, subject, object, helper, or opponent and which kind of action and by which kind of modalities take place among them. Man’s relation to nature has lately undergone a ‘modern’ biosemiotic interpretation. This means that a world view is a kind of Ich-Ton, Me-Tone or principle which determines which signs an organism accepts from its surroundings corresponding to its identity, and which ones it interprets alien and to be rejected. World-view thus serves as a kind of filter between the environments and the ‘self. The theory could be even extended in the direction of existential semiotics by presuming that such a filter also selects which ideas from transcendence are finally realized in the Dasein of an individual or community. Therefore on the basis one could try to ‘update’ Goldmann’s theory in order to build a new theory for the need of our time and situation. Nevertheless, what might be important to notice here is that a world view is not a First, it is always inferred from signs, symbols, gestures, mimics, postures of a body, etc. It is something more stable and invariant behind the immediate sense data, it is a principle which guides these signs of the surface level. But at the same time, there is no doubt that it would not be also something evidently present.

138 | 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation For instance, the British writer Nancy Mitford spoke about U-language and non-U-language; the first one represented the language spoken in the British upper classes. But her starting point was an essay published in Helsinki in the Bulletin of Neophilological Society entitled “Upper Class English Usage”, which also contained a list of vulgar expressions and their correct U-language counterparts: for instance: U-language: civilized, non-U-language: cultivated; U-language: Have some more tea? Non-U-language: How is your cup? U-language: vegetables, NonU-Language: greens; U-language: sick, Non-U-language: ill; U-language: What? Non-U-Language: Sorry! or Pardon – when one does not hear what the other person is saying, etc. Mrs. Mitford supposed that such verbal signs – like also the accent – immediately revealed to which world view the person belonged. Stuttering was an undeniable sign of belonging values of British upper class, the top of refinement, just like the aunt of Marcel Proust could from one phrase distinguish whether the performer of Beethoven’s Sonate pathétique had taste or not. These examples only try to show that world view is also something very concrete, although nominally they are recognized by their narrativisations. In semiotics Charles Morris again tried to create a typology of world views on the basis of a few principles of a living organism. In this sense his theory had a somewhat biologistic tinge. These basic movements were ‘towards’, ‘against’ and ‘away from’ leading to identities characterized as dependence, dominance and detachment, which appeared in every world view under various dosages. He called such cases as Dionysiac, Apollonic, Buddhist, Islamic, etc. The first mentioned dichotomy Dionysiac/Apollonic stemmed of course from Nietzsche. In fact the 19th century Romanticism created the manner of looking at the world through dichotomies. It was then typical to juxtapose various European cultures. In the novel by George Sand Consuelo, the story of an artist, she portrays two cultural spheres: the Italian or Mediterranean, which was based upon sensuality, corporeality, passion, direct action and expression – and the German which was something spiritual, metaphysical, introvert, inner, intimate, oriented towards history and mythology. These world views were depicted via the adventures of the soprano singer Consuelo first in Venezia and then in Austria and via her two lovers Anzoleto and Albert. Later, how often we encounter categories: die Germanen and die Lateiner in German philosophy. Ultimately, this conflict between civilisation and culture exists in aesthetics and many arts. In cultural semiotics such conflicts were universalized by Yuri Lotman as a kind of universal ‘law’ of culture’s functioning: culture is always surrounded by the sphere of non-culture with which it is in a dialectic interaction, which it not only tries to oppose, reject or conquer but which it always needs for its own survival and maintenance. And in our time we all know theories by Professor Huntington on the dash of civilisations, between Western and Arabic world. Or lately between Spanish-speaking and English-speaking

7.3 Collective subjectivity or identity as a world view

| 139

worlds in the United States. All these cases are exemplifications of theories of world views or collective identities. Therefore in the first place world view evokes something sociological – it is – like Pierre Bourdieu put it – a habitus, community and thus labels the notion as a phenomenon of collective mentalities. In fact we had in Finland a research project entitled Identity and Locality in the World of Global Communication – and which lead into a symposium at Imatra, whose papers have already appeared as a fairly extensive special issue of Semiotica. The idea of this project was to clarify how our world view has changed from what it used to be earlier. As a background observation one could notice that one does not at all live in all corners of the world in the globalized reality of Baudrillardian ‘bubble’ world, but some societies still preserve even fairly archaic forms of life. The essential problem thus was whether these earlier forms of life, culture and languages, and their worldviews could still survive in the new situation. The problem of the contemporary man was already once well formulated by the Italian semiotician Gino Stefani by saying that one has to be able to communicate globally but at the same time preserve the locality. Another Italian philosopher Augusto Ponzio has spoken about the overlapping structures of communication-production in which the communication chain sender–message–receiver is identical with the production chain: production-exchange (circulation, markets) and consumption, with all its ideological implications. In the semiotic terms we can speak of three stages of a society: ethnosemiotic or archaic society still living in the state of folklore and ancient, traditional forms of social life, sociosemiotic society which is the one of industrialization, formation of nations, institutions, and other forms of ‘mechanic’ solidarity (Durkheim) and technosemiotic society which is the one dominated by the electronic means of communication, computers, the global ‘bubble’ world of media to use the somewhat critical terms by Jean Baudrillard. The problem of the contemporary world – in this most general level – is to unite these stages within one present society into a peaceful cohabitation. One can presume that man/woman is happy only if he/she is able preserve something from each level. Instead when one is shifted from one stage to another, this may create phenomena called semiocrises in which the prevailing forms of communication and signification prove to be unsatisfactory, not corresponding to the transformed reality. The problems also rise by the efforts to return back from a stage to a previous one since the development is obviously irreversible. Moreover, crises may stem from the efforts of one stage to be ‘absolutized’ at the cost of others. We may also see how some major themes of our ‘semiotic’ lives undergo transformations through these stages, for instance as follows:

140 | 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation

Figure 7.1: Three stages of society

The major categories, ‘symbolic forms’ (Cassirer), of man are thus contextualized and temporalized, so to say, in this general outline of three-stage-model of societies. It may ultimately seem that semiotic models themselves are a typical product of the sociosemiotic stage, whereas the technosemiotic phase yields its own reified notions of theoretical discourse (supposing that theories as well are ‘social constructions’, see Berger, Luckmann). The previous scheme is of course also related to Charles Morris’s typology of discourses. Its parameters (on the left side column) are stemming from various semiotic schools, however, presumed to be a kind of ‘universals’ or philosophical bases for analyzing the events in the concrete societies under the process of transformation from one stage to the other (like Lévi-Strauss, Greimas, Barthes, Lotman, Eco, Morris, Peirce, Heidegger, Uexküll, etc.). What is the impact of the media world on the previous stages of social life? In some European regions people refuse any ‘modernisation’ of the life, fearing that their archaic, mythical world would by it disappear. Societies which have reached

7.4 Individual subjectivity or the fight between two manners of ‘being’ in the world

| 141

the sociosemiotic level, doubt the effect of global media to the very notion of subjectivity, democratic institutions, sense of history, nationalism, regionalism in their institutionalized forms. It seems as if messages by becoming media messages would lose their original weight and cogency and turn into a subordinated part of media discourse. Thus the technosemiotic level is viewed as a threat to local identities. At the same time, no one can deny its benefits, in, for instance, how in the information society knowledge and communication have become accessible to anyone participating to the new forms of communication. However, some doubt the connection of technosemiotic forms with the ideologies of efficiency and productivity (Ponzio emphasized a.o. the principle of diritto all’infunzionalità as the basic human right). So the problem is: Which kinds of narratives would make the balanced coexistence of those three levels possible for a present society?

7.4 Individual subjectivity or the fight between two manners of ‘being’ in the world What we have tried to do above is a rather pragmatic approach to the problem of semiocrisis and world view. But now when I rethink the idea of three consecutive world views as continuous phases of development, there is something familiar. It namely evokes, among many others thinkers the existential philosopher Karl Jaspers and his early work Psychology of Worldviews (Psychologie der Weltanschauungen). He also provides a typology of various worldviews having as their background a series of dichotomies as their ground: they are subject/object, nature/spirit, nature/culture, being/thinking, outer/inner, determination/freedom, sensible/intelligible, etc. In his view from the world view to be experienced concretely here and now a series of three world views unfold: nature- mechanic, nature-historical and nature-mythical. When they are seen as a continuum, one can see how from nature-mythical emerges the nature-historical and ultimately the nature-mechanical, In fact he meant fairly the same as above we intended to say with the three stages of ‘semiotic lives’: archaic, social and technological. He has a lot of critical comments on the nature-mechanical world view – our technosemiotic one, but could not of course in the 1920s foresee that variant of nature-mechanic worldview which is now globally indeed everywhere. Nature is deprived of its qualities and soul. It is interpreted as exact laws, thus calculable and manipulatable. Nature becomes a tool, there is nothing of the reality or fullness we normally find there but what prevails therein is a special unreality, whereby one can obtain most impressive effects. Nature is spatially and temporally totally subordinated to us. The satisfaction of this world view is the greater the more the phenomena discovered by it blend together with it,

142 | 7 Semio-crises in the era of globalisation i.e., they become measurable. Results can be guaranteed in advance, they can be confirmed by tests, when we have a constant interaction between theory and measurable facts. When this world view has taken the power, it is distributed everywhere. Mechanical analogies explain life, human societies and states. Individual subjective life is explained as an analogy with the physico-chemical discourse. As a contrast to it we have the nature-historical worldview, which looks after concrete types and not theoretical laws. A morphological instinct leads it. But even behind it looms the third and most original world view, the naturemythical, to see the world is to experience it. There is a kind of sentiment of proximity with the nature, it expresses itself via analogies, symbols, spirits and myths. The mythical world view can, however, also take nature as chaotic and evil. It is a world of fear. But it is a living entity, albeit with demonic and magical elements. One could think that a kind of principle of solidarity prevails there on the basis of a pre-established harmony between nature and other subjects. In nature-historical phase such solidarity would appear as the normative category, and by getting into other persons’ destiny by feeling and observing him. Instead, in nature-mechanical world view all solidarity is dead. A German semiotician Guido Ipsen has pondered the concept of solidarity and proposed that it disappears the more equal and well-to-do nations becomes, solidarity is of course possible by transgressing the boundaries of the alien psychic, and one way to do it is to presume a third principle or entity between me and you. Yet, Jaspers notes that all these phases can be unified in one person and make a synthesis. A balanced personality is the one in which they are living side by side – like in our model we supposed that happiness is based on the acceptance of all three phases from archaic to technosemiotic one. However they tend to become absolutized; philosophical world views are regretfully in a constant struggle with each other and err in their mutual misunderstanding. Goethe fought against nature-mechanical view. Tolstoi against nature-historical, in favor of the archaic. Ecological movement and attack parties fight against technosemiotic world view. The fight of world views is initiated when one of them is absolutized at the cost of others. As such, they are contemplative, but they produce also their analogous modes of action, modalities of pouvoir, ‘can’. At the end Jaspers launches the psychic-cultural worldview, as the basis of psychic-mythical narratives. Many narrative schemes stem from archaic phases but the neo-oral technosemiotic phase utilizes them as its raw material to dominate masses of receivers in the mediation processes. It is doubtless clear that semiocrises originate from this source of world view crises. Now we face the problem – having been lead to the roots of individual identity and subjectivity – how we could analyze it in the context of philosophy and semiotics. I shall next ponder this most essential phase on the ground of existential semiotics. I shall not give here the principles of this new approach

7.4 Individual subjectivity or the fight between two manners of ‘being’ in the world

| 143

to the epistemology of signs, but it is sufficient to note that it is largely based on the dialectics between Dasein (Being-There) and transcendence. The concept of Dasein of course sounds somewhat Heideggerian, but in this theory it is not accepted just in his sense.

Chapter 8 Ideologies manifesting axiologies 8.1 Introduction In the history of semiotics the concept of ideology occurs in many contexts, but its weight greatly varies with different scholars and periods. It was considered a big step forward when once upon a time the Russian Formalists, and after them the Prague structuralists, concluded that the relationship of a sign to the society which produced it was not causal but arbitrary. The sign was not a direct index of its sender, whether latter was a community or an individual person. The sign becomes ideological via its enunciator. For Bakhtin, an “ideologeme” was the utterance of a protagonist of a story (see Nöth 2000: 413–417). Particularly in Dostoevsky this appeared as a “polyphony of consciousnesses”. When two persons engage in discussion, it reveals their different ideologies (see Bakhtin 1970). The idea of the autonomy of sign naturally distinguished semiotics from Marxism. But then came the 1960s and ideology came back to some extent with structuralism, not in the vulgar Marxist sense, but influenced by the more hermeneutical Frankfurt school. In Adorno, ideology is a central negative definition, and positive when a “progressive” artist consciously takes a critical approach to his society. When semiotics developed into a discipline in the1970s there were still remnants of ideology in the debate. Roland Barthes paralleled ideology and myth (Barthes 1957), Lucien Goldmann connected it with his notion of vision du monde (Goldmann 1956), and Greimas mentions ideology in his structural semantics (Greimas 1966: 181), which was, however, most particularly an application of his mythical-actantial model. Then ideology faded into the background until it again became pertinent in the post-structuralist period, most notably under the impact of Foucault and in gender theories. Perhaps the best-known definition of ideology is the one that defines it as “false consciousness” (falsches Bewusstsein). From this point of view an ideological utterance is one that tries to mask its own axiological starting points, to justify and universalize them with some myth to deceive the receiver, or by postulating one’s own values as if they were “natural”. Ugo Volli defines ideology as “a set of discourses that constitute common sense, transformed such that that which is partial and open to change is taken to be something universal, unchanging and eternal – in short, reality” (come insieme di discorsi che, costituendo il senso comune, trasforma ciò cheè parzialee aperto al cambiamento, in qualcosa di uniservale, immutabile ed eterno, insomma nella realtà) (Volli 2000: 310). For semiotics, however, nothing is just natural. For example, in Greimas the very no-

8.1 Introduction

|

145

tion of the “natural world” already represents a semiotized world, furnished with significations. In speaking of ideology, it is typical that one supposes that what is involved are others, not me. Hence ideology is essentially an egocentric type of utterance. For instance, Americans said that the USSR was characterized by ideologizing everything, whereas their own world was something real. Nowadays it is thought that global markets are real, and all others ideological. Thus an ideological utterance is something that conceals one’s own ideology, that suppresses it from consciousness. This is why ideological arguments tend to have a certain fanatical nature. According to Terry Eagleton, it is characteristic of ideological statements that at the same time as they say something, they also contain an untruth (Eagleton 1996: 16–17). For instance, “It’s winning the lottery to be born a Finn!” A saying often heard in that country, it is a typically ideological utterance, particularly when a Finn says it. You hear it as a rejoinder when someone criticizes Finnish society, or when a Finn wants to distinguish Finland as better than other nations. The essential content in such statements is not the statement itself but the situation in which it is said: who utters and to whom. In other words, behind an ideological utterance there always looms a kind of power position. In post-colonial analysis one speaks of how a “dominant” has taken langue into its possession and forces the dominated to produce parole only within certain limits. An ideological art is typically like that. For instance, the series of twelve huge canvases portraying the reign of Maria di Medici, hanging in a gallery at the Louvre, represents a characteristically ideological, multifaceted utterance that legitimates a certain power position of the dominant. Donskoi’s films about the life of Lenin are typically ideological representations. In them a mythical-ideological hero is always seen more as a type than as a concrete token. Iconoclast myth analysis strives to unravel such ideological connotations. In Barthes’s analyses of modern myths, he situates as their signified the concept of bourgeois ideology and its hegemony (Barthes 1957). In Barthes’s model ideology functions in the place of signifié in the mythical sign. The notion of nationalism is also a typically ideological formation. The music of Sibelius’s Finlandia has an ideological meaning for the Finns, which cannot be reduced merely to the qualities of its musical signifiers (Tarasti 2001: 3–13). Such qualities can be interpreted only by the Finns, it is thought. Yet, ideologies are open to analysis; something stands behind them, namely the axiologies of a community. An ideological statement manifests hidden, immanent values. From the existential semiotic viewpoint, the difference between ideologies and axiologies is clear. At first we encounter values which in their virtual state outside the Dasein are transcendental. When an individual or group

146 | 8 Ideologies manifesting axiologies adopts some values as its own, then values transform into axiologies, which constitute more or less compatible collections of values. When ultimately an individual or a group aims to legitimize its axiologies to other subjects of its Dasein, those axiologies are transformed into ideologies. Hence ideologies represent a realized phase of originally transcendental values. They constitute a collective modalization of Dasein. Furthermore, ideologies function as ingredients of an identity so that they are stable entities in the world surrounding a subject, i.e., inter-subjectively valid and durable. They form certain fixed values, which are common to various subjects, whether individuals or groups. Such a definition seems to undermine the old one of “false consciousness”. Eagleton is particularly unwilling to accept that Marxist view, finding it impossible to think that such enormous amounts of people would accept it into their continuous everyday practices (Eagleton 1996: 12). Unfortunately, just this can happen. Huge numbers of people live under the emotional impact of media, as Genevan Professor of Psychology Klaus Scherer has stated (Scherer 2001: 16). For instance, when crises occur, their causes receive little analysis; rather, the media dwells on the emotional reactions of quite ordinary people. Typical emotional states, états passionnels, of the contemporary world are anger, frustration and rage, since there is no possibility to intervene in events, Scherer said in an interview in Le Monde (Nov. 23, 2001). This has nothing to do with whether these emotional states originating from the media were “authentic” endogenic passions or external ones, which, as Marcel Proust says, keep us for a while under their power, eventually tire us out, then leave us when our subjective judgment starts to function again. Media represent the world of Appearance, paraître, expanded to all corners, behind which is être, the level of Being. Ideology is precisely the sphere of Appearing. Althusser remarked that ideology appears precisely in the field of affectivity, in our smallest gestures and emotions (in Eagleton 1996: 19). On the other hand, ideology is considered invisible in its omnipresence unless it is made conscious. How far can man’s behavior, which he thinks to be authentic, endogenic, be explained by the category of Appearance? The situation is somewhat similar to the argument of one art historian, according to which the fact that Kandinsky never mentions nor evokes Japanese art in his writings or in his paintings, can be taken as the best proof of their Japanese influences. We cannot trust this thesis very far without evidence. The Italian semiotician Ferruccio Rossi-Landi (1973) has closely examined ideology as a hidden yet omnipresent category – what nowadays feminists and gender theoreticians understand as the “hegemony of patriarchal culture”, or Foucauldian philosophers as “panoptic”, controlling power system. In his book, Ideologies of Linguistic Relativity, Rossi-Landi quotes the linguists Sapir and

8.1 Introduction |

147

Whorf, who studied the languages of North American Indians (Rossi-Landi 1973: 29). According to them, languages differ from each other not only by their grammar but also by their world-view. He quotes Whorf: “. . . each language . . . is itself the shaper of ideas, the program and guide for the individual’s mental activity . . . . We are inclined to think of language simply as a technique of expression, and not to realize that language first of all is a classification and arrangement of the stream of sensory experience which results in a certain world-order . . . ” (RossiLandi 1973: 29). Hence every language, langue in Saussurean terms, has its own ideology, which lies hidden in its structures. This is precisely where gender theoreticians base their thesis on the dominance of the patriarchal canon. On this view, if there are generative grammars producing surface phenomena (signs) from a deep structure, then the entire process is by nature ideological and present on all levels. American radical gender theoreticians claim that if one has a bad ideology, it is always seen and heard in his/her statements. Man’s identity thus “generates” inevitably certain ideological statements and signs. This somewhat argumentum ad hominem thesis would annul the achievement of semioticians since the 1920s concerning the autonomy of signs. Perhaps we should assume, less radically, that the serpent of ideology wriggles in only at some later moment of generation, distorting its mechanisms into ideologies only on the figurative-narrative surface, but not yet at the fundamental syntax. Such an invisible ideology would appear in many levels of the generative course (Greimas 1979: 179–180; 157–161). Even the basic structures of meaning in Greimas’s semiotics can be ideological. S1 vs. S2 is an ideologically loaded distinction, which manifests when one invests it with content such as man vs. woman, rich vs. poor, Christian vs. Muslim, white vs. colored, old vs. young, war vs. peace, and much more. The actantial model is super-ideological. Ideologies also manifest on the figurative level, as in the arts. But is there any non-ideological threshold in the generation or manifestation, beyond which it becomes ideological? Augusto Ponzio considers the manifestation of ideology in signs to be iconic: a sign that conveys an ideology is somehow similar to its ideology. But he adds that no sign as such is ideological, but is that way only via some interpreter. “In ideology the relation between the sign and the interpretant is iconic or abductive. A person performs a given piece of behavior in a given context with respect to an ideology that is more or less stable and defined: such behavior is associated with that ideology by a relation of similarity” (Ponzio 1993: 63). And “if ideology is always contained in signs, it is always contained by an interpretant and for an interpreter” (ibid.: 65). Therefore what is involved is an interpretant which has the indexical power to force one to act according to an ideology, to connect its signs –

148 | 8 Ideologies manifesting axiologies be they acts or things – to a certain object, which is the same as ideology. Such an ideological discoursive practice is exemplified by military discipline, and expressions in general, as related to war. “efficiency”, “victory”, “loss”, “strategy”, “tactics”, “balance of power”, “surgical precision”, and so on. All these and more have been shifted to discourses of economy, technology, and science. When they still appeared in their original meaning, they were based upon corporeality and indexical signalling in the army. Now they assume a metaphorical meaning in their new contexts, where their ideological foundations support the virtues of society in the global techno-semiotic phase of “efficiency”, “precision”, “takeovers”, and the like. They become ideological statements, whose task is to produce certain act-signs or actions. To some thinkers, ideologies are structures of communication rather than of signification. Eagleton and Bakhtin take this position, viewing ideologies as utterances or communication, whereas the other view is that they are hidden in the grammar. Let us again think of the classical Saussurean model in which subject A says something to subject B who is facing him (1916 [1995]: 27). As noted in the first chapter, the space between these subjects becomes modalized during communication, and ideology, reducible to modalities, thus manifests in this space. In an ideological statement we might see the functioning of modalities Being/Appearing in such a way that an ideological statement conceals a certain Being under its Appearance; for instance, under the cloak of the mythical. At the same time, the statement reinforces subject A’s modality of Can, his power, which is experienced by subject B as Must, which compels him to believe the same as subject A, or act as A wishes him to do. Of course subject A can be aware of the fact that he is subordinated by the Must of an ideology, but still he continues to functioning as the medium of this ideology, like a soldier in the army is disciplined to obey the ideology that gives the orders. The only way to break free of this circle is to realize that behind ideologies we have axiologies and, in the end, transcendental values, to which we can compare the modal constellations of Dasein and thus notice their relativity. In order to grasp ideology, one needs a transcendental analysis. But what guarantees that the tools by which we try to decipher ideological grammar are not themselves contaminated by some ideology? The concepts we use to deal with ideology should be non-ideological. But is this possible? Or is Rossi-Landi right when he speaks about the relativity of linguistic mechanisms? Some turn the problem around by developing new methods of analysis. Instead of hiding behind a kind of higher-level objectivity, they adopt an overtly subjective, monological discourse, in which all phases of analysis are reported precisely and made explicit. Some believe that the bold revelation of one’s own subjectivity would lead to a more objective result, since such analysis does not

8.1 Introduction |

149

even claim to be non-ideological or objective, but expressly tries to make explicit one’s own ideologies. Yet, such scholars forget one of the great and unique benefits of being human: the ability to put oneself on a metalinguistic level. That is to say, we can agree, while conscious about the arbitrariness of our contract, that with this part of a language and its concepts, we can speak about another part of language; for example, that part containing ideological statements. In this way, we do not fall into the vicious circle of omnipresent ideology. Rossi-Landi, in his Semiotik, Äshetik und Ideologie (1976), has also pondered how in the arts the so-called realist style emerged as something non-ideological. Such realism meant a kind of direct, “natural” attitude towards the world, without realizing that such a view of “nature” was itself a product of history and society (Rossi-Landi 1976: 105–107). Such a view was common not only in nineteenthcentury arts, but one finds it to be the model inherited by mass media. News reporters and art critics believe (quite mistakenly) that they are transmitting reality as it is, simply telling the truth, not blinded by “theory” or presuppositions. In her brilliant study of censorship techniques, the Estonian scholar Maarja Lõhmus (2002) discusses various forms of information mediation that intentionally masks it as ideological designs. Though confined to Soviet media manipulation in Estonia, her models and conclusions are quite open to generalization. Similarly, when we look at realist paintings by French or Russian artists from the nineteenth century, we believe we are viewing realistic descriptions, though what is involved is a construction of reality by certain semiotic devices. We can distinguish basically two types of utterances: ideological and ideologizing. The latter manifests as an effort to dominate the receiver, or “other”. In the former case, this power has been already stabilized and is “self-evident”. An ideologizing statement concerns the Other as a stranger. In it one can distinguish an ideological tinge in speech; for instance, the British upper-class accent, the pathetic intonation of the speaker in a Russian movie, or the narrator’s voice in a Walt Disney film. Yet, as said above, to apply the concept of ideology to another person or to his/her statement is already as such a reification, an hypostatizing of this phenomenon. If one says to someone in such a situation that this or that is ideological or sounds ideological, it means a relativization of the phenomenon. To join an ideology to an identity goes even further: ideologies emerge from collective mentalities and their qualities of Einfühlung. Identity means the stability of a certain actantial and passional state. An ideological statement strives to justify that state by transforming a certain state or aspect of Dasein into a universal; in turn, a deideologizing statement aims to reducing it back to the categories of time, place, and actor.

150 | 8 Ideologies manifesting axiologies An ideological statement is an utterance that takes something as natural, as a real state of things, though this is basically an arbitrary value-choice. The postulate of arbitrariness does not, however, mean the counterpole: a subjectively narcissistic emotional reaction to everything, as if there were no history, place, or transcendental values at all. In the world ruled by the ideology of consumption, everything is decided on the basis of personal tastes and enjoyment. As a case in point, a teacher once took her class to the opera in Toronto; it was their first experience of it. Afterward, she asked how they had experienced it, and they answered, “I liked it” or “I didn’t like it” – as if in a highly sophisticated cultural text as opera, the only thing that matters is whether one likes or dislikes it, in the same way as we prefer vanilla ice cream to Coke. This global ideology has even intruded into schools and universities, which are being forced to “go along with the times”, where pupils are taken as consumers that enjoy “services” rendered by their teachers. This is quite different from the view of one French pedagogue, which encapsulates the classical view of education up until the past few generations: Schools do not give services to men, they make men (and women). If one thinks of ideologies as manifestations of axiologies, one can ask whether certain axiologies are more easily ideologized than are others. Or, is the ideology only a certain viewpoint of that axiology in a certain situation of communication? Is the ideology the same as a foregrounded, particularly salient axiology? If we accept the existential semiotic viewpoint that ideology transforms transcendental values into values of Dasein, we may ask if concealed, implicit ideologies change into explicit ones. For instance, the idea of Brecht’s epic theater was to make visible the hidden bourgeois ideology by de-ideologizing it, but it was not noticed that this device in turn led to a re-ideologizing practice. According to Greimas, axiologies and ideologies are distinguished from each other by their semiotic way of being, namely, whether the values are paradigmatic or syntagmatic (Greimas 1996: 179). Existentially speaking, in the first case the values, collectively speaking, remain outside Dasein. In the latter case they take part in its processes. On the other hand, Greimas refers to the fact that in the deep level of a generative process, the semiosis, we speak about axiologies, whereas when we shift to the surface-level, modalizing activities of a subject – his or her Want, Must, Can, etc. – then we may speak about ideologies. Another central dictionary of semiotics, the Handbook by Winfried Nöth, deals with ideology in a broader manner, both as a social system of ideas and as myth, as sign, and as “false consciousness”. There we find that both Althusser and Eliseo Verón consider ideology as does Greimas, that is, as a property of the deep structure, as langue rather than parole (Nöth 2000: 415). Likewise, semiotics itself is influenced by ideologies, which, however, semiotic research tries to neutralize by its own strategies. Semiotics is thus a particular

8.1 Introduction

|

151

discoursive activity which is constantly aware of its own ideological nature, and at the same time freed from it. For Foucault the archaeology of knowledge is the same as its ideology: values and epistemes articulate and justify certain discoursive practices in a certain age. By contrast, in Heidegger’s philosophy, ideologies may be situated within the ontological pre-state, which rules over our existence as its “pre-understanding” (Vorverständnis). In the next chapter we shall deal with ways of resisting such pre-states, especially as they exist in the values and epistemes that grip our contemporary world.

Chapter 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs 9.1 Globalization and transcendence When thinking about the contemporary world, most people probably share the feeling that they are powerless to intervene in its course in any way. “Globalization” has served as the theme of many congresses during recent years, by which is meant a new and particular economic and administrative apparatus that one has no power to change. People are losing their jobs, and those who are still employed are forced to work until drawing their last breath – forced, moreover, by abstract requirements mandated by anonymous senders. All public discourse has been taken over by a single, unquestioned model, the characteristics and demands of which are familiar to everyone, since they now exist practically everywhere. Traditional terms such as “progress”, “development”, “results”, and “education” are rampantly becoming caricatures of themselves, and serve as a means of adapting everyone and everything to this new global order: a kind of supra-individual, collective power, an actor or mentality that forces real persons to submit to its will. That force is a completely transcendental entity: an amazing phenomenon amidst today’s extreme materialism. What has happened is the “naturalization of transcendence” (Pihlström 2003). Charles Taylor (1989), pondering the existence of transcendence, has argued that certain real-world behaviors cannot be reasonably explained other than by presupposing that they manifest something transcendent. When Sartre’s Transcendence de l’égo (1957) was recently translated into Finnish, a term borrowed from the business world was used as the equivalent in the title: the externalization of the ego. The whole habitus and distinctive life-world of contemporary man appears to suggest the popularity of transcendence. Even communication is mostly virtual and transcendental. We read about people who live in a fictional, Internet reality, preferring to communicate mostly with others of the net community, using traces on a computer screen rather than face-to-face dialogue. The Internet embodies the naturalization of transcendence. For a philosopher there is something familiar about all this. If, returning to Hegel, we replace the notion of transcendence with so unfashionable a term as the German Geist (spirit), we encounter a completely consistent theory of the course of our world. In his Philosophy of History, Hegel speaks about Geist, as “abso-

9.1 Globalization and transcendence |

153

lute Spirit”, of which individuals are only tools¹. For him, the concept of Spirit is no abstraction but an individualized and constantly active force whose object is the consciousness. Consciousness is the existence of Spirit, its Dasein, which has become an object (Gegenstand) unto itself. Spirit forms a conception of itself and produces to itself a spiritual content. It becomes, so to speak, a content unto itself; it manufactures content about itself. The content takes the form of knowing, but is in fact Spirit itself. In opposition to Spirit there is matter, which is characterized by density and weight, that is, by substance. Conversely, the substance of the Spirit is freedom. Freedom is thus the essential property of the Spirit. Spirit strives for freedom, for activity is in its essence. Freedom is not based upon quietude, but rather on continuous negation and eventual eradication of stasis. Producing oneself, becoming an object to oneself – that is the proper activity of the Spirit. Here we find a pragmatic view of Spirit: it is something to be realized; it is not selfexistent; it has to be made or created – it must be earned, so to speak. For Hegel (1917: 35), “Spirit is only the end result of some action” (Der Geist ist nur also sein eigenes Resultat). Hegel reasons that man becomes what he has to be only through education (Bildung) and discipline (Zucht). What he is immediately is only a potentiality (ansich-sein), as I have also argued (Tarasti 2004b). A person, unlike an animal, must make him-/herself into something. He has to earn everything for himself, since he is spirit and must subordinate the natural or bodily man to it. Hence, spirit is the result of the subject itself. This Hegelian starting point forms the background to Norbert Elias’s (1997) theories of how, through civilizing processes, man gains civilité. Much of Elias’s output consists of juxtaposing the German notion of Kultur and the English one of “civilization” (Elias 1997: 33–38). Though he has much to say on those matters, one can condense Elias’s argument as follows: Culture is content, ideas, and spirit, whereas civilization consists of more or less “mechanical” habits, manners, and the like. As musicologist Richard Taruskin puts it, “Culture is internal, profound, conceptual – and, of course, German – whereas civilization is sensual, momentary, frivolous . . . that is to say, something French or Italian” (Taruskin 1997: 251).

1 At the time, Hegel’s Philosophy of History was one of his most popular works, in no small part because it was relatively easy to read. At the same time, one must remember that it was also one of his most roundly criticized doctrines.

154 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs

9.2 Globalization as the new civilization: Some signs of the time Some feel that civilization is a threat to culture. For Elias, globalization is the new civilization, which expands all over the world, destroying culture in its wake. Essential is Elias’s assertion that, in a civilized society, no human being enters the world already, or “pre-”, civilized. One has to undergo acculturation as part of the socializing-civilizing process. This is nothing other than what Hegel meant by his claim that Spirit is not a ready-made product, but something to be earned by work and action. On the other hand, Elias’s comparison of the as-yet uncivilized children of our culture with the “uncivilized” adults of archaic societies is misleading (1978: xiii). Lévi-Strauss (1967) proved long ago the fallacy of such reasoning, in his essay on the Structures élémentaires de la parenté. Yet, if we interpret Hegel in the context of our time, casting globalization in the role of the “bad spirit” of world history, then plainly such a role can be fulfilled only via the Eliasian civilizing process. Therefore, all processes of globalization put special emphasis on re-educating and “re-civilizing” people into the new system. To provide a framework for theoretical reflections to follow later, I next present a list of those “re-civilizing” traits and processes, as well as some predictions about the condition humaine, especially in the “global era”: (1) No more future. The concept of a future is obliterated by an atmosphere of uncertainty, a fragmented kind of life. Nobody can make long-term plans; life moves only from one moment to the next. One has to be ready for constant change, since globalization and competition demand it. What is actually meant by “change” we are not told. (2) No more past. No one can resort to history for support, since the new civilization has divorced itself from the “backward” past. The past must be forgotten actively. The attitude is that of “nous avons changé tout cela”. This history-less attitude, as a kind of barbarism, was portrayed by the cultural historian Jakob Burckhardt as early as in the nineteenth century, when he anticipated the triumph of the “global” type of man (Burckhardt 1951: 13–14). (3) A shift to the metalevel. In work, intent and product are unimportant. What matters is the manner of doing, the techniques and technology of getting things done. This shift is accompanied by the problematization of all phenomena of everyday life. Nothing can happen by itself: faith in one’s own intelligence and in Eliasian civilité requires that everything take place on the basis of “research” and “control” (the new obsession). This mind-set is linked to the principle of minimizing risks and maximizing efficiency, which is in turn based on the growing

9.2 Globalization as the new civilization: Some signs of the time | 155

conviction that everything and anything can be anticipated, counted, and manipulated. (4) Perpetual assessment of quality in all domains. People and institutions must undergo continuous self-criticism; at the same time, it is forgotten that the more energy which one puts into the assessment of quality, the less quality there is. From this obsession with assessment emerges a system of total control and selfcensorship. (5) One dominant discourse: Economic-technological. Borrowing its terms from the military, as mentioned in the previous chapter, this discourse allows for assessment and discussion only in terms of functionality/non-functionality, effectiveness/ineffectiveness (see, e.g., Huhtinen 2002). (6) Only two classes of people: Winners and losers. In this, another extension of the military metaphor, losers are not worth funding; they are kept silent by continuous pseudo-education, therapy, and entertainment. This distinction between the intelligent and the non-intelligent, as kinds of biologically determined entities, is ultimately based on theories of genetics. This classification happens without one noticing that it is just as irrational as the racist-tinged thought of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries (e.g., eugenics). Though the latter is thought to have been eliminated, a similar, essentialist doctrine has entered through the back door. (7) Elevation of ownership as a goal unto itself. Operating on the principle that “to possess things is wonderful”, this unscrupulous form of capitalism equates wealth with honesty; poverty manifests “dishonesty” and is viewed as one’s own fault. To see that this view is adopted by everyone, police and other “law enforcement” agencies are developed to new extremes. (8) The basic emotional moods in society stem from business life. These moods are greed (to assure continuous profits and results) and fear (continuous anguish about losing profits and positions), which are expounded and disseminated everywhere via communications media. (9) The reservate model of reality. This means the reversion of idea of protected areas for population under threat of vanishing, namely it refers to the seclusion of “winners” in closely guarded sanctuaries; for example, the walled compounds of urban and suburban “gated” communities. “Losers” live outside the walls, in areas rife with continuous terrorism and violence. (10) Symbolic violence. “External” culture spreads to all corners of the globe by assimilating and destroying “internal” cultures (Finol 2004). Such violence appears in communication as the supremacy of the spectacle: the penetration of global values into cultural micro-processes via music, food, cinema, and other sign systems, along with their attendant behaviors and emotional sates.

156 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs (11) Science: Total behaviorism. Everything can be explained by genetics, biology, and physics. The humanities are minimized and suppressed in favor of the natural sciences and technology. Only theology remains, and it is for disciplinary purposes – that is, to keep people in line. (12) Study is an unnecessary and unpleasant hurdle of life. It has to be cleared as quickly as possible and with minimal expenditure of energy and funds. (13) The naturalization of transcendence, as discussed at the beginning of this chapter. (14) The Huntington thesis. This idea proposes conflicts at the level of civilizations, and the transformation of Anglo-Saxon culture by the influx and positive influence of Latino culture. Do we, as intellectuals, scholars and artists, want to be a part of such a world? Can we be part of that world even without wanting to be? Or is membership in such a world necessary only so as to preserve our jobs, contacts, or group identities? Many semioticians have started to ponder such questions. In Italy, for example, Augusto Ponzio and Susan Petrilli are trying to create a special theory of “semioethics”. The German semiotician Guido Ipsen has pondered problems of solidarity in the global world. Note to mention the existential semiotics of Landowski and myself. As noted above, Finol (2004) argues that a new global culture has emerged which is not only economic but which also intrudes into the microprocesses of everyday life. (In Lotman’s terms, “outer” culture has invaded “inner” culture and subordinated the latter completely.) Finol compares such “invasions” to the expansion of the Roman empire. In Latin America, particularly, this manifests as the supremacy of Anglo-Saxon culture, as is the case all over the world. Still, in what Eco called “semiological guerrilla war”, the inner culture can put up resistance through the use of some very subtle mechanisms. That resistance is based on the notion of semiotic tension. According to Finol’s model, tension is created when a body is being pulled toward, or attracted to, two different sides. A body (cuerpo) can choose either to resist or to adapt, and a balance can prevail between those choices. If the attraction to culture A is stronger than to culture B, then adaptation or assimilation occurs; whereas if one actively engages with B, then what is involved is resistance. In everyday life these tensions become naturalized. The attacks by global culture occur on all fronts at the same time; struggle and tension emerge everywhere, on all micro-levels of everyday life. Finol believes that elements of an inner culture form the most efficient resistance to threats from the outer one(s). In turn, the Bulgarian semiotician Kristian Bankov, in his essay “Infinite Semiosis and Resistance”, has used Peirce’s triangle model to ponder the concept of resistance (Bankov 2004: 175–181). As is known, in Peirce’s theory the semiosis

9.2 Globalization as the new civilization: Some signs of the time | 157

is launched by the so-called dynamic object, which is situated outside the sign triangle, in “reality”. Bankov illustrates: . . . let us imagine a car with five people on board. They are urgently trying to arrive at some destination but on the journey the car breaks down. They all try to guess what caused the breakdown and propose the easiest way to fix the problem. But there is little time and they have to reach a consensus, since they cannot try everyone’s solution. At the same time, they make abductive reasonings about what constitutes the material object that is resistant to their purposes. A solution is found, the car is repaired, and the resistance disappears. But then the car breaks down again. Now the passengers start to quarrel with each other. Now the resistance is of a social nature: they have to reach agreement among themselves if they want to continue the journey. The dynamic object here is not material but spiritual.

Bankov describes those two species of resistance as either static (independent of individual intentions) or dynamic. From this he reasons that the nature of resistance is different in the natural and social sciences. This model fits well with Finol’s insofar as, in philosophy and art, the resistance is provided by the community in which those disciplines are formed. The idea of infinite semiosis also fits well with Finol’s theory, in the sense that, without the resistance of the inner culture, the outer culture increases and expands unhindered, smothering and destroying the original culture. Accordingly, semioticians have taken the problem of resistance under examination. That they have done so is crucial, for in the eventual semiotics of resistance, mere comments will not suffice. Resistance will amount to nothing more than a sermon unless it has a theory behind it. The issue must first be problematized, as we have done above, and thereafter conceptualized and reflected upon at a deeper epistemic level. In the end, one must build as systematic a theory as possible, the principles of which must be popularized, so that it leads to concrete human actions. The first step in that direction is a statement that is typically and universally true of all humans: we are all capable of pursuing the spiritual and pragmatic operation that one may call negation. Negation is the crucial notion in existential semiotics. It is also relevant in Hegelian logic, as that which puts the world into motion. In Hegel, negation is followed by Becoming. But what if we should intervene at this phase in his logic and presume that negation, rather than leading to becoming, is instead followed by a return backwards? If such concepts as becoming, development, progress, anticipation, directionality, and the like have all been subordinated to serve the global system, and if we want to reject this system as a whole, then we have to look at the movement of signs in the counter-current to all of that.

158 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs Some of my earlier theories have emphasized the flux of phenomena, their streaming temporality, in contrast to spatial, achronic examination detached from dynamic, forward-rushing processes. I have underlined that semiotics is progressive; it is no longer a “post-” phenomenon (postmodernism, poststructuralism, etc.) but a neo-phenomenon. Yet, we should also take into account a third alternative: the counter-current of signs, a reference backwards – with all its concepts, such as memory, return, oblivion. We have to ask, What counts as “progress” in our own time? Or, to recall Tolstoi’s question, What do we have to do? If all surrounding reality is unacceptable, then progress is made not by pushing “forward”, with all the values that entails, despite the deification of speed and efficiency, but rather by a kind of counter-movement, a kind of non-progress, the other side of the prevailing establishment ideology. I do not doubt at all the capacity of semiotics to effect such a turn. If Adorno could write his Negative Dialectics, then is it not possible to write a “Negative Semiotics” or a “Semiotics of Resistance”?

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance The heading of this section alludes to the novel by Peter Weiss (1978), Ästhetik des Widerstandes, which from an autobiographical perspective portrays events in Europe on the eve of World War II. The term is used in the domain of aesthetics and arts, in which “progress” often consists of the rejection of previous styles and trends, a rejection that occurs in the “hard” sciences, too, as “revolutions” and “paradigm shifts” in the Kuhnian sense. In the present context, the concern would be art whose universal quality is to serve as a power of resistance. In Vladimir Propp’s (1958) now-classic narrative model, the seeking or pursuit of an object by a subject-hero has generally been taken as the self-evident starting point. In Propp’s model, the role of opponent has been reserved for the antipathetic villain or the like. In the art and science of resistance, the role of the opponent is now positive, and, in fact, ultimately replaces that of the subjectactant. In later narratives, he is promoted, from an opponent to the status of a main actor. There are many examples of this in biographies of marginal artists that were misunderstood in their time, ranging from van Gogh to the Finnish artist Aleksis Kivi. Resistance in these cases is of course dictated by the historical situation, and ironically, the very marginality of the artist lends something universal to his or her posterity. Weiss describes such resistance as follows:

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

159

Die soziale Erneuerung, die Übernahme von Entdeckungen und Eroberungen aus den Händen der Herrschenden, die Herstellung der eigenen Macht, die Begründung unseres eigenen wissenschaftlichen Denkens, dies waren Themen, die wir uns in der Kunst, Literatur, vorstellen konnten. (Weiss 1978: 86; English trans. mine) (Social renewal, the complete take-over of discoveries and conquests arising from the hegemony of domination, the establishment of power, the founding of our own kind of scientific thought – those would be the themes that in art [and] literature we can represent to ourselves.)

When later the narrator of the novel is wandering in a Parisian suburb and finds himself at the atelier of the painter Géricault, he eloquently portrays the aesthetics of resistance, using the life and work of that artist as his illustration. He visits the dilapidated work room which served as the artist’s home in the years 1816–1818, during which time he created his great oil canvas, Le Radeau de la Méduse (1819). After traveling to England, Géricault returned to this Parisian atelier, dying there in 1824. The verbal description of the painting is an art work of its own, a literary one. Weiss, fascinated by the extreme situation portrayed in the shipwreck, argues that the painter aimed to put the spectator – whom nobody on the ferry is looking at – somewhere amidst the melee, as if he were clutching spasmodically at one corner of the ferry, but already too far gone to expect to be rescued. What happened above him no longer concerns the spectator. Instead, there is hope for those who stand in the painting, but who are ultimately condemned. Weiss then describes various figures in the picture, including their hopes of being rescued. After that transcendental moment, which is allotted to the African, Weiss moves into the real historical world of the painting. He conceives the painting as a fragment of a more extensive narration of Géricault’s life story, since it portrays the shipwreck which the painter actually experienced. Some of the protagonists, shown in the painting, indeed found refuge off the coast of Senegal on the Isle of Saint Louis, then a center for some of the most horrid colonialist exploitation and slave trading. The English garrison on the island refused to help the Frenchmen, who at last met up with a Moorish tribe in a land ruled by the king of Zaide. Luckily for them, the Moors were admirers of Napoleon and showed hospitality to the starving Frenchmen after they had drawn a map of Europe on the sand. The king himself had witnessed the pilgrimage of Napoleon’s army to Mecca. Now the Frenchmen could tell the king that Napoleon had continued to live after his exile to the isle of Elba. Finally the Englishmen took them into their hospital, but expected reimbursement in the form of the treasures that sank with the Méduse. Weiss goes on to compare Géricault’s work to the corresponding painting by Poussin, which was remarkably conventional and “aestheticizing”. For Géricault

160 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs

Figure 9.1: Le radeau de la méduse by Géricault

the important thing was the vision, the psychic phenomenon: his painting does not hold out the promise of safety, which glitters in Poussin. Poussin’s harmonious version evokes a kind of serene devotion, whereas Géricault unhesitatingly forces the spectator into an anguished dream. Géricault puts us amidst a rush into the unknown, forcing us to glimpse a passionate, psychic event. Finally, Weiss tells about Géricault’s own life during those hard years in which he had lost all hope. Painting had turned into a tool with which he dealt with his inner obsession – the madness that threatened to overcome him. He who had portrayed conquered and doomed, had himself succumbed. Weiss states: “But never later was I so convinced [as in Géricault’s atelier] of how, in art, one was able to create values which transgressed the being as excluded and lost, and how by shaping such a vision one could heal melancholy” (Weiss 1978: 30–33). At the same time, he notices that he was suddenly no longer interested in Géricault’s life, since the latter “was, in his giving and taking”, says Weiss, still “connected to universal relationships and bonds that constitute the basis of artistic activity” (ibid.). The just-described example of Weiss is an instance of the aesthetics of resistance in both painting and literature. In music, the same qualities appear in the life and output of composers who go to the core of musical organic process and turn the course of musical events into a counter-current. The spectral composers

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

161

of our time, for example, can use their knowledge and techniques to create sweet sound surfaces, as do Tristan Murail or Kaija Saariaho in her opera, L’Amour de loin. Conversely, and using the same resources, the artist can choose to make music that does not flow pleasingly over the ear; that is, which does not proceed “organically” but anti-organically, denying the normally corporeal logic of music. Such is the music by Finnish composer Harri Vuori, in his new symphony and in earlier works such as Ended Movements (Lopetetut liikkeet). Such music also exemplifies the artist’s willingness to deny the prevailing technological sound culture, to take a critical position towards the dominant TonWelt. Also in Finland, Kalevi Aho’s earlier works foreground the aesthetics of resistance, for instance, his opera Insect Life, and even more cogently, his abstract works such as the Triptych Laokoon and Fifth Symphony. Other music of resistance, in relation to its time, includes Magnus Lindberg’s Kraft in the 1970s. Or one may go even further back in music history, and in this context mention Wagner’s Parsifal, in which time stops and changes into space: when the opera begins everything has already happened. This was indeed an art of resistance, in reaction to the militaristic German empire. On the other hand, resistance does not have to trumpet itself abroad, to be noisily gestural or Fauvist. It can also appear in smaller forms of music that present man’s existential situation in miniature, so to speak, in a kind of simple, tonal language of interiority. Such can be found in the music of young composers in Finland such as Aki Yli-Salomãki, Jan Mikael Vainio, and Tuomas Laurinen, and some young composers in Baltic countries. In such cases, negation as resistance becomes an artistic gesture that follows upon an existential experience of the artist. My aim here, however, is to go even further, and on a deeper level investigate something like the “anti-life” of signs in their counter-current. Certain types of artists and thinkers stand as models of those who do not go with the flow of favored modalities, as Stefan Zweig wrote in his Star Moments of Mankind (1947). In that book he scrutinizes so-called great men, which are often found to be kinds of culminations of human modalities: Will = rulers and explorers; Know = artists and scientists (Handel, Rouget de l’Isle); Can = sportsmen, actors; Must = those who do their duty no matter what the cost. A person’s greatness consists in ascending to the crest of a wave and then riding it. Those are the celebrated heroes. But there is also a more exquisite type of hero, who bases his or her deeds upon the human ability of negation by using kinds of antimodalities: Not-Can, restraining from the use of force (e.g., Gandhi); Not-Will; Not-Must; Not-Know. In Chapter One we outlined Dasein and the transcendence thereof, the journeys of a subject between Daseins, a kind of traveling towards the future, to Dasein

162 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs “x” via transcendental acts of negation and affirmation. As noted in that chapter, our model contains two hidden aspects. The first concerns negation as a kind of alienation or estrangement.² Namely, when the subject temporarily exits his Dasein during his transcendental act, he can stay on this journey for any length of time. It can also happen that, when the subject returns to the world of his Dasein (symbolized by a globe in Figure 1.2), the latter will have changed. During the subject’s journey, that Dasein has itself been in motion, independently of our subject, and perhaps gone in such a direction that our subject does not return to the same world from which he departed. (Heracles long ago observed that we do not step twice into the same stream.) Dasein does not necessarily exist only for our subject nor adapt itself according to his or her existential experiences. The world may well change course during the subject’s absence. The subject that returns to a world quite different from the one he left can either accept and try to adapt to such change, or he can deny it. As noted in Chapter One, a special situation for semiotics of resistance emerges from the latter case. Our subject’s theory of the world does not correspond to it. And as discussed earlier, progress in this case need not mean that one go along with the change, but instead look at alternatives, at what might have happened, at what might have been possible. The arrows of Figure 1.3 showed that things can go backward as well. Our subject recalls his earlier Dasein, and returns to it via memory, which has retained images and ideas from those previous worlds. We earlier noted that he might have forgotten them, and Dasein may have forgotten him. Danger lurks, indeed, if he dwells too long in his position of resistance and outside the Dasein. We noted that real thinkers of resistance are always forgotten and suppressed. Nevertheless, we shall advance some ways by which such resistance might be possible.

9.3.1 Forces of resistance I: Being As is known, Greimas’s basic modalities are Being and Doing (Greimas 1966). In Hegel, Spirit is not mere Being but also Doing (action). For instance, if in an ideological context Being signifies acceptance and even promotion (action on behalf) of the dominant status quo, then one should find a third modality to portray the movement backwards. In English there is the verbal expression to undo, which

2 I am grateful to Vladimir Franta for calling my attention to the notion of negation as “estrangement” or “alienation”.

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

163

might fit here in its sense of “to cancel”. On the other hand, the semiotics of resistance involves not only abolishing something but also creating and indicating new content. What might such a new creative activity be if it were directed backwards? In his Idea of Phenomenology, in the chapter on time-consciousness, Edmund Husserl speaks about two acts: protention and retention (Husserl 1995). By Being he means the purely “now”-moment, which, however, is exceeded not only in protention (reaching toward the future), but also in retention, which preserves the past. Retention concerns the so-called primary memory, whereby we retain an experience in our mind long enough to receive it as a totality. Husserl illustrates this phenomenon with a tone (Bergson and Peirce also used melody as an example of the immediate recognition of a reality). Yet, for a scholar who has studied the life of signs as action, as pragmatic production of codes, merely ontological reflection on being no doubt serves in itself as a kind of resistance. Such is the case with Kant e l’ornitorinco (Eco 1997). As a realist semiotician, Eco argues that being exists, or “is”, before we speak about it. Therefore being precedes discourse; it is something to which we compare our speech if we want to clarify whether the latter is true or not. Eco’s position is in principle the same as Peirce’s; that is to say, behind the object is the so-called dynamic object, which “is” and which “kick-starts” the semiosis into motion. This idea is paradoxical in the same way as Kant’s Ding an sich: the-thing-as-such produces sensations in us by causal relationships that are always filtered through certain categories. But, if we are chained to our sensory categories, then how can we ever know about what the thing-as-such is, or whether “there” is anything?³ For Eco, beyond these categories and signs something exists that demands to be heard: “. . . this dynamic object, so to speak, shouts to us, ‘Speak! Speak about me! Take me into account!’ ” (Eco 1997: 20). From this Eco comes to an ontological question formulated centuries ago by Leibniz: Why is there something rather than nothing? (ibid.: 21). Eco finally concludes, deferring to Thomas Aquinas, that being is like a horizon or a bath, in the confines of which our thought dwells naturally. At the same time, he notices that the question of being is not the same as the problem of the existence of external reality. For Eco, the question of being comes before any empirical being. Nor can the issue be reduced to a problem of language; for example, by transforming it into a typical Indo-European language structure in which a subject is connected to a predicate, in sentences such as “God exists” or “the horse gallops” put into copula forms such as “God is existent” or “the horse is galloping”.

3 For more on this Kantian dilemma, see the work of Finnish semiotician of education, Esa Pikkarainen (2004: 66–69).

164 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs The later Eco (1997) has positive things to say about Heidegger, whom he had criticized negatively in his previous book, Les Limites de l’interprétation (Eco 1992: 59–61). There Heidegger was condemned as a kind of hermetic mystic who postulated that behind every being and word there is some true being, which is visible, or makes itself so, only to the elect. Yet in Heidegger, being always turns into a situation in which true Being (Seiende) appears in Dasein, which is nearest to my own being, and which therefore we cannot speak about except by speaking about ourselves. (Notice that here the category of subject enters the scene.) Heidegger’s thought is, in Eco’s opinion, completely bound up in the German language: Sein, seiende, Da-sein and so on are all terms of Heidegger’s culture. If Heidegger had been born in, say, Oklahoma and had found at his disposal only one word (“to be”), how would that have affected his theory? The fundamental modality of Being is tinged by its “thrown-ness” (Geworfenheit) into the world – flung against its will into some strange place. On the other hand, the subject is anguished by the limits of being in Not-being or death. Therefore Being signifies, according to Eco, an existential understanding of the finite nature of our existence. Eco refers to Vattimo’s interpretation of Heidegger, which distinguishes between “right” and “left” in explanations of the latter’s thought. The former emphasizes the return to being as a kind of negative, apophantic and mystical act; the left, in turn, interprets being historically as a kind of weakening and bidding farewell to history. The first-mentioned interpretation of being has often been criticized. Here we have spoken about genosigns, which bear in themselves their whole development, starting from their emergence as a kind of iconico-ontological process. What a sign is is the result of its basic Being (Tarasti 2004a: 130–136). Remarkably, Greimas’s idea of being is very similar. In his veridictory square, for example, being precedes appearance (manifestation), producing four cases in their combination. Similarly in Greimas, the beginning of the generative narrative process is Being, namely, the existing of isotopies on the deep level. I have criticized both models – Heidegger and Greimas – on the basis that Becoming, in the sense of generation, is not a continuous process starting from basic Being, but that several breaks, ruptures, revolutions, and rearticulations take place during the generative course (Tarasti 2000). In any case, Eco performs a kind of Hegelian experiment: let us suppose the existence of a kind of Spirit and World. Spirit knows the World and tries to speak about it: if the World consists of three atoms A, B, and C, then the Spirit may have three symbols – 1, 2, 3 – with which it names and speaks about the World. In the ideal case, the names match the symbols, such that A = 1, B = 2 and C = 3. Yet the Spirit can also act otherwise, connecting its three symbols in numerous ways and thus producing various manners or languages in which to speak about the World

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

165

(Eco 1992: 42–43). Still, Spirit is in a way also part of the World, and so one can think that World, in its desire to interpret itself, assigns this task to some part of itself: Spirit can “decide” that a certain, distant part of it exists solely for such selfinterpretation. This idea of Eco is naturally a kind of Hegelian parody, in which the Spirit is the most important ingredient of the world. At the same time, it also evokes Lévi-Strauss’s structural studies of the human mind (esprit). If these structures were present everywhere, then were they not also in Lévi-Strauss’s mind as he studied the myths of Indians? Mythical thought had thus taken Lévi-Strauss’s brain to the scene of its being and would interpret itself by it, as he reasons in his several volumes of Mythologiques. In the end Eco returns, in his experiment with Spirit and World, to his previously-held idea of iconic signs as transformations between two entities. The two have a certain amount of similar units, and when one finds such units to be sufficient, it is said that A is iconic sign of B. In such a case, we can state that Spirit is identical with World. Despite his back-tracking, Eco arrives at a category of interest to our study, namely, the resistance of being. Being resists infinite discourse about itself. Eco first accepts Heidegger’s argument that being is always my own being as it is thrown into Dasein. In that state, we sense that our speech about existence has its limits, of which the extreme is the end of our own being. Moreover, so-called nature sets limits on our speech. (Here Eco refers to everyday experience of nature such as day and night, or natural species, in the Darwinian sense.) The existence of biotechnology manifests such limits, as well. Eco alludes to the theory of possible worlds and notes that we can imagine how things might have happened in another way altogether. Still, such reasoning, for Eco, does not form the basis of our being. He allows that there are spheres in our being about which we can speak. Nevertheless, and in a diversity of ways, languages and cultures divide and articulate the continuum of being. All that is significant, everything which signifies, depends on that articulation. Eco asks, Could being, in a more metaphysical sense, mean this continuum before its articulation by culture? In other words, does that continuous “magma” contain lines of resistance and propensities of flow that prompt us to make articulations in a certain manner? Without noticing it, he puts the question of existence in terms of so-called organic meaning: signifying processes that imitate organically the continua of nature and which would thus be, so to say, universal and natural. Theoreticians of social constructions and scholars of civilization (such as Norbert Elias) would certainly hesitate to accept this view. Yet the difference between the overtly historical view and Eco’s structuralist approach can be resolved in Hegelian terms, by the fact that these articulations, the segmentation of continua as described by Eco, can be examined as processes in which the Spirit gradually realizes itself. The Being of now and today is the consequence

166 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs of what was before; all choices among alternatives, among various cultural articulations, are processes bound with time and history (which need not lead to the historicizing and relativizing of phenomena, as occurs with Paul Ricoeur). What is involved is a phenomenon of a deeper level, a phenomenon that has to be elucidated as the core problem of any historical process and temporality of signs. For Eco, Being is ultimately something positive, and its denial or negation is merely a linguistic trick (Eco 1992: 57). Yet, Norbert Elias says the following about the birth of civilité: It may perhaps seem at first sight an unnecessary complication to investigate the genesis of each historical formation. But since every historical phenomenon, human attitudes as much as social institutions, did actually once “develop”, how can modes of thought prove either simple or adequate in examining these phenomena if, by any kind of abstraction, they isolate the phenomena from their natural, historical flow, deprive them of their character as movement and process, and try to understand them as static formations without regard to the way in which they have come into being and change? (Elias 1978: xv)

Steering between what he calls the Scylla of static theory and Charybdis of historical relativism, Elias’s psychogenetic and sociogenetic investigation sets out to reveal the “order underlying historical changes, their mechanics and their concrete mechanisms” (ibid.). From this point of view, Being, in its static nature, is not the appropriate point of departure. The only correct epistemic theory would be a model of flux. In Eco, Being forms resistance to discourse. We cannot develop infinitely our speculations without deciding whether they are significant to our existence. Perhaps unaware of it, Eco comes to accept the hermeneutic idea of preunderstanding: the being which exists before explanation and which makes the latter meaningful. If we, as Heidegger, accept the idea that Being and Dasein are my Being, then we have included the subject. Further, we have discarded our behaviorist-positivist models, in which our being is made out to be mostly an illusion, in which we are treated as mere objects. If we reject this theory as one of the ideological errors mentioned at the beginning of this chapter, we are led to think that a semiotics of resistance might be sought in this direction. We can go still further and ask, Is it conceivable that signs and the habitual, “common-sense” temporal axis might have their own counter-current (Figure 3.2)? Might this counter-current also constitute resistance to the straightforward movement of being as it is supposed to unfold? Very often, and dangerously so, certain forms of civilization use myths in order to justify and legitimate themselves as “natural”. Therefore one has to be careful when speaking about the natural becoming of signs and about “normal” temporal processes. For they, too, might be only cultural practices:

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

167

le Néant

Dasein

$I¿UPatiRn Figure 9.2: Temporal axis, showing forward and backward currents

9.3.2 Forces of resistance II: Memory Memory is one of the fundamental experiences of mankind and one of its historic themes. All over the world we can follow the traces of mankind in architecture, art, narration, myths. It is commonly thought that real culture, in the German sense of the word as interiority and profundity, is based upon memory. Among other things, so-called living music culture is based upon music that is remembered, music that stays in one’s mind. (Boris Asafiev referred to that phenomenon with his concept of memorandum.) When we return home from a concert, for example, we do not remember all of the music we just heard, but probably only one tune, which we continue humming. When we listen to a familiar piece of music, previous hearings of it are evoked by association, and thereby we start to listen to our own life story, our own history. Or we may be joined to the Hegelian Volksgeist of the nation: “. . . the conception of spirit which realized history. What a spirit knows about itself that constitutes the consciousness of a people . . . ” (Hegel 1917: 36). For instance, when a Frenchman hears the Marseillaise, he participates in the collective memory of his people. The same occurs when a Pole hears Chopin’s Revolutionary Étude, when the Italian hears Verdi, and so on. The great theme of literature is memory. The monumental cycle of novels by Proust begins with a memory, which Henri Bergson called mémoire involontaire (Bergson 1982 [1939]). In Proust, entire worlds and fates emerge from the unconscious, all catalyzed by a single sign (a sound, taste, smell, perfume, gesture). The themes of return and of remembering the past are crucial in literature, as in Evelyn Waugh’s Brideshead Revisited. To remember means that some place or

168 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs time or person is “revisited”; in a sense, the absent past is made present, but in transcendental form. Memory, an apt and well-used vehicle for transcendence, is also a force for resistance: as long as subjects can remember how things were done in their culture and community, they are saved by their identity. The following quote comes from my travel book, New Mysteries of Paris: History represents collective memory. History-less, synchronic societies . . . like media society, do not possess a “memory” in this sense . . . . Every art work is a paradigm of memory and when we experience it, a reminiscence remains for us . . . . Art work can be detached from its original world and transferred to a new environment. When one sees immortal works of European art in an American museum, or [in a concert hall in that country] hears a performance of Beethoven, the experience is no longer that of the same Rembrandt, El Greco or Beethoven, but of something else. How is this possible, even though the work itself is the same? Because those invisible threads of memory, those nets knitted by the Norns, which connect art to a certain destiny, have broken; people no longer remember them . . . . Memory is power . . . someone decides what is remembered . . . . Man’s ability to create signification is completely bound with memory. For what is the value of signs if there is no memory to preserve them? Even if we . . . experience something existentially . . . that is not sufficient to us. The experience must be preserved, maintained. (Tarasti 2004c: 100–103)

There is thus no question of resisting the force of memory. One should rather ask, On what kind of mental mechanism is memory based? My concern here is not with psychological theories of memory, but with its philosophical content. Henri Bergson distinguishes between matière et mémoire as two phases or elements of memory (Bergson 1982: 163): (1) first, something is presented to a consciousness; (2) what is represented becomes logically or causally connected with what preceded or followed it. The reality of any mental object or psychological state is based on a double fact: that our consciousness observes it, and that it belongs to a series, either temporal or spatial, in which the terms define each other. Peirce would have called such a chain an example of “unlimited semiosis”. Upon this epistemic foundation Bergson distinguishes two species of memory. First, there is the permanent memory of the organism. It designates all those mechanisms whereby the organism is able to react to various challenges of its environment. This species is in fact a habit rather than a memory. It consists of our past experiences, but it does not form images. The second kind of memory is true memory; it sorts and preserves all our experiences and puts them in their proper places. On the other hand, this memory has to function as an immobile storage place in constantly mobile time, whereas the apex of memory blends together with the present, which changes and continuously moves according to the scheme shown in Figure 9.3.

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

169

Figure 9.3: The functioning of the memory according to Bergson

The level AB means the store of memory, with S as its apex, which touches the surface of reality. It is therefore clear that, so understood, the memory directs, from point S, our acts and choices in the present.

9.3.2.1 Remembering similitude As did Bergson, Rudolph Carnap, another great thinker though from a completely different school (the Vienna circle), built his entire world-view upon the concept of memory. In his treatise, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Carnap argues that reality is based on a unified “field of entities” that can be described or “constituted”. To constitute, for him, means the following: a being, entity, or concept can be reduced to another entity when all the expressions concerning it can be reshaped into expressions concerning those other entities. For Carnap, science can only describe structures: there is no difference between spiritual and physical entities; there is only one field of beings. Statements about physical entities can be reduced to statements about perception (Wahrnehmungen). Carnap defines autopsychic and alien-psychic entities as follows: the psychic states of an alien-psychic subject can be perceived only via physical entities, but the observation of our own psychic states requires no physical mediation. Rather, it occurs immediately. Carnap puts his entities in the following, descending order of importance: (4) spiritual entities; (3) alien-psychic entities; (2) physical entities; (1) autopsychic entities. His starting point is so-called “elementary experience”, which in turn is based upon “reminiscence” (Ähnlichkeitserinnerung). When one notices a similarity between two elementary experiences, x and y, then the previous occurrence in memory x has to be compared to y. The asymmetrical relationship portraying such an occurrence of perception y means that between x and y there prevails a reminiscence of similitude (Erinnerung). However, by reminiscence Carnap does not refer to our keeping in mind some experience that has just occurred,

170 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs but not yet vanished, and that is still influencing experience (Husserl’s notion of retention). Rather, the foundation of the Carnapian system lies in longerrange memory. It is interesting, for instance, how he “constitutes” other persons’ elementary experience of the world by their means of expression and how they impart information (we would say: by their sign relationships). Also of interest is how Carnap constitutes values from the experiences that one has with them. Carnap argues that to do so is not a matter of psychologizing. Value itself is not experiential, but exists independently from its instantiation as experience. In experience, value only becomes observable. What is essential for Carnap is the “reminiscence of similarity”: the recognition of values at moment S by a comparison of that moment to the “values” of the store AB⁴. Carnap interprets causality as a purely interoceptive phenomenon; that is to say, cause and effect are concepts of the experiential world, not of physical reality. Here he continues a line of critique going back at least to David Hume. For in Carnap’s system, what ultimately distinguishes real entities from unreal ones consists of the following principles: (1) every psychic entity belongs to a more extensive, law-like system, physical entities belong to a law-like physical system, psychic entities to a psychic system, and so forth; (2) every real entity is intersubjective; (3) every real entity has its place in a temporal order. In other words, entities are defined as identical or different on the basis of memory, which compares them to other entities and puts them into a temporal axis. What is essential is that this activity is intersubjective; that is, others besides myself can replicate this kind of thinking. In this respect, one might say that the Carnapian system differs from the Heideggerian Being, which is always being mediated by ego. Of course, this is the case even in the Carnapian autopsychic system, in which the smallest comparable units are elementary experiences; yet, they are “pure” experiences, so to speak, which do not depend on the subject carrying them. Husserl, in his phenomenology, believed likewise; but Heidegger did not. If we then think of Bergson and the aforementioned store of memories AB, which is included in each of our acts, then we constantly live “backward”: phenomena and experiences of our now-moment, on the surface of our reality, are immediately transferred to the store of memory, from which the movement continues back to other experiences to which the now-moments are compared. It is precisely in this manner that the richness of the experiential world emerges. In semiotics, an analogous case is poetry, whose richness of language, according to Roman

4 One might ask if Carnap’s recognition of values at moment S by comparing that moment to the “values” of the store AB involves an iconic or an indexical relationship.

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

171

Jakobson’s famous definition, derives from the same kind of projection: of a paradigm into a syntagm. The same occurs in Peirce’s Firstness, which we “live” at the apex of S. In Secondness this experience has already been transported to the level of AB; in Thirdness, it is compared to the entire store. In fact, the entire movement of our subject(ivity) takes place against the grain, so to speak, against the counter-current. The idea of a continuous becoming is, thus, an illusion. Hegel declares the substance of the Spirit to be freedom. The goal of the Spirit in history is thus the freedom of the subject: freedom to have knowledge and morality, to have common goals, in order that the collective subject might have infinite value: “. . . this goal of the spirit of the world is reached by the freedom of everyone” (Hegel 1917: 41). Hegel later states that this goal has not yet been attained: “Spirit is not a piece of nature, like an animal. The animal is what it is immediately. Spirit is what it does of itself, what makes it what it is. Its being is in its activity, not in peaceful existence; its being is an absolute process”. (ibid.: 52)

Why do we quote Hegel so often and so closely? It is because the idea of freedom, particularly in Hegel, is the one which Anglo-analytic philosophers have scoffed at the most. And one cannot deny that certain comical elements do appear in Hegelian reasoning: In the Orient only one was free: the despot; in antiquity some were free but others slaves. Nowadays, i.e. in contemporary Germany [at the beginning of the nineteenth century!], all are free, since they are conscious of themselves, as spiritual beings.

Of course, we cannot read Hegel almost two centuries later with any sort of naïve immediacy. We read him via a filter of interpretation. This occurs, for example, when we think, Aha! . . . spirit! . . . the global community of our time . . . Baudrillard’s bubble world, and the like. Therefore, it is essential to heed the following: the representation of reality from the subject’s activity – retention, reminiscence of similitude, and other operations – at the same time represents the liberation of our subject from false restrictions. It is the subject’s way of resisting the constitution-model of the global world into which he or she is constantly being forced. What is involved here is the return of the valuation of the subject and of his liberation. Pure philosophy can in this way be provided with ideological content. Science, however, can never posit values, but only investigate them. On the one hand, all arguments can be read ideologically, and all research is guided by some ideology. On the other hand, any argument advanced by science cannot set values but only examine them. Since all judgements can be read ideologically, and all

172 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs research be guided by some ideology, it is crucial that a scholar be conscious of his/her ideological position. For when we are aware of such, and when we put the aforementioned philosophies (from Hegel to Bergson and Carnap) in the context of forces of resistance, then we know what we are doing and are thus able to observe the ideological nature of our reasoning, so that we do not stray from objectivity or intersubjective validity.

9.3.2.2 Counterfactuality The models we have dealt with thus far concern the surface of reality, its recollection, its store of memory, the now-moment, causality. In the background looms the subject, whose very being is involved. What, then, does it mean to say that this subject’s goal would be “freedom”? It means that the course of the subject is not predetermined, but that an energetic action can take place by the subject, which, through its acts, moulds its reality. How can that process be analyzed more closely? Instead of dealing not only with what something has been, with its registration in memory – in the form, say, of the texts of history and arts – we can also inquire as to what might have been. What if a subject had chosen otherwise? This concern brings our inquiry to what Anglo-analytic philosophy refers to as a so-called “counterfactual” statement. The Finnish philosopher, Georg Henrik von Wright has examined counterfactual statements, and what follows deals with some ideas presented in his lectures and my notes on those ideas. The counterfactual statement is as follows: “If p had been, then q would have been as well”. The statement is also possible if non-p prevails. (The most common expression, “If . . . then”, describes causality.) In other words, we scrutinize here cases that could have occurred under certain conditions. The freedom of our subject and the Hegelian Spirit, which is always in the process of becoming free, are of course tightly bound with what might have been possible. In this way, modal concepts necessarily penetrate into causal explanation, despite the fact that the positivist attitude in philosophy is very skeptical of modal concepts. Let us imagine that the surface of reality, the series of Bergsonian nowmoments, could be described with a line:

Next we can probe our knowledge of what lies beneath the surface of the given, linear reality. In that case, the counterfactual statement is an argument about what is, rather than about what might be or what might have been. The graphic representation of the counterfactual statement would thus be the following:

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

173

Figure 9.4: Structure of the counterfactual statement

The models above portray alternativity: from the world of the past, alternative −P was realized. But the alternative P & Q also would have been possible. Only via this alternative does discourse on possibilities become meaningful, and only via this alternative can one speak about the freedom of an acting agent. From this, can we further infer that the more alternatives, the more freedom our subject has? If so, it would confirm that the further world history proceeds, in the Hegelian sense, the freer the “Spirit” becomes, since it would have more and more alternatives stored in its paradigm of memory. In that case, the degree of freedom is essentially bound with memory, that is to say, with the fact that the subject recalls previous events and becomes aware of them. Such recollections and awareness give purpose to world history, as described by Hegel in the following statement: World history presents . . . the development of the consciousness of the spirit beginning from its freedom and the fulfilment of such a consciousness. Development means that it is a gradual unfolding, a series of determinations of freedom, which with a concept anticipates issues [and] the nature of the freedom of the spirit [becomes] conscious of itself. The logical and dialectical nature of the concept lies in the fact that it determines itself and carries in itself definitions and rejects them, and in this rejection or negation attains its positive and richer, more concrete determination. This necessity and contingency of purely abstract definitions of concepts is studied in logics. (Hegel 1917: 148)

In the quotation above, Hegel refers to the same process that von Wright describes. Yet von Wright inquires into that reality of the past which unites the aforementioned alternatives (Hegel’s Begriffsbestimmungen). Where is the starting point of

174 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs those alternatives? What now-moment in Bergson’s model opens up that point of view? What occurs is a shift from temporality to counterfactual examination. We get a series of consecutive situations:

Figure 9.5: Alternatives under the surface of the reality

The connection from A to its causal consequence (if P then Q, or P Q) is not visible and thus not observable. What, then, justifies drawing a line from the surface of reality to its alternative or possibility? Von Wright’s answer is that at least once in the past, the occurrence A P Q must have occurred. That experience demonstrates that after A, P is possible. This perception is a necessary condition for drawing the figure. But is it a sufficient one? Similarly, world A sometimes precedes P, and sometimes −P. It must be underlined that, if we accept this argument, then in reality nothing would ever happen that has not already happened at least once before. It follows that the possibilities of the “spirit” of history for creative activity would be highly restricted. Yet, even intuitively speaking, there must be acts and consequences that are new, unique and unpredictable. According to von Wright, what is thought about the depth of possibilities is largely a consequence of what is observed on the surface of a given reality. Our conception of potentialities is a reconstruction of possibilities based upon what we know about the surface of that reality. In the context of theories of memory, such a conception is based upon retention: what we have stored in our paradigm of memory determines our view of what might have happened. Applied to history, at both the individual and collective levels, this would mean that, the more alternatives of which individuals are aware – either on the basis of their own experience or of historical descriptions – then the freer they are. To this point, Heidegger’s concepts of Dasein and Da-sein serve to distinguish between the entire reality, with its possibilities and alternatives (Dasein), and the mere surface of reality, or just being-there (Da-sein).

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

175

For the semiotics of resistance, this distinction is essential. If the surface of reality is occupied, and subordinated to, an ideology or hegemony, then it is essential that alternatives to that ideology be recognized. The more alternatives, and the more the subject becomes conscious of them, together increase the resistance. Yet, in some cases it also prevents action: the more critical one becomes, the more difficult it is to choose the right alternative, and the harder it is to start defending it with the full passion (Passion, Leidenschaft) that Hegel considered an indispensable force in history. On the other hand, one must note that not just any observation about the surface of reality can or does fulfil its potentials. We select certain observations according to images that we have even prior to the perception of potentials. Hence it would be a great mistake for one not to distinguish among and weigh the different possibilities as weaker and stronger. (In this light, one can consider the surface of reality to be a particularly “strong” alternative.) Concerning the model of cause and effect, for example, P would lose its causal role (its force as a cause related to Q) if we cannot claim that there is a valid alternative to P. Of course, one can also say that, if we want to become convinced about the validity of some counterfactual statement, then we do something: we produce the needed situation. But if a largescale, collective event is involved, then we of course cannot create it artificially; instead, we resort to our historical memory and judge whether something similar could have happened earlier. In any case, a sign of a genuine act is a genuine alternative. What gives us full certainty about the worth of alternatives is that they enable us to intervene in the course of the reality, and the fact that they provide us with something we can choose. For instance, we know the following:

Figure 9.6: Possible choices in a situation

We can say that A is the reason for (or cause of) P only in the situation A, in which both P and −P are as possible. If we are passive, then the world changes into P; if we intervene in the world, then −P follows. What would have happened if we had not allowed the world to change into −P? This question is justified by the fact

176 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs that the situation is in our control. Therefore we get a chain of interconnected concepts: causality is based upon counterfactuality, and the latter, in turn, is based upon the concept of act. For our theory of semiotics of resistance, what is most essential is that the matter of memory brings us to referring backwards, to the counter-current of signs, to the pondering of what might have been possible (counterfactuality). We have shown here that to do so is possible, via theories of memory (Husserl, Bergson, Carnap) based upon the retention of the subject, the comparison of the now-moment with moment S and its alternatives AB – ultimately, the comparison of moment S with the recognition of the values retained as paradigms, the storehouse of values, their “encyclopaedia”, to use Eco’s term. At the same time, it has been argued here that this return is possible as a logical, mental operation only if it is conceived as the act of a subject. Such a subject can effect this operation by means of many alternatives, whether they are previously fulfilled connections between P and Q, or perhaps imaginative innovations, which our subject infers to be possible in his or her situation. Altogether, this shows that, even in those realities in which everything seems to be linked to only one scheme of events, there are alternatives, depending on our subject’s mental capacities and paradigm of memory.

9.3.2.3 Causality Causality is a central philosophical category that, moreover, comes amazingly close to the idea of communication. We arrive here at the core of semiotics: Can one conceive of communication as causal activity? If so, then what would counterfactuality mean in communication? In the speech-act theories of Austin and Searle, the focus is on the speech act as communication or intention. But, as Karl Jaspers once asked, Why do we want to communicate? Would it not be better not to communicate, that is, to be alone? (Jaspers 1948: 338) Before an act of communication, the agent can choose whether to communicate or not. But after the sign has been emitted, it cannot be canceled. (Computers, of course, have an “undo” function, even for e-mail, which one can use to retract a communication; left as it stands, however, the message is indelibly and irretractably there.) When Mr. A sends a signal to Mr. B, in the famous diagram by Saussure, does that process represent causal influence? The answer is, of course, Yes, if one thinks that the effect or consequence is the meaning-effect that emerges in the mind of the receiver, Mr. B. If Mr. B’s behavior changes after he receives the message, then it doubtless has had a causal effect. On the same issue, Finnish semiotician of education, Esa Pikkarainen, has this to say: “Causal effect is therefore a change in some entity, which happens because it has come through a certain relationship to

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

177

some or some other entities . . . The partners of the causal relationship are beings and not events . . . . In order to have a causal relation at least one partner must have the ‘causal power’ to make the other partner change in one way or another” (Pikkarainen 2004: 69). In communication, however, we do not always intend or mean to cause changes. Jakobson describes this special kind of communication (phatic) as participating in the conative function. Yet, say, in autocommunication, wherein the sender and receiver are one, it is hard to see what the “effect” would be, namely, how the world has changed after the communication. Can we also think of a counter-current of signs in communication? Can we aim the arrow of communication to go counter-clockwise? Paul Ricoeur (2000), in his magisterial treatise La mémoire, l’histoire, l’oubli, closes with a chapter on “Le pardon difficile”, in which he deals with the themes of guilt, giving and forgiveness, of happy memory and unhappy history, and in the end, with the theme of forgetting. If we repent of sending a message and want to cancel it – which is impossible, if it has already happened – there remain alternatives: to regret, forget, and forgive. This is the only way to go against the counter-stream of communication and to cancel what has happened. This is true in spite of what one reads in Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov, when the oldest member of a monastery says that a man’s acts accrue to him, until time runs out and nothing more can be done.

9.3.3 Forces of resistance III: History Perhaps unnoticeably, we have come through philosophy (both phenomenology and Anglo-analytic logic) and arrived at problems of history. The sense of history forms an essential aspect of resistance to the global reality of real, synchronic time. It can also prevent savage theorizing and experimentation in science, life practices, and social processes. The causal relationship is one of the most central ones in historical investigation, as Raymond Aron notes in his Introduction to the Philosophy of History (Aron 1948 [1961]). He joins the causal relationship to the question of responsibility. Moral, legal and historical responsibilities are all based on the same logical scheme: the search for reasons. The basic difference among them concerns the order of reasons: a moralist studies intentions, historians study acts, and lawyers relate acts and intentions to judicial concepts. The historically responsible person is one who, by his or her actions, catalyzes an event whose origin is sought. In Aron’s view, any historical investigation is, by definition, retrospective. All causal research looks backwards. A historian starts with effects and goes back to antecedents. But a fact always has a number of antecedents. How, then, can we determine the true cause?

178 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs To this situation, one could add that a historian’s work is always abductive, a form of guess-work in getting at the reason. But as Aron states, the historian can only be psychologically – never “mathematically” rigorous – certain of having found the real reason or cause. Even if Napoleon did cause the defeat at Waterloo, I shall never be able to prove it, because that historical sequence of events, unique in time and peculiar in quality, can never recur. Hence every historian, in order to examine what happened, must ask what might have happened. For instance, Leonard B. Meyer (1989), in his Style and Music, considers the examination of alternatives a central factor in music history. The genius of an individual composer (Mozart, Haydn, and the like) can show itself only against the background of alternatives that a composer of that time could have used, that is to say, the contemporaneous network of possibilities. Aron recommends the following research strategy: (1) analysis of the phenomenon-effect; (2) discrimination of antecedents and the isolation of one of them, the efficiency of which is to be measured; (3) the construction of unreal developments, including alternatives, or “counterfactuals” in our earlier terminology; (4) comparison of mental images and the actual events (Aron 1948: 161). It is, however, often impossible in practice to isolate a single immediate cause, since the causes can of course be quite general in nature. Thus we come to sociological theories in which the causes of an individual event are believed to lie in complex social and statistical processes. As examples of such vast, tightly procedural studies of history, one can mention Fernand Braudel’s Matérialisme et capitalisme (1967 [1973]) and Norbert Elias’s Studien über die Deutschen: Machtkämpfe und Habitusentwicklung im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert (1989 [1997]). In the first-mentioned text, the background theory is a view of human material life as characterized by routines and in which changes occur very slowly. Braudel dares to use the term “progress”, but underlines that, though it proceeds very slowly, it is not totally static. His examination concerns the period from the fifteenth to the nineteenth century. In contrast, Elias focuses on shorter time periods, namely, the development of the German national habitus or character. The latter is in turn based on the dialectics between inner and outer forces⁵, on the civilization process, whose special nature and collapse in Germany are Elias’s quarry. This study, too, involves events on a large temporal scale, in which individual acts remain in the background and the criteria of explanation lie in general social processes. The case of Elias clearly illustrates that national histories are still being written. But as Ricoeur asks (2000: 396), Is it still possible to write “cosmopolitan” or

5 For more on the dialectics between inner and outer forces, refer back to the analysis of the principles of Moi and Soi, in Chapter One.

9.3 Aesthetics of resistance

|

179

“world histories”? Specialized histories constitute a resistance to globalizing histories in which the present is so strongly prioritized that the past is not appreciated at all. Such globalizing histories seem to accelerate and, hence, to rush headlong to the end of history itself, by portraying so many events occurring within such relatively short periods of time. As early as the French annalists, history was being distinguished into different levels, such as long-, medium-, and short-term structures, a distinction also used by Greimas in his Sémantique structurale (Greimas 1980: 172). To write a “structural history” is to take some institutional or mental entity as an invariable quantity and schema, into which framework the historical changes and details are inserted. Such reasoning is not far from Kant’s ideas about history, nor from Hegel’s action of the “Spirit” in world history. The notion of “idea” or leading principle has been replaced by that of structure. Lotman’s school of semiotics, for instance, supposes that the structure of a “text” is a universal, multileveled formation comprised of phonetics, metrics, syntax, semantics and symbols. Using this constant structure, Lotmanian semioticians have been able to reconstruct ancient Slavonic texts, once considered beyond recovery, by postulating units that take the place of missing elements, that is to say, units which should be there in order for the structure to be completed. (In principle, this reasoning is not far from the astronomy of the Renaissance, which supposed that a certain heavenly body had to exist in order for the mathematical and musical scale of eight tones to be fulfilled [cf. Eco 1986: 32].) Narrativity can in this way serve as such a structure. Historical research is naturally narrative, and all that is considered discourse obeys the laws of narration. Ricoeur scrutinizes history as narrative, but with the warning that the latter cannot function as an explanatory or epistemological criterion. In their work, of course, historians encounter narratives – stories of events – out of which they create their own narratives. A narrative theory that has developed from legends, folklore, and myths is considered by historians as too primitive to serve as a model for the writing of modern history. Narration easily leads one to study history as “individual cases” against which Braudel juxtaposed his long-term changes. For historians (and others), the greatest attraction of the narrative model is the concept of “plot”, since the latter organizes temporal events into a given order. Something changes into something else – this has been taken as the minimal condition for any narrative. Further, the plot has an impact on people’s behaviour. Lotman’s essay on theatricality provides us with good examples: The last words of heroes of the French Revolution often seem like speeches from antiquity. Ludwig II from Bavière, for example, felt that he had conducted himself like the protagonist of a Wagnerian opera. Thus, plots can be shifted from one domain of life to another. Insofar as the writing of history uses the same narrative structure

180 | 9 Semiotics of resistance: Being, memory, history, and the counter-current of signs as that of a fictional story, the text becomes its own reality and its connection to the real world is lost. Thus, the historian has to probe details and piece together fragments. Ricoeur speaks instead about the “scale” of durations, borrowing the term from cartography. When we look at a map, it is essential that we know the scale to which it has been drawn. Similarly, in historical investigation we must ask first if it concerns micro- or macro-history. The object of micro-historical studies can be an individual, whose life is scrutinized in all its details; but at the same time, that individual is understood to represent something more general. The microhistory which thus emerges can come dangerously close to unreliable, anecdotal history, or local history in its extreme. Braudel rejected such accounts as a “history of events”, since one cannot know anything about a single, unrepeated event. Paradoxically, an individual event is significant only if it has been repeated, as Carlo Ginzburg has noted. In semiotics, an equivalent view of “event” is Eco’s theory that semiotics cannot tell what a work or text was or meant to someone, but rather studies the structures that enabled such an experience. This thesis, however, is denied by existential semiotics, as argued earlier. Ginzburg takes Tolstoi’s War and Peace as an example of micro-history in which the individual (peace) and the public (war) interpenetrate. Micro-history is a kind of anti-narration when compared to theories of great men, in which, according to Hegel’s model, the reader’s attention is captured by exceptional personalities. In a chapter entitled “The Destiny of an Individual”, he says the following: “Let us fix our gaze on world-historical individuals and their fates, who have had the joy of functioning as leaders in the realization of a purpose that forms only one phase in the general course of development” (Hegel 1917: 78). But in general can one think, in the context of historical exploration, of antinarrativity in a sense other than texts that declare the end of history, its vanishing by becoming synchronized with the world? The fact is that all history, as a retrospective activity, as collective or individual memory, is also a narration of resistance, because in such activity one always transcends the surface of reality. In this respect, merely to defend the existence of history is itself resistance – and progress.

9.4 What are we resisting? It is proper to end with a self-critical look at what was said above. Namely, if all theories are only rationalisations of certain life experiences and positions of a scholar, then the same must be true about the present essay on the semiotics of

9.4 What are we resisting?

|

181

resistance. To make the question more precise: In the end, what has been (or is being) resisted here? Have I fallen into the trap of which Ricoeur warns, namely, the idea that the present time is somehow qualitatively different from previous times? Modernity – “our” time – is especially privileged when one wants to join (or intervene) in the classical activity of history-writing on the theme of the worsening decadence of modern times and symptoms of apocalyptic destruction, as compared to a past, now-lost, “golden age” when everything was better. If many have taken the “present day” or one’s own era as somehow decadent (and this has been happening at least since the seventeenth century), it is clear that the decline cannot stem from mere chronology but from some other paradigm or context, into which we try to insert our own time. Today is most notable by the vanishing of the moral dimension (Charles Taylor’s thesis): the loss of sense and meaning, accompanied by the search to regain it. The second main theme of our time is the development of technology, which threatens our freedom; and the third is the supremacy of the state. For Taylor, the first of these problems leads to the ethics of self-realization of ego, of defense of authenticity, the central value of the principle of Moi. By contrast, the worst fault of Hegel was his exceedingly strong emphasis on state or world history, or Soi. Yet, such argumentation means a relativization of the phenomenon, an historicism, as when one adopts an anthropological position. In all these relativizations we reduce the phenomenon to something else: “It is only this or that.” Globalization and its values, whose principles were summed up in my list of 14 points, can only belong to this type of literature of resistance, which has been available as early as Antiquity and the classics therefrom. Our point of departure, however, has been the phenomenological principle that the thing has to be examined as such. This requires that we engage with the existential situation of the people of our time as it appears. Being is precisely our being here and now. The Heideggerian concern, about the surrounding world in which we live, is the only credible fulcrum for theoretical reflection. But in order to speak about our own situation we have to take distance from colloquial speech and create a special metalanguage – a unique discourse and concepts with which to analyze adequately our being. To that end, I have dealt here with three important categories – being, memory and history – aspects of which can illuminate and engage with the situation of our time. At the same time, my aim has been not to lose contact with the reality of this situation, not even for one moment. We can write science about reality, at the same time as we participate in it.

Chapter 10 Culture and transcendence Is an existential semiotic theory of culture possible? Such a question came to my mind when reading recent studies and books on British cultural theory. This theory, which seems to have become dominant in many fields of social sciences and humanities and which represents to me those theories belonging to the ‘nothing but . . . ’ category, is almost unavoidable in the academic world nowadays. It is taken as a given. No one seems to be aware of its inherent cultural imperialism, which favours the contemporary, globalized, technosemiotic, market-, media- and consumption-oriented culture which is expanding over the whole world. It is at the same time a way of relativizing all other alternative views of cultures and all different approaches to these issues. The culture emerging from this new ‘cultural theory’ is nothing but an ideological version of the present world civilization. That remains the case even if we were to admit that culture can, after all, be a transcendental issue, since often the ideas, identities, etc. to which it constantly refers are absent, transcendental entities which in spite of this exercise a strong emotional appeal and have power over people’s minds. However, transcendence is totally relativized in just the same way as it was by sociology and history during the sociosemiotic phase of our societies. Communities in which we live are to a great deal imagined, just as Benedict Anderson tries to show. Does it mean that they are ‘transcendental’? Yet the major question about cultures, when they become objects of scientific research and discussion, is whether there could exist a meta-cultural theory which would be more than an ideological reflection of one culture, albeit the victorious one. A hope of such a theory would seem to be the only possibility of avoiding those ‘cross-cultural misunderstandings’ which Walburga von RafflerEngel once discussed. To discover or elaborate such a theory is a challenge indeed for the concept of transcendence itself and its explanatory power for the mundane affairs of our Dasein. However, taking into account such an issue as transcendence does not mean a shift to, for example, theology. Societies which seem to try to function upon the transcendental principle, i.e., varieties of religion, have often proved to be inefficient over a longer period. Thus, in order to obtain an existential semiotic theory of culture, it is not sufficient to apply only the idea of transcendence. One needs other aspects as well, such as seeing the situation from within, and following the ethical principle of the subject’s ability to make choices and thus influence his/her fate in the world. Any such theory which denies this subjective point of view is certainly not existential. The cold and inhuman theories of structuralism, like Michel Foucault’s, are deterministic in this sense. There is

10 Culture and transcendence |

183

something lifeless, extremely pessimistic and passive in those theories regarding man – who is, however, a political and active animal; such a creature as he appears in, among others, the writings of Hanna Arendt. She describes her subject as fighting against the dictatorship of conditions (a term also used by the Finnish philosopher Georg Henrik v. Wright), and for the ‘infinitely improbable’, which can be achieved in spite of everything. The Foucaultian vision of society evokes La Mettrie’s idea of l’homme machine – or Jean Cocteau’s machine infernale, a cruel game played with humans by the Gods. The existential semiotic view is never like that; it always gets into the skin of the protagonists of human history, its agents – and these agents can be anyone, not only in the Heideggerian negative sense of das Man – but any subject in his/her existential situations. When lecturing recently on the theme What is Existential Semiotics at the Finnish Science Society in Helsinki, I was asked by my colleague, Professor of Translation Theory Andrew Chesterman: ‘Are there any means to test your theory, or to forecast or predict something with it?’ I said to him: ‘you are very British’ – which was not intended to be an argumentum ad hominem, but to raise the eternal question whether philosophical theories in the humanities can be tested, or even need testing, by experiments or empirical facts; I wanted to point out that the truth criteria in these issues might be different from the traditional correspondence theory with its word-thing issues, being based instead on the coherence of the new model of reading facts, a new conceptual metalanguage. Then our discussion continued and my colleague put aside the idea of testing and made his criticism in another way: ‘Can you imagine any evidence which would show your theory is wrong?’ Here I distinguished a Peircean undertone of fallibilism, i.e., that scientific theories are characterized by their constant renewal when they are shown to be erroneous and that progress, if any, in science was based precisely upon this. However, the hypothesis from which I start myself is that conceptual and philosophical theories are almost always nothing but absolutizations of the personal life experiences of the scholar. If this were true, to say that a theory is wrong would mean: a) your experience has been wrong, or b) the manner you inferred your theory from your experiences, i.e., your reasoning, has been wrong. The first point would be truly tricky: how could you say to anyone that your experience, your life history, growing into a person, into an identity and into a profession from a mere physical body, was wrong? To claim such a thing would mean to undervalue and even be contemptuous of a person and of subjectivity. Yet, there are standpoints which do this. Marxists say: You represent falsches Bewusstsein and therefore your ideas are wrong. Psychoanalysts say: You are neurotic, that is why what you say does not tell us what you really are; according to the Lacanian principle, your signifiers do not reflect your true signifieds; feminists and gender theoreticians say: you represent a repressive chauvinist ideology, a patriarchal order; accordingly,

184 | 10 Culture and transcendence your standpoint is conditioned by your gender position and cannot represent any ultimate truth, nor even any authenticity. However, I have to leave this debate so as not to stray from the subject. The other point of view, i.e., my theory is wrong due to erroneous reasoning, is closer to the ‘normal’ evaluation in science and humanities. A theory is wrong or right depending on whether it represents his intuition for the scholar and whether he is able to express and communicate it to other members of the scientific community. However, let us also take the idea of testing a theory seriously to the extent that we could try to find out what kinds of cultural, psychological, and social phenomena could be understood and explained by applying to them the existential semiotic viewpoint. Taking into account the huge quantity of mankind’s cultural experiences, what we call ‘traces of humanity’ (I remember Jaroslav Jiránek saying so), we might try to interpret them by applying our existential theory and asking whether it functions as a cultural theory or not. Pursuing this line I would propose that we could use the international research project Semiotics of cultural heritages, with its approximately 60 young and more advanced scholars all over the world, as the empirical field where we could apply our theory. However, before doing so we should define what our existential theory is in this respect, and which elements of it are relevant here. In the semiotic tradition, we may ask how the other cultural theories have succeeded in progressing along the same line or digressing from it in other directions. We need to ask whether we can use the existential theory to criticize or approve the already existing cultural theories in semiotics, from Lévi-Strauss, Foucault and Barthes to Eco, Ponzio and even Nietzsche, Bakhtin, Benedict, Stuart Hall, Valsiner, Deleuze, Münster, Schütz, and many others.

10.1 The theory in brief Clearly, the reader should know in advance something about the existential theory. However, it would not be necessary to read all my books on the subject; it is enough to summarize some essentials. As in TV soap operas, the 19th century newspaper feuilleton novels, or Wagner’s Nibelungen Ring, one has to learn what happened in the previous part. The theory concerns our Dasein, or the living world with all its subjects and objects. But the area beyond the Dasein is involved just as much, and that is called transcendence. What it is is still quite open. The easiest definition I have discovered is: The transcendent is anything which is absent but is present in our minds. Modern man might think that it is something like virtuality, virtual space, some might even say that it is the internet of our time but that would be going too far! As to the structure of our Dasein, so far I have arrived at a model which is called Zemic. It consists of four modes of Being which have

10.2 Transculturality

|

185

been arranged to form a square. The logical square itself was invented by ancient stoic philosophers. The Paris school of semiotics took it up again in the 1960s and called it the ‘semiotic square’ with terms s1, s2, not-s2 and not-s1. This was used to articulate four modes of being stemming from the Hegelian logic: from an-sichsein to für-sich sein (being-in-oneself/being-for-oneself); in turn, this model was adopted by Jean-Paul Sartre in his existentialist philosophy (L’Être et le néant). Then, borrowing from these sources, I added from the semiotic theory of the body (soma/sema) by Jacques Fontanille, and from the philosophy of Paul Ricoeur, the categories of Moi/Soi. Accordingly, we have four cases of Moi/Soi, M1, M2, S2 and S1. They correspond to the body, to identity (person), to social practices and to social norms and values. Each one marks its own Greimassian modality, in the same order: will, can, know and must. Thus the last modality, that of ‘believe,’ has been reserved for transcendence which can become present and actualized at any time via acts of negation and affirmation. Such a model has not been previously presented in semiotics, but in the history of philosophy I recently found, in the work of an Arabian-Persian Sufi mystic Ibn Arabi (full name Muhyi al-Dim Ibn Arabi, 1165–1240), an analogous model of circles of transcendence, also surrounding the four modes of Being. Ibn Arabi was born in Murcia, in Spain, but after long journeys finally settled at Damas in Syria. His model portrays six circles of transcendence: 1) the divine presence (outermost circle), 2) the second circle showing the place of Man, 3) the third circle representing the presence of the divine in man (similar to what we observe in the Platonic ideas), 4) this shows Man in contact with the world, 5) the axis cutting the inner circle into four parts represents multiplicity (the categories of existing things) in the World and 6) the circle in the middle represents the World of which Man is master and its support. The four areas starting from the center towards periphery are separations among the diverse categories of the existing things in the World.

10.2 Transculturality By showing this amazing parallel I simply want to emphasise that the existential semiotic cultural theory should be able to discuss such cases across cultural and historical borderlines, and develop reading models and concepts of such high universality that even phenomena as extremely remote from each other as Hegelian logic and Sufi mystics can find a common denominator. That would be true transculturality and ‘multiplicity’ (see later Deleuze). There would thus be two parts to this task: first – a historical overview of semiotic theories, including those which we do not regard as overtly semiotic in spite

186 | 10 Culture and transcendence

Figure 10.1: Model of circles of transcendence by Ibn Arabi

Figure 10.2: Structure of the Universe according to Ibn Arabi

10.3 Criticism of British cultural studies |

187

of their use of semiotic notions, and often ignoring their origins in the various contexts of European semiotics, as in the case of British cultural theory. The second task is to consider how existential theory would, as a theory, meet the challenge of the global ethical situation in which we find ourselves now, in our technosemiotic state, having not yet, hopefully, forgotten the earlier socio- and ethnosemiotic living worlds. For a long time semiotics has been looking for ways of answering the essential and vital questions of mankind, not only by being subordinated to the service of the capitalist consumer world and economic profit, but by pondering on a non-utilitarian basis the essence of such imminent problems of world cultures as Umwelt, a non-violent society, human responsibility, growth, education and cultural identity. The existential theory, by launching such difficult concepts as transcendence, the Zemic model, new categories of signs, Schein, post-colonial analysis, the theory of resistance and modalities, attempts to offer a promise in this direction. It is a comforting fact that often the most abstract theories prove to be the most practical and have the most pragmatic consequences when facing empirical reality. For brevity’s sake, the existential semiotic cultural theory will from now on be referred to as the ESC theory. So, the ESC theory cannot be a generalisation and an absolutisation of any particular culture or society. Yet, even this is ambiguous. On the one hand, Ruth Benedict warned about this as early as her classical work Patterns of Culture (1951). In the chapter Study of manners she states that a social scholar gathers a large quantity of material for a treatise on learning, on narcissism as the origin of neuroses, but deals with only this material. In other words: he/she does not care about social systems and cultures other than his/her own. He/she identifies, for example, local Westerns attitudes with human nature and calls their description ‘Economy’ or ‘Psychology’. Yet this happens very often, and did happen in earlier times with speculative theories of the human mind. However, we should not reject such theories out of hand, since they might contain something similar to what Lévi-Strauss called, in a neo-Kantian manner, ‘categories of the human mind’ (categories de l’esprit humain).

10.3 Criticism of British cultural studies Let us consider briefly the modern cultural theory course books used in all universities nowadays. First, let us take the book by Chris Barker, Cultural Studies: Theory and Practice (2008). In its foreword Paul Willis says: ‘At an everyday and human level, cultural interests, pursuits and identities have never been more important’. Individuals and groups want [. . . ] ‘something more than passive or un-

188 | 10 Culture and transcendence conscious acceptance of a historically/socially prescribed identity (simply being working class, black or white, young or old, etc.). Everyone wants to have or make or be considered as possessing cultural significance’. This sounds rather ‘existential’ and promising. Yet, it is not specified here who that ‘everyone’ is, which I am afraid is very similar to the Heideggerian ‘average person’, das Man of the contemporary global marketing culture. After a long list of ‘possible cultures’, from interpersonal interactions to group norms, communicative forms, texts and images to institutional constraints, social imagery and economic political determinants, the author says: ‘We are condemned to a kind of eclecticism because of the very eclecticism and indissoluble combinations of the dissimilar in the increasingly complex “real” world around us’ (Paul Willis, in Barker 2008: xxii). But what is ‘real’? This was precisely the theme of a major semiotic congress in Ankara, Cankaya University organized by the architect Zeynep Onur. It is exactly the present technosemiotic global consumption world and nothing else which is absolutized here as the ‘World as such’. I have elsewhere posed this question from the standpoint of an emancipated subject: do we want to be part of that world? In fact this is already quite Hegelian. ‘Real’ equals to wirklich, and Hegel said: was vernünftig ist, das ist wirklich, und was wirklich ist, das ist vernünftig. So the logic of this world is taken as universally true. However, let us remember what the Austrian writer Robert Musil said in his Der Man ohne Eigenschaften: Wenn es Wirklichkeitssinn gibt muss es auch Möglichkeitssinn geben (If one has sense for reality, one must also have sense for possibility). There is nothing determined about reality or the world, there are always alternatives, possibilities. Even Willis speaks about the ‘postdisciplinary’ nature of cultural studies. Instead of writing endlessly ‘introduction to... that and that’, they are a privileged site for the emergence of the discipline of disciplines. He is impressed by how Chris Barker deals with topics such as world disorder, sex, subjectivity, space, cultural policy, identity, youth culture, television, ethnicity, race . . . which reveal ‘. . . some concrete grounds of a complex and rapidly changing “real” world . . . and these sites are presented in selected theoretical contexts. In one word: he aims for a supra- disciplinary base’ (ibid.: xxiii). It is certainly the case that the ESC theory shares the same goal, but not on such an eclectic basis. Barker sees all cultural forms as structured like language – how familiar that sounds! That was the thesis of the structuralists a long time ago. However, how is such a supra- or meta- or fundamental deep level of reflection to be reached? Jaan Valsiner discusses this in terms of cultural psychology (Valsiner 2007). He has a diagram which, in crosscultural psychological terms, ‘generates’ the culture top-down, from humankind to particular societies A, B, etc., to social institutions within the society, to individual persons. This model is then corrected and replaced by another, in which culture ‘belongs to’ an individual, in this model the participation is first analyzed

10.4 Language games |

189

by using samples which exemplify the psychological systems of these individuals. The theory is then tested on other individuals and so forth. Ultimately, one may attain a general theory of humankind and its cultures (ibid.: 28). This means that such a meta-level is reached inductively, by studying a sufficient number of ‘cases’ of human cultures. The existential theory is certainly close to this kind of ‘psychologizing’ of anthropological theories; however, it is not a psychological theory as such, but rather a conceptual one. We shall soon see in what way.

10.4 Language games In what follows, I shall purposely juxtapose the cultural theory and ESC theory, so that the latter’s distinguishing features are foregrounded. The purpose is not to engage in polemics for their own sake, but simply to situate the new theory among other existing theories, and to state, at the least, what it is NOT. To criticize another theory by listing all that it is lacking would be the most primitive kind of scientific debate and should be avoided, since no theory can take everything into account. Barker says in his opening: ‘I explore that version of cultural studies which places language at its heart’. He gives greater attention to poststructuralist theories of language than to ‘the ethnography of lived experience’ (Barker 2008: 3). Barker then argues that: ‘Cultural studies does not speak with one voice . . . ’ but as early as in the next phrase he admits that his whole theory draws on work ‘developed in Britain, United States, Continental Europe (most notably France) and Australia’ (ibid.: 4). He admits: it would be more accurate to describe this text as Western cultural studies. ‘I simply do not feel qualified to say how much cultural studies as I understand it, is pertinent to the social and cultural conditions of Africa’ (ibid.: 9). What follows throughout the whole book then clearly demonstrates that, true, certain French authors are accepted but they appear as individual geniuses, totally detached from their original ideas, historical roots and contexts. We all know how the American book markets are always ‘discovering’ a genius from Paris, who is full of such talents only waiting to be found out by managers; his/her output is quickly translated into English, he/she is turned into a new intellectual fashion icon – just as it happened with Foucault, Derrida, Barthes, etc.: the list is endless. Barker admits that Africa is outside his context, but where is Asia, Latin America, Russia, etc.? This is exactly what Benedict warned about: a theory is valid only within one limited area and culture – although now expanded as a new civilization via globalization to every corner of the world. But the imperialist purport of such enterprise is immediately clear. Such a totally Anglocentric theory can never be the ESC theory!

190 | 10 Culture and transcendence Furthermore Barker remarks: ‘Cultural studies is constituted by the language game of cultural studies’ (2008: 4). Is this then the famous ‘linguistic turn’, the same as in Anglo-analytic philosophy? The ESC theory admits the importance of metalanguage to deal with different cultures, but that is another issue. The claim is then made about cultural studies as politics, in that the subject is important for its exploration and representation of marginalized social groups and the need for cultural change. The author then talks boldly about the production of meaning in language as signifying practices. How can this be claimed without a semiotic theory? Moreover, the author states that ‘Cultural studies has for the most part been concerned with modern industrialized economies and media cultures along capitalist lines’ (ibid.: 9). He thus tries to combine these signifying practices with political economy. He certainly takes the present economic system as a given. Signifying practices have to be adapted to it. He then argues that cultural studies are non-reductionist. Yet nothing is said about the culture itself. The same often holds true for communication studies, which investigate only how something is communicated, and not what is communicated.

10.5 Articulation Then comes the notion of ‘articulation’. It means the formation of a temporary unity between elements that do not have to be combined. Strange! It is certainly true that articulation stems from linguistics and refers to levels of articulation, the 1st and 2nd articulation in semiotics as defined by André Martinet (see also Eco). Nothing is said about its origin. In the chapter titled Power cultural studies are said to be concerned with subordinate groups. What groups? The next chapter, on popular culture, reveals that popular cultures are obviously thought to be subordinate. This idea also appears elsewhere. For instance, popular music is regarded as being in a minority position, although it holds all the power in the market and what is now subordinated and threatened is undoubtedly classical music, as well as all of high culture in general (Roger Scruton being the only scholar with the courage to defend it in his book Modern Culture, 2005). We then have the notion of the ‘hegemonic’ text. Since images, sounds, objects and practices are sign systems which signify with the same mechanism as a language, we may refer to them as cultural texts. The distinction between verbal and non-verbal is totally omitted. Naturally, this evokes the Lotmanian theory of culture as texts. Text is there generalized to concern any cultural object or activity. A difficult point might arise when a scholar turns to an intra-textual world of objects without temporality (like painting or architecture). Texts, being faithful

10.5 Articulation | 191

to their linguistic origin, normally have a beginning and an end. Why not replace this term by the notion of narrativity and narrative? Next comes the issue of subjectivity. This is involved as a part of consumption, i.e., we exist as subjects only as consumers. ‘The moment of consumption marks one of the processes by which we are formed as persons. How we are produced as subjects’ (Barker 2008: 11). The author does not ask: How do we make ourselves? Identities are discursive constructions, we then learn. We have to study the class basis of a culture that aims to give voice to the subordinated . . . but, again, who are they, those imagined ‘subordinated’? We then move on to structuralism, with only three authors named: Saussure, Lévi-Strauss and Barthes. Lévi-Strauss is introduced via Edmund Leach – we all know how superficial that is – and it is said of him: ‘Typical of Lévi-Strauss structuralism is his approach to food, which, he declares, is not so much good to eat as good to think with’ (ibid.: 17). About structuralism, we are told that it is ‘synchronic in approach analyzing the structures of relations in a snapshot of a particular moment’. This sounds totally mysterious. Moreover, ‘structuralism is best approached as a method of analysis rather than an all-embracing philosophy’. Postmodernism is supposed to claim: ‘knowledge is not metaphysical, transcendental or universal but specific to particular times and spaces’. Here transcendence is obviously misunderstood, transcendence is not ‘there’, somewhere high up, but it is here, where we have actualized it in our Dasein, as is proposed by the ESC theory. Later on, more is said about subjectivity and identity, in the chapter on personhood as a cultural production. What it means to be a person is social and cultural ‘all the way down’. Identities are wholly social constructions and cannot exist outside cultural representations . . . but later it is admitted: ‘. . . identity is an essence that can be signified through signs of taste, beliefs, attitudes and lifestyles. Identity is deemed to be both personal and social’ (Barker 2008: 216) – i.e., according to our theory both M2 and S2. It is then suggested that ‘There are no transcendental or ahistorical elements to what it means to be a person’ (ibid.: 218). Thus the theory denies totally the concept of a ‘transcendental ego’ behind our constructed social ‘egos’. Yet if this is so, how is it possible that we can read texts that are a thousand years old as if they were written yesterday? Moreover, the book claims that what it is to be a person cannot be universal. Psychoanalysis is to be read as a set of poetic, metaphorical, and mythological stories. It cannot be the basis of a universal theory (ibid.: 223). In the chapter Language and identity we read that one cannot have an ‘I’ and one cannot have an identity. Rather, one is constituted through languages. Language does not express an already existent ‘true self’ but brings the self into being (ibid.: 225). But then we can ask: Do we exist only when we are talking?

192 | 10 Culture and transcendence Later on it becomes clear that articulation here means something totally different from its original meaning in linguistics. Following the interpretation used here, it applies, rather, to human development in general, as Kierkegaard used it once in his famous Stages of life (orig. Stadier af livet), which were aesthetic, ethical and religious. We could then say that they are levels with different articulations which always take place when we move from one ‘subject position’ to another. There is thus no organic growth from one to another, as Goethe presumed. This provides man with the freedom to rearticulate himself again when shifting to a new level. Applying this to our Zemic model, a move from M1 to M2 and further to S2 can also mean a rearticulation of one’s inner semiotic mechanisms, modalities. If one is clumsy, slow, weak, inadequate in M1, one may suddenly become, with determination, like another person in M2, and even change one’s M1 profile by training; one can even have this happen in order to reach a degree of S2. Well, Richard Wagner never became an S2 actor, although he wanted it as M2 – because as M1 he was too short and his voice was unclear. Demosthenes stuttered in M1 but became a great orator in S2. The ballet dancer Jorma Uotinen was almost paralyzed in M1 in his youth by a rare illness, but became a famous dancer in S2. Other examples could be given. Oscar Parland has portrayed this kind of event in his novels: a new ‘person’ or mode of being can emerge like a butterfly from caterpillar, as a metamorphosis.

10.6 Subject positions In modern theory we might say that the ‘subject position’ changes. As Barker puts it, ‘Thus the same person is able to shift across subject positions according to circumstances’ (2008: 231). But behind this argument is the very postmodern statement that ‘No single identity can . . . act as an overarching organizing identity . . . We are constituted by fractured multiple identities’. This is the favourite idea of many contemporary thinkers who deny the possibility of a transcendental ego. Naturally, if there is a transcendental ego, the person is not a new subject on the same level as others, but functions from another logical position altogether. Yet this is what has just been denied above. In our framework, does the subject position mean adopting one of the modes of being M1, M2, S2 or S1, and staying in it? This is certainly an error, since if you classify people according to one mode, you forget that everyone is always a combination of all four of them. Identities are better described as certain constellations of these modes with different emphases among them. In one identity, M1 is important, let us say, for a member of an athletic club, while for another the S1 mode is the most essential, as in the life of a saint in a desert, or a martyr. Therefore, if you classify a person according to

10.7 What Foucault said

| 193

the categories ‘fat/thin’, you dwell in M1, but maybe the person considers himself more in terms of M2, i.e., ‘cheerful/serious’? Yet, if subjects are regarded as idiots who do not know what happens within them – as structuralists are always claiming – someone else is making their discourse and thus subordinating them. So the emic aspect is totally lacking here.

10.7 What Foucault said Nevertheless, it is interesting in itself to raise the problem of what is described as the ‘agency’, and the politics of identity. This is linked to the theories of Foucault. It has been said that, for him, subjects are discursive constructions and products of power. But he has been criticized for not providing us with a theory of agency (Barker 2008: 232). For him, ethics are concerned with practical advice as to how one should concern with oneself in everyday life. He speaks about the ‘techniques of the self’. Ethics center on the government of others and the government of oneself. Ethical discourses construct subject positions which enable agency to occur. Agency is a discursive construction exemplifying the productive character of power, according to what Baker supposes Foucault has said. Yet, such an ethical standpoint is close to the utilitarian ethics. Ethics exist to improve the welfare of subjects. This ignores a very essential aspect of ethics, which is that, most often, to follow an ethical principle and to carry out an ethical act does not lead to any advantage, profit or promotion of the agent’s own life, but rather the reverse. A person who does good things is hated by others, and ultimately destroyed. Why? Because to do good means that one is stronger than others. This is something most people cannot accept. Yet, we might say that doing good makes evil manifest itself, and when evil is visible, observable, it is easier to fight against it. In any case, the ethical principle is a much deeper mental capacity than mere reflection of S1 and S2 in one’s mind, i.e., coming from the outside, from the Soi. It is already in Moi, or rather it is in every mode, and particularly as a transcendental, virtual value waiting for its actualization. The director of the Great Encyclopedic Center of Islamic Studies, said in Tehran at the opening of a symposium on ethics (March 5, 2014), that it is more important than religion. “Good is good, and bad is bad universally, for all human beings”. Such a conception of ethics goes indeed much deeper than the Western theories of it often do. However, what Foucault actually said was that he denied the existence of such a thing as a transcendental ego. He argues in The Order of Things (orig. Les mots et les choses): ‘If there is one approach that I do reject, however, it is that (one might call it broadly speaking the phenomenological approach), which gives absolute priority to the observing subject, which attributes a constituent role to an act,

194 | 10 Culture and transcendence which places its own point of view at the origin of all historicity, which, in short, leads to a transcendental consciousness’ (Foucault 1970: xiv). Thus he seems to deny the whole idea of agency and claims, as Barker puts it: social systems operate to structure what an actor is. However, the concept of ethics centered around the care of the self is an extremely limited view. It is true that there is something pessimistic and gloomy in the Foucaultian view of man. Famous and often quoted is the passage from the above-mentioned treatise: ‘Strangely enough, man – the study of man – supposed by the naïve to be the oldest investigation since Socrates – is probably no more than a kind of rift in the order of things, or, in any case, a configuration whose outlines are determined by the new position he has so recently taken in the field of knowledge . . . It is comforting and a source of profound relief to think that man is only a recent invention, a figure not yet two centuries old . . . . that he will disappear again as soon as that knowledge has discovered a new form’ (ibid.: xxiii). It goes without saying that such a standpoint could never be acceptable in the ESC theory. Yet, the Foucaultian archaeology project has a heuristic value in revealing a general space of knowledge, its configurations and the mode of being of the things that appear in it; all this defines ‘. . . systems of simultaneity as well as mutation sufficient to circumscribe the threshold of a new positivity’ (ibid.: xxiii). Clearly, this is the aim of an existential metatheory of cultures as well, in regard of the level of profundity. Foucault does not seem to notice that by saying that, he is positioning himself as a scholar in the role of a transcendental ego whom he wanted to remove from his scholarly discourse altogether. What Menard Boss said about scientific preunderstanding holds true here quite well. If Foucault disliked the idea of transcendence, so also did Lévi-Strauss who ten years before Foucault said the same in his Structures of elementary parenthood (1949) in the acclaimed chapter on ‘archaic illusion’. Yet, he did so with agency as it is understood in cultural theory: freedom, free will, action, creativity, originality and possibility of change through actions of free agents. Against these theses Barker proposes that subjects are determined by social forces that lie outside of themselves as individuals. He says that a great many actions of modern life are routine in character. Often we do not make self-conscious choices at all, but follow a socially determined routinized path. This is also the claim made by Umberto Eco when he talks of the automatism of the codes which force us to do certain things. Yet, for Barker ‘the best we can do is to produce another story about ourselves’, even though ‘we clearly have the existential experience in facing and making choices’ (Barker 2008: 236). However, the existence of social structures (S2) is not only negative: it also enables us to realize our actions. Thus, according to Barker, human freedom cannot consist of an escape from social determinants.

10.8 Action |

195

10.8 Action We might then ask whether the ESC theory is a theory of pragmatic action. If the ESC theory essentially deals with the change and transformation of culture, the logic of act and event fits well with its essence, following Georg Henrik v. Wright. Is a shift from one mode to another an act or an event? Does it occur by itself or only by purposeful intentional act? Acts are not changes in the world as such. They are not events. But many acts are portrayed as causing changes. To act means, in a sense, to intervene in the course of nature. Yet, an event is a shift from 1) one state to another (for instance a window is opened), 2) from a state to a series of events (for instance to start running), 3) from a series of events to a state (for instance to stop talking) or 4) changes in series of events (for instance: a walking man starts to run). One has to distinguish the act categories – for instance to perform music – and an individual act – to perform Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony. The logical difference between acts and events is in their activity and passivity. An act needs an agent. An individual event means that a general event takes place in a particular situation. An individual act is to perform a general act in a particular situation and through a particular agent. We can now already apply this kind of analysis and ask whether in our existential model changes (i.e., shifts from one mode to another, from M1 to M2, from body to person, etc.) are acts or events. It is an event when, for instance, a body grows and becomes a person, but it is an act when a certain body decides to adopt certain habits and thus becomes a person. Thus a change from M2 to S2 means: a certain person becomes a certain kind of professional, let us say in the family of Habsburgs they all become kings and queens at a certain moment; in certain societies certain types of persons automatically take up certain positions, such as warriors, priests, governors, following Dumézil’s Indoeuropean model. But if particular persons decide to take up particular professions as their choice, their decision and effort to reach these positions in S2, then these are acts. Moreover, in v. Wright’s theory one distinguishes acts and events, and then activities – series of events or processes. Events take place, but processes just go on. So by applying the Wrightian logic of change we can analyse the growth of a culture, how a culture becomes a culture. Moreover, we may ask: If M1 and M2 still represent the biological and S2 and S1 the social levels, how does the shift from nature to culture take place? Is it the Rousseauian narrative of the kind ‘all is good in nature and becomes bad in culture’? Yet we may suppose that the movement in the Zemic model is partly automatic, i.e., caused by events, and partly caused by acts. But in both cases the logical operations of affirmation and negation have their role. Forbearance is a kind of negation. An agent forbears in a certain situation from doing a certain

196 | 10 Culture and transcendence thing, if and only if he could do it but in fact does not do it. If we then go on to establish norms, there are three types of them: something should be done – an order; something is allowed to be done – a permission, something is not allowed to be done – a prohibition. Thus, if we know the modes beginning from S1 – the social norms and values – and they have these statuses, the first two, S1 and S2, launch the chain from S1 up to M1, but the third one, M2, can stop it. But even then, this forbearance can have certain consequences which, again, have their impact on the course of events. Is the movement within the Zemic model the same as the temporal course, i.e., the duration of one individual’s life and the history in the life of collectivities? The model could be formalized here: ‘should’ = M1 →→ M2, ‘allow’ = M1 ⋅ ⋅ ⋅ → M2 (i.e., M2 is permitted after M1), and ‘forbidden’ = M1 → / → M2. Furthermore, we can ask whether the movements are the same in both directions, from M1 to S1 and from S1 to M1. There is already so much use of formal schemes that we may return to the question of whether in fact ESC is close to Anglo-analytical philosophy. The use of formal languages was one of its criteria. However, if we think of the origins of the model, it was the logical square on four terms s1, s2, not-s1 and not-s2, once used by ancient logicians. With A. J. Greimas it became the semiotic square. In the ESC it became the Zemic model. If we accept this as an approval of formal logic we have already satisfied two criteria; the first one was the linguistic turn – which, however, in the ESC theory received a somewhat different interpretation. The third criterion still remains: is this the correct philosophical style? This is the hardest criterion, since a theory which also stems from Hegel, that ‘conceptual poetry’, as one semiotician said, and which uses the notion of transcendence which others hate, certainly could not meet the challenge of achieving the correct philosophical style in the Anglo-analytical sense. However, let us keep on trying to use our Zemic model and its explanatory power for another presentation of a cultural theory.

10.9 Cultivating Michael Ryan has published another course book, Cultural studies. A Practical Introduction (2010). It has the following chapters which by their titles already reveal all that belongs to the field of cultural theory: 1) Policy and industry, 2) Place, space and Geography, 3) Gender and Sexuality, 4) Ideologies, 5) Rhetoric, 6) Ethnicity, 7) Identity, Lifestyle, and Subculture, 8) Consumer culture and Fashion studies, 9) Music, 10) Media studies, 11) Visual culture, 12) Audience, Performance and Celebrity, 13) Bodies and things, 14) Transnationality, Globalization and Postcoloniality. The book begins as follows: ‘The word culture has always had

10.9 Cultivating |

197

multiple meanings. In one sense of the word, culture is inseparable from human life. Everything from how we dress to what we eat, from how we speak to what we think, is culture. You only notice this really when you change and enter another culture’ . . . ‘Culture becomes visible when we travel between “cultures” ’ (ibid.: viii). Let me note at this point another new British book about culture, namely Roger Scruton’s Modern Culture. He refers to Herder, who defines Kultur as the lifeblood of a people, the flow of moral energy that holds society intact. Zivilisation by contrast consists of manners, laws and technical know-how. Nations may share a civilization but they will always be distinct in their culture, since culture defines what they are. So reasons Scruton (op. cit.: 1). I have already dealt elsewhere with the Kultur/Zivilisation distinction in my essay on Resistance (see Chapter 9), where globalization appeared as a new type of civilization, conquering all geographical spaces and places and destroying local cultures. Culture here is the essence of a nation. Yet another theory emphasizes its Latin etymology, namely the process and activity of cultivating something. Here we meet Wilhelm Humboldt and his famous Bildung, finely translated into English by Scruton: ‘cultivation’ (not education, formation and so on). For Herder, culture, i.e., S1, constitutes practices and beliefs – S2 – creating the self-identity, or M2, of a tribe. Thus, it penetrates all the modes of the Zemic model! But then Scruton is almost the only author who dares to mention the idea of high culture versus common culture. When British cultural theory emerged, strongly influenced by the views of Raymond Williams, it was a rebellion against the elitist tradition; as Scruton says, alongside the elite culture of the upper class, there has been another culture, by no means of less value, of people who affirmed their solidarity in the face of oppression and through which they expressed their identity and a sense of belonging (Scruton, op. cit.: 3). This is exactly the case of Nancy Mitford’s famous distinction between two languages: Upper class or U-language and Non Upper class, i.e., non-U-language (for instance in low culture you say: ‘greens’, in upper class language you should say ‘salad’; in low culture one says: ‘What?’, in high culture one should say instead: ‘I beg your pardon?’). This is certainly true. In all of semiotics and its expansion in the 1960s there was always present this cultural trait: one could deal with the low culture phenomena in academic discourse by semiotic formal analysis, its rigorous method made it acceptable and legitimate in that sphere; whereas when the same approach was directed towards the high culture phenomena, they were regarded as alienated and distanced from their origins, a view which became politically acceptable in the often leftist intellectual semioticians’ communities. The success of Roland Barthes was to a large extent based on this. However, the idea of culture as something elevated, something to be reached, a kind of goal for life aspiration, from M1 to M2 via S2 to S1, was the idea behind all of arts education - and why not education as a whole? Namely,

198 | 10 Culture and transcendence if you adapt yourself to sociological relativism, you have only behaviours of equal value. In particular when you observe a society from the outside. From the inside, within the Zemic model, it looks different. Certain values become manifest only when one believes in them and follows them in one’s activities. This explains why adherents of high culture claim that they, and not the others, represent the true values of a culture. They are right in this emic aspect. We should thus distinguish between culture as a Zemic entity, i.e., in its inner aspect, and culture as a Zetic object, i.e., in its external aspect. Culture as a collection of cultural objects, culture as signs represents, of course, the Zetic view. The author then says: culture means conformity with the reigning standards, norms and rules – which is what we mean by S1. If culture means embedded norms, then norms are learned as one grows up – this means the gradual shift from M1 to S1. This means that culture consists of, on the one hand, practices in which we engage, norms by which we live in S2 and S1 in the Zemic aspect, and cultural artifacts, signs, texts, etc. or S2, S1, as the Zetic aspect, or outer entities. To make a musical recording one must not only have talent, i.e., the Zemic M2 and S2, but also a production company, i.e., the Zetic S2. Culture in the sense of artistic objects is possible only if culture in the first sense, as a way of life, gives permission, argues Dr. Ryan. Thus the Zemic and the Zetic are in constant interaction and fluctuation. Yet, there is a creative aspect in culture on the normative side. Avant-garde art questions norms and thus yields a creatively dissonant collision. In fact, in our Zemic model, transformed into a narrative model of text analysis, we encounter such collisions among all the four modes or levels. See my study on Robert Schumann’s Fantasy C major op. 17 in Tarasti, Semiotics of Classical Music (2012). Since that is the case, Ryan’s idea of certain cultural forms being victimized is very strange. Who is victimized by whom and where, after all? We may now have enough material to claim that ESC theory is certainly not the same as British cultural theory. Indeed, it tries to go beyond such kind of ‘ideological’ science which stems directly from a particular type of society, albeit a triumphantly victorious one. British cultural theory is altogether an ideological variant of the globalized market culture without alternatives. Yet it has presented some categories which are of interest, since, even when developing the ESC theory, we live in the 21st century and not in 18th or 19th century Europe.

10.10 Content and Speculation We have not said anything so far about the content of our existential theory of culture, i.e., what kind of image or view of culture it offers. Is culture something organic, something like an organism? This metaphor was once strongly promoted

10.10 Content and Speculation | 199

by Oswald Spengler and of course a long time before him by Goethe. Spengler writes: ‘Culture and the spirituality of great historic organisms differ from each other by habitus. The habitus of existence consists of a higher offer of all cultures, the manifestation of all life . . . there appears a style of a certain soul. Habitus includes a certain life span and tempo of development. The concept of life time of a man, butterfly and oak contain in spite of accidents of fate, a certain value. Similarly, every culture and period, rise and fall have their given duration expressed by a symbol’ (Spengler 1963: 98). Certainly ‘habitus’ here is not the same as for Bourdieu. Spengler utilizes such notions as the soul and symbol and talks of the Apollonian, Faustian magic symbols of the ancient Greek, Western culture, as well as of Arabian, Chinese primal symbols, art works as living wholes . . . I would not be surprised at Professor Chesterman preceding this speculation with his question: is there any evidence which would show that these ideas are wrong? Spengler fits well with youthful minds, and so I may quote myself from my notebook from 1967 (written in Vienna): ‘Sometimes it seems as if we are living in a world of two cultures: one is the authentic Faustian one (to please Spengler!) which is to a great extent national, or let us say European – and the other one is the culture of technics and mathematics, one of “numbers”, which is international. That could be called a machine culture’. Furthermore, we can of course ask whether ESC theory is a speculative theory, such as those produced in German philosophy beginning from the 18th century. If we dare to quote Hegel in semiotics, we certainly have to answer this question. Hegel aimed for a complete explanation of being. He adopted the Kantian idea of categories but for him the number of categories was limitless, and together they formed the absolute, the whole reality. Hegel’s philosophy was metaphysical or objective idealism. The objective reality is the absolute spirit. Things are concepts, such as we can know. Knowing is Einfühlung to the thing and its possession by thought. Thus Reason creates the world. Aristotelian logic operates with genus plus differentia. In Hegel the opposition of a concept is already contained in the concept itself: Sein – Nichts – Werden. Criticism of Hegel claims that without a particular speculative conviction his logic is not accessible. The absolute nature of his dialectics and certainty are based on the feeling of subjective certainty, not on objective facts. Therefore it is irrational by nature. To put it less bluntly, we might rather say that his aim was a kind of supra-rationalism. The subject he is talking about is not the same as the real, physical, psychological subject, Professor Hegel lecturing in Berlin. It is a construction, or what is called a transcendental ego, as Sartre and others referred to it later. Or we could take his philosophy as a narrative in which the implied philosopher or author is not the same as the real person (how this fits together with what Menard Boss said about the origin of any scientific thought is of course a problem). Hegel is said to represent the last attempt to con-

200 | 10 Culture and transcendence centrate on the constructive problems of ideas. He believes in thoughts and ideas as forces making world history, and therefore having great pragmatic import. If we accept the idea of a ‘system’ in Hegel, then in our ESC theory we might as well accept its connection with praxis – albeit some say those consequences were disastrous for mankind.

10.11 The organism There are many ideas of a speculative nature the relevance of which to the ESC theory needs to be examined, such as the idea of an organism. If we think of culture as Growth, as in the idea of Bildung, the metaphor is certainly striking. It means that culture is, if not reduced back to, then at least thought to stem from – nature. The whole Lévi-Straussian problem with the shift from nature to culture was with finding rules of a universal nature. It is typical of nature that it can give only what it has received, whereas in culture an individual always receives more than he gives and gives more than he receives. The exchange was called by Marcel Mauss ‘fait total social’, and mutual communication was one such universal rule where culture emerges from nature. In the chapter Archaic illusion Lévi-Strauss mentions three universal rules: the existence of rules, the concept of mutual exchange between the self and others as the mediation of this opposition, and the synthetic nature of a gift, i.e., the transfer of value from one individual to another, creating a relationship between these individuals and adding a new quality to the value. This is what Bakhtin said later about the basic nature of dialogue. This is certainly very important in our ESC theory, which so far is based upon the inner structure of one subject only. The idea of an organism, for instance in the biosemiotics of Uexküll, originates from the German speculative organism philosophy and Kantianism, namely the idea of exchange between an organism and Umwelt, which is filtered by Merken und Wirken and by Ich Ton of the organism. Yet in Lévi-Strauss the idea of an organism is strange. The manner in which Lévi-Strauss portrays the Nambikwara society and its leadership is close to the Durkheimian idea of organic solidarity. ‘Personal prestige and the ability to inspire confidence are the basis of power in Nambikwara society’ (Kuronen 2011: 1). From this the Finnish scholar Tuomas Kuronen, in his study of political leadership in Finland, drew the conclusion that the same model applies in Western culture: ‘Cultural layers, especially those built upon Western educational and conceptual institutions are privileged in the way Western people make sense of their world. They . . . are taken as granted, in a similar way the Nambikwara would take theirs’ (ibid.). What is behind such an analogy is certainly the idea of culture as a kind of organic entity, also present in the idea of Bildung.

10.12 Generation |

201

In archaic culture the tribal structure shows features of such an organic nature as semio-anthropologist Jean-Claude Mbarga has shown in his recent study of the Cameroonian culture and identity. Mbarga portrays a culture and society in which tribalism, clannism and sectarianism are dominant and make a real religion of everyday life. His approach is existential in the sense that it is not reductionist in any structural way but takes into account the life situation of every Cameroonian person (Mbarga 2012). Yet, behind it are always the aforementioned big questions of the possible organicity of his culture, and analogies with Western culture. I once saw on TV a program in which quite young African boys from Nigeria, 8 years old, spoke while fishing about how life was in the West. Their reasoning was amazingly wise, mature, and right – from their point of view, although it dealt with an issue which for them was so transcendental. The lesson from all this is that we can successfully apply the idea of organicity insofar as it does not become a reductionist model in which the primal, phenomenal, felt, lived-in realities are explained away by some abstract categories. Thus ESC theory is definitely anti-reductionist.

10.12 Generation However, the idea of organicity can take more sophisticated forms in various theoretical models going under the rubric of semiotics. For instance, the so-called generative models, no longer so ‘fashionable’, are like that. Repeating the earlier question about what culture looks like in an autopsy, one answer is that it is a multi-level organic process in which deep, unconscious structures yield the more superficial manifest structures. This is the Chomskyan tree model. Is all culture like that? The temptation to apply this model has always been there, and, among others, the Greimassian parcours génératif was supposed to be like that. However, the model taken to the extreme, as in the work by the theater scholar Kari Salosaari, has turned out to be over-rational, awkward theoretizing in which we launch a huge system in order to explain one cultural detail. Yet the heuristic value of such a model remains, since we have to find an organization and a structure for our semiotic observations. But I would hardly imagine that a generative model of Iranian culture or Cameroonian society were reasonable enterprises. Moreover, generativism can be seen in philosophy, as well in the Heideggerian system, where all is derived from the fundamental ‘Being’. Ontological semiotics can easily fall into the trap of such generativism, albeit all the evidence might show that reality is much more unpredictable and complicated, sometimes attaining the limits of irrationality. Rather, the idea of levels of articulation would save our system of

202 | 10 Culture and transcendence multi-level culture from such over-rationalisations, i.e., by admitting that a new articulation is possible at any level of culture.

10.13 Nature Anyway, the idea of organic processes stems from the concept of nature. Even Greimas had the notion of le monde naturel but there is nothing natural about it; it was, rather, nature as opposed to culture but already completely semiotized. I have dealt with this problem elsewhere. However, the historian of ideas, Arthur Lovejoy, once made a list of what ‘nature’ as a concept contained, finding 19 different cases of nature; in fact, all cultural concepts: 1) nature as objects to be imitated by art, 2) nature as empirical reality, 3) human nature, i.e., ordinary human behaviour with its passions, 4) connections among facts, cause and effect seen as natural, 5) nature as a Platonic idea which is realized incompletely as empirical reality, 6) nature as general type excluding particular traits of species, 7) nature as average or statistical type, 8) nature as antithetic to man as his works, i.e., that part of empirical reality to be touched by human art (= culture, we could add here), 9) ‘nature’ as a system of evident truths, of properties of essences, 10) intuitively felt as principles of taste or standards as statements on what is objectively and essentially beautiful, 11) nature as cosmic order, whole or half personified (mythologized) force, natura naturans, 12) such attributes as uniformity, simplicity, economic use of means, regularity, nature as geometrizing, irregularity, savagery, completeness, the richness of and manifoldness of content, 13) continuous development, 14) naturality as a quality of an artist, 15) self-expression without self-consciousness, 16) qualities which appear in ‘primitive’ art, 17) nature manifesting in the artist’s public, 18) universality and then unchangeable art in thought, feeling and taste: what is always felt, what all understand immediately and 19) familiar and close, natural as something which any individual can directly enjoy (Lovejoy 1948). This list in fact constitutes a negative definition of culture: culture is anything that is not natural. This shares with our existential approach the point that these categories are those used by subjects in real situations, and thus nature is not pushed back into the status of some mystic unity. The list can show which kind of concepts are leading our behaviour.

10.14 Rhizome

| 203

10.14 Rhizome Yet there are other theories which are perhaps less conspicuously based on the nature metaphor, like the one by Deleuze and Guattari and their famous ‘rhizome’ model (Deleuze, Guattari 1987). Their idea was to make a vehement attack against the organic tree model proposed by Chomsky. The tree model as binary thinking was adopted by linguistics as its basic image, and this was a mistake: a tree is not a rhetoric ‘image’ but just a ‘structure’; Deleuze himself regards all his concepts as images and metaphors. For Deleuze, the tree image is totally wrong, since then the idea of multiplicity is ignored. ‘Chomsky’s system has never reached understanding of multiplicity’ (ibid.: 5). A system of multiplicity is a rhizome; a rhizome as a subterranean stem is totally different from roots and radicles . . . Chomsky’s linguistic models still begin at a point S and proceed by dichotomy . . . semiotic modes of coding (biological, political, economic, etc.) bring into play not only different regimes of signs but also states of things of different status; in Chomsky’s grammar, the categorical symbol S that dominates every sentence is more fundamentally a marker of power than a syntactic marker. Our criticism of the linguistic models is not that they are too abstract but that they are not abstract enough, that they do not reach the abstract machine that connects a language to the semantic and pragmatic contents of statement . . . ‘A rhizome ceaselessly establishes connections between semiotic chains, organization of power, and circumstances relative to the arts, sciences, and social struggles . . . There is no ideal speakerlistener, any more than there is a homogeneous linguistic community . . . There is no mother tongue, only a power takeover by a dominant language’ (ibid.: 6–7). Deleuze’s reasoning has great fascination since it has a prophetic and declarative tone, but what is a ‘semiotic chain’? What is mother tongue? Certainly not S2/S1, i.e., social praxis, but something between M2/S2; it is half on the side of Moi, unlike other languages learned later. Deleuze swears by multiplicity. There are no points or positions in a rhizome – so the theory of ‘subject positions’ is also denied here! – such as those in a structure, tree, or root. There are only lines. What would Kandinsky have said (Punkt und Linie zu Fläche)? We do not have units, only multiplicities (Deleuze, Guattari 1987: 8). There is deterritorialisation insofar as multiplicities are defined from outside. A rhizome may be shattered at a given spot but it will start again. The rhizome makes a reference to DNA whose evolutionary schemas would no longer follow models of arborescent descent. There is thus a metaphorical link to biology, one might nowadays even speak of nanotechnology whose most fervent defenders see it as a new universal system for resolving all the problems of mankind, from technology to ecology. Another cultural object which Deleuze ‘rhizomizes’ is the book. The book means deterritorialisation of the world, but the world then reterritorializes the book. Follow the plants, Deleuze’s sermon

204 | 10 Culture and transcendence goes on: ‘Write, form a rhizome, increase your territory by deterritorialisation . . . ’ (ibid.: 11). Could this be also a political slogan, as has been shown by the recent events in Europe? Make a map, not a tracing! This advice was once followed by a semiotician trying to reach the Imatra semiotic congress by train from Helsinki. He forgot to change mid-way and then called from the other side of the country to the congress. ‘Why are you there and not here?’, he was asked. ‘The map was wrong’, he answered. Let us now ask how this would be linked to the existential theory of culture. It is hard to believe that any subject would at all times live in his or her culture as if it were a rhizome. Very quickly, even when moved to a totally strange environment, a subject constitutes his own Umwelt by identifying small signs around him, by gradually creating his own territory. The first cultural act is to occupy a space, says Corbusier. It is impossible to make a theory of ego, Moi/Soi, subjectivity, based upon such a rhizomatic experience. It certainly reflects a quite postmodern anguish amidst the multiplicity of ‘choices’ at an American supermarket, or in a market-oriented, consumption- and media-driven, internet society in general. All is available and at the same time nothing, since without orientation by a transcendental ego providing the concrete subject with the criteria of selection, judgement, evaluation and comparison, one is indeed lost in a rhizomatic desert amidst our globalized world. Yet even Deleuze has an aspiration towards that deeper level while talking about machining assemblages, making the unfolding of semiotic chains possible. However, this theory is certainly not existential in that it denies the subject any possibility of agency as proposed in the British theory. Deleuze states: ‘A rhizome has no beginning or end; it is always in the middle, between things, interbeing, intermezzo . . . Where are you going? Where are you coming from? What are you heading for? These are totally useless questions’ (Deleuze, Guattari 1987: 25). If such fundamental questions are forbidden in his model, we cannot take his theory as a model for an existential theory of culture. Rather, it reflects the feeling of being lost amidst a huge metropolis, something like a Western traveller in Tokyo, without any knowledge of their mother tongue, without any map, without any familiar signs. Nevertheless, later Deleuze has the courage to borrow unscrupulously from linguistics the idea of articulation, particularly double articulation, and he claims that the entire organism must be considered in relation to double articulation (ibid.: 41). Then his system even reaches theology: ‘A stratum always has a dimension of the expressible . . . to express is always to sing the glory of God. Every stratum is a judgement of God; not only do plants and animals . . . sign or express themselves, but so do rocks and even rivers, every stratified on earth. The first articulation concerns content, the second expression’ (ibid.: 42). Thank God there

10.15 Zemic/Zetic |

205

is no mistake here regarding the theory of André Martinet, and this may contain echoes of Lévi-Strauss who shared with Deleuze the same belief in the stratification of reality: geology, Marxism and psychoanalysis, all of these portrayed stratified entities. Otherwise this view is not far from that of Oswald Spengler. So at least on the discursive level, the return of the speculative theory seems possible in contemporary debates!

10.15 Zemic/Zetic Now we might go further and ponder whether our Zemic model with its internal shift from Moi to Soi would mean the same as the shift from biology to psychology, and, moreover, to sociology and then to anthropology, or simply from nature to culture. To what extent is the Zemic model a model of an ‘organism’, organic growth, Bildung, culture in the sense of cultivation? To what extent does it involve the Ruskinian idea of education or the principle of Kultur in the sense of Kunsterziehung proposed by J. Langbehn, one of the founders of the aesthetic education movement, a long time ago (1897)? There have been efforts to apply it also to communities – for example, by Markku Sormunen – but to what extent could we take ‘culture’ as just a more extensive Zemic construction? If yes, what could it mean to talk about M1, or the ‘body’s’ primal corporeality, the kinetic movement of a social group or collectivity – except in Wagnerian operas where the chorus expresses this aspect magnificently – I refer, for instance, to the chorus in Mastersingers or in Parsifal. In the latter when the ‘bodies’ of the knights have enjoyed their wine and bread, they are refreshed and believe again in their community, and turn again to being courageous. To what extent can we speak of the identity of a group? With certainty and without artistic metaphors? Within the Durkheimian organic or mechanical solidarity, to what extent can we talk about the social practices of a group? And to do so even better than when talking about an individual subject? And to what extent are there collective values and norms, even better than for single persons? Yet immediately other challenges rise up, such as the question: what is the relationship of these two Zemic models? Or is the collective Zemic rather a Zetic, i.e., external, model to a single subject? Is the subject always to be considered outside of his group, clan, tribe, sect, nation, community? How does an individual Zemic entity communicate with its collective Zemic group? If the collective Zemic group sends a message dealing with values and norms, i.e., S1, in which mode does the individual Zemic react? By his body? By his person? By his profession and role? By his individual values which may differ from the group values? All combinations are possible. Could these communications or shifts among the modes be portrayed, for instance, by modal analysis

206 | 10 Culture and transcendence in the Greimassian sense, as ‘will, know, can’, etc. For instance, when a subject is unable to realize a rule in his M1 or M2 because he is lacking the modalities of ‘know’ and ‘can’? However, we may also note here that between the individual Zemic and the collective Zemic there is a mediation, namely the dialogue between two individual Zemic subjects. This is the theory proposed by Mikhail Bakhtin, in his ideas on dialogue. Every subjects grows, lives and develops in dialogues with other members of the group Zemic class. What happens at this level? Lévi-Strauss claims: Qui dit homme, dit langage, et qui dit langage dit société. Thus we may again adopt the Saussurean model of dialogue, of two Zemic worlds encountering each other: Mr. A transmitting signs to Mr. B and the latter responding. Then we might say that the theory of culture, as well as the existential one, must include this aspect of communality and step out of its solipsistic framework.

10.16 Transfer The dialogue model could also function well on the cultural level. This becomes clear when we deal with so-called cultural transfers among different cultures, i.e., two collective Zemic units. A fine study about such an issue is the one by Michel Espagne, Les transferts culturels franco-allemands (Espagne 1999). It is based on the idea of national culture: France and Germany had to have first the idea of their almost organic nature as cultures before any exchange, in any form, was possible. In this sense there had to exist what Benedict Anderson has called ‘Imagined communities’. For his theory the national culture is a typical case of an imaginary collectivity which does not exist anywhere else than in the minds of certain groups. This was made possible in Europe technically by printing books. By reading books one could be in touch with huge communities without ever meeting them face to face. In a certain sense, then, the nation is a ‘transcendental entity’; it is something which is absent but present in our minds. This principal absence does not exclude its strong emotional impact and force when ideas such as brotherhood are linked. People are then ready to die for it, as one can still see on any TV news in our time. The nation thus would appear to be a typical cultural Zetic formation, i.e., it is never Zemic as such, but can of course become Zemic any time when it is actualized in the Dasein of the members of a group. Yet, in the case discussed by Michel Espagne, that of France-Germany, the claim made is that the easiest model for studying such transfers is the model of communication. However, here we need to point out as a commentary the view expressed by Jaan Valsiner who, when talking about cultural transfers, argues that the unidirectional scheme should be replaced by a bi- or multidirectional or mutually constructive scheme. All par-

10.16 Transfer |

207

ticipants of the cultural transfer actively transform the cultural message. Thus France influences Germany, Germany influences France, and even ‘third’ members are included, such as England or Russia (Valsiner 2007: 36). However, in the chapter Au-delà du comparatisme Espagne discusses several principles of such issues which are interesting when juxtaposing two collective Zemic entities, such as European neighbour nations (Espagne, op. cit.: 35–49). First among them is that comparison presupposes cultural areas close enough to enable one to pass over the specificities by applying abstract categories. The main problem is then, as pointed out by Espagne, who does the observing! Very often one only compares oneself to others. For instance, the notion of Bildung in education has, for Germans, almost a metaphysical meaning, whereas Frenchmen and Englishmen do not even understand what is involved. Often comparison takes place between the synchronic parallels of two cultures, without noting their chronologies. History is easily forgotten. Comparatism opposes social groups (i.e., two S2s) instead of emphasizing acculturation mechanisms. Comparisons are for grounding territories. They concern objects (Zetic units) thought to express identities, for instance national anthems. Comparison can exaggerate differences instead of convergences. Very often a scholar’s comparison of two nations only strengthens their nationalisms. I have earlier, in my postcolonial theory, noted that nationalism emerges as a reaction against a threat from another nation, perhaps imagined, i.e., a reaction against an attempt at subordination and colonization. Then such an imagined community might have only a negative role and not be considered an authentic phenomenon growing from the S1 values of a group as such. For instance, a nation may need to defend some totally physical qualities of M1. To give an example, oriental people cannot stand the smell of soured milk while Westerners do not notice such a smell because they use milk products. Someone said that he can immediately distinguish a Finn in a Parisian street by how he walks. When I wore a fur cap in the winter of Minnesota people admired it but thought it was sign of being a Russian. In such a case a Zetic sign represents the culture. Music, food, clothes, all these of course belong to such markers. Yet some Zetic units and behaviours are elevated to such a high status of their culture that they are called cultural heritages. They constitute foregrounded, linguistically marked, cultural Zetic units which have to be remembered, preserved, maintained, fostered, in some cases even renewed. The carriers of such heritages again apply their Zemic profiles to do so.

208 | 10 Culture and transcendence

10.17 Alien-psychic It is now time to return once again to transcendence. This ambiguous concept undoubtedly also has a social interpretation, such as that by Alfred Schütz and Thomas Luckmann in their The Structures of the Life-World (Schütz 1994), representing the so-called understanding sociology, Verstehende Soziologie. They give the notion quite an empirical and colloquial meaning by distinguishing three types of ‘transcendencies’: small, middle and major. ‘Transcendental’ simply means anything which is absent. However, Alfred Schütz presents quite profound views on the notion in his treatise Der sinnliche Aufbau der sozialen Welt (Schütz 1993). He deals there with the philosophical problem of alien-psychic or Fremdseelig. In this view, the only certain thing is my own stream of consciousness, Erlebnisstrom. He distinguishes two types of intentional experiences or acts: those whose intentional objects are within the same stream of experiences as oneself. So we might say – such intentional acts which take place within our Zemic model – let us say, when one’s M1 addresses M2 or S1 is ‘talking’ to M2 or S2. In semiotics, this would be called autocommunication. On the other hand, those intentional experiences which are not there are transcendentally directed, for instance acts directed towards intentional experiences of other ‘Ich’s’ or ‘I’s’. Not only are transcendences intentional acts directed to others, but transcendent are, rather, all experiences of the bodies of other egos, and even of my own body. So, what kinds of acts are those directed towards the other’s experiences? It means that one Zemic subject listens to another, and receives that person’s signs and messages, leading us into quite ‘existential’ questions. Arno Münster has noted in his study Le principe dialogique: De la réflexion monologique vers la pro-flexion intersubjective (Münster 1997: 39), that, quoting Martin Buber: ‘Only You, only the discovery of You, leads me to take consciousness of myself’. So it is in encountering the alien-psychic that we become existential subjects ourselves. As Schütz puts it: ‘this means that You and Me exist simultaneously, we coexist’. And coexistence means co-temporaneity, participating to the same duration. We share the same Bergsonian temps de durée, one might add. Nowhere else does this become so clear as when playing together with other musicians. An ensemble of three, four, five or more musicians’ ‘bodies’ must become like one Zemic entity in order to be able to produce in a certain spatiotemporal network a cultural artifact which is a composition, i.e., a particular Zetic entity, by reacting to and interpreting its embedded M1, M2, S2 and S1 modes.

10.18 Conclusion

|

209

10.18 Conclusion Next we have to turn back and ask ourselves whether we were able to answer the questions posed at the beginning. Has such a thing as an ‘existential semiotic cultural theory’ emerged from the previous observations and reflections? We might at least gather here the essential principles of such an ambitious enterprise: 1) The new notion which the ESC theory tries to launch is transcendence 2) The ESC theory is an attempt to see and analyse issues from the inside, using a model called Zemic which refers to four modes of Being 3) Agency: behind the theory is the idea of a subject as a transcendental ego, who is capable of pursuing acts, making choices and enjoying freedom 4) The theory of ESC can be tested by empirical cases of cultural life and history such as studies in cultural heritage 5) The theory is non-deterministic 6) There is a ‘linguistic turn’, in the sense that a new metalanguage is elaborated to deal with transcultural, supra-rational and metacultural issues 7) Formal language is used to some extent, stemming from the semiotic square, deontic logic and the grammar of modalities 8) The appropriate philosophical style is that of the continental and speculative theory, yet the ESC theory is not a regress in the history of philosophy 9) ESC theory is non-reductionist, i.e., it emphasizes the phenomena as such.

| Part III: Lesser Arts

Chapter 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts 11.1 General observations Performance, in French exécution, Aufführung in German or perhaps even better: Darstellen, means that something immanent is made manifest. Insofar as what is performed is a text, i.e., the performance has a certain pre-established model or starting point, what is involved is how this entity changes into some other mode of existence, a kind of transformation. Those meanings which dwelled as implicit in a text already can now burst into life and assume quite new properties. Some art forms are based upon this, i.e., they are not yet what they should be before this process. That is also called interpretation, if one wants to underline the fact that the performing subject adds there something. In the theory of semiotics this could be called ‘modalisation’ of a message or text (A. J. Greimas). Altogether, the definition by Étienne Souriau remains valid: “Performance is the material realization of an art work, and the performer is the one who enacts it” (Souriau 2000: 703). Performing is hence something physic. It is not without reason a musician or actor is compared some times to a sportsman. It is also typical that when one discusses with performing artists they do not speak about spiritual aspects or interpretations, but rather about their physical bodies, instruments, etc.: “When I this morning woke up my back had some pain.”, “Although I yesterday changed a new string to my violin, it is making some strange noise.”, etc. Moreover, Souriau emphasizes that in the so-called temporal arts – theater, music, dance, cinema – one postulates their previous creation and the performer, who is a different person than the author of a work. His/her task is to actualize what the author proposes, although the ‘sketch’ of the creator be complex, demanding and rigorous. Works can get many interpretations; in spite of a text as pre-existing entity, it has to be rendered in blood and flesh. Often one needs improvisation, when the view about one definite interpretation remains in the background, especially in our time . Far from the idea that one would aim at one precise and faithful performance the artist can always add there something new and thus foreground his/her own creativity. Yet here one might like to remark in the manner of Marcel Proust who in his speeches about theater art and performances by Berma (Sarah Bernard of course as her model), said that an artist should be satisfied to serve as a window to the art work.

214 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts In the next, I would like to launch one new aspect and present a model for analysis, which I suppose to be applicable to all performing arts. However, before it, I would like to make a panorama of the central principles of performance philosophy, and of the categories which were already prepared by the reflections of Souriau.

11.1.1 Skill Performing can be interpreted in the light of concepts like competence and performance, in the linguistic sense. Without a certain previously acquired skill or technics there cannot be a decent performance. An actor, musician, circus artist is presupposed to possess professional skill. One feels sympathy for an amateur performer but in his performance normally the fun is at performer not so much at listener. In turn, for professionals the divertissement is at the public, not at performer who contrarily can suffer from stage fright, the imperfection of his execution, or then fulfils his task with a sovereign indifference as to his/her emotions. The more skill, the less tension. On the other hand, the positive side of the tension is that one is excited only about what one considers important and significant. In general, being tensed or nervous stops when one realizes that his tension does not bring any joy to himself nor to anyone else. Sometimes in the case of avantgarde art the professionalism is almost forbidden, because it leads into routine, mannerisms and clichés, wherefrom one just tries to get rid. But there are many theories about what is the role of technical exercise in a performance, and training of a performer. Jacques Février, the French pianist advised the student to repeat same figure hundred times and reading newspaper at the same time. Some artists exercise continuously, although they would have reached the top already. Some think that an actor must train himself and body by hard physical stress. In theater and cinema the technics of a performer is completely subordinated to the will of the director.

11.1.2 Theory Is there some method or theory so that by studying it one becomes a great artist? There are, that is true, schools of performance, particularly in music for all instruments and in singing but also in theater, beginning from bel canto to Wagnerian speech song, from national violin, cello and piano schools to methods of dance at Isadora Duncan and Laban and modern dance, not to mention Stanislavsky, Meyerhold or Artaud. There are also available various schools of relaxation, al-

11.1 General observations

|

215

though what a tensed person is most frightened about is just to get relaxed. One of the most promising and all-encompassing theories of performance as a corporeal activity is certainly the prenatal style theory by Stefania Guerra Lisi and Gino Stefani which they call Globalità dei linguaggi, since it brings together all sign systems as a kind of coherent synesthesia (Guerra Lisi 2006). There are also art theories which guide performance from the background, but what is their relationship to the practice of performance? In Finland the semiotic theory of actor’s work by Kari Salosaari is such one (1989); by applying it, a whole amount of classical dramas were realized at the drama studio of Tampere University. There are structuralist schools of theater, psychoanalytic methods, psychodramas, etc. To some minds too much theorizing makes the exercise of art practically impossible. One professor of literature was asked why he does not write novels, albeit he had studied a lot of theory of narratives, whereupon he said: If the trapeze artist starts to think about where he will step next, he will fall down. Also André Helbo has pondered a semiotic theory of performing arts in his work (Helbo 1987). To his mind the concept of a ‘text’ signifies in theater many aspects. For the first, the text itself, like drama, libretto, score, can carry indications and references as to the staging. Either these ‘didascalies’ have been addressed to an actor concerning details of acting or staging, lights, clothes, sound effects, etc. . . . or to the reader, when they are not intended to be visible, or they have been directed to the ‘implied spectator’. The performance has to be defined according to Helbo as an enunciation which takes place under the presence of the observer, in the context of theatrical conventions. These conventions or codes determine a.o. transition from everyday life to scenes on stage or spectacle. Spectacles have their own theoreticians from Yuri Lotman to Tadeusz Kowzan. Lotman says that spectaclisation is the same as narrativisation. It was common to provide the life with a plot, for instance like war as spectacle in the 19th century Russia. When the normal life was monotonously cyclic, then war, parades, etc. brought some alternation and excitement. A theatrical situation is defined by Helbo as follows (op. cit.: 48): body: the gesture of everyday life are detached from their ‘real’ context and transformed into signs. Every performance contains such a process of semiotisation. – such a semiotisation is due to the fact that a ‘drunk man’ is shown distinctly: ostension determines the acting (one might add here: what is involved is the category of marqué, marked). – this foregrounding is not based upon any intention but is conventional – the meanings thus created are manifold

According to Salosaari, the basis of the semiotics of theater is living man (Salosaari 1989: 61) – and to this I shall refer myself when I later launch my theory of

216 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts performance based upon the modes of being. Salosaari quotes the speech act theory of Searle about locution, illocution and perlocution – what fits well to all rhetorics (see Tarasti 2008: 2–27). When an orator speaks he pursues a speech act and it has two dimensions: locution – the fact that one says something and what is said, which again contains two aspects: the act of proposition and the act of expression; illocution in turn means what is done when one says, and perlocution refers to what is achieved by saying. For instance a teacher of solfeggio says: Let us sing! This message includes all three aspects. Correspondingly in theater when an actor makes an act of acting what is involved is at the same time the fact that he/she is acting and what he/she is acting, and the end result is the ‘text’ of the actor, for instance he acts Hamlet. It manifests what he does when he acts and finally what he causes as a perlocution of his act, i.e., spectators are moved. Yet when Salosaari goes to examine closer what a text of an actor implies, he resorts to the semiotics of the Paris school of semiotics or Greimas’s theory, and extremely systematically. His illustration stems from Carlo Goldoni’s play Le Baruffe ciozzotte 1760, its twelfth scene from its second act as acted and videofilmed in the drama studio of Tampere University in 1971. He launches the whole generative course of Greimas in order to clarify what happens in the level of significations in a dialogue between two actors, Isidoro and Checca. The result is concretized by the following diagram, where the boxes in the middle represent acts of signification, such as to affirm, deny, doubt, persuade, deceit, blind, reveal a fraud, interpret, confirm, etc. Behind them looms a complex modal process at both actors and their dialogical interaction. Methodically speaking the crucial observation here is – and what has a heuristic value for whole theory of performing arts – that the linear course of theatrical text is transformed into pluridimensional, polyphonic – what as early as Roland Barthes said to be characteristic of theater. In this respect it is interesting that when Isidoro keeps silent, he does not disappear at all but is present on stage continuously, and interprets what Checca tells or the process of signification continues. I have brought this remark to the semiotics of music, in which always happens the hierarchisation of a linear chain of signs, for instance at the beginning of the Waldstein Sonata by Beethoven alternate or stay in a dialogue two musical ‘actors’. What is an actor in such an abstract discourse as music is a problem of its own, comparable to the poetic discourse; one may state that it is a unit carrying meanings and thematic figures, in music most often the same as the so-called ‘theme’) . In Beethoven when a theme or motif A has been heard in the bass, it receives an answer from motif B in discant and then the actor A again ‘says’ something in a text and B answers. Thus the syntagmatic chain becomes an inner dialogue. Motif A does not disappear anywhere when B occurs, it remains as a memory in the consciousness of the listener or destinator. So motifs even in music

Figure 11.1: The dialogue by Isidoro and Checca interpreted by the method of Salosaari

11.1 General observations |

217

218 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts

Figure 11.2: Musical actors in a dialogue at the beginning of Waldstein Sonata by Beethoven

modalize one other and actors have their inherent modal contents; moreover, the interpreter, pianist can modalize the score in numerous different manners. This may be the core of performance following the Greimassian theory.

11.1.3 Time As Souriau underlined performing arts constitute temporalisation of a static text. When it is gradually rendered observable by senses, subtle temporal strategies are at the same time applied there. Of many elements of actor’s gesture language most are dependent just on right timing. On the basis of Birdwhistle’s gestural theories Salosaari has developed a list of various temporal gestures of an actor: to elevate, to sink, to make denser, to decelerate, to accelerate, to expand, to diminish, to increase, to resolve, to sustain, to soften, etc. (Salosaari 2000: 8). The American Alexandra Pierce has developed a theory of ‘expressive’ or ‘generous movement’ which has the same idea (Pierce). The performer has to create for the performed work correct temporal dramaturgy. What is involved is also to find the

11.1 General observations

|

219

above mentioned narrative level. Salosaari states rightly: “Narrative activity is a kind of syntagmatic intelligence” (Salosaari op. cit.: 92). An artist can of course anticipate it in his work itself like Sergei Rachmaninov who carefully counted to which point in his work one should situate the dramatic climax. The correct timing appears as certainty, not as hesitation. However, sometimes just uncertainty can be an aspect of interpretation, as it has been told about conductor Serge Koussevitzky and his manner to start a work: he only allowed his arms to sink slowly. The musicians had to guess at which point they should begin, and this made them particularly vigilant. Sometimes it is advised that the performer has to rehearse in a remarkably slower tempo than in performance, this device particularly used in music. Sometimes the composer gives the permission for a tempo rubato, what does it mean to ‘steal time’? In the age of Romanticism, it is was said that if time were stolen one did not need to give it back. In general, musicians know that before the beat one in a bar one can slow down as much as one wishes, but at beat one has to catch the basic pulse again. Even if performing means to linearize an achronic text, or to put it in semiotic terms to syntagmatize, the problem of each performance is – when we put consecutively tones, words, gestures – how one also creates hierarchies there. Performance which is only a series of signs is without depth, expressivity and levels of meaning, i.e., isotopies – which in a witty speech are always complex. This aspect has been investigated by behaviorist methods by measuring and analyzing already realized performance using tapes and recordings. Classical example from a long time ago was La mesure des gestes by Paul Bouissac. The British musicologist John Rink believes that secret lies upon the fact how a musician shapes his performance, Do musicians ‘shape’ consciously or unconsciously their performances? At least every one with a musician’s education knows that form analysis is one of the most hated disciplines in all conservatories. That form or shape revealed by a theoretician is not necessarily cognitively that form or shape which the performer realizes and listener experiences. Mark Reybrouck has studied cognitively a.o. the rhythms of Mahler’s symphonies and obtained interesting results. John Rink again supposes that the logics of shaping is essentially similar at all performers and creators, both in Beethoven as well in Woody Allen. Rink distinguishes the notion of ‘performance motif’ which is a different thing from a thematic motif in a form analysis. He has a.o. analyzed the interpretation by Arthur Rubinstein of a mazurka by Chopin, and remarked that on the performance level it manifests the form ABA in which sections A are rhythmically irregular and B regular. Yet, why the middle section is regular? Not necessarily in order to provide a criterion or standard to how a listener observes and conceives the irregularity of sections A, but what is involved can also be the negation of the basic irregularity of the whole work. In mazurka the accents

220 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts can vary on three different beats of a bar already following the genre tradition, and the performer can vary more. Therefore: where is the basic isotopy of that mazurka by Chopin, in relation to which we can either engage or disengage, to do embrayage/débrayage. In fact this reflection leads us to ponder the dimension of depth of a linear performance ‘text’ and what is pertinent therein. In other words, which elements one has to foreground and mark, which are pushed in the background as unessential. Every performer knows this rule and particularly for works with difficult, complex and rich textures. Rubinstein admitted that he never played all the notes in Iberia by Albeniz, but picked up the essential ones. Only structural notes are played. Heinrich Schenker was a music theoretician, who created his system of analysis after all to help performers to distinguish structural notes from secondary ones. I would add here that existential semiotics in turn enables us to recognize the existential notes from non-existential ones and build the inner world of signification of the work. The problem with spectrogram analysis and other measurements is that one does not always realize that the criteria of pertinence can change along the performance. In fact, the creativity of the performance is based upon the idea that these criteria are not fixed. A good example is Richard Wagner as director of his own works. According to the eye-witnesses from Bayreuth such as Porges and Fricke he never conducted his operas twice similarly. They were changing all the time – and that is why Cosima’s efforts to maintain what was the ‘authentic’ manner in Richard’s time were comical and stagnated the interpretation of the whole drama into awkward stereotypies. Heinrich Porges wrote: “Though everything Wagner did at the rehearsals – every movement, every expression, every intonation – bore out this principle of fidelity to nature one must not forget that he was simultaneously handling the whole vast musico-dramatic apparatus and endeavouring to convert it into a living breathing organism (Porges 1881–1896/1983: 3) . . . Yet all the extraordinary things Wagner did at the rehearsals created the impression of having been improvised. It was as though everything he demanded and he himself so eloquently demonstrated occurred to him in a flash with complete lucidity just at that very moment” (op. cit.: 4). On the other hand, Richard Fricke testifies: “Working with Wagner is extremely difficult, as he does not stick to one thing for long. He jumps from one subject to another, and you cannot pin him down for one subject, which could immediately find a solution. He wants to be his own stage director, but for this detailed work, I may say he lacks all it takes, for his mind is focused on the entirety, losing sight of details and forgetting how he had wanted things done the day before . . . Wagner regularly speaks in an undertone, indistinctly, gesturing with hand and arms, only the last few words of a sentence giving you any idea of what he means . . . (Fricke 1906/1998: 32–33).

11.1 General observations |

221

11.1.4 Emotions Compositions, plays, poems, theater pieces are not yet anything before they are interpreted. Although in the 20th century art a special aesthetic category of espressivo inexpressive was elaborated, which meant the emotionless performance of a work as it stood in the text, score, etc. (at Stravinsky and Prokofiev, see Vladimir Jankélévitch 1961: 25–97), this has to be taken as the minus side of the interpretation of all arts. In semiotics it is said that the text has to be modalized in a performance (i.e., furnished with modalities of will, know, can, must and believe) in order to make any impact. The interpretation by a performer is particularly in abstract arts an important source of semantics. Jean Renoir required his actors to read their roles totally expressionlessly, so that he could then as a director add there the nuances he desired. It was said above how the Greimassian semiotics became via modalities a semiotics of passions. Yet to which extent and which emotions appear in a performance is problematic. Do they directly appear as gestures? Horowitz said that when it comes out of the face, it does not come out of the music. In the theory of tragedy by Aristotle two emotions prevailed: horror and compassion. So on stage, but how at performers? Especially in the education of performers there are a lot of old-fashioned systems based upon dictatorship of a teacher or director, in which the performer is subordinated to a discipline mixed with fear. Famous are Russian ballet masters with their cruel criticisms or conductor divas. Koussevitzky could shout to a cellist: You played wrong. But the musician said: I played exactly g and a as in the notes. “No, the mistake was between the notes!” was the answer. The idea of an authoritarian teacher is that the pupil is made to fear the teacher and lesson so much that going on stage feels like nothing beside it. So one wins the stage fright. Some are milder like Jorma Panula, whose principle in his conductor class is: Help, but do not disturb! Anyway, Stefania Guerra Lisi and Gino Stefani talk about emotonicità, a kind of basic emotionality, which appears in the vital flux of human organism and modulates into profound emotions. Furthermore they put the body into a certain muscular tone which then manifests in the global sensoriality which they call synesthesia (Guerra Lisi 2010: 63).

11.1.5 Intentional body Performing is of course corporeal activity, but this has been misunderstood in many theories and studies. What is involved is an intentional ‘soma’, not immediate physical body, although even it exists of course. Étienne Souriau spoke about

222 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts corporeal arts, whose material is human body: dance, theater, song. In this sense playing is not only purely corporeal because a musician escapes behind his instrument, but on the other hand what he produces in his utterance is totally depending also on corporeality. But it is intentional corporeality. How else could one explain for instance functioning of a symphony orchestra? One hundred musicians can be for hours packed in the same space side by side under extreme control – that is surely worse than working at a landscape office. This is possible only because they forget their physical bodies partly when they shift into another body. Although Proust would portray how a harpist picks up, tones from strings as if they were stars in the sky, or the cellist handles his instrument between his legs as if he were pealing cabbage, this occurs in the intentionality of the primary body. Of course the musician never forgets his physical body. A wind instrumentalist can have only some entrances in a symphony of one hour, but he has to concentrate in his body on them so that his blood pressure heightens before them and finding the right timing and tone is extremely stressful and physically demanding. Souriau speaks about corporeal expression but how erroneously goes research which detaches physical corporeality from intentional and measures only physical aspect and makes science and system of it. The basic unit of corporeal expression is a gesture; that notion is naturally central to all estrade artists. Also in abstract arts without immediate corporeality like in music, the notion of body has become fashionable in the recent efforts to find the behaviorist basis for music. According to Souriau, the gesture or gestus means bodily movement, especially that by arms and hands. Gesture is in the focus at actor, dancer and speaker or orator. Gestures have both expressive and indicative functions. Gestures provide information, show, imitate, let them be spontaneous or codified. Arts utilize gestures for the aesthetic expressivity by emphasizing their form, arabesque like line, rhythm, etc. The gesticulation again is based upon exaggerated gestures – in semiotics one would say on marked or foregrounded gestures. Yet it is particular that the Dictionary of the Body by CNRS (Le dictionnaire du corps, 2008) does not mention the notion of gesture at all. It only speaks like Marcel Mauss about technics of body. Yet in music to find out the correct gesture in music or its signifier and combine it to physical corporeal gesture is quite essential. Jules Gentil at École Normale de Musique said that piano playing is science des gestes and had in principle two movements: pousser/tirer (to push and draw). They formed as he said, the ‘breathing of the hand’. Very often one uses in performing arts metaphors referring to body – thus confirming the theory by Lakoff on the origin of all metaphors in our bodies.

11.1 General observations

|

223

11.1.6 Unpredictability Insofar as performance is dialogue in the sense of Mikhail Bakhtin, one of its most important characters is that its end result can never be anticipated. Souriau remarks (Souriau 1990: 703) that the “work looks less and less anything determined in the sense that performance would realize it definitely”. Hence performance is never mechanic ‘translation’ of a text into other languages, for instance from a text to tones, gestures, etc., but it is always typical that performance permits disturbances, ‘noise’ in the information theoretical sense. It is expressly presumed that performer adds something new to a text in his interpretation in order to make it living. Therefore tunes realized by computers perplex us by their machine-like quality. In any case disturbances are possible and even desirable and that is why people still want to go to concerts, theaters, opera to follow a live performance. I once asked a composer to come with me to a concert Beethoven’s Eroica featuring in the program but he answered: I have already heard it. In performance always opens some new aspect which could not be expected before. Yet how a performer obtains a contact with the audience is a problem of its own, as well as contact in general in human communication. Our Italian colleagues Gino Stefani and Stefania Guerra Lisi have arranged symposia on it and published works about contact. What they say is of most profound meaning to any performer. On the other hand, the origin of Bakhtin’s notion of the dialogue was in a kind of disputes. He stayed after the Revolution in Nävel, where public disputes on common topics, such as the existence of God were organized. There Bakhtin realized that no idea or concepts existed anywhere else than first in a dialogue, as an ideologeme or as a belief in the world of the speaker. Nevertheless, the unpredictability and unforeseeability of performance is also connected with it physicality. Performer can never be 100 percent sure that the physical aspect of performance succeeds; it is like one young student returned home from entrance examination of a conservatory crying and telling: Otherwise it went fine but fugue was cut! The first imperative of a performer is naturally that the show must go on. The chain of communication must not break.

11.1.7 Schein At the end the dialectics of Schein and Sein, appearance and being constitutes the basis for the evaluation of the reality of a performance. Performance is always juxtaposed with a text as its starting point; to some mind performance has to be always faithful interpretation of the departure text. Being in the ground of performance is, so to say, the authentic form of an art work, which a performer

224 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts either reaches or not. In order to attain it he has to study abundantly its structure, meanings, isotopies and background, history, aesthetics, artist’s biography, etc. Yet then one easily forgets that performance is not reconstruction. The socalled authenticity does not mean that performance were an obedient copy of some original. This has been tried but ignoring then what all had happened in time between the creation of the work and its new emanation, and this all cannot be deleted. Between the original and a copy, i.e., performance, intrudes our image on authenticity whereby at the end the performance is evaluated. We do not go to theater, opera, concert to listen to historical documents of ideas and emotions by people long time ago but we go there because the work to be performed has as it is said ‘ästhetische Gegenwärtigkeit’, it is talking to us here and now. By this we do not deny that there was not an aspiration towards authenticity as an obligation, but as early as François Couperin said in the 17th century: Nous écrivons différemment de ce que nous exécutons (we write differently from what we play). The notation is only starting point:

our image of authenticity

authentic text

performance as a reconstruction or interpretation

Figure 11.3: The authentic performance as interpretation or reconstruction

However in the opera performances nowadays the idea is prevailing that director builds his own work upon the original text, which disappears as mere title and pretext to render ideas of stage director. This is true particularly in recent Mozart, Verdi and Wagner interpretations. Harry Kupfer changes the end of Parsifal so that Amfortas dies and Kundry is married with Parsifal, Roman Hovenbitzer lets Elsa survive with Gottfried, etc. Recently in the Flying Dutchman the main protagonist is not saved but remains in his dammed boat after Senta’s suicide. The stage director assumes too much the average viewpoint of contemporary spectator and

11.1 General observations |

225

transforms the plot of the opera, so that it becomes compatible with values and ideas of our time. Then one forgets that in opera also music has been written to express certain semiotic universe of meanings, if narration is changed, one should change even the music. it may occur that something happens inside and music is contemplative and internal. However, director puts the scene outside although the music remains the same. Like in Doktor Faust by Busoni, in its Teatro Comunale version in Bologna in 1985 Faust was made an alpinist instead of a scholar amidst his books. Music and text constitute a close dialogue – and director changes it polemically so that singers shout to each other from extreme ends of stage. Performance is always representation. Behind it looms le monde naturel, the reality, but it is positioned at the distance of one step from it. It is like the German philosophers said Schein, appearance, manifestation. Performance is always a second degree reality. Therefore the expression ‘larger than life movie’ may sound tempting. Performance is communication of communication as Ivo Osolsobě said. How we should interpret a situation in which an actor acts sleeping on stage and falls asleep. Spectacles are also representations although they set on stage values and ideologies of spectators. Once I brought an Iranian student to an opera performance; he had never seen opera before. It was Boris Godunov by Mussorgsky and in its second act in the monastery a certain protagonist Grigory is masked as a monk. The student at my side could not exclaim aloud: But that is Grigory! From the time of Mozart on German opera houses had signs in the audience with a text: Mitsingen verboten (Forbidden to sing together). But it is just in the ideological aspect of performance where it blends together with reality, it becomes a theater ruling over one’s life, whose models are brought to real life like Verdi operas during Risorgimento, or spectacles of the Soviet Union, Third Reich and China of Mao. Yet, in a certain sense one can say that the semiotic theory of translation concerns closely performing, since one really translates there one reality into another, for instance visual notation or text into gestures, sounds, tones – or a transformation takes place into quite a particular world of Schein. On the other hand, the realization of the Schein character of the performance leads into recognition of its play function, what influences its quality. The life work of anthropologist Anthony Seeger has been the filming and recording of rituals of Suyá Indians of Xingu river at Mato Grosso. However, ultimately he was brought himself into the ritual with his cameras. Indians were allowed to look at their own performance of thousands years old ritual. This amused them a lot and they started to joke in front of the camera and improve their performance, and filmed at the end themselves. Accordingly, they did not subordinate into any anthropological object as an example of stone age man’s rites, but they moved at once from the archaic to the ethnosemiotic age.

226 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts In any case, the desire for Schein, to see performance or the intention can be on spectator’s side so strong that the following holds true: the most important dramas, cinemas, music works, etc. are those which one has never experienced, seen, heard, followed. We have only wanted to receive them, but for some reason it was not possible, but we were forced to imagine them. When I was a small boy the Finnish National Theater had Julius Caesar by Shakespeare in their repertoire. At that time there was a vitrine on the front wall of the theater with photographs from the performance. I was too young to go to see the performance, and so I made my image of it only with the help of those black-and-white photos. The rest I had to imagine on the basis of what I heard from my elder brother about the performance. I heard that particularly impressive had been the scene in which amidst Caesar’s triumph an oracle appears on stage and says: Beware the Ides of March! This scene was on a photo in the wall of the theater and it seemed to be even more impressive than the moment when Brutus slays with his dagger Caesar – namely in the fantasy of a boy. In the same way I became a Wagnerian after one performance of Parsifal when I saw it as 12 years old and after having received three records (which one German Wagnerian had sent to me after having heard of the distant young admirer of Wagner) and after one arrangement for piano namely the quire of the Pilgrims from Tannhäuser. All the other I could only read from books and hear occasionally and seldom from the radio. So Wagner was for me more or less a fictive entity. The music imagined in this way was probably much more impressive that the one really heard. Music is not in the sounds and tones but behind them. The reality of performance is always vanishing and susceptible to oblivion. From all the quantity of performances we have seen, what has remained in our minds? Probably only a few star moments. Even if the reason can be in the situation itself, wherefore we recall them. Like Boris Asafiev, composer and music scholar, contemporary to M. Bakhtin, said, we remember from performances memoranda or moments or gestures, figures, attraction points (the notion by Altti Kuusamo, a Finnish visual semiotician), or other; from them a proper living artistic culture is built. Culture has always a memory and always decides which texts are remembered and which not. Yet, performers greatly influence by their modalisations what particular points in work we do remember. For instance, I remember how at a school age I saw in TV the tragedy Daniel Hjort by Julius Wecksell, a Finnish poet, and one reply from it, the phrase by a lady with a black scarf: Och detta hat är jag. (And this hatred is me.) Hologrammically one element may stay to represent the whole art work. I also remember Zarah Leander from Cirkus Peacock at Linnanmäki, Helsinki. She sang. Vill du se en stjärna, se på mig. (Do you want to see a star, look at me.) She appeared on stage on a raising platform as a great diva, yet having already seen her best days, only now I realize how humiliating it may have been for a big star to perform in so vulgar

11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance |

227

environment after all previous. From the staging of Uncle Vanya by the legendary Finnish stage director Eino Kalima only one memorandum remained sounding from the end of the play: . . . and then we shall rest . . . Nevertheless, there are avant-garde performances which force spectators to the spectacle and which consciously break the limit of representation formed by the ramp. Some years ago an experimental drama was realized at the Theater School in Helsinki. I went to see it because the young actors told me that it applied my existential semiotic theories. However, one of the young dramaturgists warned me: remember to ask a ticket to the audience which stays passive. So I did and with full reason since the active part of the audience had to go on stage to dress in plastic coats, and others threw upon them juice and cream cake.

11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance After these preliminary reflections I want to launch one new theoretical model, which I try to apply to the performing arts. What is involved is the newest elaboration of my existential semiotic theory or model with four moments, a ‘semiotic square’, which articulates our subject and his/her being by two aspects, which may be called Me and Society, or Moi and Soi, and four interpretations of the philosophical aspects of being. I shall not start here to report the philosophical background of this theory (there is a large article forthcoming in Oxford Dictionary of Psychology); I am only satisfied to argue that in that four-part model, which origin lies in the Greimassian semiotic square but which deviates also essentially from it since it is transformed into a dynamic movement symbolized by letter ‘Z’, those four aspects are body, person (identity) , social practice, and values and norms (see Figure 11.4). For the simplicity I have numbered these four cases as M1, M2, M3 and M4, and S1, S2, S3 and S4 according to which direction one is going in the model: from a concrete, sensual body towards abstract norms and values, or from these intelligible categories towards their gradual exemplification and corporealisation. I consider these two movements the essential tensions of the ontological semiotics. Here the signs are seen insofar as they express a.o. in performance these four instances from the inside or emicly, so to say. One of my students invented that these signs could be called ‘zemic’ signs, or ‘z’ stems from this course of tension, and ‘emic’ refers to the theory by Pike meaning the internal aspect (see Figure 11.5). The hypothesis behind this model is the following: there is no performing utterance which would not be based to some extent on, would not refer to, mark or foreground some of these four cases. One can always analyze and make them explicit regardless of the genre of performing. How these modes of being, and cat-

228 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts

MOI person, identity

primary body (chotic, kinetic)

social practice, institutions

abstract values and norms SOI

Figure 11.4: The Z-model of our mind

MOI M1 (S4)

M2 (S3)

S2 (M3)

S1 (M4) SOI

Figure 11.5: The Z-model specified

egories of Moi and Soi manifest takes place via various degrees of affirmation and negation. Even in the model of Salosaari the central point were the ‘boxes’ which portrayed these modal operations: denial, affirmation, doubt, persuasion, etc. Yet in the existential semiotic model what is affirmed, denied, persuaded, etc. are just these four superimposed instances. Note that the first letter indicates the dominant modes and the one in parentheses the mode less apparent. Upon this basic ‘ontology’ are built other modalities such as:

11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance |

M1 ‘will’

M2 ‘can’

S2 ‘know’

S1 ‘must’

229

Figure 11.6: The Z-model with modalities

and the new existential sign categories pre-, act- and post, endo-, exo-, pheno-, geno- and qualisigns. I do not discuss right here the essential notion of transcendence, which still radically enriches this semiosis. In any case, if one thinks of the performer himself and his career and development it can be articulated with this model in two directions. For the first there is the body with its innate inclinations which by education, learning, dialogicity, etc. develops into permanent identity of a person. This person with his physical and corporeal properties starts to search for a proper profession, or if he/she has a body good at motion, perhaps for dance, if it is verbal body, then perhaps actor, if it has a good voice, then singer; if he has good lungs, teeth and musicality, he may become a blow instrumentalist; if he has good motorics in hands then pianist, if good sense of rhythm then percussionist, etc. Altogether, one is shifted here from M1 to M2. Furthermore, when he/she develops in this vocation further, he/she is finally able to express on the level of S2, i.e., in a role in an institute, or practice the deepest values of S1, his community. Correspondingly, if the value of Soi is the beauty in gestures, this principle may concretize in a society for instance as a ballet school and institution. It recruits to itself proper ‘bodies’ and persons, i.e., those who have the required motorics, sense of gestural language, aestheticity, outlook and person, for instance perseverance, goal-directedness, etc. So certain persons are selected to realize the values of the Soi; moreover, this is preceded by corporeality as such in flesh, sensuality, etc. or M1. To which extent this process takes place to either direction by itself, automatically, or ‘organically’, and to which extent it has to be helped all the time and supported in a dialogue with teachers, masters, maestros, etc. is a problem in itself. Or as one acknowledged art teacher crystallized his life experience: Some realize, some don’t.

230 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts However, from this model new methodical challenges follow. For the first, obviously signs which appear in each mode or M1, M2, S2 and S1 are perhaps partly ‘same’, partly different. Most often one may think that they get transformed in some way, for instance a gesture of M1, done by some body spontaneously, becomes via gradual habit a part of the person M2, from that one it develops perhaps into a genre sign in some social practice, for instance in a speech of a rhetor, ballet, playing, etc. Ultimately, sign gets sublimated into a certain aesthetic, ideological or other value. For instance, also silence is a gesture, pause. It can be a sign of M1, taciturnity, speechlessness like among autists (see particularly studies by Stefania Guerra Lisi and Gino Stefani) , it grows into character in M2, and furthermore into a trait of certain role. In the opera Peter Grimes by Benjamin Britten the hero is unable to defend himself verbally with fateful consequences. Speechlessness can appear as a dramatic pause done by an actor or musician, and finally silence can be a cultural feature and represent as value the tacit knowledge in a culture in which speech is not appreciated. If each mode of M1–S1 has its own signs, then how in them manifest pre-, act-, post-, quasi-, endo-, exo-, pheno-, and genosigns – are they then a kind of supersigns which overcode those lower level signs and above all put them into the state of continuous becoming? Some gesture can be still presign in M1 whereas in M2 it has become already an act sign, and respectively on Soi level when it is imitated, it has become a post-sign. The aforementioned question of signs proper to each mode can be also put as follows: are there purely corporeal, personal, institutional and normative signs? Let us think of g-signs (Thomas A. Sebeok) or gestures: we are in a ballet following the Swan Lake. The movement of the wings of swan imitated by arms and hands is a sign of M1. But it can be done differently when it is pursued by Margot Fonteyn or Ulanova or Plisetskaya or in the case of the Black Swan by Muhamedov or Baryshnikov, when it becomes a sign of M2, i.e., the whole personality of a dancer is included. Ballet has its particular codes, how it should effectuated following its rules, and then the gesture is ballet: S2, and at the end it has its aesthetic message together with music and plot: it is tempting, soft, sensual, fateful (see Figure 11.7). Altogether, in the problem of how one species of signs becomes another, we distinguish three cases: 1) there are signs which pass through all the modes, 2) there are signs whose Z-movement stops in one phase or mode, and 3) there are signs which are valid in only one mode. In any case the situation is such that signs belong to three worlds: natural world or ‘reality’ (which is always already semiotized, i.e., le monde naturel as Greimas said), narration or the world of the text, and its representation in time and place via actors, i.e., performance (see Figure 11.8).

11.2 An existential semiotic theory of performance |

M1

M2

’'…R ‡i’‡RZ Š…i'’ššo lš…[

’ž…S o r'žUZ lii…’

adSxR

£‡ ŽA‰€žSS zAAe•±  on‡xx

)… =¦xYYnŸ

:t{{A †lHx

S1

M2

231

Figure 11.7: Signs representing each mode

natural world

narration

performance

M1 S2

M1 M2

M1 M2

S2

S2

S2

S1

S1

S3

Figure 11.8: Three worlds of performance

Moreover, a crucial methodical point here is that we have to be able to read these ‘worlds’ transparently, so to say, through each other, or they exist simultaneously. This interpretation may be helped by an analogy from Lévi-Strauss’s mythical model or different readings of the myth of Oedipus via its various versions:

M1 M2 M1 M2 M1 M2 S2

S1

S1

S1

Figure 11.9: The reading of Z-model via its different versions

232 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts Furthermore inside each world holds true that M1, M2, S2 and S1 appear always at the same time side by side or superimposed. By which method we are then able to read such polyvalent texts with complex isotopies? Such a methodology is needed as a kind of X-ray of signs. One major criticism against semiotics has been in general that it has been satisfied to first classify signs into certain types and then search and name for each its proper token or exemplification. For instance ‘icon’ is such a label: such and such sign: well here we have an icon! . . . one states when one encounters such a phenomenon. Yet this means most often enormous truncation, simplification of the reality, schematization since no sign is only icon or index or pre-sign or quasi-sign or endo-sign etc. but represents many sign categories at the same time. When one chooses only one sign species to portray the act of signification, one pushes aside a whole quantity of other sign species, it is often also an ideological choice, the richness of signs is reduced into one dominant idea, ears and eyes are closed to other meanings. Hence the new method must be based upon a new reading manner in which the levels of the reality, modes of being, worlds from M1 to S1 are present. On which basis shall we make a selection in favour of one sign? Accordingly, I propose four readings: M1, M2, S2 and S1 and moreover inside each mode there can be particular signs in the vertical dimensions as relations of type signifier/signified, sa/sé – and in linear, consecutive dimension or signs unfolding from each other, signs becoming signs, signs which are noch nicht, not yet signs or in the ultimate case utopian signs in the sense of Ernst Bloch. Which method then were able to take into account this transparency of sign, the superpositions, and its multileveled nature, representing the state in which they appear really in our lives, in the Dasein? When I next scrutinize nearest the ‘third world’ of the signs, or performance, one aims there for inferring from the face of an actor, intonation of the voice, gesture, etc. those many levels and for interpreting the meaning as a consequence from their joint impact upon us; only then does a sign appear to us as fait total social (Marcel Mauss) . . . and at the same time as fait total individuel or fait total subjectif (which for us is body and person). Yet if we organize the aforementioned levels into a generative course, we notice that often in practice (i.e., performing texts – dramas, compositions, ballets, cinemas) the aesthetic idea consists of these levels falling into conflict among each other’s. For instance, corporeality meets resistance from the norms of society or a value of society cannot be realized since a person of a protagonist deceives it, i.e., is not worthy of some idea, or some person never obtains the profession which he should get, i.e., the shift from M2 to S2, etc. So it is on the level of narration but the same concerns also the performance, representation in time. Film director puts by purpose to a role a person, who deviates from other ‘levels’ regarding M1 and M2. Greta Garbo, the Swedish beauty is put to play in Ninotchka a KGB agent.

11.3 Performance in various arts |

233

Monsieur Hulot with his clumsy properties of M1 and M2 is situated into markedly conventional and limited spheres of Soi amidst protagonists representing it, just in order to create contrast and comics. In the Journal d’un curé de campagne, Bresson puts in the side of a spiritual young priest a prosaic substantial older priest, or two different M1:s. In La règle du jeu by Renoir the tragedy occurs finally at an innocent, and comical side person, who falls victim of an accident, shot by a jealous servant as a wrong person. Marilyn Monroe’s M1 (sensual blond) combined with a naïve character as M2 is placed in the hard American gangster world and its Soi. In Rossellini’s neorealist film Germany in The Year Zero, the distanciation is done by music, atonal avant-garde sonority which assumes a psychodiegetic role portraying the chaotic mind of a young boy or childish M1 is joined with musical signs of S2 and S1 in their ‘negative’ form. (The music serves here as a transcending device like the journal intime of the priest in Bresson.) On the other hand, our model does not need to be applied with school-like systematicity as Greimas’s generative course.

11.3 Performance in various arts 11.3.1 Performance of the text Let us begin with improvisation. In this case, no previous normative text or narrative obliges one to faithfulness; rather, the text emerges only in the performance itself. Some consider improvisation a source of freedom. Mostly, however, the improvisation involves an enactment of models adopted from an earlier text on the basis of a grammar learned by heart, as, for instance, when an artist is encouraged to improvise a fugue from a given theme, or when a speaker is asked to improvise a speech about a given subject. Sometimes a performance seems improvised on the level of appearance, Schein, so natural, immediate, and easy, as if without any premeditation; but basically it is the result of detailed planning and preparation. In turn, performances often prove to be extraordinarily stereotypical in avantgarde art, even in so-called aleatoric, or “chance”, music. Another case is “theatrics”, in the sense of staging a play, opera, and the like. Are theatrics a performing or creative art? Whichever the case, it is nevertheless constituted by some text, for instance a play, which the stage director interprets. But if it is a creative art, then it is a performance only insofar as it is a living temporal process. For example, sometimes a director overlays his own art work upon an original one, perhaps even destroying a good deal of the latter’s intentions with his own desires – for instance, when he seeks to shift an historic drama into modern times. The motive or pretext here, of course, is to bring the work

234 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts closer to a contemporary receiver, but in reality such staging belies an aspiration to foreground oneself as an artist. In Souriau’s (2000) Dictionary of Aesthetics we find a theoretical legitimization: the mise en scène as the work of a stage director. Legitimate or not, during such a process the original text and plot are often transformed unscrupulously. The stage director is an independent artist who creates a performance from a previously existing text. He provides the performance with a meaning he thinks essential, and employs actors whose acting he totally controls, while exploiting all the scenic techniques available. Thus he creates a spectacle of which he is master. Yet compared to other arts, his own is ephemeral and evanescent (Souriau 2000: 1014). Here the world of the performance is as justified as the world of the text is. It is in fact a new text, which other stage directors can then imitate. The problem of the performance is as follows: the original text to be performed can be analyzed in the Z scheme, with M1, M2, M3 and M4. As I tried to show in my recent analysis of Schumann’s Fantasy op. 17 for piano, those modes of being are levels in the text – which, however, are not interconnected as in an organic process as may be revealed in Schenkerian or Greimassian analysis. In fact, those levels can occasionally come into conflict with each other, which is remarkably enriching for the interpretation of a text (Tarasti 2012: 141). To continue: the “performance text” of a text functions by following the same four stages; yet how the original narration M – the physical kinetic energy – appears as the M1 of a performance naturally depends on which art we are considering. There are concepts that pass through various levels, such as gesture, rhetorical figure, genre and so on. Gesture can be a physical and spontaneous entity of narration in M1, which the text evokes most directly; for instance, in musical timbre, rhythm, and other elements. By contrast, the gesture of the performance of M1 lies in its realization; for instance, a singing quality of the violin, the bodily gesture of an actor, his “kinesics” (Salosaari 1989). Yet a gesture can also be a performer’s mannerism, part of his personality (M2); for instance, the martellato technique of Arthur Rubinstein, Glenn Gould’s humming, the on-stage gesture of a great actor or singer, by which his admirers recognize him/her. Moreover, a gesture can stem from the universe of Soi as a feature hidden in a genre or rhetorical system, such as the gesture of a leitmotif in film music. Not only may the music of a film be analyzed with our zemic model. The film itself, as performance, responds to our analytic criteria. This we hope to show in the following.

11.3 Performance in various arts |

235

11.3.2 Film performance-analysis Jean Renoir and Jacques Tati In this regard, let us first consider the film La Règle du jeu by Jean Renoir (1894– 1979). The main intrigue arises from a conflict between the worlds of Moi and Soi. This involves modes of Soi as rules and codes of behavior among different types and social classes of French society; and on the other hand, how these modes of Soi (S) are broken by the force of passions, that is to say, by what protagonists concretely and physically do on the levels of M1 and M2. The same idea appears in the films of Jacques Tati (1907–1982), in an even more grotesque and comedic sense, in order to parody the aforementioned rules and character of the Soi. As early as in La Bruyère’s treatise, Characters, we find various grotesque figures of social life, persons who are always playing a certain role. In Tati, the types of S2 are represented by generals, fathers-heads of families, restaurant keepers, waiters. The essential stylistic device is the obscure dialogue: the spectator cannot at all distinguish what is said, but can hear only the gesture of the voice, le geste de la voix.

Figure 11.10: Jean Renoir

Aki Kaurismäki Later, Aki Kaurismäki (b. 1957) experiments in his films with a contrary gesture of the voice. His famous dialogues go to the other extreme: the protagonists speak so distinctly, use such overly punctilious grammar, and show such deadpan expressions that serious situations are often rendered into comical ones. Kaurismäki’s actors are also totally gestureless types from Finnish or French culture. (For instance, Kaurismäki once chose Matti Pellonpää for a film simply because he had “the glance of a dog”.) In his films there prevails a rebellion against the rules of Soi. The rules of society (S1) are far away; the characters have become alienated from them, and their behavior on the level of M reveals a moral code other than that of the “official” S1 and S2 of their society. Kaurismäki plays with these levels and

236 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts with the cultural competence of the spectator. Toward the end of the movie Man Without a Past, for example, the miserable homeless persons who have fallen off the roster of society start to dance when an elderly woman officer of the Salvation Army sings a well-known Finnish tango tune. For a non-Finnish spectator this female figure is only an actress of the M1 level: an old, wrinkled, worn-out lady. Her face carries so many traces of a lived life that she is also a person on the M2 level. Every Finn, however, recognizes that this is a stunning appearance of the long-famous Finnish singer, Annikki Tähti. From behind the face of M1 steps the figure of this face as S2, and behind it also S1: the old, humanistic Finnish culture glimpsed as a moment of nostalgia.

Figure 11.11: Aki Kaurismäki

Ludwig II of Bavaria Looking at the same narrative protagonist and its realizations by different directors, we come to see how modes of performance can radically change the narration. Ludwig II (1845–1886) appears as the principal actor in films by Visconti, Syberberg, and Kätner. The first two films are well-known; the latter, less known, dates from the year 1954. Kätner’s Ludwig is a romantic hero, and this film follows the types of “Sissi movies” (about Princess Elisabeth of Austria), yet is impressive in its own genre and against the background of the historical narrative. Of course, the most striking of such figures is the Ludwig in Carl Froelich’s movie La vita di Wagner from 1913. Though his gestural expressions, and those of the other protagonists as well, are perhaps overly salient, “marked” – following the genre tradition of the time – they nevertheless display a culturally credible kinesics, evoking the time before the First World War. In contrast, Visconti starts from the demoniacal nature of his actor, which does not necessarily jibe with history and with what we know about Ludwig. Visconti’s realization nevertheless produces a fascinating narrative subject. He is portrayed as alienated and disturbed, a neurotic whose life is scrutinized in opposition to that of “normal” persons. Syberberg, in turn, takes an even greater distance from the historical narrative, and determinedly so. He creates his own surreal Ludwig, which proves surprisingly convincing also on

11.3 Performance in various arts |

237

the level of Moi. The king does not need to shout, yell or rage, since he is a king; it suffices when he whispers: he is listened to in either case. The loneliness of Ludwig is also subtly foregrounded in Syberberg’s rendition.

Figure 11.12: Ludwig II

11.3.3 Varieties of actor/actress, musician, dancer Now I intend to study different interpretations done by the same actor or performer. In this way we can see their development over time.

Max Lorenz The German opera singer, tenor Max Lorenz (1905–1975), enjoyed a long career as a Wagner performer, particularly in the 1930s and 1940s, and was the only one from the Bayreuth stars of that period to be permitted to continue at postwar Bayreuth. The secret of his performer profile was the conflict between the Italianesque, bel canto quality of his voice and a figure emanating from German mythological opera. In spite of his German-ness, Wagner found Italian bel canto to be no problem at all. In his essay “What Is German in Music?” he in fact wrote, as early as at the time of his Mastersingers, that Germany had received singing from Italy. He accepted bel canto on the levels of M1 and M2, but detached this technique from the genre tradition of Italian opera (S2). He transferred it to the emotional peaks of his myth operas, since this technique made such a profound impact on spectators and listeners on the levels of M1 and M2. The tenor Lorenz was an ideal Siegfried type, who fulfilled the Soi requirements of German culture in the physical sense on the level of S1. Lorenz’s mastery soon became apparent, and his recordings came out as early as 1927 in Berlin. His recording of Siegmund’s Winterstürme wichen dem Wonnemond constitutes the best example of that aria that exists, theoretically speaking.

238 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.13: a: Max Lorenz; b: His existential profile as an opera singer

Why is it so exquisite? Can our model also help to explain the excellence of a particular interpretation? We think so, and to illustrate in what follows. In this case, S2 – the entire genre tradition of the aria – is folkish, volksthümlicher Gesang, and thus is deliberately simple as to its style. Yet, Lorenz adds to his interpretation an aspect that stems from the Schubertian lied. That is, he interprets the aria according to the German lied tradition, the S2 of lied. This interpretation ranges far from the stereotyped, Wagnerian, consonance-saturated style, the Bayreuth “barking”. It is lyrical, soft, song-like, which lets the particular qualities of Lorenz’s voice resonate. No one since has superseded this interpretation. His voice also has a feminine aspect, momentarily reminding one of a contralto. Therefore the profile of Lorenz’s rendition is constituted such that M1 and S1 are emphasized, while on the level of S2 the lied genre is foregrounded. M1 represents the brightness of bel canto, but its S1 reference to Italian-ness forgotten, replaced by the S1 of German lied-aesthetics. What we have is not direct conflict, but rather bi-isotopies of the Italian and German styles, which are here reconciled. In subsequent recordings by Lorenz, his voice clearly sounds tired, at a time when more value was being placed on stage charisma, the performer’s kinesics, than on voice quality. We have only one film document of Lorenz, namely the climax of the duet between Brünnhilde and Siegfried at the beginning of “Götterdämmerung”; in which movie we also see Winifred Wagner and the stage director Tietjen listening to the performance. It is very short, lasting only two minutes; but we can infer from the film that the stage language was very gestural, in consonance with the Bayreuth S2 genre. Spectators-listeners were able to overlook any roughness in the voice, thanks to the gestural qualities. Lorenz also sang the role of Walther v. Stolzing. The recording of the Preislied is surprising, since nowhere on it does his voice reach its full brilliance, but

11.3 Performance in various arts

|

239

instead holds tense in the upper register. By contrast, the live recording from Bayreuth, made during the war under Furtwängler’s direction, also proves to be an interesting document. In the Preislied the same Stollen is repeated three times. On the first time Lorenz sings it intentionally slowly, with unbearable pathos. The second time he performs it faster than normal, as if passing it by. Only on the third time does he build to a narrative culmination or highlight, the shine of the Meisterlied. In sum, he applies three different performance strategies.

Kirsten Flagstad A similar conflict occurs between gestural language, kinesics, and vocal part – the levels of M1 and M2 of the interpretation – in the gestures by actress Kirsten Flagstad (1895–1962). In New York, she was filmed after the war when performing on a Bob Hope Show. Her Nordic physiognomy, her M1, corresponds on all points to the Germanic world of Die Walküre, that is to say, its narrative levels of M1 and M2. Vocally the interpretation is brilliant, the words distinct, but not shouted or overly dramatized. The Valkyrie enjoy their “hojotohoo” as they should. There is nothing gloomy or heavy about it. Yet in the staging (S2), the waving of the sword in an awkward manner produces a quite comical effect. That level is in conflict with M1 and M2. On S1, however, the figure is both vocally and bodily acceptable as a Wagnerian, super-Valkyre type. The following diagram portrays her profile of Brünnhilde and the conflicts among its various modes:

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.14: a: Kirsten Flagstad; b: Her profile as interpreter

Ella Eronen The great diva of Finnish theater was Ella Eronen (1900–1987), who is not well known outside her own country and culture. She nevertheless made herself into a true diva rather early in her career. She started in movie roles as a femme fatale figure on the order of Anna Magnani, but later she was just an aging diva, made

240 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts outstanding by her voice. Her greatest success of all time was her recitation of the Finnish national anthem (by J. L. Runeberg) in Stockholm stadium, where she performed it following the outbreak of the Winter War in 1939. That performance proved to have enormous propaganda value on behalf of the Finns.

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.15: a: Ella Eronen; b: Her profile as an actress

The pathetic quality of her voice was her distinctive feature on the M2 level. It was the dominant trait of her profile, even in Nestroy’s play Titus Feuerfuchs, in which I saw her in Helsinki in the 1960s. In addition, I saw her personally at a family visit and was astonished by her transformation from stage to civil life: after a sauna there remained no trace of the make-up of her M1 and M2. Ella Eronen was an example of how one’s M2 can become one’s own S2 genre, particularly when she recited Eino Leino, the Finnish symbolist poet, at the annual celebration of the Finnish Rosenkreutz movement. Her vocal gesture impressed one by its darkly vibrating, fateful qualities.

Olavi Reimas Olavi Reimas (1914–1995) was the main hero of Finnish movies in the 1930s and 1940s, particularly those directed by Valentin Vaala (1909–1976), which ranged from countryside dramas to salon comedies. In fact, it was Vaala who discovered Reimas. Vaala, originally a Russian director (Valentin Ivanoff), invented Reimas at a folk theater in Carelia. Reimas was an ideal hero, since he was a kind of der Man ohne Eigenschaften of the Finnish cinema, which is to say he had no M2 level of his own. On the level of M1 he was neutral, positive, plain-faced, outstanding but not overtly masculine, an actor who completely adapted himself to the interpretation of the director. He exuded nothing on the level of Moi, not having his M2 in film at all, and his kinesics, gestures, and voice all submitted to the will of the director.

11.3 Performance in various arts |

241

As a film director, Vaala was not at all a tyrant like Hitchcock, to whom actors were like cattle; rather, his direction was mild like “a summer rain”, according to one of his actors (Laine et al. 2004: 136). Vaala recalls his works of that golden age of the 1940s: “I first determined every movement, every step, every expression of an actor. I was violent against him/her . . . but now I think . . . that an actor has to feel himself what he is doing, and not be only a puppet of the director” (ibid.: 135). He considered movies primarily as an art of directing. During wartime Vaala used his own team of actors, its central figure being a dark-haired Carelian boy Olavi Reimas (real name, Unto Kalervo Eskola), who never failed to enchant audiences.

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.16: a: Olavi Reimas; b: His profile as a movie actor

Reimas was wounded in the Winter War, and lay unconscious for a month in hospital; he did recover, but with a partial loss of memory. Yet, Vaala did not abandon him, although many montages had to be repeated. Reimas was also suited for salon comedies such as the movie Man Model, in which he is the object of a woman’s erotic glance, anticipating feminist film aesthetics. The woman’s role was acted by the opera singer Maaria Eira, who from her operatic image had acquired her own M2. We may contrast Reimas with another film star of the same period, Tauno Palo, whose career continued much longer. In his roles, Palo exuded his own strong M1 and M2, and was thus quite the opposite of Reimas, who represented the gestureless, unexaggerated type of French movie hero that was favored by Renoir.

Irek Muhamedov Ballet star of the 1980s, Irek Muhamedov, danced the role of the prince in Nutcracker at the Bolshoi and then appeared in London in many roles. An unusually tall ballet dancer, he projected his own M1 and M2. In our terms, he was an Erscheinung for whom it was enough just to appear on stage. In the technical sense

242 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts also, his leaps were enormous, and he had the remarkable ability to adapt to different narrative roles of ballet. (In Minkus’s Bajader, for instance, he portrays a prince under the influence of opium.) To study such a performance existentially, without resort to the mere measurements of gestures, presents a challenge of its own, since every dancer also has his own profile. Doris Laine-Almi, an authority on ballet, says this about dance: Because the medium of dance is the human body, it already puts certain limitations on the movements to be made. On the other hand, man is able to make the same movement in so many different ways. It can be down slowly or fast, with motion or by staying in place. Movement that is only effectuated correctly following an order does not look like the same [. . . ] also the troupe surrounding a dancer changes and causes changes in the interpretation of a movement. (Laine-Almi 2000: 72)

In other words, the starting point of a dance is M1, the physical body, but as early as this level the differences begin. The S1 of a society – for instance different schools of dance and genres, from classical ballet to Indian temple dances – exercises its impact on movements on the level of S2. If a dancer creates an innovation by his person (the level of M2), this can become the source of a genre on the level of S2. For instance, the character of a faun immediately evokes Serge Lifar and Debussy’s L’après-midi d’un faune. In the narrative of a ballet the level of Moi can hide behind the level of Soi and even conflict with it, as in Giselle, where the prince reveals himself by a gesture indicative of a nobleman (M2/S2). Although classical ballet uses precisely determined steps and figures, it offers every dancer the possibility to express emotions and narratives in his own personal manner (Laine-Almi 2000: 73). M2 is revealed even in such an extremely codified bodily performance. Although dance is the most corporeal of all expressions of M1, it has connections with transcendence and S1 as well. The Persian

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.17: a: Irek Muhamedov; b: His profile as a ballet dancer

11.3 Performance in various arts |

243

Sufi philosopher and mystic Maulana Rumi (1207–1273) wrote his most important poems and visions while dancing, keeping his hand on a pillar and moving in a circle; the poems themselves refers to this movement (Hämeen-Anttila 2002: 184). Hence the enunciation of a performance can be the starting point of a performance text and narrative, and not vice-versa as is generally the case.

Valery Gergiev The conductor is a performing artist whose tool is the language of gestures. The conductor’s gestural signs extend from his personal kinesics, or M1 and M2, to gestures as a standardized sign language on the level of S2. In addition, such gestures may attain to the level of S1. A good example is Celibidache, who as a youth conducted the Berlin Philharmonic in a performance of Beethoven’s Egmont Overture in Olympia Hall in post-war Berlin. Serving as S1 here is the belief in the continuity of European culture, and finally its glorification with the final climax of the music. The performance is immersed in a strong existential situation. In the case of some conductors the M1 and M2 levels have nothing interesting to offer. Take Richard Strauss, for instance, who marked the beat with one hand, while at the same time looking at his watch. In this case, the essential work already has been done before the performance, allowing one to focus only on the Soi level, that is to say, the genre of the symphony and its aesthetics (S1).

Figure 11.18: Valery Gergiev

In the case of Valery Gergiev and his “instrument”, the Mariinsky Orchestra, we find a profile that has undergone a great change over the last 20 years, to judge by their performances in Mikkeli, Finland every summer during that period. When the orchestra first arrived they formed a clearly Russian school, with an authoritarian conductor that terrified everyone. The orchestra was strongly dominated by the normative rules of Soi of a certain school. Upon this was built the individual vision and interpretation of the conductor. Now that the orchestra has come into

244 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts contact with the rest of the world, due to the increase in modes of communication, it has shifted away from the Soi and more to the Moi. The technical brilliance has of course been maintained, yet now even “mistakes” are permitted, giving allowance to creativity, and certain nuances have been softened. In short, the Moi of the musicians has started to become foregrounded, but not to the point of conflict, because musical interpretation must preserve the technical modality of ‘can’ as stable and reliable on the level of Moi, so that the orchestra may transmit significations on other levels.

Charles Rosen It is interesting to follow some musicians in terms of the development of their careers, and at the same time note their changing profiles. Such is the case with Charles Rosen (1927–2012), a learned musician who avoids all highlighting of the Moi level. In his performances, Moi is transparent. The essential thing is always the narrative of the musical text itself. Still, on the level of Moi one notices an interesting development in the kinesics of his performance. From the 1960s to the present, the tempo has accelerated in his performances, though one might have expected it to slow somewhat with the pianist’s advancing age.

M1

S2

Z

M2

S1

Figure 11.19: a: Charles Rosen; b: His profile as a pianist.

In all the cases discussed thus far, it is crucial how the performer situates him-/ herself in terms of the square, that is, in the tensional space of fields Moi and Soi. What matters is how the performer articulates himself, how he identifies with the conventional, organic, and existential elements of the narrative. The performer has the power either to ignore them or to take them into account. To utilize those elements skilfully, he will choose gestures that portray and manifest them in his interpretation. For instance, when we analyze an actor’s performance in a film role, we would ask by what means we may examine the inner dynamics and move-

11.3 Performance in various arts |

245

ment of the “zemic” field between the modes of Moi and Soi. On the other hand, we have to note how they are all synchronically present but emphasized in different manners. In cinema and theater studies such phenomena have received little study.

Greta Garbo For instance, Greta Garbo (1905–1990) in her various roles realizes different conflicts of Moi and Soi. In the role of Queen Christina she is a dreamer, almost absentminded, on the level of M1, which is in contradiction with her S2 role and its gestures as a Queen. In Grand Hotel she is again the same oneiric heroine, who says “I want to be alone”. Which contrasts with the activity of hotel guests and the fast tempo of events.

Figure 11.20: Greta Garbo as Queen Christina

Roland Barthes, in his Mythologies (1957), has a classic essay on the “Face of Greta Garbo”. If we interpret Barthes’s observations in the light of our “zemic” model (M1, M2, M3, M4) we get the following results: M1 – “a kind of absolutization of the flesh, which cannot be reached nor abandoned”, “not so much drawn as scarped”, “a kind of mask”, “black eyes, the bow of the eyebrows . . . the form of the nourils”. “There is something considered and human here”. M2 represents a kind of Platonic ideal; in the film, Garbo is always the same (in Queen Christina). The nickname “divine” refers less to her superb beauty than to her essence as a bodily person, who has “descended from heaven”. She did not want her face ever to decline or to portray any other reality than her intellectual perfection. We should recall that, after her film career, Garbo withdrew from the public for the rest of her life; she met with no-one, even though she lived quite a long time. In

246 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts terms of S2, her face mirrored her filmic role, her position as a Swedish film star. Garbo’s face represents that fragile moment in which cinema shifts from existential beauty to the beauty of the essence, when the archetype becomes a vanishing figure. Barthes compares Garbo to Audrey Hepburn on this level, to the child-like or kittenish woman. Garbo’s uniqueness was conceptual, on the order of Hepburn. Garbo’s face is an idea, Hepburn’s an event. On S1 we have the concept of the face as an “idea”, as above. It points to an abstract aesthetic value. Referring to Garbo’s visage, Barthes calls it “. . . the face of snow and loneliness” (Barthes 1957: 95).

Romy Schneider If we stop the temporal flow of a film we notice that, like the musician, the actor is subject to time, that his or her gestures move in time. Kari Salosaari (1989, 2000) construes this motion as the constant transformation of the modalities. We take actress Romy Schneider as our case-study here.

Figure 11.21: Romy Schneider

Henry Bacon has provided us with observations on the face of Romy Schneider (1938–1982) in different montages, concentrating on her performances in two roles. In Visconti’s film Il lavoro, she plays the daughter of a rich German industrial magnate; the action begins when she discovers the adultery of her husband, an Italian count. In Ludwig she plays the role of Sissi, Ludwig’s supposed beloved. Essential, for Bacon, are the alternating expressions of the actress’s face, which is not a “petrified” one as with Garbo. Schneider’s expressions, says Bacon, form part of the narrative: “Dialogue is less important than Romy’s acting . . . in a very

11.3 Performance in various arts |

247

short time span her face expresses playfulness, irony, scorn, indignation, hatred, sorrow, humility . . . ”. All these expressions take place in only half a minute. Bacon observes the face on the level of M1: lips, eyes, voice – these are the physical tools with which the director and cameraman create her character and role, which consists of the alternation of M2 between determination and vulnerability. Cinema channels Schneider’s bravura; that is to say, it utilizes her position as S2. At the end of Il lavoro, according to Bacon, there appears an almost “existential anguish”, when the protagonist fails to create her new identity and withdraws behind the veil of her social class, into S1. In her role in Ludwig, the contrast between M1 and S1 is strongly foregrounded. S1 represents the world of real politics and its attached conventions, according to which Sissi and Ludwig cannot meet in reality. Yet, even here she masks the character, as M1 transformed into M2, since as Judith Weston (cited by Bacon) states: “Character is the one who always wants one thing more than anything else and is ready to give up all for it”. This is a sound observation. Indeed, character (role, theme-actor) in music also behaves in this way. It has a strong modality of will (vouloir); it is marqué, in the foreground, a leading thread, which subsumes all other discursive elements. In chamber music and in orchestral works that feature a lot of instruments, parts and levels, one has to hear the “melody” is, where the main idea goes. In general, only one actor can be so existentially marked. It is the performer’s task to find it, to pick it out from the plurality of the narration.

Elvis Presley We want to include in our paradigm of artists also one from popular music, the semiotically very challenging figure of Elvis Presley. It is obvious that the literature around this phenomenon, in the sociological sense, as a special conflict between emerging American and global youth culture (see Marcel Danesi’s studies) and the ‘establishment’, the genuinely Adornian struggle, is manifest here. Yet, also his development and decline from a youth idol to a tragic, aged, grotesque figure continuing by force his career, a true ‘rake’s progress’, is to be noted. The fascinating aspect here is, particularly in the best moments of the early Elvis Presley, the quality of his voice, a pure ‘genosign’ in the sense of Roland Barthes. In the love songs like Love Me Tender and Can’t Help Falling In Love his voice still has that recognizable quasi-androgynic vibration at the end of long notes, as a lyrical expansion. In terms of bel canto this is perhaps the so-called ‘head voice’ with its resonance in the whole body. So, the strong emphasis on M1 in his profile is evident in those lyrical moments, but the same underlining can also appear as ‘animal’ aggressive use of his whole body on stage, hands and limbs particularly.

248 | 11 A proposal for a semiotic theory of performing arts

Figure 11.22: a: The young Elvis Presley; b: The zemic profile of Elvis Presley

This was a revolt against other type of traditional American country song of the type of Pete Seeger, for instance. It became M2, his personal style, and then the distinguishing mark of his role as a rock n’ roll star, i.e., S2. All this lead to a particular value profile in S1, which was strongly opposed to the bourgeois and conventional American social personality.

Chapter 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking 12.1 Introduction Nearly all the great semioticians have discussed food and cooking – indeed, they could scarcely have overlooked such a fascinating and central human activity. Using a phonetic model, Claude Lévi-Strauss elaborated his famous culinary triangle of raw/cooked/rotten (and Umberto Eco has punningly bemoaned the fact that, due to his gourmandise, he can no longer squeeze himself into Levi Strauss jeans). Roland Barthes examined the syntagms and paradigms of the menu as a manifestation of modern French mythology, and A. J. Greimas investigated the recipe for la soupe au pistou as a “narrative program” (1979). Even in the cultural semiotics of Lotman food makes an appearance, when the author examines ancient Slavic texts and considers what pie decorations have to say about an entire culture. It thus appears that food and gastronomy are eminently open to semiotic study. But if semiotics is communication plus signification, then how does food communicate and function as a sign? The answer is not so simple. For first of all, gastronomy examines only one species of food, namely, the kind of excellent cuisine that pleases gourmets. Brillat-Savarin, author of Physiologie du goût (1826), succeeded in defining that special human agent – the gourmet – who alone can receive the message of good food. In other respects, too, Brillat-Savarin’s classical text emphasizes the receiver’s part in the communication of food. Altogether, gourmandise – a term which Brillat-Savarin suggests should not be translated but left in the French – appears as a marked phenomenon in the linguistic sense. As a kind of foregrounded type, it stands out from most of humanity, which eats only to live and not to enjoy. Does, then, food as a sign exist only for the receiver? If so, then food as communication would clearly represent a message directed towards that recipient, though not in Jakobson’s conative sense. In the latter case, one would attempt to use food to influence the conduct of the receiver. Yet some would say that the opposite takes place: the reception of the food sign is completed in the act of the food being enjoyed. Thus, in this scenario, food communication would be focused on the receiver and at the same time be non-conative. The role of the sender – the cook – crystallizes in the recipe, the verbal rules for food preparation. Recipes vary in character and length. Often they present in

250 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking an extremely condensed form the paradigmatic elements (ingredients), and then as laconically prescribe that the food preparation take place in a certain temporal order. Televised cooking programs little alter this procedure, though all the phases of cooking may be shown visually, step by step. In the end, it seems as if food as a sign could be summarized into a series of commands for action, a procedure which nearest illustrates the operational definition in logic: the definition of a cake is its recipe. Yet it would seem rather strange and contrary to most semiotic practices if food as a sign could be reduced to this mode of existence. Naturally, the experienced gastronome can from the mere recipe quite easily imagine how the food would look and taste if prepared according to the directions. He can mentally reconstruct the food object without actually producing it. Conversely, working from a prepared dish or from a picture of it, he can analyze and reconstruct the recipe without ever touching the food. This process is amazingly analogous to that of musical communication. The musical specialist can, by merely leafing through the score, conceptualize how the piece would sound when played. Composition contests are based on this kind of judgement. Confronted with new pieces that have not yet been performed, the judge must evaluate them by sight, or by the “inner ear”. Correspondingly, when a specialist has heard a piece, he can sometimes at least partly reconstruct its score. As the extreme case there was Mozart, who could notate an entire piece of music after hearing it only once. These two cases, however, illustrate the outer limits of musical communication. Generally, it is hard to imagine music without its physical support, the musical sign, the sounding form. But what remains between the recipe and the experience of enjoyment? There is of course the food itself as object, as a ready-made physical product. But this object cannot fully function as a sign until it is tasted, sipped, eaten – in a word, enjoyed. As the consequence of this experience, however, the corporeal food-sign vanishes; the physical basis of the communication act is annihilated. What remains is only a memory image of the sign – which can be quite powerful and generate, as in the case of Proust, a whole series of the most poetic associations. For one who travels a lot, a gastro-cognitive map of the world gradually takes shape alongside that of geography. Countries and towns find their positions on the map according to what kind of food has been enjoyed in each place. In this extreme form, dishes can also serve as signs for people – as their “doubles”, as Proust used to say. For once we have tasted the bravura of someone’s culinary skills, this becomes his or her “sign”, and it is inevitably evoked even when we enjoy that food or dish elsewhere or even only when we think of it. The undeniable, sad truth is that the semiotic sign of food is at its inception doomed to destruction, and that this species of signs does not have the same

12.2 Two historical perspectives |

251

stability as, say, those of painting, literature, or architecture. Gastronomy should thus be equated with the performing arts of music, theatre, dance, and the like, whose signs are always bound with time that is understood not only as fleeting and fragile moments but as the very physical basis on which they subsist. All the performing arts also have the same essential problem; namely, they can either succeed or fail. The notation of sign production does not guarantee success, which depends instead on the whole situation of communication in which the sign is produced, transmitted and received. As is the case with all performing arts, in food preparation, too, the slightest disturbance can prevent the product from functioning as a sign. For Greimas, food had the semiotic status of a “value object”, that is to say, an object in which values have been invested. In the construction of such objects, the essential point for Greimas is the achievement of values, their discovery and manipulation: “The objects themselves are of no interest. They are worth constructing, creating, producing only to the extent that they form the place for the manifestation of values” [Les objets ne l’intéressent – et leur construction ne mérite d’être entreprise – que dans la mesure où ils constituent des lieux d’investissement des valeurs]. (Greimas 1979: 157.) This same view applies also to music, in the idea that the music is not the same as the tones, but only manifests itself by means of them. But can we adopt such a radically “spiritual” view here? For what could food be as mere value, without the material object carrying it? Everything spiritual which is connected to food seems to be an a posteriori phenomenon. It seems difficult to isolate the food sign with any kind of phenomenological reduction, since it is always bound to its context, its multiple connections in the chain of communication and process of signification. It is generally thought that those interested in food are incurable hedonists, and that those who care about table and other manners are stiff formalists. And a philosopher might at this stage make recourse to Kant’s Metaphysics of Manners, only to be surprised that the latter’s categorical imperative – “Do to others what you wish them to do to you” – crops up in one of the central passages in BrillatSavarin’s Physiologie du goût!

12.2 Two historical perspectives It will be instructive to compare the views of two world-famous French gourmets and chefs, Brillat-Savarin and Édouard Nignon. The first of these was a wellknown doctor whose starting point in his previously cited book on taste was the “medical” observation of food and eating. The charm of the book comes from the

252 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking fact that it reads as if it were objectively precise description, while it is in fact highly subjective and evaluative. Running completely contrary to Greimas’s view, Brillat-Savarin takes the position that values, all spiritual things, all of culture and society stem from human physiological necessity, from the need to satisfy and sustain the senses. Such satisfaction ennobles one, making one happy, tolerant and benevolent toward others. Ultimately, all of society depends on gourmandise. In the chapter entitled “The Advantages of Gourmandise”, Brillat-Savarin states the following: “[Gourmandise] is the impulse which moves living foods from one country to the other; it is a judge which determines the prices of food; it is the hope which arouses competition; it is a profession which creates life and causes the perpetual circulation of monetary resources” (Brillat-Savarin 1826/1988: 135). On this view, one could say that Lévi-Strauss’s theory of three levels of society – the exchange of messages, things, and women – rests upon a fourth, deeper level. And that level is the exchange of foods. All great historical events, even conspiracies and political coups, have been decided upon, prepared, and carried out during feasts (op. cit.: 57). Brillat-Savarin views all the arts and all spiritual things as being based on sensations; they are continuations and refinements of the senses: “The visual sense created painting, sculpture and dramatic arts; the auditory sense, music; the olfactory sense, the use and cultivation of perfumes; the taste sense, the production of alimentary goods, their selection and elaboration; the tactile sense was included in all the arts; and the physical sense of love yielded coquetries and other phenomena.” When we turn to another scion of French gastronomy, Édouard Nignon, the viewpoint changes. In his book, Éloges de la cuisine française, he contrarily states that food reflects higher, non-sensual values. Nignon (1865–1934) was one of the illustrious chefs at the imperial court of Russia. At the parties of the millionaire Ivan Morozoff he concocted spectacular meals such as an aquarium of Chinese fish that sprayed champagne, and a bear sculpted from ice that proffered caviar at the same time as a lamp in the animal’s stomach made its eyes twinkle. Around 1915 Nignon moved from the court of Czar Nikolai to the Hotel Metropol in Moscow, where he prepared fantastic meals for diners in the famous hall with a fountain in the center. Eventually, though, Nignon was forced to return to Paris, when during the Bolshevik Revolution his cooks went on strike. There he became the proprietor of the Restaurant Larue and at last realized his dream of operating his own establishment. His clientele consisted of the leading artists of France, from Marcel Proust to Alfred Capus and Anatole France. Nignon had a sublime conception of the art of cooking, as the opening of his book illustrates:

12.3 Semiotic questions about food

|

253

“What is art, in general, but the lively, harmonious, subtle expression of all that the human brain can conceive about the great, the beautiful and sublime? Every work of art is determined by the intellectual and moral environment of which it is the offspring. The products of the Culinary Art are not an exception to this rule . . . .” (Nignon 1995: 21)

Nignon goes on to note that culinary art does not depend on the external brilliance of its products. The same artistic mastery can show forth in a simple pot de feu soup just as it does in Imperial chicken, the Queen’s smoked salmon, or the Royal Deer Steak, since everything depends on the savoir-faire of the performer. The mind of a great cook unites great knowledge, long practice, and a poet’s soul that is sensitive to all nuances of the Good and the Beautiful. The art of cooking presupposes strict obedience to the rules, but not as blind dogmatism. Nignon encapsulates his doctrine in the slogan, Routine est crime en cuisine. He encourages younger cooks to seek Beauty and Truth (Nignon op. cit.: 23), and exclaims: “Carry and develop in yourselves the profound love for the Culinary Art, generator of Force and Life. May your creations be healthy and may they reveal extreme care in the slightest details. Do not walk mechanically on paths already trod. Study, meditate, search always, be creators!” (p. 45) “One is born a poet or musician; one can also be born a cook.” (p. 43)

The great teacher of Nignon was Carême. And Nignon also mentions BrillatSavarin, when admitting that the invention of a new dish can be compared to the discovery of a new star. Still, Nignon’s basic attitude toward cooking artistry clearly differs from that of Brillat-Savarin.

12.3 Semiotic questions about food Let us leave our two famous chefs, and return to some basic questions in the semiotics of gastronomy: what is a gastronomic sign? How does food function as a sign? The problem can be approached from two directions. One may engage the food sign, or rather the entire gustatory “text”, by taking into account its overall functioning and context and every aspect of the food experience. Or one may scrutinize the smallest significant units of food, as in linguistics we speak about phonemes and morphemes, semes and phemes. Taking the latter approach one might call the minimal unit of food a gastreme. Or if we conceive of every sign as divided into signifiers and signified, then we might speak about gastrophemes and gastrosemes. The gastropheme would refer to the physical qualities, and gastroseme to the meaning of the food. Such a distinction immediately poses questions. Can, for instance, the taste sensation be a gastropheme and a taste exper-

254 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking ience a gastroseme? Or are the ingredients of a recipe gastrophemes, which in various combinations would produce gastrosemes? To begin answering these questions, we can turn to a history of gastronomy by the Finnish scholar Jussi Talvi. He speaks about the first “taste experience” of mankind as taking place in 1765, when a Monsieur Boulanger invented a strong bouillon for the poor people of Paris (see Talvi 1989: 213). From this event comes the word restaurant, which literally means both a food that revitalizes and restores, and the place where it can be enjoyed. Talvi says: “Such a soup may have provided the first deliberate taste experiences of man.” Should then the gastreme be defined as a deliberate, intentional taste experience? Following from this, it would appear that gastropheme/seme come nearest to the signs of poetry and not to those of everyday communication. And yet, since the terms “seme” and “pheme” imply a certain generality, we should perhaps reserve the terms “gastropheme/seme” for referring to the “poetic” function of the cooking art, and use terms such as “culineme” (or “culinopheme/culinoseme”) to describe generalized cooking in all its forms. Lévi-Strauss elaborated his famous theory of culinary triangles, raw/cooked/ rotten, which serve as three distinctive features in the world’s cooking systems. For instance, in the Finnish dairy-products culture, milk = raw, cheese = cooked, and rotten = soured milk, yogurt, and the like. In the category of “cooked”, LéviStrauss distinguishes several modes of production which provide foods with their particular meanings. In this way one might try to analyze the gastrophemes/semes that do not depend on subjective experience, and on this basis determine the distinctive features of various food cultures. To food we could easily apply the commutation test proposed by Roland Barthes: one switches the places of the supposed gastrophemes (for instance, two materials) and then observes whether this change produces a difference on the level of gastrosemes, or taste experience (just as in French we can change the consonants /p/ and /b/ and get two different words pas and bas). Omit the apricot jam from a Sacher torte, or replace it with orange jam, and the item is no longer a Sacher torte. When we move from reflections on the smallest units of meaning to food in its global signification, we find that the latter meaning comes not so much from the food itself as from the broader context(s) in which it appears. Food is a part of man’s life-world, or Umwelt, his/her whole life praxis, which provides food and the enjoyment of it with significations. This is particularly true in societies which still live either entirely or partly in a so-called ethnosemiotic state, which is characterised by a certain cyclicity, the adaptation of life to the alternation of seasons, religious occasions, feasts, and so on. In such a state, the meaning of food is not so much determined by its inner qualities, gastrophemes and semes, but by what Greimas called isotopies and what Lotman termed semiospheres. These terms refer

12.3 Semiotic questions about food |

255

to the semiotic continuum that enables the life of its constituent, individual signs. The existence of this continuum is clearly proved by the so-called traditional food cultures, which the gastronomes do not often appreciate: The history of gastronomy without exception shows that the so-called average person has created none of those delicious foods which we can enjoy even today. People have created traditional foods, but a major part of them are, however, the foods of times of starvation . . . they cannot be polished to become something more refined. (Talvi 1989: 201)

Yet there are numerous descriptions of gastronomically delicious foods, created “anonymously”, which reflect the entire living world. In Gogol’s short story, The Old-World Landowners, Afanasy Ivanovich and Pulcheria Ivanovna spend quiet lives in their village house which is bubbling over with abundance. Although the servants steal as much as they can, nothing is missing from the table of Afanasy and Pulcheria. In fact, the two protagonists do hardly anything, and their repeated dialogues go something like this: How is it, Pulcheria Ivanovna, should we not taste something? What would you like to eat now, Afanasy Ivanovich? Perhaps pies with fat or puppet pies or perhaps salted mushrooms? Strangely, in the description of their food habits the order of the dishes seems not to follow any preestablished narrative program, which in this case would be a menu. As Roland Barthes has shown, the menu has its paradigm, the store of possible dishes, and its syntagm, the linear course of their enjoyment. Yet it seems that in Gogol’s story there is only one paradigm for Afanasy and Pulcheria: the inexhaustible food store from which they impulsively choose things. This reflects an ethnosemiotically articulated culture, in which food symbolizes a certain stable, static, sleepy, but at the same time undeniably poetic life style. The narrator describes such an isotopy, or semiosphere, of food in the following way: . . . always when my wagons approach the verandah of such a house, my heart is taken by a wonderfully sweet and quiet state . . . the faces of those old people always have such mildness, they reflect such hospitality and pure mindedness, that one deliberately abandons, even if for only a while, all unscrupulous wishes and unnoticeably shifts to their silent, close-to-nature life . . .

Gogol’s novel also describes the abrupt mutation of a society from an ethnosemiotic to a sociosemiotic state in which organic solidarity no longer prevails, but everything becomes mechanized and isolated. Most modern cookbooks, which only give prescriptive advice for preparation without reporting on the origin of the dish, present food as detached, as its own more or less artificial product. Such food can be offered to anyone, and enjoyed anywhere and at any time.

256 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking When a recipe book does describe the origin of the food and its context of usage, it better attains to the original ethnosemiotic state. Some cookbooks almost presuppose that the reader’s competence is sufficient to cover the life style which is reflected in the dishes. For instance, Mary Emma Showalter’s Mennonite Community Cookbook (1986) is such a book. Although the recipes in it are very scanty, they are fascinating because by following them the reader imagines himself as reconstructing part of an almost extinct life-style – the world which the movie Witness showed to millions of spectators around the world. One encounters here the art of cooking as an oral culture, which the author attempts to reach by literal means: Since a cookbook of the favorite recipes of Mennonite families had never been published, I now began to sense that the handwritten recipe books were responsible. I asked wherever I went and was astonished to learn how many of them had been destroyed in recent years. The daughters of today were guilty of pushing them aside in favor of the new, just as I had done one day. It is true that many of our mothers were still using the old favorite recipes, but were doing so by memory. When I found them, the little notebooks were usually at the bottom of a stack of modern cookbooks and were kept only for memory’s sake. Through the years many had become so worn and soiled that in places they were no longer legible. (Showalter 1986: ix)

To the same category belongs the cookbook by Princess Olga Obolensky, published under the title Herkkuja ruhtinattaren keittiöstä (Delicacies from the Kitchen of a Princess). The recipes are quite ascetic, and at the end of the book there are facsimile printings from the Finnish-language version (from the first edition in 1931). Still, the recipes are made appealing by the fact that they reflect a certain life-style at the manor of Rantalinna, near Imatra. By preparing, for instance, “The old cake from Riga” according to the book, we can imagine ourselves to participate in that earlier way of living.

12.4 Cooking as a generative course Thus far, I have approached my object from two angles: from its smallest units of signification and from its broader social contexts. Can these two approaches be brought together so as to elaborate a unified methodology for examining food? This poses quite a challenge to semiotics, but it is surely possible to do. Cooking can easily be paralleled to a generative course. In the same way as generative grammar presents the rules for the production of language, we could consider a recipe as a collection of rules for “producing” or “generating” food. Yet there are many kinds of generative grammars. A. J. Greimas, among others,

12.4 Cooking as a generative course

|

257

has applied his own theories to a recipe from Provence for la soupe au pistou. The preparation of food is made explicit with a particular “narrative program” in which the sender-cook attempts to conjoin his receiver-guest to the value object, la soupe au pistou. In my own work, I have applied Greimas’s theories in a somewhat different way, especially to music (and as was stated above, noteworthy similarities exist between the generation of music and food). In doing so, I have distinguished four levels which from the isotopies, go to the spatial, temporal and actorial categories, and further to the modalities, ultimately reaching the surface level of phemes and semes (see Figure 12.1). The isotopes of food have already been discussed above. They indicate that whole world of Dasein with all its significations, which forms the background and starting-point of culinary activity and which determines its raison d’être. The isotopy of food can be ceremonial, for instance, as in the category of a “formal dinner”, to use Emily Post’s vocabulary (such a meal is often illustrated by dinner scenes in English upper-class castles in the novels of Wodehouse and in their film realizations or in my own novel Retour à la Villa Nevski, 2014). Or the food isotopy can be ritual, such as the Eucharist in Wagner’s Parsifal. It can be biologicalmedical, as occurs when one dines in a restaurant containing live food (housed by aquariums, cages, and the like). It can be social, as dinner is envisioned in Minnen från mitt liv, hemma och ut (1931), the memoirs of the Finnish sculptor and gourmet, Ville Vallgren (whom we shall return to later). The food isotopy can be economic: a business lunch during negotiations; it can be political: say, in the encounter of two heads of different states (for instance, the rector of Paris University V, Pierre Villard, has investigated the history of a dinner set that was used only at royal meals). The isotopy can be erotic: Dejeuner sur l’herbe in Manet’s painting or in Renoir’s film. There can be an endless amount of isotopies, any of which can constitute the starting-point for all cooking and culinarism. They provide the whole semiosis of food with sense. On the next level, food is approached via three categories: spatial, temporal, and actorial. Some basic questions regarding spatiality are these: Where is the food eaten? How is the food related to a certain place? If such a thing as a “spirit of place” exists, how does it appear as a food sign? True gastrosemioticians are recognized by the fact that they do not remember places by their names, events, atmospheres, or smells, but by what they eat and where they eat it. Conversely, certain foods perform their gastronomic markedness function only if they are enjoyed in a certain place. Due to a kind of intertextual infiltration, the “semes” of a location penetrate, so to say, to the place of the gastrosemes; they connect on the level of experience to the network of semes which in our minds characterise that place. An entirely different type of map emerges on the basis of

258 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking

Figure 12.1: Generation of food

these gastrosemes, which experience scatters in often unexpected places. A guest may arrive in New York for the first time in the morning and, after the long flight, stagger to a coffee shop. With his coffee, he is probably offered pancakes, whipped butter, and bacon. In such a way the new arrival is initiated into American-ness

12.4 Cooking as a generative course

|

259

via a taste experience that unites the sweet and the salty – two rather opposed phemes – in the same meal. Or when the gastrotourist arrives at Rio de Janeiro or São Paulo, the thick juices of caju, goiaba, abacaxi and the like may give him his first conception of the tropics, which he perhaps glimpsed from the window of the airplane. In Mexico one is invited to taste a certain black mushroom which belonged to the diet of the Aztecs, thus at once being transported to a distant culture. When one has seen Pablo Neruda’s house at Isla Negra in the Pacific, one may drive to San Antonio to taste the soup made of fish with unbelievably coloured shells, which experience is mixed in the mind with the sea-evoking poetry of Neruda and the contours of the Andes. And many a semiotician has paid a visit to the Tudor Room on the Bloomington campus of Indiana University, or has taken morning coffee at the Up-Town Café with Thomas A. Sebeok. The list could be continued endlessly. Cooking, as any performing art, is also a temporal activity. Precise timing on the microlevel is one of the most essential aspects of the “generation” of a meal. The principle of the quandité of time, as one French philosopher calls it, is most important in gastrosemiosis. Some dishes require several days’ or even weeks’ patience; in others a delay of one minute can be fateful. For instance, Nordic rye bread cannot be prepared hastily; and if French chocolate cake remains in the oven one minute too long, it is no longer French chocolate cake. Some dishes are connected with cyclic periodisation, or what could be called the ethnosemiotic calendar. (Finnish life, for one, still strongly follows such seasons and their particular foods.) As to the last Greimassian category, that of actoriality, it is quite apparent that cooking cannot take place without actors. For who else has the competence or savoir-faire to prepare food, judge it, and “perform” it? Édouard Nignon defines such competence and performance in his Éloges (cited above) and sees it as based on three principles: experience, theory, and reasoning (1995: 43). Marcel Proust invented the notion of a “Sonate pathétique of cooking”. To him cooking, musical performance, and receiving guests were cases of the same category, whose perfection in each case was a certain simplicity, moderation, and charm (Proust in his preface to John Ruskin’s essay, “Of Kings’ Treasures”). The three categories of place, time, and actors together constitute the situation in which the semiosis of food is realized. In addition to these basic principles, all the other species of signs – icons, indices, and symbols – obtain in the semiosis of food. The next level of generation concerns the modalities of cooking. Modalities are the ways by which participants in communication colour and “humanize” their messages and sign objects. Modalities are thus the most dynamic part of the semiotic process and hence the most difficult to fix as categories and concepts.

260 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking The one who prepares the food and the one who enjoys it both “modalize” the food. In addition, some modalities are already included in the food object itself. For one, the modality of “knowing” already appears in the requirement that food satisfy our curiosity, in the sense that it must be a new taste experience. We do not willingly serve the same food to our guests on two consecutive occasions, just as at a concert of new music one normally does not perform a previously heard piece (unless it is a masterwork which the audience insists on hearing). Then there is the modality of “will”, in Schopenhauer’s sense. Culinary activity is based upon the Wille zum Essen, a kind of meta-will. Though the cultural differences are great in this area, the ingestion of every meal follows an energetic process which makes one eat its various segments in the “right” order, such as the alternation of sweet and salty dishes (in Italy, for instance, the ice creams and sorbets as mid-deserts may cool the overheated modality of will before the next meat dish arrives). The modality of capability, or “can”, appears in the technical realization of the food, its virtuosity and performance. As Ruskin said: only the one who has measured the resistance of the material can judge the modality of “power” (can). We come next to the modality of “must”, which in this case refers to all the norms that govern culinary communication. These norms can stem from many different isotopies (nutritional, medical, social, and so on), but they can also originate from the next level of generation. Finally, the modality of “belief” refers to food as the manifestation of a certain symbolic value, food as conveying a certain persuasiveness. When all the other modalities are in harmony with time, location, and actor, we experience the food to be in its proper “place”, thereby manifesting the category of truth. But of course it is also possible to cheat or to “lie” with food by substituting the wrong ingredients, altering a recipe, serving a dish in improper order, and so on. As the last level of generation we have the phemes and semes of the food, its smallest units, already pondered above. This level concerns the food as “such”, that is, as combinations of phemes and semes. The generative model just sketched proposes various rules and levels of cooking. The model is Greimas-inspired, but it does not seek to produce a strictly formal analyses on the order of his own study of a Provençale recipe. Rather, my theory can be taken as a mnemonic and heuristic model of gastrosemiotic analysis. It fixes our attention on all essential aspects of food, and also helps us to judge whether a menu or recipe is lacking some crucial aspect of meaning. My model is not generative in the prescriptive sense, such that by it one could produce, say, skilful, authentic, convincing, surprising, or even “correct” dishes. Rather, it is descriptive, insofar as with its help one can model any processes related to cooking and elucidate them with a particular metalanguage that has

12.5 An application: cooking in Paris according to Ville Vallgren |

261

already proved itself in connection with other verbal and non-verbal sign systems. In this way, cooking is elevated from its often underestimated status as one of the “lesser arts” among human texts and sign activities. Furthermore, my model is evaluative, since it tries to analyze the goodness or badness of the product, and to answer why certain combinations of gastrophemes and semes are successful and others are not.

12.5 An application: cooking in Paris according to Ville Vallgren, Finnish sculptor and gourmet Here I shall test the applicability of my theory by analyzing one well-known cookbook, written by the Finnish sculptor and gourmet Ville Vallgren, entitled The Food Catechesis of Old Man Ville. Vallgren’s descriptions of food are rare in the literature, in the sense that he moves on all levels of generation. The bohemian life of Paris forms the background for his recipes, a life in which he participated from 1877–1921. He lived in artistic neighborhoods in Montmartre with such wellknown Finnish and Swedish artists as Gunnar Berndtson, Stigell, Aukusti Uotila, Otto Wallenius, Carl Larsson, Ernst Josephson and Axel Munthe. They often held merry afternoon feasts to celebrate expositions in their favourite restaurants Jesus Syrak, Clarisse of Café Neapolitaine. In the mornings Vallgren would often be awakened by his roommate, Pelle Ekström, who had already bought brioches and prepared coffee. Ekström would ask the rising Vallgren, “Behagar Ers Höghet morgonkaffe?” (Would your Excellency like to take morning coffee?) In his memoirs and in passing comments in his food catechesis, Vallgren writes about his Parisian friends; for instance, how Émile Zola disapproved of the way the Russians were treating the Finns (at that time Finland was still an autonomous part of Russia). Vallgren notes ironically that the real reason for Zola’s indignation was that he received no royalties from any of his novels that were printed in Russia. Paul Verlaine was once saved by Vallgren when he left the Café Procope drunk, since he never enjoyed other than a ham sandwich and a beer. After Verlaine had recited the poem Il pleure dans mon cœur, Vallgren took him home to Rue Monsieur le Prince, and soon thereafter Verlaine died. In sum, Vallgren’s circle of acquaintances consisted of all kinds, from creative originals to shiftless idlers. (When reading his stories one notices how little things have changed. For his Paris is not so far from that of the contemporary Finnish movie producers, the Kaurismäki brothers.) I shall now analyze in more detail one day and its meals from a week in Paris, as described at the beginning of Vallgren’s food catechesis. The week was supposed to serve as a model of how meals could be planned with reason and altern-

262 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking ation, although at the end Vallgren came to the following conclusion (Vallgren 1994: 53): Now we have eaten one whole week and lived, feasting heartily, well, and expensively. We cannot continue this way any longer, although it is good to do so sometimes; but if we should go on living in this reckless way, the bark of our stomach would soon capsize on the waves of our life. So, we must be moderate and save our health capital and not spend it all, along with any interest . . . a good, simple food and drink (wine, of course) will guide us in our daily work to happy days at the age of 100 years.

Figure 12.2: Ville Vallgren in Paris

The spatial, temporal, and actorial situations appear quite clearly in Vallgren’s text: the place is Paris; the time, one week from May 31, 1920; and the actors are Ville and his artist colleagues. The “we” form of the story refers not only to this community but also to the readership, in which Vallgren includes his “us”. The chapter is entitled “The cooking worries of Wednesday”. The narrator notes that, having eaten too heavily on Tuesday, today he might eat somewhat lighter. So he decides to prepare scrambled eggs and adds the following remark – which recurs

12.5 An application: cooking in Paris according to Ville Vallgren |

263

throughout the book: “Everyone knows how good scrambled eggs are prepared in Paris.” The narrator thus refers to an oral tradition that certainly exists, but which cannot be defined explicitly. The eggs require white wine (a Bordeaux Graves) rather than red, says Vallgren, who always chooses the drinks. He has a clear conception of the compatibilities and incompatibilities of certain gastrophemes and -semes. “[W]e can eat kidneys or calf liver. I would rather eat kidneys”, says Vallgren. The recipe for kidneys follows: butter is browned in a pan into which the kidneys are placed after they have been doused with hot water and vinaigrette. Then come chopped mushrooms and onions, and finally red wine or Madeira. (Vallgren often uses wine in food, which Carême, according to Nignon, completely rejected.) Then Vallgren announces: “Now it is ready. With it you can eat cooked potatoes or stewed beans or carrots”. Vallgren’s text is very “deictic”, in the sense that his cooking always takes place at certain places and times to which the reader is pointed. If we wish to have rice, Vallgren advises that “we stir well two cups of rice in cold water and with them pieces of ham and small round spring onions”. In three hours the food is ready to be enjoyed with either red or white Bordeaux. Then follows good Roquefort cheese, “since it fits well after the mild rice”. This method of putting dishes in series could be called the “inner indexicality” of the meal. One dish, so to say, “invites” the next by a forward-proceeding, indexical reference. It is also essential that the dishes are not blended, but are eaten one after the other, in the syntagmatic order. Finally, one takes “big beautiful cultivated strawberries with sugar, together with a creamy and healthy fresh cheese called petit suisse. Add some swigs of Château d’Yquem and we are satisfied”, Vallgren announces. One notes that in Vallgren’s text every food sign is sanctioned according to descriptions of the euphoric or dysphoric modalisation of the receiver. Moreover, all the described recipes are extremely easy to prepare, thus requiring or exhibiting a very small degree of the modality of “can”. As the text continues the depiction of food ceases, and Vallgren declares that he will leave by car for a dinner tour in the countryside, to the “charming Meudon, which is on the shore of the Seine”. When the company arrives at a famous restaurant, the Pêche miraculeuse, they immediately order eel ragout, since the expert knows that that dish takes a long time to prepare. From the verandah, the group can see the River Seine, its “water calm in the evening sunshine”. This makes Ville remember a meal he had in the same place on May 17, when the national day of Norway was celebrated. He similarly recalls vernissage dinners of the nineteenth century, with many celebrities, ranging from Edelfelt to Strindberg, sitting at a table placed on the green meadow, and their “speeches and song as one big choir”. In his memoirs Vallgren tells how “all” Paris was astonished when they

264 | 12 On culinemes, gastrophemes, and other signs of cooking sang the “Suomis sång” (a well-known choral tune written by Friedrich Pacius) in the restaurant Clarisse: När Suomis sång gick av stapeln, blev det stort jubel, succen var storartad, vi måste sjunga den fyra gånger. Alla voro förvånade och undrade huru vi hade kunnat åstadkomma någonting så vackert. [When the song of Finland was sounding, jubilation broke out; so well was it received that we had to sing it four times. Everyone was amazed and wondered how we had been able to produce something so beautiful.]

The essential thing to note here is that food and eating are not detached phenomena. Rather, they call forth other artistic performances and associations. Then the dinner is described in detail, beginning with the main course of fish, which is followed by grilled chicken. The burgundy wine taken with the dishes puts the company in a rollicking mood and loosens their tongues to the point of speechmaking. Vallgren quotes his own ode to Paris and the River Seine, in which he describes the latter as wriggling like an eel – an iconic sign that connects the food and its environment: “It offers its poetry as a balm to the man who understands the Parisian atmosphere of life, where nature, food and wine, this Trinity provides man with a sentimental but passing moment. Amen”. Now they take asparagus and drink champagne, dropping sweet strawberries in their glasses. Finally come the cheese and fruits, and thereafter coffee with cognac. “Then we drive by car through the forest of Boulogne, each to his home”. Only now does Ville tell us about the preparation of the eel ragout, which in his excitement he almost forgot to do. This means that our gastrosemiotician is not always thinking about cooking, but that he wants to enjoy it immediately. The eel is described as one “actor” of the story: The eel, this ugly snake fish, is of course peeled, but it is still alive; it is chopped into pieces, but the damned thing still lives. Ach! How cruel! Now it is put in the pan but it still lives. Only when we stuff its stomach with the pieces of calf kidneys and calf liver does it become frightened and die.

It is noteworthy that the ingredients appear in this narration as anthropomorphized actors. They are not mere semiotic objects, but characterized as having the same modal properties as the sending and receiving actors. The food lives in union with its isotopy. Nothing is formalistic or mechanical, neither the description of procedures nor that of the meal, which has not been reified into a rote recipe.

12.6 Conclusion

| 265

12.6 Conclusion The theories of Barthes and Greimas have led me to the narrative of Vallgren. In his story the generation of food does not take place straightforwardly but via many twists and turns. Undeniably, the main protagonist of the Wednesday story becomes the eel. And the story itself wriggles, iconically following the lead of this archi-actor. Vallgren transmits his enthusiasm to the reader, and the meal inspires its receivers to other action as well. At the feast the food is omnipresent, but at the same time it provides a marvellous, material isotopy to something quite spiritual, an artistic celebration of Paris in the spring. In this model tout se tient, everything depends on everything. The story and the model show how food belongs to the intertextual network, in which it can, in the words of Lévi-Strauss, function as a sign of something quite different.

| Part IV: Heimat

Chapter 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism 13.A.1 Introduction Many signs are in the air that new philosophical foundations and frameworks are nowadays searched for the studies of signs. One of the characteristic features of the European semiotics has been to show that the so-called ‘natural’ sign practices and discourses are in fact artificial and arbitrary. If they are like de Saussure said conventional, they could as well be otherwise, what means that these practices could be changed. According to this epistemic standpoint, all the symbolic activities of man are arbitrary or constructed. But the arbitrariness does not mean any accidentality in the sense of indifference or occasionality. In some respect the idea refers to the existential choice that is true: the human community has done a certain choice for one kind of discursive practice, accepted it and maintains this langue. Yet, as well it could have chosen in another way. Therefore arbitrarity does not mean any negligence of historic and traditional aspects. Certain series of events in the past of a society or culture or individual have caused it to choose such and such practice.

13.A.2 What semioticians say about nature Accordingly, are there at all any practices legitimized by ‘nature’? There is a whole school of sociobiology which claims (Edward O. Wilson 1975) that man’s social activity is based upon biology. With this argument the school obviously represents a kind of determinism (see a.o. the scheme of Wilson about altruism, egoism and meanness and their genetic impacts, Wilson 1975: 119). Likewise, the psychoanalysis of Freud means the reduction of man’s behaviour into ‘human nature’ which is as Freud presumed. In fact even so modern a theory as the idea of Julia Kristeva about khora and symbolic order is based upon the hypothesis of human nature which appears as a prelinguistic kinetics of desires, rhythms and gestures. This deeper archaic level of the human mind is always present in man’s symbolic, read: semiotic, behaviour, and be observed behind it. In the structural anthropology by Lévi-Strauss nature is seen as the counter player of the category of ‘nature’. In his study Structures élémentaires de la parenté he was looking after rules which at the same time were cultural – hence conventional – and based on nature, and found only one, the taboo of incest. By

270 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism his notion of archaic illusion he warned us to consider the so-called traditional cultures somehow more ‘natural’ and infantile as ours. Later the view of the Paris school of ‘nature’ was that it was a kind of figure appearing in texts. By certain mechanisms of discourse it provides us the illusion or meaning effect (effets de sens) that some discoursive practice were, so to say, natural. A.o. students of Greimas analyzed natural scientific discourses, like Françoise Bastide (1979) in her essay on Le foie lavé. Approche sémiotique d’un texte de sciences experimentales (which Greimas himself furnished with a preface by stating that even such concepts as ‘seen’ or ‘demonstrated’ are mythical phenomena; by them one constructs an object of knowledge on syntactic, taxonomic level. The author states how Claude Bernard in his speech in 1855 proceeds according to a kind of ‘generative course’ although deals with phenomena of natural world. He builds up level by level more and more complicated entities and takes into account more and more actors while pondering the formation of sugar in liver. Another scholar of the School, J. L. Excousseau (1985) in his essay “ ‘Objectivité’ et ‘subjectivité’ dans les sciences physiques” studies the meaning effect of objectivity. In his foreword Jacques Fontanille says that what is involved is a cognitive calculus between semiotics of natural world and formal theory. If we look at the dictionary by Greimas-Courtés and the word nature, we read: 1. La nature désigne, par l’opposition à l’artificiel ou au construit, le donné déjà là ou l’état dans lequel se situe l’homme dès sa naissance : en ce sens, on parlera des langues naturelles ou du monde naturel ; 2. Dans le cadre de l’anthropologie structurale, et tout particulièrement du système lévi-straussien l’opposition nature/culture est difficile à définir ; dans cette perspective, la nature ne peut jamais être une sorte de donné premier, originaire, antérieur à l’homme, mais une nature déjà culturalisée, informée par la culture. (Greimas-Courtés 1979: 250)

Greimas has also the entry le monde naturel. There are altogether four different definitions of it. “Nous entendons par monde naturel le paraître selon lequel l’univers se présente à l’homme comme un ensemble de qualités sensibles, doté d’une certaine organisation qui le fait parfois désigner comme ‘le monde du sens commun’ . Par rapport à la structure ‘profonde’ de l’univers, qui est d’ordre physique, chimique, biologique, etc. le monde naturel correspond, pour ainsi dire, à sa structure ‘de surface’ ; c’est d’autre part, une structure ‘discursive’ car il se présente dans le cadre de la relation sujet/objet, il est ‘l’énoncé’ construit par le sujet humain et déchiffrable par lui.” (Greimas, op. cit.: 233)

The other essential definition deals with the language-likeness of the so-called natural world. Can we verbalize the essence of the natural world? For instance . . .

13.A.3 Auguste Comte

|

271

“la zoosémiotique fournirait aisément de nombreux contre-exemples . Il suffira seulement de noter, contrairement aux langues naturelles, seules capables d’exploiter les catégories sémantiques abstraites (ou les universaux) les organisations sémiotiques, reconnues à l’intérieur du monde naturel sont determinés par le caractère implicite de ces catégories . Surtout le monde nature est un langage figuratif, don’t les ‘figures’ sont faites des ‘qualités sensibles’ du monde et agissent directement, sans médiation linguistique, sur l’homme.” (Greimas, op. cit.: 234)

Greimas also warns that “le monde naturel ne doit pas être considéré comme une sémiotique particulière. mais bien plutôt comme un lieu d’élaboration et d’exercise de multiples sémiotiques. One can distinguish there between ‘visions significatives’ and ‘pratiques signifiantes’. To the former belong expressions like ‘le nuage annonce la pluie’ or ‘la mauvaise odeur signale la présence du diable’; to the latter vast fields like la gestualité, la proxémique, etc. i.e. les comportements plus ou moins programmés, finalisés (a priori ou aprés coup) et stéréotypés des hommes, analysables comme des ‘discours’ du monde naturel.” (Greimas, op. cit.: 234)

Consequently the category ‘nature’ escapes in this theory further and further away, since the semiotizing activity of man tries to occupy and adopt to itself greater and greater part of the this field of non-culture – almost in the same sense as Lotman speaks about the spheres of culture and non-culture (but in purely anthropological sense). Yet the triumphs of natural science has been here conceived as precisely contrary process: nature occupies more and more place. The further the neuro- and other type of cognitive brain research proceeds, the smaller seems the sphere of culture, the symbolic and spiritual activity of man to shrink. One considers progress in science that all is rendered measurable. “Try to measure everything , try to count everything, and what is not measurable or countable, try to make it measurable and countable” – the old guide line of natural scientists. Is this not a rather great paradox regarding the semiotic approach?

13.A.3 Auguste Comte In his work La philosophie positive Auguste Comte says (in the chapter Considérations philosophique sur l’ensemble de la biologie): La philosophie théologique ou métaphysique prend pour principe, dans l’explication des phénomènes du monde, le sentiment immédiat des phénomènes humaines. La philosophie positive au contraire subordonne la conception de l’homme à celle du monde. L’étude directe du monde a pu seule produire et développer la grande notion des lois de la nature,

272 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism fondement de toute philosophie positive. Cette étude, en s’étendant graduellement à des phénomènes de moins réguliers, a dû être enfin appliqué à l’étude de l’homme et de la société, dernier terme de son entière généralisation. (Comte 1911: 160–161)

But Comte also warns – as an opposition to the doctrines of metaphysicians – that biology should not fall under empietement exagérées de la philosophie inorganique. Method in which Comte believed in the study of living organisms was comparison. He distinguished there the following phases: 1) comparaison entre les diverses parties de chaque organisme déterminé; 2) entre les sexes; 3) entre les diverses phases que présente l’ensemble du développement; 4) entre les différentes races ou variétés de chaque espèce; 5) enfin, et au plus haut degré, comparaison entre tous les organismes de la hiérarchie biologique. (Comte, op. cit.: 180)

Later he had to admit that the comparative method fitted worse and worse when one was shifted to the field of human beings: . . . sa valeur scientifique diminue, pour les organismes supérieurs, à mesure qu’il s’agit d’appareils et de fonctions d’un ordre plus élévé, don’t on trouve la persistance moins porolongée en descendant l’échelle biologique. Tel est surtout le cas des fonctions intellectuelles et morales, qui, après l’homme deviennent à peine reconnaissables . . . (Comte, op. cit.: 185)

In other words even Comte admits that phenomena of human action are gradually more and more individual and not comparable with each other.

13.A.4 German thinkers from Kant to Schiller Nevertheless, how this issue was dealt with in Comte’s time in Germany, in the promised country of philosophy? It was thought there that nature could for the first mean by Latin terms nasci (to be born, to originate) something which had emerged or grown without help, like the birth of the whole world. Yet in the second place, it means the essence, nature like human nature (Michael Inwood 1992). In both sense nature is something else than culture, at the same time opposed to art and anything artificial. Nature is opposed to man and his spirit. From this stems the distinction Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften. According to Kant, the a priori principles of natural sciences were matter, force and movement, and the movement had further two directions: attraction power and propulsive

13.A.4 German thinkers from Kant to Schiller

| 273

power. Yet in his Kritik der Urteilskraft Kant ponders the teleological character of nature. In the chapter Dinge als Naturzweck sind organisierte Wesen (Things as natural goals are organized essences) gives rather exact definition to what means that an object is a part of nature, natural: So one requires from a thing or body (Körper) which by its inner possibility is taken as nature’s goal, that its parts together, both regarding its form and relations of its connection, produce mutually from their own causality a whole, whose concept is again (in the being which provides such an object with its particular causality) the cause following the principle which says that the influencing cause has to be joined together with the final cause of goal. (Kant, the chapter Kritik der teleologischen Urteilskraft, 1974: 322)

Then Kant confirms that in such a natural entity or body or product (Produkte) each part has to be taken as a tool or organ, since it exists for the sake of itself and of the whole. Yet even this is not sufficient (since it can be an artwork, and therefore exist only for its goal), but it is also an organ serving other parts, not any means for art, but material for all nature producing tools: only then such a product or entity as organized and organizing itself, can be called natural goal. (This Kantian statement can be later scrutinized as a kind of episteme to all such products and constructions of European culture, which claim to be or of which it is claimed that they are dictated by ‘nature’, self-organizing entities, whether they be societies of art works, let us say compositions, Kant, op. cit.: 321–322.) However, Kant still continues: “Organized being is not any machine: it has a moving force. It has in it some building force, namely such one which it gives to matter, which does not have it, or the forwards-unfolding building force (bildende Kraft); it cannot be explained by mere capacity (mechanism) of movement (Kant, op. cit.: 322). Therefore for Kant the organized entities manifest nature’s own goal and intention or Zweck, what constitutes the basis for the teleology of nature. Such teleological feature cannot be any longer reduced into mere causality. “Nichts ist in ihm umsonst zwecklos, oder einem blinden Naturmechanismus zuzuschreiben” (ibid.: 324). In any case Schelling went still farther away. He adopted from Spinoza the medieval view about natura naturans or building nature as an opposition to natura naturata or builded nature. Nature consisted like the sphere of the spirit, of phases, steps or levels or Stufen, which Schelling called by the term Potenzen (forces). The steps of development in nature were more or less parallel to man’s developmental phases. Nature is intelligence transformed into the rigidity of being. Hegel criticized the natural philosophy of Schelling, and particularly its analogies, but adopted from Schelling the view that nature is petrified (versteinerte) intelligence. However, Hegel does not carefully distinguish between logics and

274 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism natural philosophy, since to his mind the logical idea liberates itself, puts itself into movement (sich entlasst) as a free decision (Entschluss) and determines itself as external or intuitive. Entschliessen signifies since the beginning opening but the prefix ent- means separating. Therefore the logical idea does not directly transform itself into life, but nature returns to its beginning and remains mere space. There it has various phases like mechanics (time and space, matter and movement), physics, organic physics (organic life). Each phase is shifted to a higher phase just like categories are connected to each other in logics. Nature does not have a history. Nevertheless, one central idea of Hegel was to show that mind – even when it observes nature – is itself also originating from nature. This were not possible if nature would consist only of units and processes, which were completely alien to the mind. What remains unclear in Hegel’s philosophy is whether his nature means the nature of natural scientists or nature as such. Moreover, to which extent the natural phenomena are necessarily a priori: as a contrast to the idea they were fortuitous. Hegel’s method was to compare the phenomenon (Erscheinung) to a conceptual determinant (Begriffsbestimmung) supposing that there is some general scheme of nature, whose ways of realization are accidental. But where the distinction goes, he does not reveal (here I have summarized Hegel following Inwood’s interpretation, Inwood 1992: 195). Hegel was not fascinated by Schelling’s idea of blending to nature, but he sees the spirit to be in a conflict with nature. He supports the view by Hobbes, that the state of nature means war of all against all. When man thinks of something he at the same time changes it. Therefore when man thinks of nature, it becomes less alien. The practical activities set forth this work, for instance the transformation of nature into park, the production of artefacts, etc.). Yet, after all one of the most fascinating definitions of nature is found at Friedrich Schiller. I have elsewhere dealt with J. W. v. Goethe and his insight of nature, particularly in his Metamorphose der Pflanzen and how it influenced upon music theory (see Tarasti 2003: 3–25). The interesting conception of nature by Schiller is found in his essay Über naïve und sentimentalische Dichtung (1795). The essay launches with an impressive definition of the concept of nature or rather by a statement that ‘nature’ is itself our own notion: There are moments in our lives in which we dedicate a kind of love and touching attention to nature in plants, minerals, animals, in the manners of primal world and peasant people, not because they would please our senses or would satisfy our understanding or taste (for both also the contrary can be true), but because they are a part of nature. Every more refined mind, who does not lack ability to feel, experiences this when he walks out of doors, lives in the countryside or visits thinkers of old times, briefly when is surprised by a glance at the building nature. (Schiller 1795/1997: 3)

13.A.4 German thinkers from Kant to Schiller

| 275

According to Schiller, our observations of nature are naïve. We experience a.o. art as a contrast to nature. “Nature in this sense is to us nothing else than a Dasein with its own laws, the stability of entities by themselves, existence by its own and unchangeable laws.” (Schiller, op. cit.: 3). After listing various objects of nature Schiller at the end states about them: Not these objects but the ideas which appear via them are what we love. We love in them the silent creative life, tranquil activity by itself, the existence by its own laws, the inner necessity, the eternal unity with itself. (op. cit.: 4)

Better one could not define what we in this essay understand by the concepts of ‘nature’ and ‘organism’. They (natural objects) are what we were, they are what we have to become. We were part of nature like they, and our culture has to lead us back – in its journey to reason and freedom – to guide us back to nature . . . We are free, and necessary, we change, by they stay the same. (op. cit.: 4–5)

In fact Schiller determines in his naïve attitude a kind of iconic sign relationship. His category ‘the necessary’ represents iconic isomorphism between man and nature. Instead, his concept of ‘freedom’ means the same as the arbitrary, conventional sign relationship. We are free to form our discourse as we wish. In this sense we are in our semioses detached from nature. A. W. Schlegel has in his essay Poesie defined two species of poetry, which are akin to Schiller, but also deviate from it in essential respects. When thinking of what might be organic/inorganic art and music the idea of A. W. Schlegel is crucial (in fact he is by his definition looking after the same as Julia Kristeva by her notions of khora/symbolic order). The two classes of Schlegel are Naturpoesie and Kunstpoesie: For art poetry holds true the historical development of different kinds of art, their mingling together etc. The natural poetry manifests via artistic poetry, but it is eternal and universal because it is based upon nature of man. By it we finally attain the natural history of art. It portrays the emergence and necessary origin of art, and manifests only by such arts, whose organs are natural to man. The natural organs of art are activities whereby man expresses his innermost and for it most apt tools are words, tones and gestures. They are the basis of poetry, music and dance. (Schlegel 1994: 102–103)

His distinction is thus the same as our hypothesis of beginning on the ‘organic’ and inorganic’ art. The organic art appears often via the inorganic and through it, like the natural poetry via the art poetry.

276 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism We can follow this reasoning in the development story of Occidental ‘soul’ from the Church father and antique thinkers until the outburst of the ‘modern’. The ‘modern’ means that man becomes conscious of his interiority – and at the same time necessarily his discrepancy from cosmic order of nature. The deists, and still John Locke thought that there was the order created by the Providence, to which human life belonged as a part of the Divine place of this cosmos. We realize this when we look at the ‘Order of things’. In fact one returns to this in romanticism, or we reach again the unity with cosmos when we listen to the voice of nature within us. Like Charles Taylor has summarized this view: “We have to re-establish the contact with the impulse of nature within ourselves” (Taylor 1989: 370). This doctrine, which is compatible with the previous deism in the sense that the Divine order appears in nature and in us as a part of nature, was formulated in a figurative form also by romantic poets. The poem by Friedrich Schlegel: Durch alle Töne tönet / Im bunten Erdentraum / Ein leiser Ton gezogen / für den der heimlich lauschet contains the same idea. The naïve attitude by Schiller meant a rediscovered unity with nature whereas the sentimental attitude the fact that even when we get detached from Nature we stay longing for it. Goethe said: Genie ist wiedergewonnene Naivität. In congeniality man returns to nature.

13.A.5 Différance But as Taylor states the romantics thought in addition that nature had to manifest via human action and this leads us, according to him, to the typical romantic expressivist theory. Every man is individual and different. This originality is the standard following which we have to live. The concept of individual difference is granted in all its banality. But it is not what Derrida later understood by différance. Derrida’s différance is rather a separation from cosmos, a kind of primal order. This caused that man was able to define his signs as arbitrary constructions. Nature or the realm of the signifié was irrefutably pushed behind the fence of the small line dividing the sign into signifier and signified. No immediate iconicity or isomorphism, identification, return to nature beyond this small line and its frontier was any longer possible. All that which remained beyond the line represented the Other. However, as early as here one can see how in a deeper sense the philosophy of the Other is not the primary philosophy of mankind. At the end all the distinctions disappear and as Schiller said we become again a part of nature, we blend to cosmos, and return to the primal order of things. In fact, in this manner the important event of semiosis takes place: the creation of the original distinction, the emergence of the proper Derridean différance as a difference between the signifier and the signified. The arbitrariness and

13.A.5 Différance

| 277

conventionality between them symbolizes man’s separation from cosmos and ‘nature’. Moreover, the small line in this familiar diagram can well represent an entirely third relationship in the structure of sign. It would change the dyadic sign theory into triadic. John Deely has in his philosophical inquiries emphasized that sign is not any object among other objects, even less any ‘thing’. Sign is a relationship. Since Deely is Peircean he believes that this element is created by a third element, interpretant. In the dyadic or binary sign theory again the signifier and signified are apart from each other, but they are united by the small horizontal line, which could be well thickened into an entire sphere, no-man’s land between signifier and signified, to that area in which the arbitrary contract about signification is signed. It is the field where also modalities exercise their power. It is the place where power is enacted, in which someone determines the contract. This ‘someone’ can be of course the Heideggerian das Man, but well also some specific entity in the process of signification - let it be a nation, culture, group, school class, or dominant, who sets the signs in their proper places.

Figure 13.1: Old and new sign theory

To this new sign diagram we can insert many dichotomies of Western culture, like nature and culture. Nature is the area repressed by culture under it. Romantics thought that nature was allowed to appear through the line or wall or filter or grill when a subject listened to his inner voice in which nature spoke to him. Sometimes it spoke via a certain actor somewhat like Erda, Mother of Earth appears in Rhinegold amidst the fighting gods and giants. Culture can be the same as civilisation, which gives nature articulation. Instead of culture one can also imagine Kristeva’s ‘symbolic order’ when the voice of nature is heard via ‘semiotic khora’. Roland Barthes applied the idea Kristeva about phenotext (culture) and genotext (nature) to song and spoke about pheno- and genosong. In the place of signifier one can insert the shadows of Plato’s cave metaphor, whereas underneath looms the real world of ideas. The small line represents also mimesis in the sense of Paul Ricoeur. What is involved is also distinction manifest/immanent,

278 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism parole/langue, or Sebeok’s language/modeling systems, which are just situated under the spoken languages; this can also mean surface/deep structure, sameness/otherness, etc. almost endlessly. Major part of semiotic processes take shape following this diagram. But what does the small line represent? Wall, gate, filter, window? If we draw arrows to the scheme leading from down to up, what does this represent?

Figure 13.2: Filter between signifier and signified

Do the arrows represent the original semiotic movement, force, energy, movement, which yields the expression, that which is meant in German by the term Ausdruck? Then the arrow down would mean what v. Uexküll understood by his concept Merken whereas the movement up would be the same as user, to express (in my own theory). Wirken by Uexküll would then convey what happens in the borderline between signifier and signified horizontally, action by signs. There is also another class of otherness which is necessary and is connected to the temporality of our existence. We cannot know what happens in the future – albeit the category of nature forces us to think of nature as a goal-directed entity, as something Zweckmässiges like Kant said. Nature has its telos, goals. By recognizing them we can guess the ways whereby the Other becomes the Same. We have to become unified with the telos of nature. Since romantics thought that nature represented the inner voice of man, man when becoming himself, significant to himself, also became a part of cosmos. By this means the transcendent cosmic order was realized in the dimension of man’s interiority. Yet why the inner voice should be heard somewhere by someone? Schlegel’s poem postulates precisely someone who listens, but not actively, but ‘secretly’. This means that by participating to external communication, the outer dialogue with the world man does not find himself and his cosmos. This happens only by being in autocommunication with oneself. In any case the expression theory or Taylor’s ‘expressivism’ means that man is still apart from cosmos, and that he from this subject position has to express

13.A.6 In biosemiotics

| 279

himself to someone and by some means. This is remarkably more that any mimesis or doctrine of imitation. Man does not only imitate nature or himself by copying them into his signs, but expresses himself via his signs. Man needs signs in order to express himself. Husserl’s distinction between Bedeutungszeichen and Ausdruckszeichen comes here to the foreground. However Taylor is right when he says that the expressivism theory has become the most central content of the ‘modern’ project. When we detach from it the nature’s voice felt intuitively by the romanticists, which speaks inside and due to which when expressing himself man expresses cosmos and returns to union without, when this connection is eliminated we are shifted to the age of the postmodern: the expressivism of each man, society, culture, style period without taking care of other subjects expressing themselves. There are no unifying standards connecting various individuals, no Kantian categorical imperatives, which would unite various subjects. There is mere self-expression on the basis of accidental taste judgements. Therefore the postmodern is the continuation of the modern, but its decline. Here we have already a lot of ingredients for a philosophical interpretation of semiotic theories, but our image of nature metaphors were not complete without one thinker, Jakob v. Uexküll. Although it is true that he came to influence semiotics as late as in the last decades (notwithstanding Italy; Ugo Volli’s oral communication). Uexküll is the founder of the so-called biosemiotics.

13.A.6 In biosemiotics The cornerstones of Uexküll’s thought have been presented in his concise essay Bedeutungslehre (1940), which a.o. shows that a biological approach does not at all mean Comtean ‘positive’ philosophy in the sense of determinism. Quite contrarily, amidst the core of biology we come fairly metaphysically sounding conclusions. According to Uexküll, the movement in nature was not mechanic causality, but was based upon two significant processes: Merken – to signify – and Wirken – to react. He thought that any object could serve as carrier of meaning (Bedeutungsträger). This means two things: either the object is a so-called Merkmalträger, carrier of sign, which is received by a subject. Or it is this subject whom Uexküll calls receiver of meaning (Bedeutungsempfänger). Nevertheless, a subject must possess a particular organ or Merkmalorgan in order to receive it. According to Uexküll, all significant forms in nature from the shapes of clouds to the corollas of buttercups floating in the wind are significant. Significant form which has a duration is always the creation of some subject and not that of a mechanical object. The organs and their forms of all the plants and animals contain significant factors. The next diagram illustrates this:

280 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism

Figure 13.3: The Uexküll model of semiosis

The most important statement by Uexküll is that every organism lives in its own subjective world of signification, Umwelt. There is no objective Umwelt, common to all. When we walk through a meadow, the ‘meadow’ represents completely different realities according to whether it is a plant, insect, cow, or man. He compares each organism to a kind of clock mechanism whose bells start to ring when the binds composed by organs start to pull them. These binds are those signs from Umwelt which it accepts as its proper Bedeutungsträger. For Uexküll each organism is a formation which consists of living cells. They all have their Ich-Ton, or Me-Tone. The tones of these organs ultimately form the Lebenston, living tone of the organism in question. Uexküll observes a spider waving its net. It does not see itself, its net and the thickness of its knots. As little it is seen by a fly which flies to the net. Spider sews its net before any fly has flied to it. Therefore it is not able to build the net according to the model given by any particular fly, but its own a primal image of a fly. Uexküll exclaims: Haloo! I hear how mechanists shout: but here the Umweltlehre becomes a metaphysics. The one who looks after causal factors outside the concrete world is naturally a metaphysician. Well, good. Then in addition to theology is the present physics also metaphysics. (Uexküll 1940: 21)

13.A.6 In biosemiotics

| 281

Organisms are determined by a score unperceivable for senses. It rules over temporal and spatial dimensions which constitute properties of an organism. Therefore there is primal score of both a fly and a spider. Between them there is a certain connection. Behind the phenomena the unity of various primal images and melodies is realized according to an all-encompassing plan of signification. All the organ subjects and organ melodies form the symphony of an organism says Uexküll (op. cit.: 31). Meaningful factors in plants and meaning carriers in animals function as a kind of counterpoint. Like in a duetto both parts have to be written to correspond note by note each other, in the same manner are in nature the meaning factors in a contrapuntal relationship with meaning receivers. The development of the forms of living beings becomes only then comprehensible when we are able to infer from them nature’s own composition study.

The highlight of Uexküll’s essay is the chapter entitled Die Kompositionslehre der Natur (op. cit.: 32). All the natural phenomena are based at least upon the presence of two factors just like in the harmony the minimum are two simultaneous tones: the meaning carriers offered by objects and the meaning receivers contained in subjects. When two organisms are in a harmonic sign relationship with each other, it is necessary first to judge which one of the organisms serves subject and which as object, i.e., meaning carrier. If we know the ‘functional’ sphere by organisms we can clarify the signifying and reacting aspect (Merken und Wirken) of both of them as a kind of counterpoint (somewhat like in a Bakhtinian dialogue). The semiotic nature of the biology by Jakob v. Uexküll has been further clarified by his son Thure (for instance in his essay “Endosemiosis” 1993). Basing upon this I have scrutinized two species of signs, endo- and exosigns and their interaction (see chapter in the book). There we are far from the reduction thesis of the positivists, i.e., the principle that the phiiphenomena were reducible to ph-phenomena or physical phenomena. Rather the contrary is true. We try to resolve the problem itself or what we mean when we speak in general about nature and organism as epistemic categories. Thure v. Uexküll thinks that Jakob’s Umweltlehre particularly well fits together with Peirce’s triadic semiotics. But there is no reason to presume that it were the only semiotic theory, which were compatible with the idea of Umwelt. The concept of Umwelt is evidently related to Greimas’s isotopy and Lotman’s semiosphere or more specifically to culture. Organism, a semiotic actor or subject, like Uexküll says can fall to its proper or wrong isotopy. It can fall into the semiosphere to which it belongs or outside it. Each culture has also its own Ich-Ton, according to which it recognizes the signs

282 | 13.A Metaphors of nature and organicism around it (Merken) and functions in turn (Wirken) in the sphere of non-culture surrounding it. What does not belong to Umwelt, belongs to the Otherness.

13.A.7 Semiogerms Which kind of dynamic relationship prevails between an organism and its Umwelt, isotopy, or semiosphere? I want to present alternatives with five different theses or the cases as following: we can speak of particular ‘semiogerm’ or ‘semiocell’ or ‘semio-actor’, which notions would cover both biological and cultural, vegetarian and animal as well as human worlds. It functions as follows: 1) a semiogerm grows from its own Umwelt ‘organically’: it lives and feels to be there at home. Umwelt is the Heimat, home region in the semiotic sense of the semiogerm. 2) the relationship of a semiogerm to the Umwelt is temporal or historical process or it can grow gradually into it or out of it (Goethe’s metaphors of Hamlet’s character as a seed of an oak planted into a two small a pot). 3) a semiogerm lives in a complex Umwelt or in a pluri-isotopic environment and either adapts well to it or destroy in it. In fact the ‘organic’ can mean just the strength of a semiogerm or ability to adapt itself to various changes of the Umwelt. For instance postmodern society offers a contradictory cultural sphere for the activity of a subject. 4) a semiogerm grows in its Umwelt but it develops following its inner ‘code’ to different direction, it is at the end stronger than its Umwelt and destroys it or transforms it as suitable for itself. This is the property of the strongest semioactors: at the end they completely dominate their own Umwelt. 5) a semiogerm becomes again implanted into an environment alien to it (for instance a semioactor is moved to another culture, milieu, a plant or animal species is transported to another sphere, in the arts a style is borrowed from an earlier period, a citation, etc.); it can also encapsulate there or remain without a dialogic Merken/Wirken relationship to its environment. Or then it can start to change its Umwelt familiar to it. What is involved then is not any Einfühlung, which is an enlivening by acquaintance, but Ausfühlung, a recognition outwards, the transformation of the Other into the Same.

Chapter 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music A “biosemiotic” introduction to the analysis of Jean Sibelius’s symphonic thought 13.B.1 On the musically “organic” A crucial part of the aesthetics of Western art music deals with the concepts of the organic and organicism. In a still broader context, music is connected to the episteme of “nature”. According to Claude Lévi-Strauss, by music we become conscious of the physiological roots of our being. In learned music, a special “pastoral” style was developed to portray nature. For example, many of the so-called topics of the classical style relate to nature and the outdoor life, such as the horn signals in Weber and at the opening of Beethoven’s Les adieux. When Adorno said that “Sibelius’s music is all Nature” (Es ist Alles Natur), this statement referred to many things, but for him it was overall a negative aesthetic category in the musicosocial situation in 1937. Closer inspection shows, however, that Jean Sibelius’s work ranks alongside the “Nature music” of Beethoven’s Pastoral Symphony and the overture to Mendelssohn’s A Midsummer Night’s Dream. The inconsistency in Adorno’s thinking was that, when Sibelius evoked nature it was doomed immediately, but if Mahler did it, then it represented the progressive Hegelian Weltlauf. Nature appears in so many ways in the aesthetics of Western art music that only Arthur Lovejoy, in his classic Nature as Aesthetic Norm (1948), has attempted to list them all. Nature can mean human nature, the cosmic order, imitation of nature, truthfulness, objective beauty, simplicity, symmetry, balance, the primacy of emotion, spontaneity, naïveté, primitivism, irregularity, avoidance of symmetry, the expression of artist’s voice, the fullness of human life, the savage, the fecundity, evolution, and so on. All of these categories obtain in music. Along with the development of the idea of absolute music – which meant instrumental music – there emerged the idea of the symphony and symphonism. This notion was in turn intimately related to the idea of organic growth. This aesthetic norm took hold, becoming an influential value in the entire tradition of symphonic music. In some countries, such as Finland, to write a symphony is still considered the high-mark of a career, whereas in France people shrug their shoulders and remark, “Symphonie, c’est lourd, c’est nordique”. As is known, De-

284 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music bussy once left a concert hall in the middle of a Beethoven symphony, complaining “Oh no, now he starts to develop.” According to Ernst Kurth, there were two important lines of development in the history of Western art music. One was the periodic formal principle, based on the lied and the march and developed by Viennese classicism. It is characterized by clear-cut two-, four-, and eight-bar units, out of which more expansive musical forms could be composed. The other principle was linear art, independent of any strict measures and bar lines, which started with Palestrina’s polyphony and culminated in J. S. Bach’s melodies, an example being the freely undulating line of the Chromatic Fantasy. These two principles were the basic forces of musical formation. In addition, for Kurth music was kinetic energy. The aural, manifest form (signifier) of music was not essential; music only appeared by means of or was represented by it. Thus, all of music approaches the status of “nature” if one interprets the latter in a Bergsonian way as élan vital, or living energy. For Kurth music was “organic” when it followed a free motor impulse. Quadrangular, periodic rhythm was for him something artificial, a kind of “cultural” filter overlaid upon nature, even though it was based on corporeality in the sense of singing and marching. At approximately the same time as Kurth, another music theoretician in the German field, Heinrich Schenker, developed his own conception of tonal music, which was also based on “nature”. Nature was for Schenker the triad, produced by the natural overtone series, which he called the “chord of nature” (Urklang), whose intervals were filled by a primal melodic line plus a bass, together forming the Ursatz. Prolongation of the latter by means of artistic improvisation produced the only “good” music. Good music – that is, the only music worth analyzing and listening to – was of course tonal music and particularly German tonal music. Schenker drew his concept of organicism from Goethe and the latter’s doctrine of the metamorphosis of plants. Kurth and Schenker represent two different views of organicism in music. According to Kurth, organicity or “kinetic energy” arises primarily in the ebb and flow of the linear, horizontal movement of music, or in semiotic language, in its syntagmatic structure. By contrast, for Schenker the organic appears in the vertical movement from a deep structure towards the surface, from Hintergrund to Vordergrund, that is to say, in music’s paradigmatic structure. From the syntagmatic perspective, the organic nature of music obtains by a certain arabesque movement. L’art nouveau, for instance, would be an ideally “organic” style period, with its twining arabesques in leaf-like shapes. From the paradigmatic view, organicism is seen as the inner growth and unfolding of music. Stefan Kostka, in his Materials and Techniques of Twentieth-Century Music, defines what the organic

13.B.1 On the musically “organic”

|

285

is in music, as opposed to the inorganic. In the sub-chapter called “Nonorganic Approaches to Musical Form” he writes the following: A traditional painting depicts something, and if the painting is a good one, every part of the canvas contributes to the effectiveness of the visual message that the artist is trying to convey. In traditional literature every passage has its purpose – fleshing out a character, setting the mood, developing the plot, and so on. The same is generally true of music in the European tradition: the composition is considered to be greater than the sum of its parts, a work of art in which each passage has a function that is vital to the overall plan of a work. Think of any tonal work that you know well, and imagine what it would be like if its parts, themes, transitions and so forth were randomly rearranged. It might be interesting to see how it would turn out, but the piece would almost certainly not be as effective as a whole. (Kostka 1999: 152–153)

Kostka goes on to emphasize that twentieth-century music evidenced a widespread reaction against the traditional organic view, that is to say, against the idea of a composition as a teleological process. He singles out the so-called “moment” form of Stockhausen as the antithesis of organicity. In a broader sense, however, the organicism of music can be connected with the general problem of the arbitrary, conventional articulation of a sign system versus the iconic or indexical articulation of same: all grammars, including musical ones, are in Saussurean theory arbitrary and constructed, based on a set of particular rules. These rules can further be made explicit and thereby artificially generate music endlessly, according to the model, or langue. Contrary to this approach – which exemplifies the idea of nonorganic form – is the view of music as a design or Gestalt, terms used by the Canadian composer and music semiotician, David Lidov. Grammar, as a set of static rules, can of course never be organic. Only can design or gestalt be related to something living. In support of this view, we can note that reformers and inventors of musical grammars, such as Schönberg, rarely number among “organic”-sounding composers. Nevertheless, in some cases even music written according to serial techniques can sound “organic”, as do symphonies by Einojuhani Rautavaara. This leads us to ask, At what point do we experience music as being organic? Is it the case that organicity, when experienced consciously, no longer seems as organic as it did before? In other words, is the organic an unconscious category, such that we should return to Rudolph Réti’s ideas on the thematic process? In some cases it seems that organicity is the consequence of a certain activity of the musical enunciator, whether composer or interpreter. If too much deliberation goes into the composition, then the resulting music is no longer organic. Only when composition takes place in a trance or under inspiration is the result organic. Such a case would involve a special dialogical relationship between the utterance and the act of uttering, between the text and its producer.

286 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music Yet even this definition does not help us to clarify what “organic” means as a quality of a musical text. Why is one composition organic and another one not? One explanation is that all mechanical repetition and potpourri-like formations are inorganic. This idea is advanced by Boris Asafiev in his intonation theory. As late as in Beethoven’s symphonies “a composition became an organically and psychologically motivated whole, which unfolds as growth and development” (Asafiev 1977, vol. 2: 489). As an example Asafiev points to the overture to Wagner’s Die Meistersinger. It is a hidden symphony, whose parts – sonata allegro, andante, scherzo, and finale – have been blended together in such a way as to follow each other logically. They occur, one after the other, as various phases of a cycle, as a single line of development (ibid.: 490). Asafiev also calls such an organic form “dialectic”. If such a fusion is to be taken as particularly “organic”, then it is exemplified by such pieces as Liszt’s B-minor Sonata, Schubert’s Wanderer Fantasy, Sibelius’s Seventh Symphony, as well as the blending together of the first movement and scherzo in the latter’s Fifth Symphony. Reminiscent of Asafiev’s view is Carl Dahlhaus’s interpretation of Beethoven’s symphonic form, when he insists that musical form is not like a scheme that can simply be filled with individual themes (Dahlhaus 1985: 369). Beethoven did not compose “in” form but “with” form. He may, for example, shift transitional material or aspects of the main theme into a subordinate theme. The difference between Schubert and Beethoven is thus clear. In Schubert the form is associative, potpourri-like, but in Beethoven it is “developing variation” (which term Dahlhaus borrows from Schönberg): the idea of connecting certain motivic passages to each other is experienced by the listener as a musical logic and as a counterpart to mere association. In semiotic terms, syntagmatic linearity alone is not sufficient – neither inner iconic similarity nor mere inner indexicality. The musical form has to be experienced as somehow goal-directed, or in Kantian terms, als zweckmäßig, otherwise the music is not organic. Asafiev, too, pays attention to the goal-directedness of music, distinguishing between two types of telos or finalities in the symphonic literature: either the cheerful and free fusion of the personality with the cosmos (Beethoven) or spiritual pain and isolation amidst the crowd, oblivion, and tragic destruction. For Asafiev, musical finality is achieved when some leading idea is revealed, which captures attention and out of which the growing waves of development emerge (1977, vol. 2: 483). This Asafievian ideal is almost literally realized in Sibelius. In the Fifth Symphony, for example, there is a struggle to the end between these two forms of finality, and the listener remains unaware of which solution the composer has chosen. Thus, in order for music to be organic, it is not enough that there be motivic and thematic unity, i.e., that the music consist of more than fortuitous variation.

13.B.1 On the musically “organic”

|

287

Nor is it enough that these variations follow each other indexically and smoothly. Music has to progress towards some goal or telos; music must be directional. But is not all music as a temporal art directed towards something? Here we do not mean the primary temporality of music but temporality as “marked”, as Robert Hatten (1994) might put it. In organic music, musical time is organized towards a certain goal. How is this goal created? That is, How does a listener know that the music has a goal and a direction? Leonard B. Meyer, in his Explaining Music (1978), presents a theory of melody that emphasizes well-formed melodic shapes. There are certain musico-cognitive archetypes, the breaking or deficient fulfilment of which causes the listener to remain waiting for the right solution, the correct design. (On this view, Lidov’s theory of design would be sufficient to explain the organic nature of music.) For instance, if we hear at the beginning a “gap-fill” type of melody, then a telos of music is created by the unfilled gap, which may not be completed until the very end of the piece. This tension keeps the music in motion and produces the kinetic energy, the catalysing impulse. An example is the opening of Sibelius’s Fifth Symphony, where a motive sounds that is incomplete in three respects. Firstly, this motive, which Tawaststjerna calls a “bucolic signal”, is first rhythmically syncopated and heard in a strange 12/8 meter. Secondly, its verse structure is irregular, as Lorenz Luyken has remarked (1995: 42–43). Thirdly, it is based on an open fifth-fourth intervallic shape, which causes the listener to remain waiting for these gaps to be filled (see Figure 13.4). Harmonically the music hovers around the six-four chord of the E flat major, a device similar to that which occurs at the beginning of Beethoven’s Sonata op. 31 no. 3. Beethoven lets the phrase cadence on the tonic rather soon, however, whereas Sibelius delays it until the very end of the symphony. There we also hear the fifths and fourths filled with a stepwise scale passage and leading tones: it is the great and relieving climax of the whole work, all the more since we have been oscillating between various tragic alternatives just before it arrives. The extremely restless and ambiguous theme on the Neapolitan chord ceases its wandering and is filled with a scale in E flat minor (which the sketches show to be one of the symphony’s founding ideas). But even at the end of the symphony, where the tonic is confirmed with a cadence, rhythmic balance is still not reached, since not all of the cadential chords are on strong beats. There is a particular irony in this, a musical pun, the wish to show that this is not altogether too serious – a rare moment in Sibelius! The situation recalls what happens in a play when the clown returns and addresses the audience directly to recite the final words, or as in the closing morality segment of Mozart’s Don Giovanni. Music thus has its own telos, which sets energies in motion. They emerge from musical designs, gestalt qualities, of which we expect the completed form. Accord-

288 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music

Figure 13.4: Sibelius, beginning of the Fifth Symphony

ing to Jan LaRue (1994), music has a special dimension of growth that binds all the other musical parameters together – this term in itself sounds rather “organic”. Can “organicism” arise from some other quality of the musical texture? For instance, Sibelius’s music typically has fields that constitute the elements for the so-called “space dramaturgy” analyzed by Luyken (1995). Sibelius’s music often seems to be driven into a kind of fenced-in area, from which there is no exit. The formation of such fields was already evident in early Sibelius, for instance, in En Saga (in Finnish: Satu), realized by means of a simple repetitive form. That is to say, the same melody or theme recurs until, by repetition, it loses its character as a musical subject that distinguishes itself from its surroundings, its musical Umwelt. The music itself becomes a subjectless environment. This is a particularly Sibelian way of deactorializing the music, so as to make it an impersonal and vegetative natural process in which no thinking or feeling subject can be seen. In the Fifth Symphony, such a field is formed by the chromatic lament motives in the first

13.B.1 On the musically “organic”

|

289

movement (score numbers J–M), which one hears for a very long time. (Such a situation is not far from Ligeti’s field technique, which in turn is not the same as the “sonoristic” fields of the Polish school [see Mirka 1997].) But this predominantly “static” field arises from a continuous, micro-organic process. How does one enter into such a field, and how does one get out of it? In the Fifth Symphony the field is simply exhausted: one does not leave it by means of a musically determined “escape route”, such as modulation (as occurs in the Second Symphony with the D minor field in the Finale which leads into the parallel major.) The question of the organic nature of music can also be interpreted as a question of the right method of analysis. One can imagine that methods based on musical “functions” would better take into account the organic quality than do tectonic, segmentational, mechanistic models (to which unfortunately the major part of music-semiotic analyses belong). The basic problem of organic music does not at all concern how music can be divided into smaller pieces but rather how the music coheres. Boris Asafiev viewed music as consisting of three main functions: initium, motus, and terminus. In Greimassian semiotics these correspond to the so-called aspectual semes: inchoativity, durativity, and terminativity. In Claude Brémond’s narratology, they parallel the three phases of storytelling: virtuality, passage/nonpassage to action, achievement/inachievement. According to Asafiev, the musical organic process always presupposes these three basic phases. Quite similar theories have been developed elsewhere.¹ But there may be still other means by which music becomes organic. I have elsewhere (see Chapter 13.A) introduced the biosemiotics and doctrine of Umwelt by Baltic biologist Jakob v. Uexküll, whose ideas have been provoking lively discussion among semioticians quite recently. What if we were to take his ideas seriously in music? As is known, his theory is based on the idea that every organism functions according to a pre-established “score” which determines the nature of its Umwelt. The organism connects to that world by two processes, Merken and Wirken. Every organism has its particular Ich-ton which is determinant of its being and acting. We can see in this concept an analogy to music, and say that every theme, every musical motive, every intonation lives in its own, characteristic musical Umwelt. An organic composer takes into account expressly the relationship of a musical event to its musical environment. A good example of the relationship of a theme to its Umwelt would be the variations of the Andante theme in Beeth-

1 Another, interesting “narratological” view of music can be found in the analysis manual of Ivanka Stoianova, used in her music courses at Paris University VIII. Stoianova takes her ideas often from her teachers in Moscow.

290 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music

Figure 13.5: Beethoven, Fifth Symphony, mvt. 2, mm. 106–109

oven’s Fifth Symphony (Figure 13.5). There the main motive is continually shifted into new, interesting-sounding milieus; the listener pays more attention to these environments than to the theme itself. In the classical tradition, melody and accompaniment are derived from the same material (as at the beginning of Schumann’s C major Fantasy, where the accompaniment figure is the same as the descending theme in the upper register), in which case the organic nature of music lies in the interaction of musical event and its environment. By contrast, the postmodern style – early examples of which are Poulenc’s Concerto for Two Pianos and even Stravinsky’s neoclassicism – uses quotation techniques and avoids the aforementioned organic unity. The environment of the theme must be alienating. That is to say, if the context is tonal, then the citation has to distinguish itself as something dissonant. And if the context is atonal, the citation has to be distinguished by its tonality. In Sibelius’s Fifth Symphony, even in the earlier version of 1915, there is a strangely dissonant, piercing variant of the so-called Neapolitan theme which is superimposed on the “Swan theme” – this is one of the rare futurist and fauvist moments in all of Sibelius’s

13.B.1 On the musically “organic”

|

291

output. There the theme really appears as if it were in a wrong isotopy or musical Umwelt. Are there other means by which music can become organic? Wilhelm Furtwängler in his writings paid attention to the biological foundation of all music. However, the use of the term “biology” in music is metaphorical and thus as ambiguous as the concept of “nature” when applied to any art form. To Furtwängler, the so-called “absolute” music of the classical period was much more than functional, casual music. Dahlhaus remarks that Vienna’s musically rich and manysided Umwelt enabled the emergence of the classical style. But Furtwängler believes that there was something else as well: It is not only casual music bound with life . . . it is not directly connected with the ballet, play or drama, but can also well be so. What it touches, it changes. It gathers into it the fullness of the entire organic life and reflects it there like in a mirror. It creates from itself the extremely broad world of independent musical forms – lied form, fugue, sonata form are only its basic types. It is able to do so because it is enough for itself. It naturally corresponds to man’s biological presuppositions. (Furtwängler 1951: 27)

Furtwängler then asks, “What are these biological presuppositions? They are based on the alternation of tension and relaxation: “The ascending and descending movement of tension and release reflects the rhythm of life: as long as we breathe, one activity is at rest, the other one in motion. The state of rest is more original and primal . . . One of the basic doctrines of modern biology is that in complicated bodily activities . . . the relaxation of tension has a decisive meaning” (ibid.). This is certainly an acceptable view. In my own theory of semiotics I speak of two basic modalities, ‘being’ and ‘doing’, derived from Greimas’s model. But they also concern the definition of the organic in music (Tarasti 1994). What brings about being and doing in music? What gives us the impression that we either simply ‘are’ in music or that something is happening? These questions can be answered by observation of the temporal, spatial and actorial articulations in music. These articulations belong to the music of all cultures, not just to Western art music. Furtwängler, however, relates ‘being’ (relaxation) and ‘doing’ (tension) strictly with tonality: “The state of rest in music in its full cogency is only produced by tonality. Only it is able to create an objectively existing state of rest (subjectively we can of course consider any personal impression as rest).” Furtwängler is thus bound to a certain musical ontology. The deepest level of music for him is always tonal, since it is based on the natural determining force given by the triad. It is the beginning and the end of everything.

292 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music Furtwängler’s tonal ontology is a long-abandoned position, but in the context of our essay it has a certain meaning. Even some semiotically oriented scholars base their theories on a “biological” ontology, though without joining it any longer to tonality as a kind of ahistoric, universal principle. Ivanka Stoianova, for instance, thinks that musical form has two aspects: processual and architectonic. The processual aspect refers to musical enunciation, and the architectonic evokes the musical utterance as a ready-made text, as an art-work outside time. Thus we get two musical counterforces: the kinetic aspect, which is based on motion, change, process; and a static aspect, which is based on immobility, stability and architectonics. Musical form as a process, as aural manifestation, and the presence of an aural architecture are two sides of the same artistic activity. Architectonic form – the external mould as described by Réti and Kandinsky – seems to be an effort to immobilize the stream of music. All musical style periods, from the classical to the romantic to the avant-garde, include such an immobilizing effect, which stems from architectonic form. The means of stopping the musical stream consist of hierarchic, historically determined formal schemes, whereas processuality appears in transformations and emergent contrasts, such as developing variation. For Stoianova, the ‘being’ of music is not precisely as it is for Furtwängler. It is not an ontological or teleological end-state of music toward which everything strives, but is rather the stopping of “normal”, and hence, “biological”, musical time. In this sense, generative models are epistemologically contradictory. The idea of a surface that is gradually generated from a deep structure is based on hierarchies, and thus on something static and architectonic, hence something which stops the musical movement. This has as its consequence the static, atemporal character and artificiality of generative analyses. They are mechanistic elucidations of musical grammars using hierarchic axiomatic rules. But at the same time, the idea of a generative course contains the thought of a process, in which the immanent is in the end made manifest. The generative course thus refers to a basic semiotic force of the whole universe: the movement from content to expression. Whether Greimas’s generative course or Chomskyan schemes, generative models can make explicit the “organic” course of processes of meaning, but at the same time they contain an inorganic and architectonic aspect, which is a strange principle when applied to phenomenal musical experience and belongs in this sense to the project of the “modern”. We can try to clarify further what the “organic” in music is, with a more detailed formal and style analysis. A good example is provided by Veijo Murtomäki’s (1993) study of organic unity in Sibelius’s symphonies. He confirms the importance of organic metaphors among all the representatives of the so-called “dynamic” form theory in German musicology. He mentions Kurth, Schenker, Halm

13.B.1 On the musically “organic”

|

293

and the continuation of their thought in Schönberg and even Anton Webern. The musical views of the latter are permeated by the metaphor of a biological organism that develops from a single, initial idea. From it emerges the inner unity (zusammenhangen) of music. (It is interesting to note even here the contradictory tendency of these reformers of musical grammars and pioneers of the “modernist” project, who used models of thought inherited from romanticism. In addition, Schönberg and Webern were certainly different persons as theoreticians and composers. How a serial piece can be organic remains in this context unanswered.) In any case, Murtomäki lists in his study five ways in which music can be organic, with special emphasis on how Stoianova’s immobilizing forms – such as sonata, symphony, string quartet, and so on – become organic or processual by means of cyclic technique. For Murtomäki, organicity obtains when a composition with more than one movement is made to sound like a whole, and this in turn is the same as cyclicity. Cyclic procedures can be either external or internal; that is, they can either unify the materials or join parts together: (1) First, movements may be linked by similar thematic openings. (2) Either thematic “germs” or cells are moved almost imperceptibly from one movement to another, or themes appear in an easily recognizable guise in the later movements. (3) A special motto or idée fixe may appear in every movement. (4) The principle may be one of family unity: the parts are connected with metamorphoses of the same theme. (5) The most sophisticated way is continuous variation, a method of metamorphosis in which new ideas result from a process of transformation. The last-mentioned case is the most exciting one. When do we experience in music that some process “generates” or gives birth to another event? Put another way, when do we experience that some event T is the consequence of a former event P? Does event T serve as the telos of event P? What precisely does this mean? The finale of Sibelius’s Second Symphony is doubtless a good illustration of the idea of a telos, given the way that it is attained only after much struggle. But we can also imagine a process during which the listener does not know what will follow. Only when the result of T is heard after the process of P does one realize, Yes, this is exactly what everything prior to it was working toward. In such a case, one cannot say that T serves as a teleological goal of P, since it is perceived as such only after the fact. How can we semiotically analyze and interpret such relationships? From a narratological perspective we can consider some event a subject and its goal to be the event, an object that is searched for by the subject. At first the subject is disjuncted from the object, but then reaches or is conjuncted with it, taking it into possession. For instance, a theme in the dominant key “wants” to be united to the tonic. Yet this does not quite correspond to the truth, since the result of the metamorphosis can in fact be something which its preceding event is not aware

294 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music of, so to say, or does not even “want”. Only the musical super enunciator – the composer – knows that event T is a logical, organic result of process P. Or rather, the subject S is transformed into another subject S1 or Q or X, when the music steps, as it were, into “otherness”, when it shifts to some kind of non-being via the process of becoming. What is involved, then, is an organic, abruptly contrasting shift from a subject S to a subject Q. The subjects S and Q are felt to belong to the same musical Umwelt, in which we move from the Lebenswelt of subject S to that of subject Q. To end this section on the metaphor of the “organic” as a music-theoretical episteme, we can note that the same thing happens with it as with the notion of “nature”, discussed above. As Lovejoy’s analysis and our cases show, “nature” can mean almost anything, both order and disorder. In the same way, organic unity and growth can mean almost anything whatsoever. Why, then, do we examine a phenomenon about which we cannot only come to the same conclusion as did the first-year student mentioned by Umberto Eco, who modestly presented “a short comment on the universe”? It is because nature and organic growth have meant something to philosophers and to musical scholars, especially to those studying symphonic thought. They are notions loaded with strong ideological concepts, whose precise meaning can be obscure, but which have been and are still used when we speak about essential things in music. We cannot ignore these terms only because of the uncomfortable fact that their linguistic usage is not always logical and coherent. Next I shall ponder their relevance to Sibelius, particularly regarding his Fifth Symphony.

13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic” One could respond to the challenge posed by Adorno, by claiming that Sibelius’s music is “organic” whereas Mahler’s music is “inorganic”. In that case, the terms organic/inorganic would be primarily analytic concepts, such that “organic” music would be based on the following conditions: (1) All the musical actors live in their proper Umwelt; in semiotic terms, the themes move in their proper isotopies. (2) All the musical material stems from the same source; that is to say, thematicity, in semiotic terms, would be innerly iconic. (3) All the musical events follow each other coherently; this is LaRue’s principle of growth, or the inner indexicality of music. (4) The music strives for some goal; this has to do with temporality and the aspectual semes of beginning, continuing, and closing. Sibelius’s music can be experienced in many ways as “organic”. First, many think that the category of Nature is present therein. As Lorenz Luyken has stated, Sibelius’s music refers to the pastoral quality, in the manner of Beethoven,

13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic”

|

295

Mendelssohn, and Wagner. There is much evidence, on the part of both Finnish and non-Finnish scholars, that the poiesis and aesthesis of his music is connected to Finland’s nature. When Leonard Bernstein introduces Sibelius’s mixolydian mode in the Sixth Symphony to an audience of young listeners in New York, he says that it evokes the lonely forests of Finland. When music semiotician Jean-Jacques Nattiez visited Helsinki in April of 1979, he spontaneously started to whistle the opening motive of the Violin Concerto when looking at the frozen sea from the bridge of Seurasaari in Helsinki. But closeness to nature does not make music innerly, analytically “organic”. It is only a category of reception. What about the level of poiesis? Erik Tawaststjerna carefully studied the sketches of the Fifth Symphony and their elaboration. He connects the Fifth Symphony to Scriabin’s ecstatic-mystical view of art and to the Russian composer’s empathy with the cosmos. After quoting a poem by Scriabin, Tawaststjerna says, “But it is not erroneous to think what appealed to Sibelius in Scriabin was precisely the ‘cosmic’ dimension of his music, which is related also to his efforts to break through the boundaries of tonality.” This quotation has to be read in the light of our interpretation of the project of the “modern”, insofar as it represents the detachment of man from “cosmos” and insofar as “organic” music means a return to this cosmic unity. For Scriabin it meant going to the extreme limits of tonality (albeit Prometheus closes with an F sharp major tonic). But in Sibelius the “cosmic” style and rejection of the modernist project meant expressly the acceptance of tonality. The ecstatic E flat major at the end of the Fifth Symphony is related to the finale of Mussorgsky’s Pictures at an Exhibition, which also cadences to a similar, waving, clock-like motive. From this we might infer that the organic style and the return to cosmic unity, in the philosophical sense advanced by Charles Taylor (1989) in his The Sources of the Self, is not always the same as the return to tonality. This engagement, this embrayage (Greimas’s semiotic term), can also take place on levels of the musical text other than spatial ones. Tawaststjerna’s study in fact seems to prove Sibelius’s organic symphonic logic is based upon composer’s way of elaborating the material; it is clearly the category of poiesis. Tawaststjerna is moreover inclined to think that the organic quality of Sibelius’s symphonies emerges as a result of a trance-like process guided by the unconscious inspiration of the composer. When discussing the creation of the Fifth Symphony he deals with many of the various ideas found in the sketches, which Sibelius used in his Fifth or Sixth Symphonies. He compares this process to a puzzle whose pieces are fragments of a mosaic “floor of the sky” (Tawaststjerna 1978: 61). In this phase the symphony still essentially appears as a paradigmatic table, and its elaboration is a completely rational, non-organic occupation. But then Tawaststjerna continues:

296 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music “In the case of Sibelius I am inclined to consider his creative work an interaction of inspirational and intellectual components. Their relationship continuously varies. Basically he was dependent on his inspiration. He had his ‘wonderful’ trances . . . . The shaping of the themes seems to have happened intuitively.” (Tawaststjerna 1978: 65)

Nevertheless, if we think of our aforementioned criteria for organicity, one might state that on a paradigmatic level the organic trait stems from the inner similarity of the musical substance. Tawaststjerna reduces all the motives of the Fifth Symphony to two: the so-called step motive and the swing motive. But even this is not enough: the material has to be put into a syntagmatically coherent order. Only then can we experience music as organic. Erkki Salmenhaara, another Finnish Sibelius specialist, has a similar view of Sibelius’s organic techniques. Like Tawaststjerna, he stresses that organicity emerges in the mind of the composer, who using musical criteria chooses from an endless group of paradigms those which are meaningful regarding the intended musical shape. In his study on the symphonic poem Tapiola Salmenhaara quotes the British scholar Cecil Gray: “The thematic materials in Sibelius . . . seem to regenerate in a way which the biologists call cell division: they are split and broken into seven theme units, when every bar of the original organism is subjected to a development”. Therefore under the conventional formal outline of music there looms another shape which is dynamic, processual, or, in our terminology, “organic”.² In the chapter on “Sibelius’s Organic Principle of Variation”, Salmenhaara starts to deal with the organic nature of the composer’s logic: “By organic development it must be understood that various results of the development – different themes and motives – are in an ‘organic’ connection with each other”. What is interesting here is Salmenhaara’s term “results”. Themes in organic music can be experienced as results of some process – which is not the same as the telos, the Kantian Zweck. There are of course processes that from the beginning aim for a certain goal, but there are also processes whose result is not known in advance. For instance, the transition to the Finale of Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony, the long pedal point on G, leads finally to the theme of victory, which is something like a product of this process: we know to expect something, but are not sure exactly what. The same thing occurs with the intermediate section of the Waldstein, which leads to the sunrise theme of the last movement. Sometimes the result of the process is quite amazing, as in Sibelius’s Karelia music, where a long transition takes place before the theme bursts out: the national anthem of Finland. The result does

2 The differentiation between the static and the mobile recalls Ivanka Stoianova’s distinction between architectonic and dynamic forms.

13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic”

|

297

not grow organically from the previous material but is a quotation justified by an extramusical program. Salmenhaara also defines what is nonorganic music, one example being the variation sets of the classical style. In them the gestalt of the theme remains the same; it is just ornamented – think of Unser dummer Pöbel meint or Ah vous dirai-je Maman by Mozart. On the other hand, Salmenhaara emphasizes that in an organic variation what is crucial is not the goal of the process but the metamorphosis itself. “It is like a self-reflecting process: the main thing is not that the development form bridges among architectonic climaxes, but the aim is for continuous transformation, the constant turning of the motives into new shapes.” This latter comment is of great interest since it excludes telos from organicity: the organic transformation does not have a goal to strive for; rather, the variation becomes self-reflexive. What kind of phenomenal experience would this evoke? Doubtless a kind of static, slowly changing sound field. Has Salmenhaara unknowingly projected the Ligetian field technique onto Sibelius in order to see him as a representative of a certain avant-garde movement? If organicity were the same as Ligeti’s field technique, that would place Sibelius within the panorama of the new music of the twentieth century. The listener easily experiences such fields as a kind of stasis, a limbo from which there is no exit. This situation undeniably occurs in Sibelius’s Fifth Symphony, especially at score letters J and K, 1st movement (Figure 13.6). The Allegro moderato section of K–P, and also the fluttering, Mendelssohnian figuration of the strings in the last movement, contain such self-reflexive organic transformation. It is essential to this line of reasoning that we speak about music as shapes or Gestalts but not as grammar, recalling David Lidov’s two principles of “grammar” and “design”. There are composers, such as Arnold Schönberg, who have concentrated on reforming musical grammars. Then there are composers whose main contribution is at the level of gestalt, who make innovations even when the grammar remains the same. Debussy, Stravinsky, Sibelius seem to belong to this line. Therefore Adorno could not appreciate them. His hyperrational music philosophy is definitely bound with the project of the “modern” in the aforementioned philosophical sense. Music is grammar, conventional, arbitrary, and it has to maintain this aura of artificiality in order to be progressive. Music which functions via iconic shapes would mean a rejection of the critical distance and consciousness of the listener. Since over the course of time humankind has become disconnected from nature and cosmos, one must remain constantly aware of this primal negation and difference. The return to unity with the cosmos, with nature, would mean the return to a lawless and barbarous original state (the Germany of the 1930s is an example). It is always regression. The idea of organic music is precisely to return the listener to the cosmos, to natural principles which appear as the art of pre-

298 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music

Figure 13.6: Sibelius, Fifth Symphony, mvt. 1, m. 81 (Wilhelm Hansen)

13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic”

|

299

linguistic gestalts. Organic music is pre-linguistic, non-verbal, in the profound sense of the word. It is impossible to reduce Sibelius’s music to the languagelikeness of tropes or rhetorical figures. There is, however, one difficulty in defining the organic, and it is clearly noticed by Salmenhaara when he says, “. . . organic transformation has one special feature which is difficult to analyze, namely, it is musical by nature. Precisely here we have the difference between the motivic techniques of Sibelius and Schönberg. The music of the latter is theoretical and technical in nature rather than based on musical gestalts.” The twelve tones of a row can be manipulated in many ways which do not have a meaning-creating shape. Seen in this light, organic music is precisely music of design. How, then, can we prove that music based on a complicated motivic technique is organic? Only a tiny part of all possible motivic transformations is really used. Only those motives which are musically meaningful are taken into account, and that is why the organic unity of these motives is also noticeable to the listener. The musical construction does not follow any external system – just purely musical logic. Hence the term “organic” means the same as the “musically logical” which in turn means the “musically meaningful”. So we have fallen to a circle. What does it mean for something to be “very musical”? Sometimes it means the rendering of the emotional content of music, or that the musical performance in some way touches or speaks to us. But if we say that a musical text is “musical”, that reveals very little indeed. We cannot only look at the text, the score. We must consider the entire situation of musical communication, not only the utterance, but the utterer as well. Only the choice of the human “brain” or enunciator or composer can make any music organic. Thus, what is involved is a quality that is made manifest by the musical enunciator, in the dialogue between musical material and the persons who deal with it. Insofar as the musical mind intuitively filters and shapes musical materials into a certain gestalt quality, music becomes organic. Neither mere mathematical structure nor grammaticality suffice to make music organic. Although utterances may be “well-formed” or “grammatical”, we do not necessarily experience them as organic. Principles said to stem from the brain of the enunciator have been studied by statistic-mathematical methods in Russia, which methods are derived from the so-called “law of Zipf”. The latter says that, when all the notes or words of an art work are counted, they can be shown to follow a certain distribution along the “Zipf curve” (the Estonian scholar Mart Remmel told about this). Using this model, one can determine when a work is overwritten or underwritten, that is, when it has too many or too few notes. Works written by a great master in one breath, as it were, follow the Zipf law better than those written in episodically. Here the question of the organic is shifted from the textual level

300 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music into a cognitive question: How does the enunciator pick those elements which on the textual level will become organic? To begin to answer this question, one might try to apply Uexküll’s biosemiotic theory to music. As discussed above, each organism has its own Ich-ton, which determines the kinds of messages it receives from the outside, from the Umwelt that surrounds it. If this concept were applied to music, it would mean that every composition is a kind of “model” of a living organism, the latter understood in a certain “as-if” sense. The life of such an organism, its ‘being’ and ‘doing’, is guided by its view of itself, which helps the organism to choose according to its “inner” score those signs which it sends and receives. If a musical organism consists of motives, these motives constitute kinds of “cells” that communicate with each other, as happens in living organisms. This communication is completely determined by the inner organisation of the organism, its Ich-ton. Music is the symbolic description of this process. The musical organism that emerges from the brain of the composer somehow takes shape from a certain basic idea or isotopy, what Sibelius called an “atmosphere”, which determines which motives are accepted into this inner process and which ones are rejected. When we observe this microlevel of musical “cells” the life of the musical organism, we can follow what some cell or motive or “actor” is doing and how it does so, that is, how it influences other cells. Sometimes the “act” of a motive at first goes unnoticed, becoming influential only later. Sometimes the composer decides upon the Ichton of the work as early as in the opening bars. For instance, the core motive of Sibelius’s Fourth Symphony sounds at the very start of the work. In the same way, the “bucolic” horn signal at the opening of the Fifth Symphony is a “cell” which, in order to become a complete gestalt, needs to have its interval filled, and this is heard only at the end of the symphony. So we can say that, in music as in living organisms, one cell “calls out” for another. Precisely this type of inner process in a work makes it organic. Organicity or organicism is therefore dependent on the enunciator’s – i.e., the composer’s – consciousness. In organic music, this consciousness in turn follows the biosemiotic principle by which motives communicate with each other according to a certain “inner” score. One may presume that the inner score is different in each work. But one may also claim that in certain respects it is always the same, as Schenker’s, Kurth’s, and Asafiev’s theories assert. Nevertheless, the idea of an organic composition cannot be limited to a single, universal principle. For nature’s scope of variation is unlimited, and thus always capable of producing new types of organisms. Basically, however, the organism always decides upon its own Umwelt or relationship to external reality. It is the organism that determines which signals, style influences, motivic borrowings, and so on that it accepts from the style of the time, from other composers, and even from itself. An instance of

13.B.2 Sibelius and the idea of the “organic”

|

301

the latter occurs in Sibelius’s moving materials from the Sixth Symphony to the Fifth. That is to say, the Ich-ton of the Fifth Symphony, its “inner score”, allowed certain signs to be shifted into its own “cells”, while rejecting others. We can now return to the thesis presented above, namely, that Sibelius’s music is organic and Mahler’s is not. The Ich-ton of Sibelius’s symphonies determines precisely which musical cells are accepted and adopted into the inner network of musical communication, that is to say, into the “community” of its musical actors. In contrast, Mahler chooses very heterogeneous elements; his music’s Ichton is far more fragmentary than that of Sibelius – it is contradictory and “modern”. Mahler’s symphonies encompass everything, but do so without the aforementioned selection criteria of the Umwelt. His musical actors do not communicate with each other as intensively or as intimately as they do in Sibelius. Rather, Mahler’s work is ruled by “unit forms” ’, by topics and musical cells articulated by social conventions. His music adapts itself more to structures of communication than to those of signification. One of the best-known recent interpretations of Sibelius’s Fifth Symphony is the one by James Hepokoski (1993). His central concept for explaining formal issues in Sibelius is the so-called rotation principle. Hepokoski denies the relevance of traditional Formenlehre for Sibelius, since according to the composer his musical form grew from the inside out, as he said often to his secretary Santeri Levas (see Hepokoski 1993: 22). Hepokoski says that it is typical of Sibelius to use repetition to erase, so to speak, the linear time of a work; he does so by letting certain elements, motives, and entire sections recur cyclically again and again. Hepokoski thinks this phenomenon stems from the Finnish Kalevala recitation, as shown in the song Illalle (op. 17 no. 6). There a figure of 11 notes is repeated 16 times! Hepokoski notices that the rotation idea occurs not only Russian but also in Austrian-German music, such as that of Schubert and Bruckner. In Sibelius, however, the rotation is a process rather than an architectonic scheme or mould. In this sense, such rotation suits well as an example of organic music. In Hepokoski’s view, the rotational process starts with some musical statement that serves as the point of reference for later statements. The statement can be extensive at first hearing, containing various themes, motives, and figures which can even differ one from the other. It returns later, when it has been transformed a little, and it can return many times, such that it is heard each time more intensively. In Hepokoski’s theory the rotation principle in Sibelius is connected with the idea of a telos, that is, with the final climax of a piece as the goal of the musical process. Together, these two principles – rotation and telos – help explain the form of entire works, such as the Fifth Symphony. From the perspective of organicism, Hepokoski’s notion of rotation provides the inner iconicity of a work,

302 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music and telos serves as the extreme point of maturation of the work, which, so to say, pulls earlier rotations toward itself, causing them to grow and transform. From the beginning, inner processes among musical signs aim for the climax. This view differs from Salmenhaara’s, which stresses the self-reflexivity of the transformation process. Hepokoski emphasizes more the syntagmatic nature of music, whereas Salmenhaara adheres to the paradigmatic one. From a biosemiotic perspective, we can consider the telos of a symphony to be the same as its Ich-ton, which is revealed only at the end. On this view, Sibelius’s symphonies constitute symbolic portrayals of his “wonderful ego”.

13.B.3 Organic narrativity The present study would not be complete with our relating the organic principle to an important species of musical semiosis: narrativity. Narratologists succeeded in demonstrating that very different texts – texts extremely varied as to their material and to their external shapes – can be based on just a few narrative categories. Here we speak of the narrativity of a symphony on the level of form, not of aesthetic style. If Richard Strauss’s Alpine Symphony and Heldenleben are narrative on the level of verbal reception, in Sibelius narrativity should be understood in a deeper sense, as a property of dynamic formal processes. If music is organic, can it also be narrative? Is narrativity like language, rhetoric, grammar and other categories that separate the listener from the world of musical gestalts? Not at all – insofar as narrativity is understood in a broader sense, as conceptualized in Greimas’s school. Narrativity is a way of shaping the world in its temporal, spatial, and actorial course. Does “organic” narrativity thus mean that the text is articulated according to some primal narration? that it is a story of man’s conjunction with or disjunction from nature and cosmos? Narrativity covers many of the sign processes discussed above. Further, one might assume that, in certain forms, it is precisely the way in which man’s Dasein imitates the cosmic principles of nature. Narration can of course focus on description and classification of the inner events of Dasein, but it can also be the way in which the world of transcendental ideas is concretized in temporality. As a temporal art, music is thus one of the best means of narrativizing transcendental ideas. In closing, I return to Sibelius’s Fifth Symphony, in order to make a narratological interpretation that relates to the aforementioned ideas of nature, the project of the “modern”, and metaphors of organism. My interpretation stems from two listenings during which this narrative program was revealed to me. The first listening occurred at the beginning of the 1960s, probably at a concert given by the Finnish Radio Symphony Orchestra at the Solemnity Hall of the University

13.B.3 Organic narrativity

| 303

of Helsinki, under the direction of Jussi Jalas. Since I was a teenager at that time, my seat was quite near the front of the hall, on the right side, from which one could clearly see the conductor. Nothing remains in my mind from that performance except its climax: the Largamente assai at the end of the finale, the unison orchestral tutti on the note C. There the dissonance is at its sharpest, and the listener does not at all know where this tragic development might lead – until soon after it the whole symphony cadences and turns toward the tonic E flat major as its final telos (compared to which the E flat tonic at the end of the first movement was not a real return to home). At this crucial juncture, on the C and its leading tone, the conductor raised himself to full height and trembled all over (something Sibelius is also said to have done; see Tawaststjerna 1978: 147). This corporeal sign has remained in my memory. The second listening was in the summer of 1998 when Esapekka Salonen, visiting conductor of the Mariinsky Theater Summer Festival in Mikkeli, included on his program the Fifth Symphony of Sibelius. By then I was already familiar with the piano score, which naturally deepened the experience. At that hearing, the true climax and solution of the work revealed itself as the events in score letter N, Un pochettino largamento, the E flat minor section. The melody of that section is the first full theme-actor in the entire symphony, which is articulated in the manner of a lied, in periodic form and with a “normal” cadence. This theme is thus experienced as representing a kind of human subject that shows itself against the backdrop of “cosmic” views. As noted earlier, Sibelius’s music often gives the impression of a landscape without any human protagonist. Here the subject enters the stage, and it is the suffering, sentimental subject of Schiller (1978), a subject disjuncted from its object and given to resignation. It is a Tchaikovskian, resigned self, whose story has come to an end and whose speech is finally cut off (N: 16), as if by the dysphoric weight of its emotion. It is a subject who is detached from the cosmos, and yet it is basically the same subject which we heard as early as in the previous movement, where it hovered restlessly, not knowing its fate. Tawaststjerna reduces it to another important theme grouping of the Fifth Symphony, the step-motive, which was one of the very first ideas in the work. Certainly these motives were earlier fragments of a subject, but here in the Un pochettino largamento section the subject steps into the foreground as a complete person who has suffered a catastrophe. At the end of the theme, the E flat minor turns into major, which is like a deus ex machina solution to the threat of impending tragedy. The subject is rescued, so to speak, by being shifted to another cosmic level of nature. The latter is represented by the well-known swing-motive, which according to Tawaststjerna belongs to the other central motivic group of the symphony. The association of this motive with nature is obvious already from

304 | 13.B Metaphors of nature and organicism in the epistemology of music the viewpoint of poiesis, as evidenced by Sibelius’s diaries, in which he mentions swans in reference to this theme. This theme thus symbolizes nature and cosmos for the whole symphony. But just when we have reached it, as a safe haven and salvation of the individual from tragedy, even this level falls into a crisis. The swing-theme is led into deeper and deeper dissonance via modulations that move still further away from the tonic. The theme-actor whose fate we were following was thus not safe, as we had thought. What is now involved is nature’s crisis, Sibelius’s Götterdämmerung. The crisis culminates in the above-mentioned C, after which the music leads to a cadence on the tonic of E-flat major with many ensuing chromatic tones – an answer to the gap opened by the “bucolic” motive of the first movement. Therefore the answer which has been kept secret is finally revealed in full light. Perhaps representing a kind of rescue on the cosmic level, it is impossible describe this moment verbally. In any case, there remains yet one more surprise: six sforzando chords punctuate the ending, played by tutti orchestra. These resume the problem of the horn signal and its solution, but the effect is very surprising, lightening, consciously alienating – all is only play; we can sigh in relief. Yet this description holds true only for the final version of the symphony. In the earlier version, from 1915, the subject-theme appears to the very end as detached, disjuncted from the cosmos, as an individual and alienated theme-actor who does not unite with the cosmic order. As a symbol of the modernist project, it constantly evokes its existence by means of dissonances. Its relation to the ambiguous Neapolitan motive is quite clear as early as in section D of the Finale, when the swing-theme bursts out and the subject-theme is heard as a savage, illogical, and dissonant counterpart, such as one hears in the riotous simultaneities of Charles Ives. There the subject-theme obviously belongs to the same family as the descending and ascending leaps of fourths in the Neapolitan motive in the first movement (see B: 5–6). The impression is even one of bitonality, and was noticed at the first performance of the work. Otto Kotilainen spoke of a “strange, piercing signal which . . . gives an upsetting impression.” The effect is completely modernistic, and it also represents, in the philosophical sense, the subject of the project of the “modern”, which is alienated by its separation from the cosmos. The gradual unfolding of the subject-theme in its various “rotations” is indeed one of the most characteristic events of the whole symphony. It is the central narrative moment. In the 1915 version, the theme never seems to find its proper isotopy, its own Umwelt. Its difference remains until the end, when it returns in the Un pochettino largamente, and even there it is still the tragic and isolated theme actor, who is destined for destruction. But in the Un pochettino largamente section it takes on an extremely appealing sensual shape, as if a last gesture is made to serve as the counterpart of the swing-theme. This is related to the idea of the return

13.B.3 Organic narrativity

| 305

to the cosmos. In the 1915 version, this subject-theme does not merge with nature in the end, as it does in the final version of symphony. It remains as the pedal point of the strings, to remind one of its existence – even the six chords at the end are heard against this pedal. In the philosophical-semiotic sense, the 1915 version keeps to the modernist project in its narrative program. The separation of the subject from cosmos holds to the very end. By contrast, in the version of 1919 the subject fuses with the cosmic level. Thus, even in the narrative sense, this symphony represents the “organic” in music.

Chapter 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician ‘. . . he was one of those slow Finns . . . ’ (Thomas A. Sebeok)

14.1 Introduction For a semiotician the analysis of a national culture is a paradoxical task, especially when he examines the culture to which he himself belongs. The cultural analysis of the French semioticians has been, in general, iconoclastic, breaking myths and uncovering their mechanisms; the assumption was that in the background there was a kind of ideological anti-subject who exploited the semiotic processes of a culture for doubtful aims. Yet one might also imagine a kind of ‘positive’ semiology, which does not break myths, but instead supports the efforts of a given community to maintain its particular universe of signs. The community can benefit from such knowledge, especially in a situation where it is subject to some outer or inner threat. A culture can be said to be under a ‘threat’ in many senses: it may be a socalled primitive, traditional culture which is about to disappear (i.e., ‘the last remnants of a certain cultural form’); or it may be some national creature under the pressure of unification with some other, greater culture; it may even be some national culture subordinated to the subversive influence of a stronger culture. Umberto Eco has spoken of a semiotic guerrilla war, waged not against the sender of a message but during the reception process, in the interpretation of a message (Eco 1985: 151–160). He is referring to the messages streaming from the mass media: no semiotician can prevent them as such, but one can learn to read these messages and texts in such a way that their influence is reduced. As to the Finnish culture, a semiotic analysis is not difficult insofar as the object of analysis is easily defined. In the theories of Yuri Lotman the crucial aspect is the way in which some culture distinguishes itself from other cultures or ‘semiospheres’: The basic concept of the semiosphere is precisely that of a ‘limit’ . . . . The closed nature of semiosphere becomes manifest in the fact that it is not capable of communication with extrasemiotical or non semiotical texts. In order to become something real for some semiosphere, they have to be translated into some of its inner languages – i.e. culture has to ‘semiotize’ these extrasemiotic facts. (Uspenskij et al. 1973: 3)

14.1 Introduction |

307

This is precisely the case with the Finnish culture: the limits of this culture, the Finnish semiosphere, are very clear, since they coincide with so many other superimposed limits: geographic isolation, language, human types, manners, traditions in a word, the unified Finnish culture. The authors of a cultural history of Finland, Päiviö Tommila, Aimo Reitala, and Veikko Kallio, say: Finland has very seldom been a country which has expanded its culture elsewhere. Cultural innovations have, in general, come here from other countries. One of the central tasks of Finnish cultural history, therefore-particularly as to such periods of great change like the nineteenth century – is to clarify how and through which channels various cultural phenomena have come into Finland. How they have been received, how they have spread, how they have become integrated into the already existing tradition of the country and how the new cultural stratum thus created has again met the waves of subsequent new influences. (1980: 5)

In the semiotic sense, then, Finland has been a field for the reception of various influences and messages, and it has also become accustomed to this role as a receiver in intercultural communication. An interesting thread thus runs throughout our cultural history – the various ways in which the Finnish culture has been able to transform these external impacts into Finnish (i.e., to ‘semiotize’ them). If we follow the ideas of Lotman’s school, somewhere in every culture a kind of generator of structurality looms, which yields new structures. These structures, as we know, make possible the social life of man, in the same sense that the biosphere makes human biological life possible. In Lotman’s theory this ‘generator of structures’ (or sampo, ‘mill’, to use a word from Finnish mythology) is easily identified as a kind or organism: ‘The semiosphere is a semiotic personality’ (Tarasti 1988: 794). Furthermore, as Lotman states, the limits of this semiotic personality do not necessarily overlap with the physical boundaries of a human figure, but the same ‘person’ may include a whole family, with its servants (as an example one may mention lvan the Terrible, who usually had a disobedient boyar killed with all his relatives). We are thus rather close here to the romantic view of culture as a kind of organism (Tarasti 1988: 794). We do not need to search so far afield for illustrations. In his essay ‘Nationality and the ideal of a nationality’ Johan Vilhelm Snellman writes: Nationality is the social personality of a nation, which means that the social life in all its forms has to be original, to distinguish itself from the originalities of all other nations, in order to deserve the name of a nation. (1928: 294)

Snellman’s idea may be linked to Lotman via Hegel and speculative German philosophy. Nevertheless, a national culture is, of course, by no means an already given and unproblematic entity for a semiotician. In the background of a national cul-

308 | 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician ture, there indeed lies a certain physical unity, a spatially, temporally and actorially definable landscape, climate, race, etc. – all the various factors whereby scholars have attempted an interpretation of a national culture. But what is essential is that a national culture starts to search for these signs and emphasize them in an entirely different manner. For a semiotician, culture is always something arbitrary, artificial, conventional. When a semiotician realizes how national signs have been made, he no longer speaks in terms of a national ideology. In this light, too, Snellman’s ideas prove to be amazingly semiotic: he speaks about an individual in whose knowing and willing (the Greimassian modalities) the language and national character also have their own spiritual meaning: These are not such because an individual conceives them to be free in a spiritual sense [read in semiotic metalanguage: to be arbitrary] and as such he may use them for his deliberate purposes. For him they do not mean the same as they meant for his fathers. He knows that the distinction has been created spiritually [read: arbitrarily]. One might therefore say: nationality is the social life of a nation, insofar as by sociality one understands the unity of knowing and willing of all particular individuals and different generations of a nation. (Snellman 1928: 294)

We can make Snellman’s text sound very semiotic by simply interpreting the concept of ‘spirit’ in a Greimassian way as the modal dimension of man – i.e., as the attitude of a subject toward an object, which can be seen as the indispensable catalyzing force of any semiotic process (also in the theory of Charles Morris and George Herbert Mead; see for example Mead 1938). Introducing Greimas into this network of interpretation is totally justified, more particularly, since his thinking also has its roots – in spite of its Cartesian appearance – in the traditions of Eastern European thought. In analyzing national culture semiotically, we should not begin simply by making a list of texts representing it – in our case, Kalevala, the essays of Snellman¹; Maamme kirja (The Book of Our Country) by Topelius²; paintings by GallenKallela³; an opera by Sallinen⁴ or Kokkonen⁵; a Sibelius symphony⁶; the novel Seven Brothers by Kivi⁷; a film based on it by Jouko Turkka⁸; a building by Aalto⁹;

1 Johan Vilhelm Snellman (1806–1881), a philosopher, statesman, and awakener of national spirit in Finland. Snellman based his activities on Hegel’s philosophy, which had been taught at the University of Helsinki since the early 1820s earlier than elsewhere in Scandinavia. He studied in Germany and published there an essay titled Versuch einer spekulativen Entwicklung der Idee der Persönlichkeit (see Snellman 1982). Upon his return to Finland he worked as a journalist, sharply criticizing the cultural and political situation of Finland at the time. For this reason he could not get a chair in philosophy until 1856 at the University of Helsinki, which was under the control of Russian authorities. Subsequently Snellman gave up his university position and was nominated as a senator.

14.1 Introduction |

309

a ‘Finnish design’ bottle, etc. and then continue by analyzing them with all those subtle methods developed by both the European and the American branches of semiotics. This would not display the functioning of these texts as a part of a national culture. The essential aspect of a cultural semiotics is not the structure of a sign, but the relation of a sign to its semiotical background, to the semiosphere where it lives and exists. Lotman leaves aside all the disputes about whether signs should be studied with Peircean triadic categories or with the Greimassian gen-

2 Zachris Topelius (1818–1898), one of the national poets and writers of Finland. Topelius’s bestknown novel was Stories of an Army Surgeon (published as several volumes in 1851–1866), in which he depicted the often forgotten role of the Finns in the history of Sweden. Topelius was also a journalist and wrote many books for children. Particularly, his Book of Our Country (in Swedish, Boken om vårt land; in Finnish, Maamme kirja, 1875), has been much used in schools well into this century. 3 Akseli Gallen-Kallela (1856–1931), a painter, one of the best representatives of the Finnish National Romanticism in the arts. Gallen-Kallela studied in Paris at Academie Julian, where he learned a naturalist technique; however, his own style developed only after he became inspired by Kalevala, the collection of Finnish poetry published and edited by Elias Lönnrot as early as 1835. Gallen-Kallela’s large canvas paintings on such themes as Kullervo, Lemminkäinen, Väinämöinen, and Joukahainen, all heroes from Kalevala, belong to the most central ‘visual texts’ of the Finnish national culture. 4 Aulis Sallinen (born in 1935), a composer, particularly appreciated for his operas, whose librettos are often taken from Finnish literature. The Red Line was performed by the Metropolitan Opera of New York in 1979, and The King Leaves for France in the opera of Santa Fe in 1986. 5 Joonas Kokkonen (1921–1996), a composer and academician, one of the most distinguished Finnish composers of our time. Kokkonen continued the Sibelian symphonic tradition, but his vocal works, like his opera The Last Temptations (performed by the Metropolitan Opera in 1979) and his Requiem, are also internationally acclaimed pieces. 6 Jean Sibelius (1865–1957), the greatest Finnish composer. Sibelius studied in Berlin and Vienna and by the turn of the century had become one of the creators of the national-romantic style in Finnish music. His first symphonic poems were written on subjects taken from the Kalevala (like En Saga, The Swan of Tuonela, etc.) or related to Finnish patriotism (Finlandia); he later became, particularly through his series of seven symphonies, a reformer of the symphonic form in general in the music of our century. 7 Aleksis Kivi (1834–1872), a writer and poet, the most remarkable original talent of Finnish literature and the greatest humorist of Nordic literature. Kivi’s main work was his novel The Seven Brothers, which portrayed the life of Finnish peasants with a realism that was not accepted by cultural authorities of his time. Kivi died forgotten, mentally ill, and in extreme poverty; his greatness was discovered and officially recognized only years after his death. 8 Jouko Turkka (born in 1942), a reformer of Finnish theater through his highly original and often extravagant stagings and education of actors. 9 Alvar Aalto (1898–1976), the best-known Finnish architect, with an international reputation. Aalto created a form language of his own and realized it with his original style from monumental buildings to small, functionally designed objects.

310 | 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician erative model. he says that no single and functionally discrete sign system can function in isolation from other systems of signs. It only functions as part of a semiotic continuum, which is full of heterogeneous formations on different levels (Uspenskij et al. 1973: 4). Let us take one concrete example: in the novel by Antti Jalava entitled The Asphalt Flower (1981), the conflict between Finnish and Swedish culture is depicted from the viewpoint of a young immigrant boy in Sweden. The events take place in the recent past. The Swedish classmates of the Finnish boy tease him, reminding him that he cannot pronounce two successive b’s. In a Swedish lesson they ask him to utter the word ‘abborre’, which he can only pronounce with two voiceless consonants as ‘apporre’. In structural linguistic terms, what is involved is the simple distinction between p and b, between the voiced and voiceless consonant in Swedish, a distinction which Finnish lacks. However, in this semiotic situation, the word not only serves as a linguistic unit; it expressly becomes an index of cultural boundary as well. The differences between two cultures are manifest therein, the distinction between culture and non-culture. But how then is a national semiosphere created? How can it be analyzed if not through texts representing it? If we ask anyone what is typically Finnish, the answers invariably refer precisely to representative texts: a Sibelius symphony, a painting by Järnefelt¹⁰, the voice of Aino Ackte¹¹ or Martti Talvela¹², etc. Yet these examples transmit a message about the Finnish identity only against a certain background. The famous violin teacher Joseph Gingold, who has taught many generations of violinists the Sibelius concerto, said that only after having come to Finland and seen his home Ainola in the darkness of a December morning did he understand what this work was all about. Only as part of the semiotic continuum can products of a national culture please and charm with their original composition, structure, and other properties, and in this way become well-known parts of the world culture, the ‘universal civilization’, to use Snellman’s expression. Naturally, each text also has its own autonomous hierarchy; it is in this sense,

10 Eero Järnefelt (1863–1937), a Finnish painter, a contemporary of Gallen-Kallela and Sibelius, who with his lyrical style captured the beauty of the Finnish landscape. 11 Aino Ackté (1876–1944), a Finnish soprano who had one of the most brilliant careers in the Finnish performing arts. Ackté drew great attention singing principal roles at the Grand Opera of Paris in 1879–1903; subsequently she also sang in the Metropolitan Opera of New York in 1904–1906, and later founded in Finland the well-known opera festival at the medieval castle of Savonlinna as early as in the 1910s. 12 Martti Talvela (1935–1989), a Finnish bass singer, one of the greatest bass voices of our century. Particularly appreciated are his interpretations and recordings of the role of Boris in Mussorgsky’s opera.

14.1 Introduction

|

311

for example, that Sibelius is listened to in the United States as part of the ‘tonosphere’ experienced by Americans or that a Finnish novel can be read as part of an international ‘literosphere’, etc. It is precisely imitative, mimetic behavior that forms a model upon which the power of a national culture is based. National cultures are primarily interested in maintaining themselves as they have always been. Therefore, they have to create mechanisms of behavior which guarantee that certain attitudes, evaluations, etc. are conserved as long as possible, or as is said in the jargon of national ideologies, from one generation to another. This is why the basic category of every national culture is iconicity, according to which a sign is similar to its object. Discussions about national culture often allude particularly to national symbols. Nevertheless, this is only one side or dimension of the matter: the symbols must also have the power to produce a certain kind of behavior. In other words, they must exercise indexical power upon the people for whom the symbols are created. They should reflect as similar something which characterizes the observable reality of the national culture in question. On the other hand, these national icons continuously have to yield other iconic or similar signs, in order that the entire culture should preserve its original national nature. Hence, an artist may create a text or symbol which is originally not intended at all to serve as a national ‘icon’. lt is produced for merely aesthetic or other reasons, but then it gradually for entirely external reasons-assumes an iconic character in the culture. For example, if in a documentary film Jean Sibelius wanders in the forests of Järvenpää dressed in a fine suit, according to the bourgeois habits of the turn of the century, this is not yet iconic behavior as such. But if fifty years later our academician Joonas Kokkonen or composer Paavo Heininen¹³ appeared there in a tie and dark suit, this could be said to be iconic behavior, since what is involved would perhaps be an imitation of the original hero. By so doing they would show that they occupy the same mythical role in the national musical culture. Sibelius has become a role in the national culture, and years later one can still ask, ‘Who is now the Sibelius of Finland?’ – just as at the end of the nineteenth century it was asked in Helsinki, when the great national composer Friedrich Pacius¹⁴ had returned to his native Germany, who would now become ‘our Pacius’. It is precisely this kind of conduct which is iconic in the true sense of the word.

13 Paavo Heininen (born in 1938), a composer, one of the leading avant-gardists of Finnish contemporary music. 14 Friedrich Pacius (1809–1891), a German composer, who became, after having settled in Helsinki as a music teacher at the University, the founder of musical life in the capital. His musical interpretation of the poem of J. L. Runeberg was accepted as the national anthem of Finland.

312 | 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician Another example is Vänrikki Stoolin tarinat (The Tales of Ensign Stål), a collection of poems by Johan Ludvig Runeberg¹⁵ depicting the heroes of the war of 1809; this is a literary work which was undoubtedly intended right from its publication to establish national and iconic hero figures. Its introduction includes a narrative situation in which a younger person is told about the heroes of the war, so that he will identify with them and imitate them later himself. One has to identify with symbols of national culture (paintings, poems, dramas, novels, films); otherwise they lose their efficiency and ability to function in a national culture. And identification is quite literally, according to its name, an iconic sign category. There are thus two phases in national iconicity: first, the creation of the sign itself; and then its endowment with iconic relations in order to facilitate the identification of the receiver. In art music this means that one has to use folk music themes to make it sound ‘national’. ln the same way, in literary texts, fictional characters have to use expressions from the spoken language; poems must contain descriptions which in some indefinite way are iconic for example, in arousing associations and images similar to those of daily life. In some cases the iconicity in poetry is multiple, as in the famous poem by Ilmari Kianto: ‘Kuulkaa korpien kuiskintaa, jylhien järvien loiskintaa’ (Listen to the whisper of forests, the waves of austere lakes)¹⁶. The images and symbols refer to a certain landscape which can be found in Kainuu (Northern Finland), yet they are also presented in the form of rhyme and alliteration, which represent iconicity on the level of the linguistic sign itself. Novels, moreover, may contain iconic imitations of some other art form. If one were to write for the Finnish culture a work equivalent to Foucault’s The Order of Things, dealing with the epistemes of the entire national culture, one might start rather like Foucault does, with his analysis of the painting L’infanta by Vélasquez (Foucault 1970: 3–16), which is based upon the representation of representation. One might start from the first chapter of the novel Tuomas Vitikka by Eino Leino¹⁷ and its static iconographic portrayal symbolizing the Finnish culture at the turn of the century (Leino 1928: 91–98). Annamari Sarajas (1962) has drawn attention to this novel with her ana-

15 Johan Ludvig Runeberg (1804–1877), one of Finland’s national poets, who wrote in Swedish. His collections of poems depicting Finnish heroes of the war of 1809 (The Stories of Ensign Stål, in Swedish Fänrik Ståls sägner, in 1848 and 1860) have had a lasting impact on Finnish nationalism until our time. The first poem of these collections, ‘Maamme’ (Our Country), with music composed by Friedrich Pacius, became the national anthem of Finland. 16 Ilmari Kianto (1874–1965), a writer with a strongly naturalist style, depicted life in Kainuu, Northern Finland. 17 Eino Leino (1878–1926), a poet whose major contribution concerned the national romantic and, later, symbolist movements of the arts in Finland.

14.1 Introduction |

313

lysis of Eino Leino’s ironic, distanced attitude to the Finnish national culture and its exaggerated national-mindedness. The description represents a kind of iconicity in many respects. What is depicted there is an idyllic Finnish ‘Stilleben’ from the nineteenth century with a group of people gathered in the courtyard of a manor. The portrayal is done in a mildly ironic tone, person by person, in such a way that each type corresponds to a certain class and figure in Finnish society and culture. At the end a German professor is introduced: he has come to the country in order to learn about the indigenous folk-life; his name is Dr. Friedrich Gottlob Meyer, Extraordinary Professor of Aesthetics and Art History from the University of Heidelberg. He has taken his place to paint the static scene. At the same time, the viewpoint of the narrator is, as it were, shifted to become that of the foreigner, and it is given to be understood that the scene in the novel has been described as it appears in the canvas painted by Meyer. But when this person is again described, one notices how the whole first chapter of the novel is in fact a kind of ‘nostalgic’, ‘iconic’ portrayal, like a family photograph. The extremely static quality of the scene serves at the same time as a symbol of the stability of the Finnish culture of the period. The rich use of alliteration in the text serves as an internal icon, i.e., as the principle of repetition, which again provides the impression of some kind of stylized Kalevala-like prose, although this device is used very deliberately in order to create comic effects. The principle of repetition in the prose functions as a means of estrangement. The development of a national culture thus contains two ‘semiotic’ phases: (A) In the first phase, icons of national identity in various arts and representative texts in a broader sense are created or invented: what is involved here is the search for an icon to fit an already completed conceptual and abstract system of thought in order to concretize it, plus the fact that the artists, scientists, and distinguished people of a nation themselves produce these ‘icons’ of national identity, while the receivers only subsequently identify with them. (B) In the second phase, one starts to produce new national icons using the ready-made icons of the ‘first phase’. This is the typical phase of folklorism, where the national character is no longer created, but preserved. How soon a national culture crystallizes or stagnates into this second phase depends on many historical and extrasemiotic factors. Nevertheless, this second phase is characterized expressly by the schematization of the national identity, stability, and a corresponding canon of behavior, a defensive attitude, the rejection of external influences, the jealous conservation of the original. (Vesa Kurkela has discussed the problem in his study of musical folklorism [1989].) On the other hand, iconic signs of a culture are not efficient unless they are provided with indexical linkage (i.e., a reference to corresponding semiotic activ-

314 | 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician ity or behavior). Usually national icons are combined with some implicit or explicit verbal index: do as the sign advises, imitate it, keep yourself within its limits! Biographies are one constant and central textual genre of a national culture. They are produced precisely in order to create models for behavior which would guarantee the continuity of the national culture and support its existence for the members of the same community. For outside readers such biographies naturally appear in quite a different light. For example, some of Jean Sibelius’ utterances, which his biographer Erik Tawaststjerna (1976) quotes from the composer’s diaries (‘Do not give up the pathos of the life!’ or ‘You wonderful ego . . . ’ etc.), have become almost proverbs in Finnish culture. But when these parts of the biography are read as English translations by foreigners, they appear differently. Maamme kirja (The Book of Our Country) by Zachris Topelius, a very central ‘national’ text, also contains biographies meant as ideals for the young, with builtin indexical references to corresponding semiotic conduct. For example, it is said of Matias Aleksanteri Castrén¹⁸: ‘he has revealed to us the cradle of the Finnish nation. Others have then, animated by his example, continued his work . . . . This is why no Finnish man or woman can forget this faithful man, who suffered so much and worked so hard for our nation and for mankind’ (Topelius 1981: 106). However, the icons of a national culture do not emerge from nothing, but spring forth from the particular semiosphere formed by the particular nation and culture. Semioticians of culture strongly emphasize that the signs and texts of a national culture cannot function at all without the existence of a semiosphere. This is well illustrated by the collecting of folklore instigated by the national cultural ideology, culminating for instance in the immense archives of the Finnish Literary Society. At least as regards the music collection, it is sad to think how much work has gone into saving some tunes from distant Siberia; now that they are conserved, modern scholars are less interested in studying them than in the rock and popular music of contemporary Finland, which is considered a more important subject. Thus, changes in the Finnish semiosphere also alter attitudes toward texts which were earlier held to be central to the culture: these may be relegated to the category of almost forgotten texts, or swept away altogether from the collective memory of the culture. How then can one analyze the semiosphere? One student of Lotman, Igor Czernov, has claimed (1986) that the semiosphere is not so useful as a concept since it cannot be properly observed. A firmly empirically minded Anglo-Saxon

18 Matias Aleksanteri Castrén (1813–1852), a linguist and folklorist. His journeys among the Fenno-Ugric peoples living in Siberia led him to publish a number of studies dealing with the languages and cultures of these peoples.

14.1 Introduction

|

315

anthropologist would hardly accept such a notion. But let us remember the motto of empiricism: try to make everything measurable. How can we make the concept of the ‘semiosphere’ measurable? Without doubt, what is involved here is precisely what the Hegelian Snellman would call the spirit of a nation, or what the romanticist Topelius would call the national character. Topelius writes: If we travel abroad and meet there our compatriots from different parts of our country, then we notice that they are in many regards very similar . . . . Such a mutual similarity or property of a nation (a national character) can be more easily felt than explained. (1981: 124)

In fact, in the field of semiotics, and particularly in the Parisian school of semiotics, even such vague objects as emotions (passions) are, as we know, analyzed semiotically (see for example Greimas 1983: 213–246). The idea is that the emotions can be reduced to some few modalities, which are very restricted in number (i.e., seven altogether): being, doing, willing, knowing, being obliged to do something, being able to do something, and believing. For each emotion we can write a strictly formal scheme, providing it with a semiotic definition. When Topelius portrays the qualities which give rise to the Finnish semiosphere, he lists the following: ‘The Finns are dominated by a deep and true fear of God’ (= a positive articulation of the modality of believing); ‘it (the nation) is diligent and persistent’ (= modalities of willing, doing and being able to do); ‘it is hardened and strong’ (= the modality of being able to do); ‘it is patient, unself-demanding and vital’ (= several modalities in different constellations); ‘it is a peaceful nation’ (= the modality of being dominates that of doing); ‘it is also courageous and capable of fighting in a war’ (= modalities of doing and being able to do); ‘even when conquered and subordinated it has always maintained its own way of living and thinking: it is therefore an extremely durable and obstinate nation’ (= a complex combination of the modalities of being able to do and doing something); ‘once it has placed itself under a government, a foreign one or one of its own, it has never rebelled against it therefore, it is faithful’ (= modality of being obliged to do); ‘it has often neglected the use of its rights and power when there has been a need of them: consequently, it is a slow and hesitant nation’ (= modalities of willing to be [vouloir être] and willing to not-do [vouloir non-faire]); ‘but under the violence and subordination it has not accepted to remain under the yoke of the oppressor – it is a nation which loves freedom (willing to not-be [vouloir non-être] and willing to do [vouloir faire]); ‘and finally it has in its lonely forests, far from the centres of the civilized world, raised itself into enlightenment – it is thus a nation which desires knowledge and culture’ (= modalities of willing and knowing [vouloir savoir]) (Topelius 1981: 126).

316 | 14 Finland in the eyes of a semiotician In fact, Topelius’s generative model of the Finnish identity is an unusually consistent narrative of the Finnish semiosphere. After this general depiction of the semiosphere, he puts these modalities of the Finnish character into a narrative whose main actor is the farm-hand Matti. Through the portrayal of this ‘one’ actor – which in the text has two ‘senders’, the Finnish people and God himself (as the hidden actor revealed only at the end of the text) – he makes the abstract semiosphere concrete and clearly observable and measurable as a certain behavior which is also provided with a strongly positive mythic category – i.e., its euphoric articulation (even in the description of the weaknesses of Matti, in such a way that the negative sides of his character are made comical). In other words, as regards their semic content these two consecutive sections of the text are identical, but they have been narrativized in different ways. All this takes place in chapters 70 ‘The Finnish people’ and 71 ‘Matti’ (Topelius 1981: 124–129). Precisely because of its euphoric evaluation and concreteness, the latter text represents something with which the reader is more apt to identify -and it is just this identification that constitutes the indispensable precondition for the functioning of the national icons. Therefore, the latter text is by its nature more indexical than the former. It encourages iconic or imitative behavior, or at least allows the reader to recognize the modalities in question within himself, to experience them as acceptable, and in this way to provide the more extensive actor, ‘the Finnish people’, with a positive, euphoric articulation. It is by and large this kind of semiotic mechanism that we find in Topelius’s text. To conclude, one might mention two typical features of the Finnish semiosphere. First, we have to notice the poverty of the Finnish universe of signs. In the Finnish environment there are rather few distinct signs for the receiver to decode – compared to many other cultures. Other cultures are accustomed to receiving a constant stream of messages from all sides, messages which may even be mutually contradictory. They have thus learned to understand a varied and polyvalent universe of signs, and have been able to adopt the corresponding semiotic conduct whereby one can survive in such a universe. Since the Finnish universe of signs is limited, and more particularly, since the signs tend to be interpreted with the same, overlapping codes (this is precisely the so-called unified national culture), one experiences all the foreign signs which penetrate into this static semiosphere as somewhat threatening. From this, another trait can be inferred: there are not many elements borrowed from other cultures in the Finnish context. If one thinks of artists who have tried to become familiar with foreign cultures and ‘translate’ foreign texts into their ‘own’ language, it becomes evident that their efforts have usually remained peripheral to their own culture. One may think, for example, of Gallen-Kallela’s African period, the rejection of international modernist movements in different

14.1 Introduction

|

317

phases of Finnish musical life, etc. An entirely different chapter is formed by those artists, scientists, and thinkers who have felt so strange in the Finnish semiosphere that they have considered it wiser to move permanently abroad (A. I. Arwidsson, Armas Launis, etc.). They form an interesting case in the history of the Finnish semiosphere. In fact, artistic texts which represent a negation of the prevalent semiosphere, a kind of antithesis to it (for example in the form of a cultural criticism), remain in the history or the collective memory of the Finnish nation. But texts which are wholly messages from ‘elsewhere’, whose codes are too far removed from this semiosphere, are neglected and have no influence. They represent texts which the culture cannot translate. On the other hand, semiotic texts and ways of behavior coming from outside which are perceived as threats to the dominant semiosphere become objects of a particular kind of resistance. Then the rejection and resisting usually form a particular semiotic program of behavior in the culture in question. What was resisted in the nineteenth century and again in the 1920s was the Swedish culture and language; at the end of the nineteenth century the Russian culture; and now more and more the American. In the name of the untouched quality of the pure Finnish semiosphere one seeks to reject all elements coming from outside which cannot be fused with the semiosphere itself. At the same time, in the resistance to Americanism, for instance, one is not necessarily opposed to Americanism itself, but to a certain new, quick, and aggressive variant of Finnish behavior, which is called and supposed to be something ‘American’. Since ‘quickness’ and ‘aggressiveness’ do not belong to the inherited Topelian model of the Finnish identity and its modalities, they have to be rejected. The myth of the slow Finns has to continue.

| Part V: Precursors

Chapter 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce (1855–1916), the American classic between Hegel and Peirce 15.1 Josiah Royce as a historical figure Josiah Royce’s name may not immediately leap to mind as one related to current semiotics. Peirceans, however, know of his role in the life of Charles S. Peirce, whose fame has greatly overshadowed his contemporary colleague, although Royce had a firmly established position in the American academic life of his time. My interest in Royce is as a possible link between Hegel and semiotics. This is not only because in Peirce’s system do we encounter those “Hegelian” triadic distinctions, but rather because Hegel is one of the most important background figures in European semiotics, in the more “hermeneutic tradition” of sign theories. In my own version of it – existential semiotics – many issues raised by Jaspers, Heidegger, or Sartre come originally from Hegel. This holds true as well for the early, still phenomenologically oriented structuralism of MerleauPonty and Greimas, not to mention those again phenomenologically oriented post-Greimassians in France and elsewhere. What Max H. Fisch (1986) has written about the relationship between Peirce and Hegel, in his lifelong studies of Peirce’s various philosophical sources, is of course seminal. It was my privilege to meet and get to know this philosopher at the Annual Meetings of the American Semiotic Society in the 1980s. Moreover, some years ago I received a book entitled La philosophie americaine, peut-elle être americaine? (1995) by the eminent Peirce scholar, Gérard Deledalle. In it the author interprets the entire American pragmatist movement: Peirce, Royce, William James, side by side. Deledalle says this about Royce: Born in California, Royce, after studies at the University of California followed courses by Lotze in Göttingen then by the Hegelian G. S. D. Morris at Johns Hopkins University. Upon the advice of William James, he decided to dedicate his life to philosophy. He first taught in California and then, again upon the recommendation of James, obtained a chair at Harvard where he taught until his death. Under the influence of Coleridge, Emerson had introduced Kantian idealism to America, and there Royce, until the beginning of the 20th century, imposed an absolute idealism, which not only resisted pragmatism, but ultimately absorbed it into an absolute pragmatism [. . . ]. Royce’s idealism is a typically American phenomenon, not only in its pragmatist aspect, but especially by the logical dimension which Royce gave it, whose origin is certainly in Lotze, but whose true inspiration was the inventor of pragmatism and the first modern logician, Charles S. Peirce. (Deledalle 1995: 115)

322 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce In my own efforts to penetrate Roycean philosophy, I first located his Basic Writings (Royce 1969), but those two volumes did not contain Royce’s semiotically most exciting essays. I next got an edited version of his Lectures on Metaphysics (1915–1916), and thereafter read his main work, The Problem of Christianity (1913). Many works of Royce refer to Christian doctrine, but this does not mean that they represent pure theology. The same is also true, for instance, reading Kierkegaard: Christian theology is there, but what is interesting is the manner of philosophizing which has to be read through the lines. Quite similar is the case of the great Russian contemporary of Royce, Vladimir Solovyov (1853–1900), a very influential Russian philosopher who remains almost completely unknown in the West. As with Royce, in his theology and his philosophy, Christian (in this case Greek Orthodox) doctrines are mixed with Hegelian and speculative German rationalism. Figures like Royce and Solovyov might be topical at a convention of semioticians, in a session on Forgotten Pioneers of Semiotics, as there used to be at meetings of the American Society. But those figures are current for anyone who is seeking new philosophical bases for any semiotic approach. As to spiritual connections between two such extremely different thinkers as Solovyov and Peirce, both scholars are “synechistic” in nature. In his essay Synechism, fallibilism and evolution, Peirce writes the following: “Synechism is that tendency of philosophical thought which insists upon the idea of continuity as of prime importance in philosophy and in particular, upon the necessity of hypotheses involving true continuity” (Peirce 1955: 354). And where else would the idea of “continuity” come than from Hegel. Max Fisch writes: But though for his first attempts at a definition of continuity he turned to Aristotle and Kant, Peirce the synechist thought of Leibniz and Hegel as his leading forerunners among philosophers, because it was they who, in their different ways, and Hegel more than Leibniz, had made continuity a central principle of philosophy. (Fisch 1986: 263)

We must add that Peirce never studied Hegel deeply and was in no phase of his life a typically Hegelian thinker. But among his close friends there was one who had studied Hegel deeply, and it was Royce. Fisch has verified that as late as in May 1902 – when Peirce was already over sixty – he wrote to Royce and proposed that he come to Arisbe, Peirce’s country home in Delaware and spend the summer there, so that the two could pitch into logical problems and Royce could teach Peirce more about Hegel. But Royce declined, and so we can only mourn the fact that Peirce’s only occasion to get familiar with Hegel never came to pass. Now let us move on to some information about Royce’s life, in order to have sufficient background for the presentation of his ideas. If you still wonder why

15.1 Josiah Royce as a historical figure

| 323

I bring this figure into a book on semiotics, one hopes that at least his proximity to Peirce would justify it. Following this introduction, I need to answer another, perhaps even more serious question, namely, Why Hegel and semiotics? Why should we return to this philosopher, whose work some consider “mere conceptual poetry”? But first, about Royce. There exists no good biography of this enigmatic figure in American intellectual history. Mrs. Royce said it was her husband’s personal wish that his personal history not be published. Still, according to McDermott there are two aspects of his life that should be taken into account: his early religious experience and the ambivalent nature of his personality as a “preacher” in the role of an extraordinary intellectual virtuoso (McDermott 1969: 4). Royce was deeply influenced by the frontier experience of his early days in California, and his individualism can be traced to this background. He accommodated his individualism, however, to “imported” European metaphysics. At the same time, we cannot separate Royce’s individualism from his idea of community. And here his religious sectarianism comes into the picture. Puritanism in the American context was a form of non-conformism as well as an effort to form a community against the experience of suffering. One of Royce’s very early essays was on the “Practical Significance of Pessimism”, which opens with comments about looking at a battlefield after the struggle, with all the wounded people, their groans, pains, and anguish. He asks what human life is, then answers: “A vapor vanishing in the sun? No, that is not insignificant enough. A wave, broken on the beach? No, that is not unhappy enough. A soap bubble bursting into thin air? No, even that has rainbow hues. What then? Nothing but itself. Call it human life”. (McDermott 1969: 6)

Royce was a typical Californian in a nineteenth-century culture dominated by the New England mind. Those of Puritan lineage suffered from inferiority-complex thinking, typical of the fine and elegant European style of New Englanders, and to compensate for this they made plain dress and natural expression into positive virtues. In this sense Royce’s philosophy mirrors a colonial experience. After studies in Germany, Royce accepted a position in California but was deeply dissatisfied, claiming there was “no philosophy in California, from Siskoy to Ft. Yuma, and from the Golden Gate to the summit of the Sierras”. This, however, did not stop Royce from writing “ponderous and brilliant” philosophical prose and analyses of logic and metaphysics, as well as unabashedly sentimental, popular pieces. He was described in a journal article by John Jay Chapman:

324 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce I always had that feeling of Royce that he was a celestial insect. Time was nothing to him. He was just as fresh at the end of a two hours’ disquisition as at the start. Thinking refreshed him. Royce had a phenomenal memory; his mind was a card-indexed cyclopaedia of all philosophy. Many of his admirers like William James saw this also as his weakness. It was said: if only he had never been taught to read Royce would have been a very great man. (Chapman 1919: 372, 377)

Royce’s life touched Peirce’s on many levels, and he is mentioned in Joseph Brent’s Peirce biography in at least six major sections. Brent (1993) claims that few in the professional American academy were able to appreciate Peirce’s originality of mind and his real achievements until well after the turn of the century. The years 1883–1891 marked the destruction of Peirce’s career and the beginning of his descent into ruin and poverty. He was dismissed without warning from Johns Hopkins University and accused of negligence of his duties at the Coastal Survey. Royce was one of his very few defenders. Peirce, with his wife Juliette, would visit Royce’s house where the two would talk about synechism. In 1886 Peirce visited Cambridge and his brother Jem’s house, where James, Royce, Fiske, Francis Abbot and Ralph Barton Perry were present. Apart from Royce, no one understood Peirce’s triadic logic. Later, in 1891, Peirce tried to save his classmate Francis Ellingwood Abbot in a dispute which is one of the most unpleasant events in the history of American philosophy. It started with Royce’s “professional warning” in the International Journal of Ethics, where he accused Abbot, one of the original members of the Metaphysical Club and author of the book Scientific Theism, of fraud and plagiarism. Peirce took Royce’s attack as wrong-headed and wrote to The Nation: “Prof. Royce’s article was written with the avowed purpose of ruining Dr Abbot’s reputation. Royce was plainly, overtly trying to injure Abbot and take away his bread and butter.” Both Abbot and Peirce were outlaws of a sort, and Abbot later committed suicide (1903). He wrote in his diary: “I am still toiling to finish my great work, yet with no hope of a hearing now or after my death”. Peirce wrote five years later in despair: “Nobody understands me, America is no place for such as I am. I detest life and just as soon as I can frame up a plausible excuse to myself, [. . . ] I shall follow Frank Abbot’s example – except that I shall leave no unreadable book behind me. No, no.” Nevertheless, the Abbot episode was soon forgotten, and a year later Peirce and Royce became allies, and Royce studied Peirce’s logic. To conclude this introduction, it should be said that one reason for my foregrounding Royce is that his philosophizing deals with problems of relevance also to my own reflections in existential semiotics, some basic ideas of which easily be interpreted in the light of Roycean philosophy, starting with the nature of the concept of Dasein, and what it means.

15.2 Why Hegel? |

325

To speak of Dasein and transcendence, affirmation and negation, and the like, is possible only on the basis of Hegelian logic. But Royce’s ideas might help to us develop also a theory of social semiotics as something existential, since for Royce the social nature of things was quite fundamental, an aspect that remains to be developed since my original foray into existential semiotics (Tarasti 2000).

15.2 Why Hegel? In the chapter on Solovyov who, like Royce, was deeply interested in moral issues, I try to define a “Romantic semiotics”, the basic axioms of which are these: (1) Meanings exist even before one starts to analyze and explicate them (the hermeneutic principle of preunderstanding, Vorverständnis). (2) Meanings are based upon processes; that is, they reveal themselves gradually during changes and in the development of time, place and subject. (3) They take shape immanently, within a certain “system”. (4) They emerge from differences within a system. Such principles have, as their inner law, that the immanent gradually becomes manifest, a process called much later the “generation” of meanings, as in Chomsky’s linguistic “trees” and Greimas’s “generative course” and similar semiotic constructions. We shall later see whether Royce’s philosophy fulfils these criteria. For now let us see how Royce’s experience of Hegelianism may be taken as an analogy to what happened in Finland in the nineteenth century. There Hegel’s doctrine is connected to the name of Johan Vilhelm Snellman, the great statesman and awakener of the national spirit, whose statue stands before the Bank of Finland in Helsinki and whose portrait hangs at Helsinki University among the gallery of national heroes. First, Snellman was a philosopher and visited Germany only thirty years earlier than Royce. Even he felt the colonialist pressure, and the typically Finnish inferiority complex (like that among the American Puritans, mentioned above, in elevating simplicity as a virtue). Snellman wrote interesting cultural-semiotic descriptions of his travels in Germany in which he ironized the Schöngeist culture of Berlin. In 1848 Snellman defended his thesis in Tübingen on the topic Die Idee der Persönlichkeit. But does the fact that Snellman was Hegelian justify the currency of Hegel today? Now that the idea of the national is gradually fading away in the European Union and becoming only a picturesque regional quality, an object of semiotics of tourism rather than a semiotics of political culture? Now that the last castles of totalitarian thought, based on one version of Hegelianism, have collapsed in Europe, does Hegel retain any kind of actuality? Indeed it does. The fact is that we live a more Hegelian time than ever, but in a completely new sense than the Marxists could imagine. Electronic mass communication has made the world into

326 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce a kind of Hegelian or synechistic continuum, in which tout se tient. Anything that happens in one place is known everywhere. The Absolute Spirit of our time is communication, media, hypermedia, internet, virtual reality, and more. In the case of Snellman, he as a statesman exemplifies how practical action can be based on a consistent philosophy. Snellman’s successor in the chair of philosophy at Helsinki University, K. G. T. Rein, wrote that Snellman was a significant man in spite of his Hegelianism. There are, however, valid reasons to suppose that semiotics could serve as a theory of the contemporary world in the same way as Hegelianism did in its time. It might be interesting to make idea historical comparisons in this sense¹. But this is enough background for my also taking Royce seriously in semiotics. Arnold Schönberg once asked, Why is there no Great American Music? In a similarly polemical way one might ask, Why is there no Great German Semiotics? The answer is simple: German semioticians rarely use their own roots in the history of philosophy from Hegel and Kant to Heidegger, but have subordinated themselves to Anglo-American empiricism. Nevertheless, great semioticians all over the world are indebted to German speculative philosophy: from Peirce to Lévi-Strauss, from Lotman to Kristeva. Greimas said he felt much more empathy with those Romantic scholars than with the empirical positivists who, among other things, tried to show that ancient Finns were ridiculous in their worship of stones or trees: in fact, no one worshiped a stone or a tree, but the spirit that was living in them. And how Hegelian is Marcel Proust, in his belief that a spirit looms in every object, which a person provided with the right instinct can free. One might thus interpret Hegel’s Absolute Spirit (Geist) simply as the semiotic content. Such a semiotics could become a cornerstone of new semiotic thought, just as medieval (Scholastic) Catholic theology and philosophy have become for Umberto Eco and John Deely. Now, an essential distinction in semiotic theory is whether we think that the binary opposition, the relation between two contrary terms – which Greimas considered the beginning of all semiotics as early as in his Sémantique structurale – prevails on the same level of reality (as do s1 and s2), or whether they are thought to be situated on two different levels of reality (Greimas’s distinction, paraître/être). The first-mentioned semiotics investigates a text first as a linear unit; whereas the latter catalyzes the semiotics operating in depth. One might argue that the latter type of semiotics already appears in Saussure’s notions

1 At least in a country like Finland, the confrontation of semiotics and Hegelianism may prove to be very exciting.

15.2 Why Hegel? |

327

signifiant/signifié or Hjelmslev’s expression/content, such that from the signifier, one proceeds in depth into the signified. Hegel’s science of logic can be interpreted as a kind of presemiotic generative course, if we take into account both aspects – the parallel contrasts of Being/NotBeing – as well as those phases proceeding in depth, namely Being, Essence, and Existence. The internal Hegelian auto-movement of the concepts was a movement on both levels. It would not be difficult in this sense to “Hegelianize” Greimas’s semiotics. The basic modalities of Being and Doing, their negation, and the semiotic square which they form could be put into a spiral, such that Being would lead linearly or syntagmatically to the appearance of the term Not-Being, from there into Doing, and on to Not-Doing. Thereupon the next phase would again start with Being, but Being on a new qualitative level, one step higher than at the starting point.

Figure 15.1: The Hegelian movement from being to not-being

Hegel says, “Logic has to be conceived as the system of pure reason, the realm of pure thought. This realm is the truth as such, without a veil, both in itself and for itself” (Hegel 2010: 50). If we replace the word logic with the term “semiotics”, we get a new definition of semiotics. In Hegel’s thought, all the variety, alterations, and contingencies of Being – the stable, durable element – are represented by the concept and the generality hidden within it. Even this is compatible with semiotics, since such a phenomenon, too, can be seen as a product of semiotic concepts and mechanisms, and can at the same time be reduced to abstract notions and to their articulations as certain engagements and disengagements of spatio-temporal-actorial substances. Hegel considered it his task to make us conscious of “the logical

328 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce [read: semiotical] nature which animates the spirit, strives and acts therein”. For him, there is nothing in the object other than what has been invested therein. Hence, we may say that the “object” is a semiotic object, constructed by the Doing, Being, Acting, Knowing, Capable, Believing and so on, of a modal subject. To Hegel’s mind the object is nothing but the totality of a concept. In other words, the object consists of all those semiotic articulations and operations which we invest therein and by which we interpret it. One may see this corresponding to semiotical “analysis without residue”, that is to say, that nothing may remain in the object that was not semiotically construed. Hjelmslev’s exhaustivity principle would thus be fulfilled. On the other hand, there is a danger in Hegel’s system and in some semiotic theories as well, which is that of launching a heavy conceptual mechanism in order to solve a relatively small problem. Complexity is needlessly multiplied. Therefore one should also learn the bon usage de la sémiotique. Using the Greimassian system, for instance, one must know to situate the analysis only on a certain level of the generative course. Unnecessary complexity is the aspect of Hegel strongly criticized by Bertrand Russell. The latter remarked that, in order to use the word “John” correctly and reasonably, I do not need to know everything about John but only enough to recognize him. He no doubt participates in manifold relationships, close or distant, with everything that exists in the world, but we can speak about him while ignoring all that which is not immediately present in what is said. In Russell’s view, Hegelian doctrine is related to the premise that there is more truth in the whole than in the parts. This premise was taken up later by the structuralists. Hegel asserted that the truth is a totality. But the latter is only an essence, totality is only an essence, which is completing itself through its development. The totality is essentially the result: only at the end is it what it is in truth or reality. In this sense, Hegel connects the concept of truth to the aspect of temporality and the seme of perfectivity. He divides logic into three parts. First come objective and subjective logic, these being the logics of Being and Concept, which can be easily paralleled with the distinction between empirical semiotics, investigating various pragmatic conceptual sign systems, and the theoretical-interpretative semiotic tradition. These two Hegelian branches join into a third, mediating and reflective branch: the logic of essences (Wesenslogik). Is there also a mediation between the corresponding two kinds of semiotics? What would mediate between objective semiotics – say empirical studies of signs, biosemiotics, and the like – and more subjective semiotics, such as the Greimassian system, Kristevan semiotics, Derridean deconstruction, and so on? If objective semiotics gives us taxonomies of things – like Sebeok’s taxonomy of

15.2 Why Hegel?

| 329

the drums and whistle system – then subjective semiotics, similar to Hegelian subjective logic, organizes taxonomies into various kinds of semiotic models, by such notions as isotopies, débrayage, figures, difference, khora, etc. How this shift takes place would form a proper “Wesenssemiotik”. This would mean a particular hermeneutic realization, in which the semiotic essence or nature of a phenomenon is suddenly revealed. The observer suddenly realizes – this is in fact a semiotic problem! This is not necessarily a momentary intuition, say, of this type: in a bank the first number of the queuing number denotes the cashier, and the second number one’s turn. Rather, it involves a more complex series of inferences, as in Peirce’s abduction. Greimas never explicitly presented such rules of inference; but they must exist – otherwise semiotic analysis would not be possible. There is very little research about the “path” by which one recognizes a phenomenon to be of a semiotic nature. If both Hegel and his Finnish pupil Snellman emphasize “self-consciousness” and “the movement of the spirit”, then let us presume that our analogy with Hegel is not far-fetched, if we want to develop this sphere of knowledge based on understanding. Now, Hegel’s Wesenslogik went no further than definitions of identity, difference, and contrast. In Greimassian terms, such a reflection went no further than the relationships included in the semiotic square. Hegel says that in science one has to develop from a notion an idea that represents the reason in the object. He moreover states that to approach something as reasonable (read semiotically: meaningful) signifies that one does not bring the reason to a phenomenon from the outside, but that the object is reasonable as such already. This recalls the anthropological principle of emic observation: the phenomenon is studied immanently, with its own concepts. For Hegel, the catalyzing force of a concept lies in its dialectics. And yet, it has been argued that a dialectical method has to be sensitive to its object and that the method cannot be separated from its object and be elevated to the status of an abstract generality. Is semiotics an object-sensitive method, which would always be based upon the “inner motion” of the empirical facts and adapt to that motion? At least generation in the Greimassian method meets the requirements of such a dialectics. That is to say, the generation can be started or stopped at whatsoever level. Accordingly, there must be a kind of “superlogic” or “metalogic” that determines which semiotic notions are reasonable for the portrayal of a phenomenon. In Hegelian logic, the motion from being to absolute ideas can be interpreted simply as moving from a text to a code, from the substance of a phenomenon and its semes and phemes, to its deepest isotopy. Such reasoning is of course inductive, but we can also turn the Hegelian/Greimassian logic upside down and proceed

330 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce from the deductive starting-point axiom – the absolute – towards being; or if the reasoning is abductive then the movement may well stop on some level. Hegel tied his logic to a sense of history and temporality: “No one can truthfully transcend his time as little as to peel off from his skin [. . . ]. Philosophy is completely identical with its time.” We see this as well in the history of semiotics. Semiotics is always bound up with the level of knowledge reached in each epoch and unfolds from a total epistemic situation prevailing in the sciences and various national scholarly traditions. When we think of the intellectual climate in Germany at the time Snellman and Royce were there, we notice analogies to semiotics. When Snellman visited Tübingen, it was said that some had come from Hegel’s school and some from empirical research; whereas the first-mentioned tried to complete their philosophical speculation with criticism and history writing, the latter aimed at explaining empirical facts. Therefore despite the variety of disciplines and views represented there at the time, family resemblances dominated in scientific thought. The same can be said about semiotics and semioticians, whether biosemioticians, social semioticians, Greimassians, Peirceans, Lotmanians, Derrideans, or otherwise. We need go no further with hypothetical analogies between the Hegelianisms of the mid-nineteenth century and semiotics of the turn of the twenty-first century². With this background in Hegel, we can return to Royce.

15.3 Back to Royce Royce’s early thought was very much under the influence of Hegel, and thus was to a large extent based on a distinction between the absolute and the individual. Such a statement is found in his essay “The Conception of God” from 1897, in the middle of his career. But from this moment on Royce gradually moves from the Hegelian concept of the Absolute, certainly under the influence of Peirce, and heads in a more empirical direction with his new concept of “interpretation”. A common thread throughout his writing is the idea of community, which displays itself also in his more journalistic writings, such as his essays “The Squatter Riot of 1850 in Sacramento” (1899), “Race Questions and Prejudices” (1908), and “Provincialism” (1908).

2 It has, however, not been said (yet) of any semiotician as was said about Mr. Axel Adolf Laurell, a docent of theoretical philosophy and Hegelianism in the 1840s in Helsinki; namely, that he had taken ten years to get familiar with Hegel, and another ten years to get rid of him.

15.4 Toward the world of interpretation |

331

In existential semiotic terms, Royce confronts the problem between the Absolute in the form of some ideas which are imperfectly realized in the life of an individual, that is to say, the problem between transcendental ideas and the world of Dasein. The latter is certainly the Roycean World of Doubt as he puts it: “When we turn from our world of ideals to the world actually about us, our position is not at once a happy position. These ideals . . . do not make the world, and people differ endlessly about what the world [in our terms, Dasein] is and means”. Still, Royce thinks it necessary to study the world in its eternal aspect. He admits however the possibility of error in dealing with what we have called “transcendental ideas”: That there is error is indubitable. What is however an error? . . . No single judgement is or can be an error. Only as actually included in a higher thought, that gives to the first its completed object, and compares it therewith is the first thought an error. It remains otherwise a mere mental fragment, a torso, but the higher thought must include the opposed truth, to which the error is compared in that higher thought. The higher thought is the whole truth, of which the error is by itself an incomplete fragment.

From this Royce infers that thought is infinite, clearly sounding the Hegelian tone of his early writings. In his massive work, The World and the Individual (1899– 1901), the fundamental theme is the relationship between the “idea” and “being”. But from here Royce takes a new, more semiotical path. Alongside the concepts of conception (idea) and perception (being), he brings in the concept of interpretation. In psychological terms he characterizes interpretation as an essentially social process that transforms our inner life into a conscious, internal conversation, a form of autocommunication through which we “interpret ourselves”. From this position Royce ends up with the idea of a community of interpretation, which obtains metaphysical dimensions in his thought when he comes to the idea of the Hope of the Great Community. Whether semioticians form this kind of ideal community of interpretation I am not sure. Such a community is, at the least, very controversial and certainly not “unified”. In Royce’s late work, The Problem of Christianity (1913), Peirce’s impact is particularly strong; and in his lectures on Metaphysics (1915–1916) he offers a synthesis of all his earlier achievements (see Tarasti 2001).

15.4 Toward the world of interpretation In his preface to The Problem of Christianity, Royce describes it as a result of research that first appeared in his book of 1908, The Philosophy of Loyalty. He believes also that it is compatible and in harmony with his earlier The World and the

332 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce Individual from 1899–1901, but confirms that it is not a repetition of the old. Says Royce: I now owe much more to our great and unduly neglected American logician Mr Charles Peirce, than I do to the common tradition of recent idealism, and certainly very much more than to the doctrines attributed to Hegel. It is time I think that the long customary, but unjust and loose usage of the adjective “Hegelian” should be dropped [. . . ] my own interpretation [. . . ] despite certain agreements with the classical Hegelian theses, differs from that of Hegel’s school, in important ways

The titles of the various chapters of Royce’s book give us a flavor of his thinking. The chapters in Part One, called “Lectures”, are the following: Lecture I – The Problem and the Method; II – The Idea of the Universal Community; III – The Moral Burden of the Individual; IV – The Realm of Grace; V – Time and Guilt; VI – Atonement; VII – The Christian Doctrine of Life; VIII – The Modern Mind and Christian Ideas. Part II continues the lectures: IX – The Community and the Time-Process; X – The Body and the Members; XI – Perception, Conception and Interpretation; XII – The Will to Interpret; XIII – The World of Interpretation; XIV – The Doctrine of Signs; XV – The Historical and the Essential; XVI – Summary and Conclusion. In what follows I shall not pay too close attention to the theological content of the book, but concentrate rather on its philosophical and semiotic essence. Royce starts the first Lecture by pondering the sense in which a modern man can be a Christian. Interesting here is what Royce considers “modern”. He takes it as a completely fictive entity, such that the creation of our day’s discussion will be replaced as early as tomorrow by a new type of modern man: “For by modern man most of us mean a being whose views are supposed to be in some sense not only the historical result but a significant summary, of what the ages have taught mankind” (Royce 1969: 63). So modern man is the product of what history has taught mankind. Such a definition is certainly far from the so-called Project of the Modern, or “modernity”, meaning the separation of Man from the cosmos, as Charles Taylor puts it. Of course even Royce’s type of modernity includes the aspects of history and education, and thus the possibility to change, to redefine one’s essence, and in this sense his view might be interpreted in parallel to later philosophical definitions of modernity. For Royce the Christian doctrine contains three essential ideas. First is the assertion that the way of salvation lies in the union of the individual with a universal spiritual community. The idea of a union becomes a constant theme in Royce’s philosophy following his early experiences with Puritanism. Second is the idea of the individual’s moral burden, including that apart from the spiritual community, which the divine plan provides for his relief; in short, the individual is

15.4 Toward the world of interpretation |

333

powerless to escape from his innate and acquired character the character of a lost soul. This idea of guilt and a plan to get rid of it may be interpreted as a particular narrative program. For example, there is in Proppian theory an initial lack and a special narrative program to remedy it: to be disjuncted from the dysphoric object of guilt and conjuncted with the euphoric object of grace. Royce’s view could be semiotized in this manner. The third point is much the same: the only escape for the individual, the only union that he can obtain with the divine spiritual community, is provided by the divine plan for the redemption of mankind. In terms of modernity, the crucial thing here is union with a community and not with the cosmos itself. In Roycean terms, the idea of community intervenes between the individual and his salvation; hence he gives this level of community more and more emphasis as time goes on. In Lecture II Royce speaks of the idea of a universal community which again evokes semiotic interpretations. He writes: “As an essentially social being, man lives in communities, and depends upon his communities for all that makes his civilization articulate (ibid.: 80). Royce believes also in the metaphor of organic unity: [Communities] have a sort of organic life of their own so that we can compare a highly developed community, such as a state, either to the soul of a man or to a living animal. A community is not a mere collection of individuals. It is a sort of live unit, which has organs, as the body of an individual has organs [. . . ]. Not only does the community live, it has a mind of its own a mind whose psychology is not the same as the psychology of an individual human being. (Royce 1969)

Here we see the influence of Wilhelm Wundt as well as the organistic tradition of philosophy. The next point is the concept of Loyalty, by which Royce understands “willing and thoroughgoing devotion of a self to a cause, and which is therefore the interest of a community”. We could thus also interpret Loyalty to be the principle which holds the community together, and if the community is the same as the Dasein of existential semiotics, then loyalty is the principle whereby an individual can transcend his own Dasein, both toward other Daseins and toward pure transcendence. Royce eloquently describes empirical cases of loyalty: the individual revels in his service, as a player to his team, the soldier to his flag, the martyr to his church. He speaks of a social enthusiasm which thus animates individuals. And he says that loyal motives are not only moral but also aesthetic: “The community may be to the individual both beautiful and sublime” (ibid.: 84). This remark calls to mind the ways in which some semioticians and aestheticians view our postmodern world. Wolfgang Welsch (1996), for example, holds the Nietzschean view that the whole contemporary world can be understood only

334 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce as an aesthetic phenomenon. But can the whole world of media and worldwide electronic communication be seen otherwise, as the realization of Royce’s Great Community? Deeper analysis may prove this “community” to be an illusion, however, since the effect of all these modern technological means of communication has been rather the contrary one: to isolate people from real loyalty and communication, each in his or her own “bubble” world. Moreover, Royce says that those who are loyal are essentially alike. Such a universal community that Royce has in his mind is in essence a community of the Same, of people thinking and acting in similar ways. Maybe through the media power of the modern world people become loyal in that sense; that is, similar in their values and enterprises – the instantiation of what is called “globalization”. Even here Royce remains very Hegelian, when he states that loyalty is “a practical faith that communities, viewed as units, have a value which is superior to all the values and interests of detached individuals”. How different this view is from that of the great British contemporary of Royce, John Ruskin, who emphasized the individual, not the group, as the one who thinks and judges and evaluates, not the group.

15.5 The moral burden of the individual Royce believes in original sin and the moral burden of the individual, who unaided cannot escape that condition. This leads him to reflections on social matters, which are more relevant in our semiotic context. Anyone who studies human nature must make a distinction between the conduct of men and their consciousness of it, says Royce. In his view, all of our more complex conduct and consciousness is trained by a specific sort of environment, namely a social environment. As solitary beings we could never develop ourselves. If a man or an animal were to live in a totally unsocial state, he as a solitary creature could find no other instance of conduct with which to compare his own. Whatever occurs in our actual social life can be and often is repeated with endless variations in our memory and imagination. Thus these thoughts and memories enrich our social environment. In this way we are able to compare ourselves with others, and this comparison makes us view ourselves and attend to the social will, which is “law”. His reasoning here comes very close to that of George Herbert Mead and his view on the origin of symbols, namely his distinction between “I” and “me”, the latter being our ego as seen by others. This type of Will (vouloir) represents a special modality: a co-actorial, social Will. But Royce is quite a realist in his ideas about the nature of the social, and he has no illusions. True, the aforementioned comparison leads to self-

15.5 The moral burden of the individual

|

335

consciousness, but also to rivalry, contest or criticism, about which Royce gives the intuitively obvious rule: “The greater the social tension of the situation in which I am placed, the sharper and clearer does my social contrast with my fellows become to me” (Royce 1969: 111). Hence the greater the social tension, the more I am aware of my own conduct. Therefore conflicts are an inevitable part of one’s spiritual, or as we might say, existential development. This does not mean that we should be at war with our fellows, but rather that we become selfconscious as moral beings through the spiritual warfare of mutual observation in the course of rivalry. He gives us the maxim that “the moral self, then the natural conscience, is bred through situations that involve social tension” (ibid.). Thus we see that Royce is not a mystic recommending withdrawal from the world. Rather, our level of moral being depends on the social community in which we live, on the whole Dasein, which includes our fellows as well. On the ethical side, this situation increases the moral burden of the individual, making it ever more heavy. Society always breeds men who are inwardly enemies of each other, because every man in a highly cultivated social world is trained in moral self-consciousness by his social conflicts. High social cultivation breeds spiritual enmities, for it instils what we call “individualism”. The higher the cultivation, the vaster and deeper, the more spiritual and more significant of these inward and outward conflicts. Therefore Royce argues that individualism and collectivism are tendencies, each of which, as our social order grows, intensifies the other. To see how true this is, one need only follow the history of the arts – not to speak of the sciences, and not least in semiotics: ongoing polemics, various schools fighting each other, eminent artists and scholars at odds. In semiotics, Are you Peircean or Greimassian? was the question for a long time, the answer leading immediately to an unavoidable and unresolvable conflict. In the next Lecture, “The Realm of Grace”, Royce tries to resolve the abovementioned problem. The solution lies in the nature of the community to which one belongs, a community that can be either good or evil, beneficent or mischievous. Royce postulates an ideal group, however, which he calls the “Beloved Community”. It embodies values that no individual as a detached being could even remotely approach. Such a society is based upon the principle of Loyalty. It is taught by a great leader, but such a person must himself be loyal, and in order to be loyal he must first find his lovable community. Loyalty is thus a concept that is fulfilled in our Dasein. The next Lectures, on “Time and Guilt” and “The Atonement”, are of a more theological nature. More to our present concerns is the chapter on “The Community and the Time-Process”, in which Royce addresses the problem of existential loneliness.

336 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce Royce adheres to the Leibnizian doctrine of monads. One man cannot feel the physical pain of another man. What he feels is his own emotional reverberation at the sight of its symptoms. Royce believes that each of us lives within the charmed circle of his own conscious will and meaning; each of us is more or less clearly the object of his own inspection, but remains hopelessly beyond the direct observation of his fellows. My act is my own – an echo of contemporary social pluralism – but when one belongs to a social community, the situation changes. Our ethical pluralism makes us proudly state, My deed is my own! But our collective life makes us say not I act thus , but Thus the community acts in and through me³. So he in fact draws the same conclusion as that of the later structuralists, from Lacan to Foucault. At this moment Royce introduces the notions of history and memory. The individual self is no mere present datum or collection of data but is based upon an interpretation of the sense and value of life, which in turn carries the memory of its own past. Royce asks, Can many different selves, all belonging to the present time, possess the identically same past as that of their own, personally interesting past life? Royce’s response: A community constituted by the fact that each of its members accepts, as part of his own individual life and self, the same past events that each of his fellow-members accepts may be called a “community of memory”. Further, a community whose members accept the same future for themselves can be called a community of expectation and ultimately a community of hope. Clearly such ideas are intimately bound with the idea of temporality, as it explains metaphysically the emergence of an historical community. The next Lecture, on “The Body and the Members”, adds much to the value of temporality. Royce thinks that the first condition upon which any kind of community depends is the power of an individual self to extend his life, in an ideal fashion, so as to regard it as including past and future events which lie far away in time. The self is essentially a life that is interpreted in a certain way and that interprets itself. Royce believes memory and hope to be the strongest forces to function as such extensions. In modern semiotic terms, such extensions are nothing other than the modalities postulated by Greimassian semiotics. Without modalities a communication would not be possible, insofar as every act of communication entails an effort to fill or bridge the gap between subjects s1 and s2. Heidegger, on the other hand, spoke about Sorge, care or worry, as the basic human attitude in the life of a Dasein (community). Heideggerian “care” would be the same as modality as such, but without any particular manifestation as Will, Know, Can, and so on.

3 Royce quotes the German: “Ich denke nicht, sondern es denkt mir.”

15.5 The moral burden of the individual |

337

Thus the real deeds of a community are cooperative. Every individual, in his own extended life, includes also the cooperative deeds of other members of the society. Men form a community only insofar as they cooperate. With this Royce has laid the foundation for what follows in the book: sign theories in the proper sense. This part starts with Lecture XI, on “Perception, Conception and Interpretation”. Here Royce relies heavily on Peirce, and one might be tempted to think that the whole significance of Royce to semiotics would be simply that he managed to insert Peircean sign theory into a social semiotic context. The concept of interpretation is crucial. Royce adduces concrete cases familiar to anyone: a stranger in a foreign country, a philologist rendering the meaning of a text, a judge construing a statute – always interpretation is involved. Royce admits his indebtedness to Peirce, and regrets his earlier misunderstanding of the latter’s thought. He reports that Peirce in fact invented pragmaticism, which at that time was being much developed by William James. Moreover, Royce says that Peirce was in no way under the influence of Hegel or German idealism. Royce even says that, twelve years ago, Peirce wrote the following in a letter to him: “But when I read you, I do wish you would study logic. You need it so much.” We shall later see that Royce’s understanding and usage of Peirce were quite unique. When defining the difference between perception and conception Royce quotes Bergson’s metaphor of a gold coin as perception and a bank note as conception. The notes constitute promises to pay the cash, and conceptions are useful guides to possible perceptions. This is illustrated by the case of our travels abroad. In one’s own country his coins are valid, but beyond its borders those bank notes may have no value. When we communicate with our fellow men, we are like these travelers: crossing the boundary into a new country, we encounter there a largely strange world of perceptions and conceptions. We are never sure about our neighbors’ perceptions, but their conceptions are so generally communicable that they can be taken as identical with our own. This process of passing from conceptions to perceptions is precisely interpretation. When Hamlet says to Ophelia, “I never loved you”, and Ophelia answers, “But that is what you made me believe”, then we have a typical case of interpretation – and of misunderstanding. Royce gives as another example of interpretation: an Egyptologist who translates an inscription. At first, two things are needed: the translator and his text. But he also needs a language into which the inscription will be translated. So the translator interprets something, but he interprets it only to one who can read English. If the reader knows no English, we do not have interpretation. Here already we have a triad: the Egyptian text, the Egyptologist-translator, and the possible English reader. They are all equally necessary. The mediator (translator,

338 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce interpreter) must know both languages, and thus be intelligible to both persons whom his translation is to serve. We have a triadic relation: (A) Somebody interprets (B) somebody/something (C) to somebody. And this is essentially a non-symmetrical relation; that is to say, the terms must be in this order. When a man perceives something the relation is dyadic. A perceives B. But when A interprets B to C we need three terms. Royce goes further, reasoning that when a man undertakes conscious reflection, he interprets himself to himself. Even here the triadic relationship obtains. Man interprets his past self, say, as a promise to his future self: “This is what I meant when I made that promise.” Here three men are present and taking part in the interior conversation: the man of the past whose promises, notes, old letters, etc. are interpreted; the present self who interprets them; and the future self to whom the interpretation is addressed. Royce insists that this process of interpretation differs psychologically from perception and conception, in these ways: (1) There is always someone who addresses someone. (2) The interpreted object is itself something of a mental nature. Peirce uses the term “sign” to designate this mental object. (3) Since the interpretation is a mental act, the interpretation itself is a Sign, and this new sign calls for further interpretation. Hence the social process is endless, as with infinite semiosis. Perception terminates in the object perceived, and conception is satisfied with defining a universal type or ideal form of somebody’s thought. But interpretation both requires the sign to be an interpreter and a further interpretation of its own act, because it addresses some third being. In Royce’s opinion, only death can stop this process of interpretation. The next lecture bears a very Schopenhauerian title, “The Will to Interpret”. The will to interpret makes its three members into a community of interpretation. Royce correctly points out that all this evokes the Hegelian dialectic, wherein thesis, antithesis, and higher synthesis play their roles. But Royce says that Peirce’s idea of the mediating third has, historically speaking, nothing to do with Hegel. Peirce’s concept is a very general process, of which the Hegelian dialectic is only a special case. Hegel’s illustrations of his own processes are ethical and historical. Still, says Royce, there is no incompatibility between Peirce and Hegel. When we take on the role of interpreter we enter the Community of Interpretation. Nevertheless, the problem remains: how can we know that any community of interpretation exists? This question brings us again to the very center of metaphysics. Royce answers that, since we all have the will to interpret, there must be somewhere a community that is aiming towards such a goal. So for him the ultimate instance of reality is the Community itself. Any conversation with other people, as any process of our inner self-consciousness, unfolds only as it is based on the thesis that we are all members of a community of interpretation.

15.6 Royce’s metaphysics and last insights on interpretation

|

339

This is the real world for Royce, and his definition of reality. He simply sees it, like Peirce, as a semiosis, a process of interpretation, the only difference between him and Peirce being that for Royce the process of interpretation is essentially social.

15.6 Royce’s metaphysics and last insights on interpretation Royce’s Lectures on Metaphysics in 1915–1916 were drawn from notes taken by his pupil Ralph W. Brown, these forming a synthesis of all his earlier thought. Now reality, knowledge and truth cannot be separated from the community of interpretation. The earlier Hegelian Absolute has been replaced by the idea of interpretation. He confirms his idea of the self as being a kind of community of its own. I am not merely my physical organism, is his first argument. The socalled individual man is in certain respects a social group. He consists of various selves. So he comes close to the idea of M1, M2, S2, S1 in the existential semiotics. Royce’s view of the self is thus pragmatic: the self is nothing given; rather, it is expressed in a life. You are yourself by virtue of the fact that you are engaged in doing something. One has memory and expectation, and in consequence every man has a past and future life as essential parts of him. One has three different selves: past self, present self, and future self. Thus Royce calls the self a “social group” and lists concrete empirical cases of communities: 1. The judicial community consisting of A. Plaintiff, B. defendant, C. judge; 2. The banker’s community: A. borrower, B. lender or depositor, and C. banker; 3. The agent’s community: A. agent, B. principal, and C. client; and 4. the insurance community: A. insurer, usually a corporation, B. an “adventurer”, C. beneficiary. All these communities display the same triadic morphology. If I buy insurance, it is my future self who gets the money in an accident; a money-lender is in the present, but the person who is going to receive the loan is in the future. So there is not particular psychological continuity between past, present, and future selves. Their stability establishes an ethical relation among the various selves. The general formula for identity is coherence of life plan or what we might in semiotics call a narrative program. Royce reasons that the self is defined as a life lived in accordance with a plan, or to use the word idea, as a life with a coherent idea. In existential semiotics this would mean a life that is following some transcendental idea and is in this manner becoming something existential. Perhaps the most important passage in Royce’s lectures, for us at least, unfolds his notion of “The Triadic Community of Interpretation”. The cooperation of A and C brings them into some sort of social unity, which makes them think

340 | 15 From absolute spirit to the community of interpretation: Josiah Royce and feel as if they were one person. The same sort of unity may characterize an individual. He is not an individual because he has an individual organism. Rather, a self is a self by virtue of the fact he or she is doing something that constitutes a plan having unity or coherence. Royce then says, contrary to behaviorism, that this unity is something one cannot grasp by merely observing the organism, but only by discerning what a man means, what he is after. This parallels our understanding of narrativity, when we speak of a desire as the catalyzing force: the actors are defined by what they are seeking. In communities of interpretation, the most important function is the inter-mediation brought about by B. Thanks to it, A, B, and C act as if they were one man. To bring about such solidarity is the main task of B. The interpreter, we recall, is the one who addresses C on behalf of A; and as Royce defines it, a self is a self by virtue of some coherence of plan. B is a self who desires to carry out a plan which furthers not only A’s will alone, nor C’s will alone, but rather the united will of all three. Therefore B must be loyal, the willing servant of the cause and plan of C and A. Accordingly, B is always the most important member of the community in question. It is B who both defines and expresses the community’s united purpose. He more or less invents its united purpose. Thus B as mediator is a truly active and creative person. He brings C into touch with A and A into touch with C. The combined will of A and C has to be created constantly, and that is B’s task. Hence he is the most obviously and explicitly loyal member of the community. For Royce, no activity of man is too lofty to be interpreted by a community of interpretation. As an example he takes the scientific community as based on three roles: collector of facts, the theorizer, and the verifier. These three phases correspond to Peirce’s definitions of various ways of reasoning: collector – retroductive methods, theorizer – deductive methods, and verifiers – inductive methods. Thus we can now see that Royce in his late philosophy not only studied and followed Peirce, but gave Peirce’s thought a new interpretation. Royce is only minimally a nominalist; that is, he does not turn philosophical problems into problems of language and naming. There is always something of a pragmatic attitude in Royce’s reasoning. But some of his theories of the social nature of knowledge and truth anticipate later theories of epistemes as social constructions. When he emphasizes the role of B, the interpreter or mediator, he comes close to some present-day media philosophers. It seems to us that many things exist only as mediated by what we call “media”. In science, as well, some people who only mediate others can have crucial value – a comforting thought to organizers of scientific congresses, publishers of journals, editors of others’ texts. Royce gives much value to such activities. Some philosophers have levied the charge that, when we say something is a sign, we

15.6 Royce’s metaphysics and last insights on interpretation

| 341

diminish the “existentiality” of anything we are speaking about. It is “only” a sign instead of being something real. Royce shows how erroneous such a view is. Something is real only through the process of interpretation, which always entails a corresponding community of interpretation. What position Royce will retain in the development of social semiotics is hard to say. Yet, as I have tried to show above, it is certain that he at least makes a genuine contribution to the understanding of Peirce’s thought, as it reflects upon the possibilities for social semiotics in the context of existential semiotics.

Chapter 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by Susan Petrilli 16.1 Introduction The name of Victoria Lady Welby has become familiar to anyone studying semiotics in the last decades, thanks to the correspondence between her and Charles S. Peirce, available since 1977, edited by Charles S. Hardwick, and published by Indiana University Press. In that publication, Welby appears as an intellectual companion of Peirce. Often “geniuses” (who are mostly men, as one may notice!) need some other, less striking and independent correspondent in order to mirror their ideas and develop them further without too much resistance or “intellectual effort”, in the Bergsonian sense (Bankov 2000). In music, this phenomenon was addressed by Alfred Einstein, cousin of Albert, who in his Greatness in Music (1941) claimed that genius distinguishes itself from mere talent by what is called in German Verdichtung (poetic density). This quality accounts for the difference between Mozart and Salieri, Beethoven and Cherubini, Verdi and Donizetti, and so on. If projected into the intellectual area, one might say that a genius has “density” in his text, whereas the other person, “the double”, would have less. Does this mean, then, that Peirce’s thought is “dense” and Welby’s “thin”? Moreover, the Berlin professor Walter Schmitz had also studied the Welby phenomenon in many of his remarkable articles (see references). Yet, I learned about them only after having written this chapter. In any case, history must always be rewritten, and this Susan Petrilli has done with her monumental editing and commentary on Lady Welby’s life and work, in the recent 1048-page volume entitled Signifying and Understanding: Reading the Works of Victoria Welby and the Signific Movement (2009). Here Welby comes through as an extremely exciting literary and philosophical woman intellectual who was in touch with most of the famous names in science of her time, from Henri Bergson to Bertrand Russell, who led her life in British upper-class circles as the Maid-of-Honor of Queen Victoria, and who tried to get her voice heard as a pioneer and independent thinker in the challenging fields of meaning and semantics. Yet, sad to say, she remained in the shadow of such figures as Michel Bréal, who published his study on semantics in 1897, at the same time Welby was launching her own new science of “significs”. A major and deeper question raised by a reading of Petrilli’s volume is, Why didn’t “significs” did become the dominant

16.2 The challenge of originality

| 343

term for all issues concerning meaning and signification? Despite the fact that some tried to launch a movement around it, as Petrilli shows, “significs” was never taken into broader usage. Such was the case with all the other neologisms that Welby invented. In the age of feminism, the immediate and easy answer is of course, because she was a woman. Yet even in this feminist age, no one has written about her work as that of a woman genius. She was overlooked, for example, by Julia Kristeva in her study on Le génie féminin (1997–2002), who instead chose for her examples Melanie Klein, Hannah Arendt, and Colette (!). I once thought that if I were to write such a treatise I would include Cosima Wagner, George Sand, and Simone de Beauvoir. Yet now, after reading and learning about Welby, it seems to me that there should be one from the Anglo-Saxon sphere as well. At the least, Welby might number among what Gertrude Stein called “would-be-geniuses”. Or even more?

16.2 The challenge of originality Another, more generalized conception of the problem may be asked as follows: Why do certain undeniable innovations in science remain unaccepted by the majority? Everyone knows that the scholar’s life is a happy one so long as he/she only repeats the commonplaces, the mainstream ideas, the accepted schools and paradigms of thought. The problems start at the very moment when he/she becomes or tries to become original. Most find this attempt odious, and turn their backs on the dissident. Our genius candidate encounters particularly great obstacles if he/she invents a new terminology or totally new concepts. Very few thinkers see their neologisms accepted into general usage by scientific communities. Plato coined the “khora”, but it was not adapted for semiotics (by Kristeva) until some 2000 years later. There was, however a scholar in Moscow who used it in the meantime. All this is to say that there is a chain of communication and transmission of ideas and concepts. Yet, before answering the question in the case of Welby, we must examine her thought as such and determine whether it really has such substance or “density” that would justify our speaking of her as a forgotten pioneer in her field. For this, Petrilli serves up convincing evidence gleaned from her meticulous source-studies. In particular, there is an abundance of unpublished essays by Welby, each of which reveals exciting ideas. But as you know, it is not enough to have ideas and intuitions, as Greimas once said. In science, one has to put them into discourse, into models that can be communicated to others. In this respect, an interesting revelation by Petrilli, which I did not know, is that Welby never

344 | 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by S. Petrilli had what we call a formal education. Normally before entering academic life, one has become at least a baccalaureate. Welby did not have even this. Whereas she became extremely well-read, something in her texts may stem from her lack (or avoidance) of formal training. Schemes or structures of scientific communication, a kind of logic of discourse, are perhaps not lacking, but different in her reasoning. Non-British readers may say, Well, hers is only the typical Anglo-Saxon fear of theory. Theorizing and conceptualizing are continental features, something “Cartesian” or “Hegelian”, both of which constituted horrors to those empirically minded scholars in the Isles. As an instance of her reasoning, let us examine how Welby uses the concept of “three”, which is so essential in Peirce.

16.3 The idea of “three” Much study has gone into the origins of Peirce’s categories of First, Second, and Third. For example we have Max H. Fisch’s essay collection, Peirce, Semeiotic and Pragmatism (1986), where appear the chapters “Peirce’s Triadic Logic” and “Hegel and Peirce”. In the former, Fisch shows the origin of triadism in Kantian logic, about which Peirce said, “Kant, the King of modern thought, it was who first remarked the frequency in logical analysis of trichotomies or threefold distinctions” (in Fisch 1986: 180). Peirce made that remark in his essay “One, Two, Three, Fundamental Categories of Thought and Nature” (1885). Peirce’s affinity with Hegel was clear right from the start. William James noticed it, and Peirce himself several times admitted it. Hegel’s objective logic operated with “Three” – namely Being, Not-Being, Becoming – and obviously served as a model for Peirce’s semiotics, as he wrote in 1902: “But now we have to examine whether there be a doctrine of signs corresponding to Hegel’s objective logic, that is to say whether there be a life in Signs, so that [. . . ] they will go through a certain order of development” (Peirce, quoted in Fisch 1986: 273). A little later Peirce wrote to Welby: “My three categories appear always more and more clear to me. These resulted from two years’ incessant study in the direction of trying to do what Hegel tried to do. It became apparent that there were such categories as his” (Peirce, quoted in Hardwick 1977: 189). This has to be remembered, although Peirce in his famous declaration of semiotics in his letter to Welby in 1909 deems the nominalists to be wrong and the realists to be right; he does not list Hegel among those nominalists on the order of literateurs, samplers on the level of the wine tasters of Bordeaux, whereas philosophers’ names from Kant to Leibniz do appear there. Here is Peirce’s famous definition for the “real”: “Real is such that whatever is true of it is not true because some individual person’s thought or some individual group of persons’ thought

16.4 Royce as Lady Welby’s contemporary |

345

attributes its predicate to its subject but it is true no matter what any person or group of persons may think about it” (ibid.: 116). This definition, incidentally, is exactly the same as that given by the British pre-semiotician John Ruskin, when he said that opinions which are individually taken as wrong do not become right by the fact that a majority of people support them.

16.4 Royce as Lady Welby’s contemporary Of course, the Hegelian impact on Peirce stands out especially in his relations with Josiah Royce, with whom Peirce planned to take lessons on Hegel quite at the end of his life. Yet it is almost funny to notice how Royce, the best-known Hegelian in the United States, himself emphasized his own originality. In the preface to his The Problem of Christianity (1913) Royce says that the book is the result of researches which first appeared in 1908 in his book The Philosophy of Loyalty. He believes that it is also compatible and in harmony with his earlier The World and the Individual (1899–1901), but insists that it is not a repetition of the old. He writes: I now owe much more to our great and unduly neglected American logician Mr. Charles Peirce, than I do to the common tradition of recent idealism, and certainly very much more than [. . . ] to the doctrines attributed to Hegel. It is time I think that the long customary, but unjust and loose usage of the adjective “Hegelian” should be dropped [. . . ] my own interpretation [. . . ] despite certain agreements with the classical Hegelian theses, differs from that of Hegel’s school, in important ways. (Royce 1969)

Royce’s interests and output indicate a certain proximity or soul-mate affinity with those of Welby. For if Welby included ethics and religion in her Significs, so did Royce. Royce’s work is important in this context because he dealt with quite similar topics as Welby, and at the same time. But these parallels did not intersect. It is true, for instance, that the early Royce was very much under the influence of Hegel. It has been said that his early thought was to a large extent based on a distinction between the absolute and the individual. Such a statement is found in his essay The Conception of God (1897), i.e., in the middle of his career. But from this moment on Royce gradually moves from the Hegelian concept of the Absolute, certainly under the influence of Peirce, and heads in a more empirical direction with his new concept of “interpretation”. A common thread throughout his writing is the idea of community, which displays itself also in his more journalistic writings, such as his essays the “Squatter Riot of 1850 in Sacramento” (1899), “Race Questions and Prejudices” (1908), and “Provincialism” (1908).

346 | 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by S. Petrilli Moreover, Royce inferred that thought is infinite, making the Hegelian tone of his early writings quite clear. In his massive work, The World and the Individual (1899–1901), the fundamental theme is the relationship between the “idea” and “being”. But from this starting point Royce takes a new direction which we may qualify as more semiotical in nature. Alongside the concepts of conception (idea) and perception (being), he brings in the concept of interpretation. In psychological terms he characterizes interpretation as an essentially social process, one that “transforms our own inner life into a conscious interior conversation, wherein we interpret ourselves”, a form of autocommunication (Lotman). And from this position Royce ends up with the idea of a community of interpretation, which obtains metaphysical dimensions in his thought when he comes to the idea of the Hope of the Great Community. Whether semioticians form this kind of ideal community of interpretation I am not sure. At the least, such a group is very controversial and certainly not a unified community of interpretation. In Royce’s late work, The Problem of Christianity (1913), Peirce’s impact is particularly strong; and in his lectures on Metaphysics (1915–1916) he offered a synthesis of all his earlier achievements (see Tarasti 2001). One wonders why Welby and Royce had no contact with each other, as Petrilli indicates was the case. Another notable lack is that Welby never mentions John Ruskin in her writings, although he was certainly a well-known figure in the contemporary British intellectual world, significant for his art-education philosophies. Perhaps he was socially too radical for Welby, who never, it seems, put her thoughts on ethics into a social program or critique – despite the fact that she emphasized Significs as a practice rather than as speculation. Be that as it may, let us return to the issue of how the idea of “Three” came to these thinkers. It is evident that the concept of Three, used by Peirce, Royce and others, existed long before them in the tradition of philosophical thought, and that they only continued this type of academic discourse.

16.5 Welby’s independence as a scholar Welby, however, as a vigorously independent scholar, almost an esprit contestataire, argued that she discovered Three by her own reasoning. On November 18, 1903 she wrote the following to Peirce: “With regard to the relation between the triad, [. . . ] that of Hegel (also that of Comte) I may say that long before I knew anything about Hegel, I was asking myself, why my thinking when I tried to make it clear, fell naturally into triads. Then I looked around and found more or less the same tendency everywhere” (in Petrilli 2009: 291). So she thought “Three” to be her own invention, but its occurrence elsewhere proved it to be a universal entity.

16.5 Welby’s independence as a scholar

| 347

As a private thinker, she believed one could arrive at such a truth in one’s own way, outside the academic tradition of philosophy. Peirce, when reviewing Welby’s What Is Meaning? (1903), also considered one of its merits to be that “[. . . ] of showing that there are three modes of meaning”. On Welby’s independence of thought Petrilli has found other evidence as well. This was seen as early as in Welby’s discussion of terminology. When semantics was launched it had many rivals, including semasiology, sensifics, significs, sematology, symbolonomy, and more. It showed courage to try to coin a term for an entirely new discipline. Also the ways in which Welby dealt with, among other things, the problem of Three showed her independence. In her essay on “Threefold Laws” (1886) she had already reached this conclusion: “From the study of development of human intelligence in all directions, and through all times, the discovery arises of a great fundamental law [. . . ] the law is this: that each of our leading conceptions [. . . ] passes through three different theoretical conditions: the theological, or fictitious, the Metaphysical or abstract, and the Scientific, or positive” (quoted in Petrilli 2009: 333). Here Welby mentions as her model Auguste Comte’s law of three stages. Yet, Welby continues to question: Let us see then whether we can utilize Comte’s idea[. . . ]. Speaking Man passes through three “phases of mind” which we may consider as 1) the Moral, the Logical and the philosophical, or the Way of right conduct, right reasoning, and right generalization, 2) the Mathematical, the critical the Scientific; or the Truth, abstract, historical, positive, and 3) the Vital, the Energetic, the Generative, or the Life: sensuous, conscious, creative. In other words Man mentally develops by a threefold process that is by the tentative, the corrective and the effective. (ibid.: 334)

Welby was very much occupied with Triads, as was Peirce, but she also warned: “By this time the reader [. . . ] is suspecting a disguised version of Hegel. But although Hegel is one of the most notable of thinkers who have ‘thought in threes’ he is also one of the most dangerous of those who have allowed the idea to master and to warp their whole mental world.” This was something Welby wanted to avoid. But have we ever got rid of trichotomies? I recently sketched the development of human societies via three stages: archaic (the mythical), historic (the sociosemiotical), and the contemporary globalized universe (the technosemiotical). Is this not a new version of Comte?

348 | 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by S. Petrilli

16.6 Who is a significian? Despite her caution, Welby divides her Significs into three parts: (1) Sense, (2) Meaning, and (3) Significance. Welby, in defining these branches, describes (1) “sense as the most primitive, and it occurs, for instance, when we ask “in what sense” a word is used. For Welby the answer depends on the “essentially expressive element in all experience”, which is the organic response to the environment. (It may seem that here is a foreshadowing of the biosemiotician’s notion of Wirken as the primal response to the Umwelt.) The term “sense”, however, does not carry the purport or intention of the speaker; therefore we use the term (2) “meaning” to indicate the specific sense that something is intended to convey. This would be the phase of modalities, or something similar to speech-act theory and its illocution. Yet, the factor which transcends both of these previous definitions is called implication, the ultimate result (perlocution) or outcome of the experience. And for this we use the term (3) “significance”. For instance, we may say that an event or phenomenon had a profound influence on his life, “the significance of which cannot be overrated” (Hardwick 1977: 167). Significance is thus the broadest of the three divisions. Welby also speaks of a particular scholar or personality whom she calls a “Significian”. This man has three attitudes: sense = verbal or “sensal”; meaning = volitional; and significance = moral. (These resemble the three existential stages of man, which Kierkegaard had already proposed.) Welby’s ideas clearly go far beyond purely linguistic definitions, just as Greimas’s system would do later with his invention of modalities, which exceeded the boundaries of verbal language and made his semiotic theory a general one. Welby with her “system” also reaches what Petrilli (as well as Deely 2001) call “semioethics”, something broached in my Existential Semiotics as early 2000, which weighs the moral and ethical aspects of signs. Another essential point in Welby’s thought, as mentioned above, was that her Significs was a kind of practice of signs; it thus had a pragmatic dimension leading to application, in education among other fields. Can we see a deeper course or structure in Welby’s trichotomy? Can it be considered a kind of generator of signification, a generative model? In existentialsemiotic terms, can we say that “sense” equates to pre-signs”? These last are signs not yet fixed, as when we hesitate in our language use and ask, In what sense did you use that word? We may then ask if “meaning” be taken as an act-sign, i.e., a sign used in the actual situation of communication in which we always want to express something, such that we have intentions and modalities. Finally, is “significance” not a kind of post-sign, which is a realized sign with all its social and contextual impacts and consequences? It seems that Welby’s system may be subsumed under the existential semiotic one; or into Roman Ingarden’s phe-

16.7 Problematic language |

349

nomenology, with its virtual, actual, and real phases – adopted by Greimas for his virtualizing, actualizing, and realizing modalities. When Petrilli “contextualizes” Welby’s thought into that of contemporary semiotics, she most often mentions, besides Peirce, thinkers like Bakhtin, Lévinas, Ponzio, and Sebeok. But if Welby’s theory is interpreted in a “universal” manner why not, to test its validity, insert it into other conceptual schemes as well? Welby’s famous article on Significs, which appeared in the Encyclopedia Britannica Vol. XXV in 1911, can be seen as an abridgment of much of her prior thought, a summation of her most important results. Therefore Petrilli’s study is of vital importance because it shows the broad discoursive field from which Welby’s ideas stemmed.

16.7 Problematic language Much of Welby’s thought deals with language, though essentially she saw language as the origin of confusion and misunderstanding. Her relation to language was thus ambiguous. On the one hand, she trusted language and considered ordinary colloquial speech, the common-sense language, as a determining factor. She was also interested in diverse language uses, although not in the sense of a Nancy Mitford and her theories of U-language (upper class expressions) and non-U language. It does seem, however, that she anticipated what positivists later called the “linguistic turn”. If such is the case, can we say that she fulfilled one criterion by which some scholars are said to represent “Anglo-Analytic philosophy”? Note, however, that there are two other criteria as well, one of which is the use of formal logic. Peirce used it, but Welby not. In Petrilli’s book (2009: 355), the diagram of literal and metaphorical meaning, though perhaps not formalized enough to be taken as a logical scheme, shows how any expression balances between two categories: actual/literal expression and figurative/metaphorical expression:

Figure 16.1: Literal and metaphorical meaning according to Welby

350 | 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by S. Petrilli The third criterion of Anglo-Analytic philosophy, namely “the right philosophical style”, may be harder to specify¹. Welby herself questioned naïve behaviorism and empiricism, as the following lines from her poem “To A Discoverer in danger of catching the new Specialism Disease” show: . . . All else is an airy vapour, you know, Though good in its place and way; I can’t waste my time on irrelevant things I care only to measure and weigh!

This may evoke for us the principle of an empirical scholar: try to measure what is measurable . . . (as once expressed by the Estonian linguist Ilse Lehiste). The end of the poem, which was written between the 1880s and 1890s, is even more “existential”: And see that while working at problems you love The rest of your life isn’t spoiling!

On the other hand, Welby criticized language, such that “the bad use of language implied the bad use of logic, incoherence and confusion in reasoning which deviated evolutionary development” (in Petrilli 2009: 29). Petrilli concludes: “She invested the critics of language not only with the task of diagnosing the maladies of language but also with the therapeutic power of recovering and reinvigorating linguistic expressivity” (ibid.). Heidegger went even further, holding language guilty for the decline into das Man Sein with its inauthenticity and gossip. Welby emphasized, as Petrilli puts it, “the need to improve our expressive devices, therefore language and communication generally, in order to avoid misunderstanding” (ibid.: 99). Petrilli then concludes that Welby aimed for the improvement of interpersonal relations and of human behavior in general. Petrilli states: “In the era of global communication today nothing seems more real and concrete than the prospect of global conflict and its many phases [. . . ]. Welby’s foresight is astounding!” (ibid.) For me, this also calls to mind the American linguist Walburga von Raffler-Engel and her theories of cross-cultural misunderstandings. As more evidence of Welby’s semio-ethical concerns, we find her writing in 1902: “Significs affords also a means of calling attention to the backwardness of language in comparison with other modes of human communication and to the urgent need of stimulating thought by the creation of a general interest in the logical and practical as well as the aesthetical value of all forms of expression” (ibid.: 195).

1 I am indebted to Nathan Houser for sharing with me his ideas on Anglo-Analytic philosophy.

16.8 Metaphors

| 351

16.8 Metaphors Obviously Welby considered any ambiguity and figurativity in language as a vice and a deficiency, as her view of metaphors reveals to us. In What Is Meaning? (1903) her reflections came very close to Peirce’s ideas on iconic signs and indexicality. But in contrast, Welby distinguished among cases: casual (or general) likeness, likeness in all but one point or feature, valid analogy (or equivalence), and correspondence (reminiscent of Umberto Eco, on fakes and forgeries as correspondence between two systems and their elements). Yet, going further such analogies become metaphors that, in Welby’s view, should be abandoned. As soon as we see a figure of speech, apparently so harmless, we should insist upon its replacement by another which may turn out even worse still (Petrilli 2009: 368). The use of metaphors brings us to the subject of ambiguity. Welby argues that “voluntary and beneficial discord may be compared with intentional and beneficial ambiguity”, and then herself makes a metaphor by music: “In one sense discord may be described as the condition of true music, of which the essence is significant and ordered harmony. So ambiguity [. . . ] is the condition of the highest forms of expression” (ibid.). Greimas, in his way, put it that all witty speech depends on complex isotopies; in rhetoric, we call this troping, i.e., the putting into conflict of discordant figures. Welby continues: There are three forms of involuntary discord, all fatal to music: (1) defective tuning of the instrument, (2) defective “ear for music”, and (3) defective larynx or lungs in singing, defective hands, fingers and arms in the use of instruments, i.e., organic distortions. These cause what we now call “noise” or disturbance in communication. Welby mostly refers to corporeal qualities here (in Moi1, as I would put it), emphasizing different moments of musical communication. She then says, however, “But while intentional discord is in music good, intentional discord in communication is always evil”. Of this pernicious ambiguity she lists the cases: (1) We have defective “tuning” of language. This means concretely that there should be a “perfect relation between every element of Expression” (ibid.). Thus, claims Welby, we need to train a generation for this. (2) We have the defective mental ear and eye on the part of the “performer”. (3) We have defective organs as instruments of expression. We even say that this or that, a certain truth or reality, a certain beauty or good, is “indescribable”, beyond one’s capacity to express.

16.9 How to educate our expressive powers “The fact is that as children we have never had our Signific powers systematically trained, and thus our organs of significance are not yet fully developed.”

352 | 16 Victoria Lady Welby – A pioneer of semiotic thought rediscovered by S. Petrilli Obviously, Welby’s Significs is for her a project for developing our ability to discern subtleties of meaning. Hence she says in What is Meaning? that Significs is linked to education because it would be considered first as a method of mental training. But what did that mean in reality? To apply her own first category of Significs we should ask, In what sense is she using the term “mental training”? She answers in her essay “Linguistic Consciousness and Education” (1908): “Education for meaning implies developing the capacity to identify distinctions and to establish connections among different subjects, ideas, problematic fields of research” (Petrilli’s paraphrase). The same applies to semiotics in general: it is often said that the utility of all semiotics is precisely that it enables us to see and recognize hitherto unknown connections. It means the same as programs for school teaching. The difference is that nowadays semiotics in the classroom treats of quite naïve and simple cases of signs, such as food, media, advertising, and so on. Welby, however, speaks about more complex nuances of expression. Altogether, for her significs was a “practical extension” of semiotics (Petrilli 2009: 272): “Significs concerns the practical mind, e.g. in business or political life, more closely and inevitably than it does the speculative mind” (quoted in ibid.: 274). Yet, it remains to ask what such a project would concretely imply. Is it similar to Royce’s communities of interpretation – a new manner of looking at and interpreting the world of our Dasein? Is it the same as Roland Barthes’s “structural man” who deconstructs and reconstructs cultural objects?

16.10 Transcendence On the other hand, Welby is not tied strictly to concrete reality since she takes into account that which transcends our everyday experience: “That which ‘transcends’ in any sense the ordinary limits of experience is often rightly enough referred to the vague, unknown, unsafe, unreal . . . ” (Petrilli 2009: 276). Still, her transcendence is of a rather empirical kind, something which “the telescope and spectroscope bring us”. Her mind is basically on the side of concrete facts. In her early essays she was still pondering theological issues, but she later turned them into practical questions and problems of language. When William James had studied religion and published his treatise The Will to Believe (1897), Welby was interested in a questionnaire of life in the future, when the issue of immortality becomes a series of questions of the following type: “Would you prefer a) to live after ‘death’ or b) not?” This type of research was of course one way to enact Significs. The “I”, for Welby, was a kind of diagnostic activity: “We must be brought up to take for granted that we are diagnosts [sic!], that we are to cultivate to the utmost the power to see real distinctions and to read the signs, however faint,

16.10 Transcendence |

353

which reveal sense and meaning. Diagnosis may be called the typical process of Significs as Translation is its typical form” (quoted in Petrilli 2009: 167). In a letter to Peirce, dated November 20, 1904, Welby defined more closely what she understood by transcendence: The best I can do is to say I wish instead of the Future we could begin to talk of the Unreached as the Yet distant! We do already talk of the near or distant future, and ‘future’ itself, like all the time-words, is non-temporal. It is just Beyond Now, and the now is essentially here. This gives the transcendent a new legitimacy. What we transcend is a garden-hedge or a horizon; and you may go on transcending till you are back again at your own back-door! But meanwhile the round world has moved on and dragged you, the transcendentalist, with it, on a freshly transcendent expedition. (Welby, quoted in Hardwick 1977: 40)

Needless to say, this rather strongly evokes my first model of existential semiotics, with its transcendental “journeys” (Tarasti 2000; also 2009c). It also reminds one of how sociologists Schütz and Luckmann define transcendence, in dealing with the concrete and empirical matter of understanding (verstehende). Thus, the seemingly rather utopian project of Significs and Significian can take on such quite practical manifestations as diagnosis and translation. Welby’s goal was indeed ambitious, as Petrilli describes it, in “her plan to develop and adequate theoretical-linguistic apparatus in a significal key to review and reevaluate the history of the development of the human species and account for the development of human behavior” (Petrilli 2009: 29). Ultimately, Welby dealt with all the major philosophical questions relevant to herself and to her environment. She also came to write about subjectivity and difference among I, Me, and Self. In that sense she is extremely “modern”, perhaps even au courant. Petrilli’s great work has rescued from oblivion an important scholar of the past, a pioneer in the history of the semiotic movement, whose thought provokes the most diverse interpretations. She ranks among the great classics of semiotics although her Significs project never became part of mainstream philosophy nor even within the scope of semiotics. She herself was a true “significian” throughout her life, and much remains to be learned about her writings. Finally we have the access to the sources of Welby’s activities, thanks to Petrilli’s years of devoted research.

Chapter 17 Vladimir Solovyov 17.1 Background Vladimir Solovyov first came to my attention when the Finnish semiotician Henri Broms wrote about him as a “myth-generating” philosopher who along with such figures as Chaadaev and Berdyaev had played a crucial role in forming Russian culture. Then my colleague Pekka Pesonen, Professor of Slavic Literature at Helsinki University, informed me of certain texts by Solovyov that are accessible to scholars who do not read Russian. There is an entire series of volumes of his works in German, titled Deutsche Gesamtausgabe der Werke von Wladimir Solowjew. The first of these volumes, the dictionary, includes Solovyov’s most essential articles on philosophy, theology, and mysticism, taken from the BrockhausJefron Lexikon of the years 1891–1900. It is fascinating how the author can, in the same book discuss such purely philosophical notions as Schein, causality, Wissen, immanence, intuition, truth, ontology, objectivity, reason, space, rationalism; alongside such theological-mystical entities as pre-existence, will, eternity, all-unity, ideal, idea, idol, metaphysics, mysticism; and also such historicophilosophical and political terms as power, nationalism, patriotism, Western identity, and the like. Familiar names appear, including those of Kant, Hegel, Comte, Wilhelm Wundt, and Hartmann, along with names not so well-known to the Western tradition, such as Valentinus, Pelagius, Gregorius Thaumaturgus, Maximus the Confessor, Hermes Trismegistos; and finally such historians and well-known Slavophiles in their time as Danilevsky and Léontine, aunt of Marcel Proust. What appeals to us in this eclectic mixture is the kind of “structuralist” attempt to create a global world-view. In this volume by Solovyov disparate phenomena relate to each other on a spiritual basis that cannot be grasped immediately, thus tempting one to read further. I have even borrowed from Solovyov for my own system the ideas of “world soul” and the Gnostic concept of “pleroma”, while knowing, however, that to pick discrete terms by mere intuition may later prove to be problematic; for with them come a whole system of thought which in the end can be something quite different the one first imagined. After later reading Samuel D. Cioran’s book on Wladimir Solov’ev and the Knighthood of the Divine Sophia (1977), it became clear to me that the often long and rationally well-focused definitions in the dictionary showed only one side of this thinker in whom also dwelt a “mystical Eastern man”, as Henri Broms puts it. This aspect of the writer manifests as a poet and a scholar who constructed a special doctrine of “sophiology”. As Nikolai Berdyaev has said,

17.1 Background

| 355

there was the rational and reasonable daytime-philosopher Solovyov and the irrational, “night-time” Solovyov with his mystic visions (cited in Cioran 1977: 39). Whichever was the “real” Solovyov, he played a key role in the development of nineteenth-century Russian culture. In addition to writing on general issues of cultural policy and philosophy, Solovyov produced essays on the national problem in Russia, which include such texts as “Über die Nationalität Rußlands” (1884), “Die slawische Frage” (1884), “Rußland und Europa” (1888). In those essays he turns out to be thoroughly different from the “Eastern” Solovyov who adheres to Russian Messianism, Slavophilism, and Russia’s special commission to proselytize Europe and the entire world. For example, “Die nationale Frage in Rußland” begins impressively: The national question is for many peoples the issue of existence. Russia cannot have such a question. During its thousand-year history Russia has been a unified and independent great power. This is the definite fact, which is beyond any questioning. But even more urgent is the question: why and in whose name it exists. What is involved is not a material fact, but an ideal destination. The national question in Russia is not a question of existence, but the question of a dignified existence. (Werke IV: 9, translation mine)

Solovyov later puts the matter quite frankly: Moral duty demands that a nation give up its national egoism, conquer its national limitations, and transcend its isolation. A nation has to conceive of itself as what it really is: a part of the unity of the world. And it must experience solidarity with all the living parts of that unity. This goal requires, in Solovyov’s view, an act that does away with national isolation and egoism, and such an act is possible only if complete freedom of thought prevails in Russia. This freedom is attainable only if one admits that Russia has great and independent forces, which in order to manifest themselves must adapt to more generally European forms of life and knowledge. He sharply rejects Slavophile talk about the extra- and anti-European essence of Russia. Such artificial originality has always been an empty demand. Unless Russia gives up the right of power and begins to believe in the power of right, nothing good can follow. Only by keeping in close touch with Europe has Russia attained anything significant. The best in Russian culture is thus basically European: Pushkin and Lermontov in literature, Sergei Ivanov in painting, and Glinka in music. Even of Glinka, the first so-called “nationalist” Russian composer, it was said in his time he joined the heart of Italian music with the brain of German music. Now, a century later, Solovyov’s ideas are no longer of general interest. Solovyov does, however, enjoy currency in a science like semiotics. He is an integral part of the nineteenth-century heritage, a great system builder in the manner of Hegel, and also related to Kierkegaard, John Ruskin, and even to the later Charles

356 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov S. Peirce. Could Solovyov be taken as a model for a post-structuralist semiotics searching for its inspiration in philosophy? Does he belong to the semiotic tradition of thought? Did he ever use the concept of sign? Solovyov’s system is clearly semiotic, in the deep sense that he believes in the basic movement of the sign-reality, or sign-force, which designates the shift from content towards expression, from the immanent towards the manifest, from signified towards signifier. Indeed, behind his extremely rational philosophical apparatus looms his complicated, sophiological-mystical vision, such that Solovyov to a modern man forms an almost incomprehensible blend of Orthodox theology, theosophy, and poetic visitations. Yet, none of this changes the basic structure of his thought, which is semiotic in the deeper sense mentioned above. I link him with the tradition of “Romantic” semiotics, which starts from the following four hypotheses: (1) Meanings exist even before one starts to analyze and explicate them (the hermeneutic principle of pre-understanding, Vorverständnis). (2) Meanings are based upon processes; that is, they reveal themselves gradually through the changes and developments of time, place, and subject. (3) They take shape immanently, within a certain “system”. (4) They emerge from differences within a system. Peirce’s life has certain commonalities with Solovyov’s: both corresponded with women who understood their thought, and both mastered all the fields of philosophy, from epistemology to ethics and aesthetics expressed. Peirce illustrates the principle of “Romantic” semiotics in his essay “Evolutionary love”, where he writes the following: Suppose for example, that I have an idea that interests me. It is my creation. It is my creature – it is a little person. I love it; I will sink myself into perfecting it. It is not by dealing out cold justice to the circle of my ideas that I can make them grow, but by cherishing and tending them as I would the flowers in my garden. This is the way mind develops; and as for the cosmos, only so far as it yet is mind, and so has life, is it capable of further evolution. (Peirce 1955: 363)

Moreover, Peirce situated the aforementioned principles of “Romantic semiotics” in one category which he called “synechism”, defined as “that tendency of philosophical thought which insists upon the idea of continuity as of prime importance in philosophy and in particular, upon the necessity of hypotheses involving true continuity” (ibid.: 354) Nevertheless, most of the past century’s study of signs has been what we call “classical” semiotics. Romanticism died upon the arrival of the Modernist project. Yet one wonders if it is possible to revive the Romantic model now, early in the twenty-first century. Postmodernism and post-structuralism have opened the doors in this direction, and the further it progresses, the deeper semiotics penetrates into hitherto unexplored realms. If the invention of modalities was in

17.2 Moral philosophy

| 357

the 1970s was considered revolutionary, now they are considered a sort of norm, studied positively, and even quantified as computer units (see Tarasti 1995). The modalities have since been followed with the idea of meta-modalities, which form a relatively new and unexplored metaphysical realm. The Romantic semiotician always exceeds the limits of Sameness, reaching out to Otherness and journeying towards the unfamiliar. It is from this perspective that Solovyov has pertinence today, that is, not always by virtue of the content of his ideas, but by the style and aspirations of his thinking. When one reads the purely rational definitions of his philosophy, they display a certain strength and quietness of thought stemming from the conception behind them. Of course one might doubt the wisdom of continuing to formulate global systems now at the beginning of the twenty-first century, when the quantity of knowledge from which to abstract a system has grown so enormously larger than it was during the time of Solovyov and even of Peirce. But this need not be a futile pursuit, so long as we remain conscious of the difference in our historical situations and at the same time do not give up the principles we have; universality, for instance, the four theses mentioned above, and Peircean synechism.

17.2 Moral philosophy Solovyov’s collected papers include many heavy volumes of pure philosophy. The earlier Solovyov is represented by Kritik der abstrakten Prinzipien (1877–1880; now in Werke I), which deals with many problems inherited from Kant, Hegel, and Schopenhauer, such as issues of the highest positive and abstract principles in life, consciousness, and creativity. He first ponders ethics, then goes on to social problems, the economic foundations of a society, and the concept of justice; next comes religion, society as a religious union, and the dependence of ethics on metaphysics. These reflections are followed by an epistemological section and the definition of the very notion of knowing. He deals with naturalism, ontology, realism, atomism, monism, empiricism, positivism, sensualism, and rationalism. The last chapters of the Kritik hold special interest for our own existential semiotics, in their allusion to issues engaged by Hegel, as discussed elsewhere in this book. Among them, for example, are the following titles: “The difference between Being and ‘To Be’ ” (Der Unterschied des Seienden vom Sein), “Being as the Absolute” (Das Seiende als das Absolute), “Absolute Being and Absolute Becoming” (Das Absolute Seiende und das Absolute Werdende), “Man as the second Absolute” (Der Mensch als zweites Absolutes), and “Belief, imagination and creativity as the basic elements of all objective knowledge” (Glaube, Einbildung und Schöpfertum als die Grundelemente aller objektiven Erkenntnis).

358 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov His philosophical trajectory evokes that of Greimas, who once said that knowing consists only of islands in the sea of belief. Even Greimas elevated the modality of Believing to the highest category. Solovyov shares with Peirce the centrality of ethics, and other parallels between the two thinkers can also be found. For instance, in a short paper from 1877, entitled “Three forces”, Solovyov states that three basic dynamics have ruled over the history of mankind since its inception. The first force endeavors to subordinate all grades and spheres of mankind to some higher principle with which all the different and multiplied forms should be fused. In its extreme form this means the dominance of one and the subordination of others. A contrary principle is complete freedom in which the general becomes abstract and where empty senselessness, egoism, and anarchy reign; this involves a multiplicity of discrete elements without inner connections. Both of these forces are negative in nature, and if they truly did rule over the development of mankind then its history would amount to a mechanical oscillation between these two principles. There is yet a third force, however, which joins the unity of the highest principle to the free manifoldness of the discrete forms. These principles of Solovyov correspond to the three species of development portrayed above by Peirce: tychastic development, which means fortuitous variation (Solovyov’s second principle of multiplicity); anancastic evolution, which designates a mechanical constraint or necessity (Solovyov’s first principle), and agapastic evolution, which in Peirce means the same as “creative love”. The functioning of these three principles in the cosmos was denoted by Peirce with the terms tychism, anancism, and agapism. Solovyov’s most extensive work is a large treatise entitled The Justification of the Good (Werke V: Die Rechtfertigung des Guten: Eine Moralphilosophie), which contains a thorough development of his ethics. According to Solovyov, morality depends on determinism. The animal world follows mechanical necessity, or as Peirce would say, “anancism”, the first species of determinism, which excludes morality. The second species is psychological: it accepts certain elements but excludes others. The third species is rational-ideal, which gives place to all the demands of the ethical. According to Solovyov, all morality originates in the sense of shame. Shamelessness in a person reveals that the spiritual principle is not yet operating in him (Soi ?). With the help of shame, people distinguish themselves from their animalistic nature. Man also has another emotion that serves as the origin of the ethical, namely, compassion (Mitleid). The third emotion is respect (Ehrfurcht), devotion and obeisance to something higher than oneself. This last constitutes so-called natural religion and means that one respectfully loves something that is more complete than oneself. The emotions of shame, compassion, and respect form the basis of man’s relationship to that which is inferior to him, equal to him, and

17.2 Moral philosophy

| 359

superior to him¹. The mastery and domination of the material and the sensual, solidarity with other living beings, and voluntary obeisance to a supra-human principle comprise the foundation of ethics to Solovyov. In the next chapter Solovyov ponders asceticism as an ethical principle. He presents three forms of asceticism and states that in no doctrine is the evil, material, physical world identified except in the Brahman concept of Vedanta, according to which the world emerged through a fraud of the primal spirit. The world appears as a deceptive difference, and by mortifying the flesh one can uncover this fraud and attain unity. Another doctrine from India teaches that evil is proof that spirit becomes a permanent ally with the primal materia, or nature. The third kind of teaching is Buddhism, for which both spirit and matter are indifferent; everything is empty; there are no objects of desire, and asceticism is reduced to the simple modal state of not-Will. One can easily see what kind of implications these concepts have for such classic semiotic concepts as the modalities. Solovyov believes that we judge our role in worldly processes not only in relation to concrete psychological phenomena but also in relation to the general principle of dignified or undignified being (that is, good and evil). Such a consciousness makes one participate in the goals of the process. Insofar as we allow a good idea to direct our actions, we can positively participate in general life. But because all this is realized in material nature, two principles fight within us: the spiritual and the fleshly. The “fleshly” does not mean the physical organism as such, but aspirations contrary to the spiritual soul that threaten to drown that spirituality in materiality. In such a case, material nature appears as something really evil, since it tries to destroy that which is dignified in human existence. The concept of the fleshly ought not be confused with that of the corporeal, since physical bodies, even for an ascetic, can be “spiritual”, “transfigured”, “heavenly”, and so on. Solovyov rejects all this, with the statement that good ascetics can at the same time be cruel, evil-minded egoists. Asceticism in and of itself is not essentially good and cannot alone constitute the highest ethical standard. Next Solovyov scrutinizes the sense of general solidarity. he abandons the Schopenhauerian philosophy of compassion, saying that man’s ability to feel em-

1 This distinction in social categories is the same as that developed much later by the Canadian literary scholar Northrop Frye, in his Anatomy of Criticism (1957). In that book Frye distinguishes among three narrative modes: the grotesque, in which the protagonists of the story are inferior to us; the realistic, in which they are on the same level as we are; and the mythical, when the protagonists are superior to us. In fact, many principles of narratology can be expanded into philosophical ones; e.g., as we have done in this book with Greimas’s modalities. Perhaps such principles were originally applications, abridgments, or fragments of philosophical categories considered within our primary Dasein.

360 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov pathy with the suffering of a stranger seems to be enigmatic. It presupposes that I have to some extent identified myself with the Other and have thus for a while abolished the boundary between the I and the not-I. The state of general is a mystery to Solovyov, and yet it is the secret of all ethics, something which reason does not comprehend but still something quite ordinary. If one wishes to define a semiotic act in terms of ethics, it would mean precisely the transition of the I to the not-I. This process involves the emergence of difference, and at the same time an identification with that difference. Everything that exists belongs to the same unity, according to Solovyov; there is nowhere a complete discreteness. Therefore Mitleid, compassion, is the sign of the inherent solidarity among everything that exists. This state of affairs is considered entirely rational by Solovyov. Conversely, the irrational is alienation or subjective differentiation. Compassion does not presuppose, however, that I completely identify with another creature but that I remain non-identical with it; the boundaries between beings are not abolished. When Solovyov says that compassion means I recognize in the other its own meaning (Bedeutung; Werke V: 132), we are approaching near to semiotics. From ethics, which is crucial to his overall philosophy, Solovyov turns to the matter of virtues. For him, the good as an ideal norm of the will, or that which we should want, does not coincide at all with the real object of the will, i.e., that which we in reality desire. In its own way, good lays certain responsibilities on us, but unfortunately (1) not everyone wants to take on their rightful obligations; (2) even among those who seek after good not everyone is able to attain it, i.e., not all are capable of mastering the bad inclinations of their nature; and (3) among those few who have suppressed the evil within themselves, i.e., among the virtuous, not even they with their goodness can overcome the evil that rules over the world. This last-mentioned idea becomes central in Solovyov’s later philosophy, in which he abandons himself to a Wagnerian apocalyptic vision of the final battle between good and evil. To comment on the essence of the good in a semiotic sense, one might offer the following thesis: the only reward of a good act must be the act itself. Otherwise we could not explain the fact that, generally speaking, the better we treat other persons, the worse they become. This might sound pessimistic, but the positive side of the matter is that goodness makes evil appear, and when evil manifests itself openly it is easier to fight, and its effects can be remedied. In this way ethics connects with our third principle of “Romantic” semiotics, namely that the immanent becomes manifest. In further writings Solovyov pays much attention to eudaemonism, to the fact that everyone desires only his/her own good or pleasure. In such a view, life is reduced to pleasure, according to Solovyov; but from this fact one cannot infer any general rule for action. There is no general universal pleasure, but only various

17.2 Moral philosophy | 361

kinds of pleasure which need have nothing in common with each other. In reality, the idea of pleasure blends with the immeasurable chaos of fortuitous needs. Erotic desire displaces every other desire. The supreme good from this standpoint is a state that provides the greatest possible satisfaction. But this state is not just the sum total of pleasures, because one must subtract from that total the sum of unpleasant states. The highest pleasure is the one that produces maximal joy and minimal suffering. In this case, moral choice would be based upon judging between various alternatives. This is not acceptable to Solovyov, because our destiny depends on many factors that are not subject to our decisions or measurements. The destruction of all good also casts a shadow over present enjoyment. Moreover, according to Solovyov it is certain that the strongest enjoyments are not those recommended by reason, but those which follow from wild passion. Neither do the highest spiritual or aesthetic pleasures suffice as the greatest good, since the latter must must apply to all people. No development of democratic institutions can endow a donkey with the ability to enjoy the symphonies of Beethoven.. Solovyov next ponders utilitarian ethics, which claims that since we are not only individuals but also part of a collective, we find real happiness only through serving the common good. Nevertheless, utilitarianism, as represented J. S. Mill and others, is but another form of eudaemonism. Utilitarianism only appears to coincide with altruism. The utilitarian refers to the general solidarity, claiming that the happiness of an individual is inextricably linked with the happiness of the community. But according to Solovyov there exists a general solidarity that, like a natural law, influences individuals regardless of their will and their behavior. This general solidarity is not the same as the general welfare or common good. For from the fact that humanity enjoys solidarity it does not follow that it would be happy, since solidarity can obtain even amid disaster and destruction. As a direct continuation of Solovyov’s rational philosophical reasoning, but in literary form, his Drei Gespräche enacts a discussion between five different persons who argue about the world situation, politics, war, and peace. This involves a kind of Bakhtinian polyphony of consciousnesses whose contrapuntal parts are these: the General, who has distinguished himself in battle; the Politician, a resourceful man who is serving the state with his theoretical and practical innovations; the young Duke, a moralizing friend of the people who has published more or less effective pamphlets about social problems; a middle-aged Lady who is interested in everything human; and Mr. Z, whose age and social position are unidentified (but who is revealed to be the alter ego of Solovyov himself). These discussions, which resemble those in a Chekhov play, seem to take place in southern Europe, since Solovyov describes the setting as a garden from which one can see the Alps. The discussions meander from topic to topic as the protagonists

362 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov present their own experiences and tell long stories. Among other issues they dispute the justification of war. Solovyov puts his own ethical positions in the mouths of these personages. Little by little the discussion shifts to reflections on good and evil. Among other things, Mr. Z says this: It is now so that [. . . ] evil is obviously stronger than good; when this apparent fact is taken as the only reality, one has to presume indeed, that the world is the creation of the evil principle. But how is it then possible that in spite of the presence of evil, people argue that there is no evil and therefore one does not need to fight against it? This is something my reason does not comprehend. (Werke VIII: 245, translation mine)

In what follows the central issue concerns how evil can masquerade as good. As illustration, Mr. Z brings produces a manuscript written by a Russian monk; it is a story about the Antichrist, which Mr. Z reads and the others comment on. The Antichrist tale is a science-fiction sort of narrative about the future, when in the twenty-first century (our very own) Europe is threatened by another Mongol invasion. This threat causes the European nations to band together, or as the narrative puts it: “Europe in the twenty-first century is a union of nations which are all ruled more or less democratically”. The Antichrist is not a Mongolian Khan, however, but a hero accepted by everyone. He seeks the ultimate good for mankind but does so only out of infinite egoism. The task of this new superman is to bring salvation to mankind via spirituality. He publishes a book on “The Man of the Future” in which he promises eternal peace and prosperity. But a fight breaks out between the Antichrist and Church fathers, and some people do not accept him as the supreme leader. The final battle is waged in Jerusalem and involves mystical turns of events in this fight over souls and not material goods. At this point, according to Solovyov, mankind has already given up materialist thinking. If Solovyov lived in our own time he probably would see traces of Antichrist everywhere and would severely criticize postmodern society as a mixture of extreme eudaemonism and fragmented dissolution, whereas for Peirce it would illustrate tychism.

17.3 Sophia and the World Soul In his rationalistic, “daytime” output one must also include Solovyov’s theological treatises, which advance a kind of theosophy, the doctrine he called “sophiology”. They include lectures on God-head and manhood, as well as writings about the unification of churches and the foundation of a universal theocracy. I will pass over these, in order to get to his “night” side, or mystical aspect of his work. Such writings influenced, among others, Russian symbolists such as Bely and Blok. At

17.3 Sophia and the World Soul |

363

the same time, they represent the strangest and most irrational side of Solovyov’s personality. I have not had access to a comprehensive biography of Solovyov, but some sources mention an extensive treatise about him written by Prince Yevgeny Trubetskoy. My knowledge is thus based on the study by Samuel D. Cioran (1977). According to Cioran, Solovyov tried to create a philosophical and rational basis for Christianity. His aim was not purely theological, however; even more important was the founding of his principle of Sophia. Sophia, argues Solovyov, is a rational necessity, while at the same time appearing as a mystical mediation between the divine and the earthly. Sophia is a mystical symbol of a rational process. It is interesting to note that Solovyov’s highest principle was clearly a gendered creature: a female. Sophia also appears in his texts under the title of the “Eternally Feminine” and “Aphrodite Urania”. Sophia’s other-worldly guises are manifold; she is identified with the concept of World Soul, Mother Earth, and Mother Nature. Solovyov started from the texts of the Gnostic mystics. He believed that there was a state of truth or an ultimate model from which humanity had strayed, and in order to regain this state one had to return to the beginning of the cosmogenic process. Wisdom could be obtained through its personification as Sophia. The myth of Sophia itself is complicated. The originating cause of the universe is a Monad, called the Father; unbegotten and imperishable, he is the source of all that exists. Not subject to time or space, he is solitary and self-existing, reposing within himself. In his solitariness he projects and conceives the dyad of Nous and Aletheia (Mind and Truth). They in turn project the synergy of Zoe and Logos (Life and Word), which produce Anthropos and Ecclesia (Man and Church). This creation of pairs of Aeons continues until there are some twenty eight or thirty Aeons in the Pleroma (fullness, plenitude). The youngest of these Aeons is called Sophia. She decides, in imitation of the Father, to create an offspring without a partner, but can only produce a formless substance, a shapeless and imperfect mass. The rest of the Aeons become frightened by Sophia’s presumptuous deeds, fearing that she might destroy the harmony of the Pleroma. The Father consoles Sophia and orders a further projection through the synergy of Nous and Aletheia, which produces Christ and the Holy Spirit (Cioran 1977: 18–19). Solovyov’s cosmogony describes particular spheres in which these creatures pursue their actions. The inferior physical world is under the power of the Demiurge, who believes himself to be its creator, whereas in fact Sophia is its original cause. Nature and the physical world appear as the World Soul. Sophia is immovable, divine, eternal, whereas the World Soul is extra-divine and subject to conditions of time and space. Sophia represents the non-contingent Queen of Heaven, and the World Soul stands for the contingent and material body of the natural world. The World Soul is materia prima, a freely operating spirit in the

364 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov extra-divine world; she is capable of desiring existence for herself outside of God, of putting herself into a chaotic state of anarchy. Thus the content of the World Soul represents nothing less than world history and world processes. The World Soul does not appear as Sophia herself on earth, but rather as her potential spirit or potentia1 agent. The closest Sophia comes to the World Soul is when the latter unites with the Logos. In the action of the Logos, the active principle of Oneness, Sophia makes herself known to the World Soul. United with the Logos, the World Soul can progressively raise herself to identification with Sophia, an act which can be consummated only at the end of cosmological history in the union of Heaven and Earth. The work of the World Soul culminates in the creation of man, the crown of the world process and initiator of history. At the same time, the World Soul creates not only man, with his masculine and feminine sides, but also mankind and society. Born of the will of the World Soul and bearing the concealed divine principle, man is the perfect son of two natures, one material, the other divine. Only man can become the effective agent of Sophia on earth. By his rational acts he can make the heavens descend to earth. Sophia’s triple incarnation is described in Solovyov’s essay, “La Russie et l’Église universelle” (published only in French). Sophia is also present in the concept of earthly love, by which one can confirm the absolute value of another human being outside oneself. Thus, Solovyov’s theory of love is based on the polarity of the male and female principles; hence gay and lesbian relationships have no place in it. Behind this quite extraordinary theoretical construction stands the personality of Solovyov, which we should like to know more about. Solovyov was an extremely delicate and nervous character. he was often sick and feverish, and during bouts of illness he became particularly susceptible to visions and hallucinations. He could sit for hours in the library of the British Museum in London, looking at one page of the Kabbalah. When asked what was so interesting about it, he replied, “In a single line of this book there is more intelligence than in all of European science” (quoted in Cioran 1977: 41). One Russian intellectual has said that Solovyov revealed his inner visions only to women, claiming that at the most important junctures of his life he followed the directions of the spirit of a certain Norman woman of the sixteenth or seventeenth century, who appeared to him whenever he wished. The person who best knew the hidden side of his life was his brother, Mikhail Solovyov. In the private papers and correspondence of his brother, Mikhail found such incredible and scandalous material that he had to destroy it in order to sustain the intellectual and moral reputation of Vladimir. One aspect of Solovyov’s life came to light only some years after his death, in the memoirs of writer Nikolai

17.3 Sophia and the World Soul

|

365

Valentinov, entitled Two Years with the Symbolists. Upon discovering many intimate love letters signed with the letter S, Valentinov declared Solovyov a mentally unbalanced pervert. Solovyov clearly meant these letters to be read as coming from Sophia (S), but the handwriting reveal that they were written by Solovyov. This is not so extraordinary given that Solovyov was practicing the so-called automatic writing later favored by the surrealists, whereby he would jot down telepathic messages purportedly delivered from other realms. Solovyov’s irrational views are best conveyed by his poems, the most famous of which is Three Meetings (Tri svidaniya) from 1898. There Sophia appears in three forms: (1) as the perfect archetype who moves freely between the heavenly and earthly worlds; (2) the World Soul, or nature, the feminine principle of matter, which can receive the Logos and thus become divine; (3) the earthly woman, the feminine complement of the masculine principle, the union of which produces society. This poem, according to Solovyov, humorously depicts the most important events of his life. Its style oscillates between farce and profound revelation. According to the poet, Sophia first appeared to him in 1862, when he was nine years old. She manifested as “earthly love” and did so in a church sanctuary, possibly during evening service amid the intoxicating incense, icons, and music that set the stage for spirit apparitions. The second visitation of Sophia occurred thirteen years later when Solovyov, then a young university lecturer, left home to pursue studies at the British Museum. Lastly Sophia appeared to him in the Egyptian desert, bidding him to join her there. Solovyov immediately quit work in London and traveled to Cairo via Paris, without stopping en route. He satirically describes the Cairo Hotel, with its Russian and other foreign clientele, as well as himself wandering about in the desert, dressed elegantly in top hat and overcoat. He is attacked by Bedouins, released, then finds himself alone in the night among the jackals. In despair he receives his third vision, for which the first two were but preparation. In these poems Sophia never appears under her own name but is addressed as “thou” or “eternal friend” or “Queen”. As the feminine nature principle she is called “Earth-Mistress”. The last-mentioned variant might interest semioticians who have attended conferences at Imatra in Finland, since the latter town appears in Solovyov’s poems about Lake Saimaa, where he often went for meditation. In the poems “Saimaa” and “On Saimaa in winter”, both dating from the year 1894, this lake acts as a synonym for World Soul: The lake splashes with impatient waves. Like the swelling tide in the sea, The disharmonious element surges towards something, Contends with something, a hostile fate.

366 | 17 Vladimir Solovyov That toward which the lake surges is unity and identification with Sophia. Images of water in Solovyov’s poetry depict the unbounded nature of the World Soul, which in its restless motion reveals the struggle for unity. In “On Saimaa in winter”, the World Soul receives its most poetical names, such as “the radiant daughter of sombre chaos”. In it Sophia plays the role of World Soul, appearing as Finnish nature in winter: “You are all enveloped in luxuriant fur, Becalmed you lie in unresisting sleep. The radiant air does not waft of death here, This transparent, white silence. In serene and profound repose, No, I did not seek you out in vain. Your image is the same before the inner eye, Fairy-Mistress of the pines and rocks. You are unsullied like snow beyond the mountains, You are full of thought like the winter night. You are all in rays, like polar flame, Radiant daughter of sombre chaos!”

A mystery of Solovyov’s life, one which particularly influenced Bely, Blok, and other Symbolists, was his relationship with a woman named Anna Nikolaevna Schmidt. She lived in Nizhny Novgorod and did not get to know Solovyov and his philosophy until the last months of his life. Unmarried and living with her sick mother, she was believed to be an incarnation of Sophia. Schmidt had written things similar to those of Solovyov, but without ever knowing about him; e.g., her text “On the present-day life of Margarita”. She claimed to have been reborn twice on earth, first bodily and then spiritually. Solovyov and Anna Schmidt met only once, in April 1900. Schmidt sent Solovyov about thirty letters altogether, only seven of which have been preserved. Hence their correspondence cannot be compared to that between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby, which we examined here in the chapters on those two thinkers. ln the end, what can we make of Vladimir Solovyov as a pre-semiotician? To take him as such, we would have to interpret “semiotics” more broadly than linguistics-based theories would do. Mystical, “Eastern man” though he was, most of his output was Hegelian and rationalistic. Obviously he saw no conflict between his mystical doctrine of Sophia and his other philosophical constructions. Solovyov remains a part of the forgotten nineteenth-century heritage, which brought to light many ideas and issues that the twentieth-century later took as its own creations.

Chapter 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch 18.1 Introduction There is no doubt that the complex and rich phenomenon of what is called Russian formalism belongs to the very special cultural heritage of the whole international semiotic movement. This means that it is something to be remembered, to be returned to in order to understand what happened later. In fact, in the West it has undergone the same fate as other semiotic schools and groupings, namely that only individual scholars dive up, they are reprinted and even worshipped as big gurus, but then often ignoring their original context. That is what has happened most typically to Mikhail Bakhtin, for instance. Yet, when we explore deeper the history of semiotics, we notice how many of its central notions are just stemming from those years named under Russian formalism. So it is high time to show gratitude to that period, one of the most creative but also controversial of the discipline. One should, of course, not focus in such topics without competence in Russian language. Historical study of wie es eigentlich gewesen ist remains more or less superficial without the reading of original sources. Yet, it may also reflect the reception of its ideas in a new and maybe broader context. Thinking of great figures of semiotics the same happened also with French and Italian scholars in the Anglo-Saxon world. We once had a talk about Roland Barthes and how his reception started in the UK. Personally I have to admit then that my knowledge on Russian sources, albeit very important for me, has depended on various translations. In the case of Finland there might be even more justification for this approach taking into account the tiny role Finnish academic life may have exercised on Russian formalism. My report here starts therefore with these origins, in spite of possible misunderstandings and misinterpretations. So I am lead and obliged by the topics itself to establish the scholar’s position first and go back to the early 1970s. Yet, that is also the time when several Russian formalists started their triumph in the West. Now every anthology or encyclopaedia of the history of semiotics must contain a chapter on Russian formalism. However, the first problem we encounter here is how to define the phenomenon and how to distinguish it from other cultural phenomena of the period, i.e., the 1910s and 1920s. Certainly, it is one of the fascinations of the thing that it is hard to say whether it belongs to science or art. Who was then, after all, a Russian formalist?

368 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch Yet, the first time we read as young students about scholars like Propp, Šklovsky, Tynianov, Eichenbaum, Tomashevsky, Jakobson, Bakhtin was due to a Swedish anthology Form och struktur by Kurt Aspelin and Bengt A. Lundberg, (Litteraturvetenskapliga texter I urval, 1971). It contained translations of classic essays by Šklovsky on artistic devices, by Tynianov on literary evolution, and Eichenbaum on Gogol’s novel. Quite naturally the book then moved from this origin to Mukařovský, then to French structuralism, and ultimately to Yuri Lotman. You note in Finland we are bilingual, so the whole semiotics started in my country by a young student group, which called itself a ‘structuralist group’ and was unable to read French, Italian or Russian and therefore resorted also, as to Umberto Eco and his La struttura assente, to the Swedish translations Den frånvarande strukturen. After this promising beginning in Sweden, until recent years, they did not continue semiotics so energetically as in the neighbouring countries Denmark and Finland. Anyway, these classical texts fascinated us. The next time I heard about Russian formalism was in the introduction to semiotics a course offered at the Department of Folkloristics at Helsinki University by Professor Vilmos Voigt. This course for the first time told about the sources in St. Petersburg or Leningrad and Moscow and also revealed the role the Finnish folklore studies had in Propp’s theorizing. What was involved was the classification method of fairy tales and folk songs by the brothers Krohn and the primary school teacher Antti Aarne. This was first time I heard about these Finnish scholars. Five years later in Brazil where I left as a student of Lévi-Strauss, I found a book entitled Inteligência do Folclore by Renato Almeida which had, to my surprise, a whole chapter on Escola finlandesa. This source and Prof. Voigt showed how important a role these Finnish scholars played for Propp when he was writing his Morfologiya skazki. Later I used to mention this often until my colleague from Petersburg wrote me that I was wrong and that Propp elaborated his model independently. I believed in him but now this problem got back to my mind and I wrote to Prof. Voigt who again emphasized this connection. Later, it became clear that this was just the origin of a discipline called narratology, a branch of semiotics. In the 1980s when I visited and lectured at Musée de l’Homme in Paris, in the seminar by Prof. Gilbert Rouget, I could notice that the only authors the French anthropologists knew about Finland were just the dissertations by Krohn brothers, in the turn of century, once published in German. Another aspect which attracted in Russian formalism was its artistic connection. It was obviously also an artistic practice, and not only the one persecuted later in the 1930s under Ždanov time in music, in the criticism against Shostakovich, Khachaturian and Prokofiev, but an aesthetic standpoint linked to the emergence of modernism. One could link such world class artists like

18.2 Wassily Kandinsky |

369

Mayakovsky, Stravinsky and Eisenstein to it. I remember I saw sometime in 1972 at the Helsinki Festival a Russian movie from the 1920s about a young movie director in Moscow from whom a British impresario had commissioned a film on new life in Moscow. The young hero did it with his girlfriend. Then it was shown to the impresario; there were scenes of progress in Russia, children going to school, new buildings, etc. But in every montage the girlfriend was put in the foreground so that her pretty figure covered all the rest. The impresario got furious: I did not order a film of your girlfriend he shouted. No, but she was only a priem , an artistic device, the young man defended. So this was for me a proof that the vocabulary of Russian formalism had really intruded the artistic creation in those years.

18.2 Wassily Kandinsky Another figure which became familiar was Kandinsky. I could not imagine more ‘formalist’ a book as his Punkt und Linie zu Fläche, albeit written later in the 1920s. I found it in Paris as a French translation Point, Ligne et Plan. His effort to create a universal grammar of all the arts, based on correspondences of colours, forms, sounds sounded truly ‘structuralist’ but resonated also from the Scriabinesque symbolism. Later having seen an exposition of Kandinsky I read in the anthology that, in fact, Kandinsky was originally a folklorist and ethnologue who travelled among the Zyrians (syrjäänit, a Finno-Ugrian tribe), wrote about their archaic life, painted and made drawings on their figures, costumes, houses, artworks, and copied especially their abstract ornamentations. This happened in 1889 at Vologda region habited by the Zyrians. In Moscow Ethnographic Society in 1888 he had already delivered a lecture on the beliefs of Perms and Zyrians. Kandinsky was aware also of the Finno-Ugric origin of his name stemming from River Konda area and the word konda meaning ‘honka’, a fur tree in Finnish. Several specialists of art history have said that the Finno-Ugrian ornamentation was the first impulse to Kandinsky’s non-figurative art. His correspondence with A. Schönberg illuminates also his visions on the artistic form. To me all this sounded truly ‘formalist’, but in encyclopaedias in vain I try to find his name in the histories of Russian formalism. Instead, Malevich and suprematism are often mentioned alongside Jakobson. Kandinsky’s view of the form was dynamic; it was based upon inner tensions of the art work. This view then was shared in musicology by Boris Asafiev in his intonation theory which was soon in the 1970s discovered to be a pioneer of musical semiotics. The new issue in all this, compared to earlier theories, was to see the important point in the text itself neither in the mind of a genius creating the art work

370 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch

Figure 18.1: A non-figurative painting by Kandinsky from 1913, from which the emergence of Russian formalism is counted

nor at receiver’s side. So, essentially the whole epistemic movement was antipsychological by its nature. It tried to base the aesthetic analysis on the object and its structure. It was hostile to any hermeneutic program or poetry linked to arts. It was the new objective scientific spirit of exactness which was underlined. Stravinsky’s musical poetics later was characterized by the same spirit of antipsychological nature: He did not see a reflection of any psychic content in music, as he said in his lectures at Harvard. This was certainly a formalist attitude. When Boris Gasparov visited our structuralist group in Helsinki around 1973 he emphasized however that this asemantic or antisemantic approach was in fact only the minus side of the primary semantic nature of music. The same was stated by the French philosopher Vladimir Jankélévitch when speaking of Prokofiev and calling his style ‘espressivo inexpressif’. This meant that the asemanticity was a certain historic phase in style evolution and not a synchronically valid universal truth. However, Stravinsky could then be situated in the tradition of formalist aesthetics stemming in music from Eduard Hanslick in his essay Vom musikalisch Schönem (1854) and continued even by Lévi-Strauss who claimed that La musique, c’est le langage moin le sens. Morpurgo-Tagliabue in his L’Esthétique contemporaine spoke about formalism in general as a line of the 20th century aesthetics and then meaning by it a larger phenomenon than just Russian formalism. What is the relation of this type of formalism in general in the arts – and the Russian formalism –

18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music

|

371

Figure 18.2: Kandinsky’s ethnographic studies of the Zyrians (Finno-Ugrian tribe ‘syrjäänit’) around 1887

is an interesting question. Certainly the roots of Russian formalism especially in St. Petersburg lay in the modernism like symbolism and futurism. Andrei Bely with his original theories on symbols and novels. There is a nice passage in the novel The Way of Sufferings by Alexei Tolstoi portraying a salon in St. Petersburg where Scriabin is played and in the walls listeners are looked at by radically distorted futurist paintings. This was the Zeitgeist.

18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music However, if I have been much dwelling in the musical field here, this may have its legitimization in the theories of Russian formalists themselves. Namely, most of them coined their new concepts as metaphors from musical practices. I do not know if attention has been much paid upon this fact so far.

372 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch Roman Jakobson and his dominant. It is one of the most central notions of formalist theory, it is defined as the integrating factor of an art work, which leads, determines, and transforms other components of the work. It could be a principle within the art work, a system of rhyme, or it could appear in the canon of poetic norms of certain literary trend. For instance in renaissance period pictural arts were dominating others. In romanticism it was music which was central. It had its impact on the evolution of genres when the emphasis or dominant was shifted from one genre to another. Šklovsky and estrangement. The concept of estrangement was not just of musical origin although Verfremdung was central idea of Bertolt Brecht and in the music at his ‘epic theater’ from the same years. The alienation as an artistic device was strong in a novel like Master and Marguerite by Bulgakov. Alienation as breaking the automatisms became essential in the semiotic aesthetics of Umberto Eco, as well. I wrote in 1972 some lines about estrangement as an artistic device in my note book: “The concept of estrangement in the arts is very essential. What is then involved is the variation of the distance between man and aesthetic reality. The ability of an artist to move us, to have an impact on us, is just based upon these consciously planned judgements and control of this distance. There are art works which do not longer make any effect because they are too close to that reality from which they are stemming. The tendence art emanating from an actual political situation is just like that. Yet, to the same class belongs also the art which operates on a purely psychological and individual level – great books of ‘confession’ which mostly make the same impression on audience as a person penetrating to our company by force. Aesthetic reality exists as such appearing a.o. in art works. Nevertheless, what is the relationship of man to this reality? Does the man himself still live in this reality, or only at it, on the borderline of it, or then so far, at such distance that there is no longer any touch. On the other hand, how this law of distance, which rules over the experiential semantic conception of art, looms already in the semantic structure of an art work as its crucial variable. Then it can be paralleled to intensity. The intensity of a work varies according to at which distance the creator of an art work situates the recipient, which ‘position’ he/she is forced to assume. This holds true for ‘old art’. Contemporary art (painting, literature, atonal music) allows to the receiver of art a creative freedom just on this self-estrangement dimension. As in a microscope one gets always new miracles visible, in the same way an art work reveals from its hidden parts many kinds of structures. Previous structure disappears when a new enlargement foregrounds a new one. Such is in fact analysis of art, a kind of microscopic study. Two aesthetics which scrutinize the same object, art work through different enlargements, see there different issues and also talk about different things.”

This was in the 1970s, but now we note how Adorno spoke in his aesthetics exactly in similar manner of distance in the arts (then I did not know yet his theory). Yet, in the contemporary art it is not difficult to find other illustrations for estrangements which has its permanent place in the avant-garde technics. Let

18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music |

373

us quickly look at opera stagings and videos, one fashionable, almost unavoidable genre mixture of contemporary stagings, one variant of that Regietheater in which the stage director builds his own work upon the original. I know no case in which video and film would have been successfully mixed with the performance of opera. Of these two genres certainly authentic opera performance is stronger than its filmed version. If you were asked whether you like to see La Scala or Metropolitan or Mariinsky ‘real’ version of an opera, or its filmed one , I think most would choose the real one. Yet, the filmed opera has become its own genre which was first separated from the original. So one could go to movies to Bergman’s Magic Flute or Zeffirelli’s Don Giovanni. In film in a case like The Umbrelllas of Cherbourg the singing serves as a particular estrangement technics. But then the video penetrates inside the opera, as a kind of representation of representation (theater is of course always that as Ivo Osolsobě once said!). Can video then serve as an ‘ostranenie’? Yes, to some extent and at the beginning. By its force it definitely wins over the stage performance, singers are put in the background. Let us think of Harry Kupfer’s Parsifal and its Blumenmädchen scene with slightly pornographic films replacing the real quire on stage (Wolfgang Wagner with whom I saw it once in Helsinki, did not like it). But when it becomes mannerism it fails. Peter Sellars’s version of Tristan with continuous video films with other actors than the real singers completely draws the attention from them and destroys live performance. In Andriy Zholdak’s radical version of Yevgeny Onegin (Savonlinna Festival, July 2013), the video takes 2/3 of the stage, and the opera appears there as an almost ‘normal’ staging. Yet, one third of stage is in real action with same singers as on video, but grotesquely distorted representing obviously the Tchaikovskyan subconscious, i.e., making visible what actors really think of all. So Olga and Tatyana are modern teenage girls, kissing each other, Jevgeni occurs always as an animally erotic object in a 19th century swimming dress, etc. Screen is also one second belated from the real performance, all the time. Estrangement has reached an extreme point. Yet, video loses its power totally when the singers video film each other and see themselves as represented by it. This new mannerism putting singers standing there with a camera or mobile phone with Facebook all the time at hand is no longer estrangement but the contrary: if the original idea was to break the automatism of everyday life, now it brings the stage reality back to our daily experiences. Distance between stage and spectators shrinks, and all this at the cost of finer subtleties and real meanings of the composer, music, singers, orchestra and all. The stage has become a narcissist reflection of the modern spectator, the popular commercial mass media culture with all forms of the symbolic violence which has intruded into art. Why should we go to opera to see there only the perpetual continuation of the everyday life?

374 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch Opera is no longer getting us familiar with the knowledge of the Other. All belongs to the Same. This is the end of the ostranenie. Mikhail Bakhtin and his idea on Dostoevsky’s ‘polyphony of consciousnesses’; Bakhtin says that Dostoevsky as a writer is distinguished by a particular ability to perceive simultaneous, contradictory, conflicting elements, not continuous developments like Goethe but like a five part fugue in which parts alternate and develop in a counterpoint and harmony, this is the particular voice-leading technique of Dostoevsky. Bakhtin quotes Grossman who speaks of modulation at Dostoevsky. (Later also Greimas and Fontanille speak in their semiotics of modulations of passions!) Mikhail Glinka is also quoted when he said: All in life is counterpoint – and this Bakhtin interprets that all in life is dialogue, based on dialogical opposition. In fact, even musical counterpoint is then an application of the dialogical principle (I tried to show the same three years ago in my speech on Dialogical Self at Cambridge University, organized by a research group of psychotherapists and psychologists using Bakhtin as their foundation; you only need to play some fugues of Bach and show how he puts subject and response into a dramatic conflict [like in F sharp major fugue of Das Wohltemperierte Klavier I] and lets at the end the response ‘win’ the main subject!). Then nothing is more avoidable than monologue, one speaking subject. (This I noticed concretely in the aforementioned congress when one morning I went early to the breakfast room in order to enjoy it just alone and peacefully. Having chosen the utmost corner of the hall, quickly people started to gather around me with their lively talk; later I noticed they were all Bakhtinian psychotherapists who thought I was an alienated person who needed dialogue – although that was just what I wanted to escape!) Yuri Tynianov and his ‘orchestration of poetry’, this means a poet says things due to phonetics letting the innovations on this level hurt against the semantics. If I utter you in Finnish a verse: Porkkanan oranssi sokaisi, you receive it as a phonetic ‘music’ by the mere sounds of the vowels. But its meaning is nonsensical: ‘The orange of a carrot blinded one’. Tynianov had as well reflections on genre which hold true as well for music as for literature. His essential idea is how we recognize a genre, how we identify it. To which extent poem is a poem and now some other text. If I say Il pleut à Paris it is a statement. But if I continue Il pleure dans mon cœur, it is poetry by Verlaine, following Klinkenberg). If I say: Put the tiger in tank, it is certainly advertisement, but of course could be a part of collage poetry. If I say Wer nur die Sehnsucht kennt, weiß was ich leide or Kennst du das Land wo die Zitronen blühn, they are obviously poems by the mere order of the words. What Tynianov wrote about genre shifts, changes, dissolutions is close to Asafiev, namely what he said at the same time of musical genres and their development. Yet, Asafiev was even more semiotic since for him the signified was primary. When the emotional content changed it

18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music

|

375

needed new musical signifiers, and this caused the so-called ‘intonation crisis’. On the other hand, later formalists, in Prague circle days, stated that the relationship between changing society and arts was not a causal one but symbolic, sign relationship, and this was of course against the official Widerspiegelung theory. Žirmunsky and his treatise on metrics and versification; my hypothesis was that Igor Stravinsky in his Oedipus Rex applied Žirmunskian ideas to the musical versification of Latin language chosen by the composer because it could be tested as pure phonetic material devoid of semantic connotations. I thought that this was possible for Stravinsky only after his emigration in his neoclassical period (Tarasti 1979). Of Žirmunsky as such we know his efforts for a comparative typology; his bioand bibliography were published in 1962 (140 pages), his Festschrift in 1964 on the problem of comparative philology, and among his own books studies on Goethe in Russia, Central Asian Epos, Theoretical Problems of National Epos (on the origin of Kalevala, a view criticizing Krohn). Žirmunsky also wrote about limitations of formalism in the 1920s even before it was officially abolished by Ždanov visit to Leningrad University in 1947. Yet in Moscow slavist congress the comparative study was rehabilitated. Žirmunsky was at the end of 1950s against phonology, although he studied it himself; and in the beginning of 1960s against structuralism, albeit he used it much himself in his metric interpretations (for this information I am indebted to Vilmos Voigt). Boris Tomashevsky and several concepts in his essay “The Structure of Plot” (which I have read as Finnish translation in the anthology Venäläinen formalismi, edited by Pekka Pesonen and Timo Suni) Tomashevsky presents a systematic vocabulary to study narratives launching concepts like theme, fabula, subject, tension, motif, exposition, time, space, kinetic space, estrangement (ostranenie), canonic and free devices, parodies . . . all these notions are relevant also for music and, say, for musical narrativity. Yet, when transplanting them back to musical field one has to be careful since many of them are defined and used somehow differently when applied to music, like the first one: ‘theme’. In a novel theme is the basic issue, what the story is all about, like The Last Days of Pompeii, love story of Anna and Vronsky, society of learned men in Hesse, development of one young man like in Goethe’s Wilhelm Meister. However, in music theme is a particular unit of musical discourse, in tonal music characterized by certain length, clearcut harmonic basis, clearly melodic formula, etc. In fact, I already sketched an essay in which Tomashevsky’s approach was ‘musicalized’ and another one in which completely traditional music theoretical study of symphony or sonata by such composer like J. Brahms will be semiotized showing his narrative structure; this will concern a perfectly absolute music without any programs. I was inspired by a study on Brahms symphonies by

376 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch my colleague Erkki Salmenhaara from 1978 which I studied for my speeches at the Mariinsky Summer Festival led by Valery Gergiev in Finland, having several Brahms symphonies in their program! In Salmenhaara’s view all the Viennese classical symphonic music (i.e., symphonies, sonatas, string quartets and other chamber music pieces with larger forms) could be classified as to the key architecture with the following diagram. There were only a few basic types which were used by great composers. Most common was the tonic type (in major indicated by T and in minor t) The most common is the use of subdominant in the side movement, type is TS. Also very common is tonic-dominant-tonic. Both these types constitute the major symphony type. In minor they are rare, and as known in the minor as a contrasting tonality serves most often the parallel major type tP; next big group is formed by key relations which Salmenhaara calls modal parallel, i.e., in major the major side key situated at the distance of major or minor third (both upwards and downwards). Theoretical possibilities are thus if the key is C major in this TPm type as follows: C A C, C as C, C E C, C es C. Also modal minor parallels of type Tpm appear, but more seldom. In minor a modal parallel solution (parallel key being almost always major of type: tPm is as common as parallel major). I wanted to cite this because in that scheme we have in musical terms something similar to Tomashevsky’s classification of the narrative technics or Vladimir Propp’s study on the morphology of the folktale. Here we only talk about symphonies and sonatas instead of novels or fairy tales. The key distinctions are not only abstract spatial relations in the inner tonal space but they are already semantically loaded. Even the choice of a key is not at all arbitrary. Let us say: anyone writing in E flat major after Beethoven Eroica must face the heroic character of this key. Everyone writing in F major must remember its pastoral quality (Beethoven’s Sixth “Pastoral” Symphony in F major), anyone using D minor must recall Mozart’s Don Giovanni and D Minor Piano Concerto. So the historic character of a key could be created by one single work. In the time of Russian formalism also the synaesthesic meanings of keys were discussed by artists: Kandinsky portrayed different angles with various colors, Rimsky-Korsakov and Scriabin had their diagrams of correspondences of keys and colors. Individual composers thought of keys in terms of colours. For Sibelius the combination of orange, red and black was D major. Anyway, the classification evokes the idea of the basic theme of each story, whether it goes from ‘sad’ minor to ‘victorious’ major, whether it starts and ends happily but has excursion (shifting off, débrayages!) into darker fields. The global plan of a work is just its symphonic structure strengthened by thematic (actorial) and motivic elements on more superficial levels of the work. However, just as Propp came to 31 basic functions of Russian fairy tale here we can see 58 types of symphonic literature. Just as a fairy tale teller can choose from the ideal repertoire

18.3 Its key concepts are metaphors from music

Type T CC CCC CCCC CcC CcCC CCcC Type TS CFC CFCC CCFC CFcC CFCc Type TD CGC CGCC CCGC CGCc Type Tp CaC CaCC CCaC CacC Type TPm CAC CCAC CA#CC CgC CCA#C CcA#C CA#C CEC

|

377

Type TSp CFaC Type t aA aAa aaAa aAaa Type tP aCa aCaa aCA aCaA aCAa Type tPm aFa aFaa aFaA aaFA aaFaA aFaa aFAa aCa Exceptional types CcE#AFC aAF(D)Aa(A) aB(g)FCea

Type Tpm CeC CCgC Type N CCC

Figure 18.3: Key relationships in Viennese-classical symphonies according to Salmenhaara 1979: 26

378 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch what he wants to foreground similarly a composer has here a repertoire of basic tonal types of the plot of the work. Analogies between story telling in a novel and symphony continue when we pass further in the study and examine more figurative expressions in both fields. In any case one has to note if one builds one’s narrative theory of art, say music or literature, that Propp’s model concerns popular culture, whereas novel or symphony is art, so they are on different levels, and this may limit Propp’s application to aesthetics of 19th or 20th century. Proppian models function certainly again well in the popular culture of our oral age. Altogether, this might even lead us to think of the birth of Russian formalism aus dem Geiste der Musik like Nietzsche about tragedy.

18.4 Lev Karsavin (1892–1952) One name which above sounded perhaps strange in this collection was Karsavin. Certainly he is among those scholars well known in Russia but totally ignored in the West. I heard about him rather recently in connection to the Lithuanian philosopher and aesthetician Wilhelm Sesemann, who had invited this Russian intellectual from Russia to Kaunas University in the 1930s. Unfortunately, these two extremely important scholars remained there after the occupation of Lithuania and did not emigrate early enough, so they shared the destiny of being sent to Siberia, where Karsavin died in 1952. Sesemann, however, survived and returned as rehabilitated to Kaunas, where he lived until 1962. About Karsavin and his last writing we have the beautiful French translation Le poème de la mort (Éditions L’Âge d’Homme, 2003). Particularly its postface contained valuable information for me. Entitled Une philosophie de la dépossession, it shows how Karsavin in that extreme existential situation could create a most fascinating concept of omnitemporality, something like Marcel Proust, a notion I am using in my own existential semiotics nowadays. But, why I want to raise these two names just in this context of Russian formalism, although neither of them is directly mentioned in any Western encyclopaedia of semiotics as Russian formalists, is due to their important position of mediating formalist ideas to other scholars who became influential in the semiotic field. How many know that Sesemann was the logic teacher of A. J. Greimas at Kaunas University, where he attended his course in 1934 as his study book clearly shows? How many know that Greimas, the founder of the Paris school of semiotics, said later that it was from Karsavin he realized that the Lithuanian language could be used as a scientific discourse? This Russian scholar had namely learned Lithuanian so fully that he could write and publish using it. Certainly even less known is that the first Finnish semiotician is the celebrated nephew of Sesemann,

18.4 Lev Karsavin (1892–1952) |

Figure 18.4: Greimas’s study book at the University of Kaunas in 1934 (from the archives of Rimtautas Kašponis, reproduced by permission).

379

380 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch Finnish poet Henry Parland, who in the 1920s wrote cultural essays inspired by Russian formalists like Žirmunsky, on Russian and American movies, on the Jewish Theatre of Kaunas, etc., which when now read look like ‘Roland Barthes before Roland Barthes’. However, this young man passed away at 22 years old in Kaunas at his uncle Sesemann’s residence, where he had been sent by his parents to avoid the temptations of Bohemian artists in the restaurants of Helsinki. Henry had got his ideas via his uncle, whose treatise on aesthetics which appeared in Lithuanian in the 1960s Žirmunsky had provided a preface for. (Later I had correspondence with my teacher Greimas about a possible English translation of this important study, but as far as I know it has not even yet been realized.) And Sesemann was a half Finn. An honorary member of the Finnish Semiotic Society, psychiatrist Oscar Parland (1991) has studied the life of his brother and uncle, and a monograph on Sesemann has also been published recently by the German scholar Thorsten Botz-Bornstein fairly recently (2006). Anyway, now we have entered this very fascinating but chaotic area of the emergence of Russian formalism. The linguist teacher of Roman Jakobson Prince Trubetskoy as known had written about his ideas of the Turanian language which followed the principles of phonetic harmony. Behind this was the idea that the

Figure 18.5: Henry Parland, the first Finnish semiotician, in Kaunas in 1930, half a year before his passing away

18.4 Lev Karsavin (1892–1952) |

381

essential Russian character was in its ethnicity in pre-Slavic prehistory best reflected in the phonology of the Turkic languages of Central Asia. Trubetskoy derived a theory of national psychology from phonological data, which, according to the American scholar Richard Taruskin, was ‘breathtakingly virtuosic’ (1997: 395) These phonological principles and laws manifested in the use of different types of vowels: if the first syllable contained one of the back vowels a, o, i, u, then all the other syllables of that word must contain one of these back vowels. If the first syllable contains one of the front vowels ä, ö, i, y, then the other syllables must contain one of these vowels. A mixture of back and front vowels in a single word was not allowed – like in the Estonian word ‘aitä’ (thanks!) In some Turkic languages similar laws also regulate the use of consonants like k, g, and l. Some consonants are allowed only in back-voweled words, whereas some like d, b, g, j, z, and zh are allowed only between vowels. The same harmoniousness and pedantic observance of uniform law was also noticeable in the grammar of the Turkic languages. Then Trubetskoy drew his conclusion also as to the character of Turks: they love symmetry, clarity, stable equilibrium. Once it was obtained he wanted to preserve it as a universal system. Moreover, he said that this is a characteristic of all Turanians, including Eurasian Russians. Turanian psyche imparts cultural stability and strength to the nation, affirms cultural and historical continuity. All that is best was due to this primal Turanian character among Russians; all that is worst was the fault of Peter the Great, who brought the disastrous Romano-Germanic toxins. Trubetskoy’s fantastic visions were particular because he based his neoprimitivist thinking as emanating from, so to say, ‘modern’ empirical science, i.e., linguistics. Taruskin thinks that this worldview and Eurasian ideology explains also such a work in Stravinsky as Svadebka, also known as Les Noces, a musical portrayal of Russian wedding ceremonies. Yet, from Trubetskoy Lev Karsavin developed the Eurasian ideology even further, referring to Turanian character as a higher symphonic personality or ‘symphonic subject’. Karsavin wrote: “A symphonic subject is not an agglomeration or simply the sum of individual subjects but rather their concord (symphony) the coordination of the one and many and – in the ideal and at the limit, the all-inone.” Accordingly, a nation is not only a sum of social groups but their organized and coordinated hierarchical unity. The culture of a nation is no mere sum but a symphonic unity of more local cultures. Similarly, national cultures can constitute a larger cultural unity, e.g., Hellenistic, European, Eurasian. Thus the higher symphonic personality lives in a kind of pleroma as Taruskin defines it, i.e., the state of renouncing the I of the lower or smaller sphere for the sake of the higher. Karsavin uses here a musical metaphor, comparing the individuum to a single voice, the carrier of a cantus firmus, within the vast polyphonic texture of the total-unity, the

382 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch pleroma (Taruskin 1997: 404). This idea is not only close to Scriabin – the sister of Karsavin was the famous ballerina Tamara Karsavina, so he lived amidst musical circles – but also to Vladimir Solovyov and his ideas of Russian culture. Yet, Solovyov disagreed completely with the idea of a specific mystic Russian Eastern character, all that is good in Russia came from Europe; he says in his essay “Über die russische Frage” that there is no question of whether Russia exists, but the problem is whether it exists with dignity, forgetting its national egoism. So he came to the same conclusion as Karsavin, yet by other routes. What are we to think of all that, and what does this have to do with Russian formalism? At least the idea that one art work like Les Noces was only a sign or symbol of a certain ideological movement, like Taruskin saw it, is anti-formalist. Since the emergence of linguistics we have known that a new articulation can take place in every level of generation of meaning. So an art work never exhausts its potential of signification to any background philosophy. To put it as simply as Beethoven once: Music is higher form than any philosophy.

18.5 Wilhelm Sesemann I have written a small essay earlier about Karsavin’s colleague who tempted him to Kaunas, Wilhelm (Vasily or Vasilius) Sesemann. The young German scholar Thorsten Botz-Bornstein has also written about Sesemann. The nephew of Sesemann Oscar Parland gave me copies of some books by Sesemann published in German. The most important point I could find there is that meaning was always something ungegenständlich, immaterial, so to study it empirically is very hard. In fact, in Greimas and his notion of isotopy we find the same argument – although isotopies could be said to consist of recurrent classemes – and the semiosphere by TartuMoscow school, or to put it like the American semiotician John Deely: sign is never a thing, it is an object. Botz-Bornstein, moreover, has discovered that for Sesemann the meaning was neither totally subjective, i.e. to be studied as the state of human mind, nor completely objective, i.e., existing in a text, but living between them, in a form he saw to possess a certain rhythm. Sesemann was influenced by Russian formalism, but his view on the form was rather dynamic, almost kinetic. The place where he put it between the subjective and objective comes close to Greimas’s concept of le monde naturel, which was not at all anything natural but something already semiotized by the human mind. As said, Žirmunsky was Sesemann’s close friend. The Lithuanian scholar Rimtautas Kašponis has studied the youth of Greimas and discovered a lot of things. However, Sesemann also criticizes Russian formalists; his view of struc-

18.5 Wilhelm Sesemann |

383

Figure 18.6: Sesemann in 1912

ture was that it was inner rhythm which constituted the true aesthetic moment. This was close to Lossky’s notion of the organic whole or neo-Kantian efforts to dynamize static logical systems. Elsewhere, however, Sesemann emphasized the two forms of knowledge: kennen and wissen, of which the first one was more important. Not the notion of ‘device’ priem from Šklovsky was the true essence of an art work. In his study Iskusstvo i kul’tura (which, by the way, appeared in 1927, the same year as Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit), Sesemann said of it: “The notion of device as used by the school of the Formalists which is for them a substitute for form in spite of all the methodological convenience it offers it cannot be considered sound from a philosophical point of view. Form understood only as a device of artistic expression takes in a subjective-intentional character and seems to exist without any relation to the material itself” (quoted from BotzBornstein 2006: 41). Yet, elsewhere he said: “Formalists are absolutely right in insisting that poetics should above all flow out of linguistics.” But Sesemann’s ‘formalism’ is an aesthetic one” (ibid.: 41), but it is true that he was a philosopher and aesthetician in the first place and moved on to another level of abstraction than more concretely thinking formalist scholars.

384 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch Next I try to take some cases of how the ideas of Russia formalism were later received and how they exercised their impact on subsequent semiotics. Let me call it like Thomas Sebeok ‘global semiotics’.

18.6 Vladimir Propp Certainly then the name which first dives up is Vladimir Propp. The innovation made in Morfologiya skazki as early as in 1928 is decisive. Now we can only ponder from which kind of network of ideas it emerged in order to understand its fecundity. The basic realization of Propp when dealing with Russian fairy tales was that elements of one tale could be transferred to another tale without any change. For instance Baba Yaga can appear in most diverse fairy tales and plots. The very notion of plot is defined as follows: one chooses at random one part of a tale, and provides it with word ‘about’ and then definition is ready: for instance tale containing a dragon fight is of type: fairy tale about fight with a dragon. Propp found all other classifications earlier unsuccessful. For Veselovsky plot consisted of several motifs, a motif develops into a section. Plot is a theme which consists of various situations. For him motif is primary, plot is secondary. But Propp thought that we have to first segment a tale, only thereafter can we make comparisons. All questions in the study of tales lead to that so far unresolved problem that why all fairy tale in the world remind of each other. How can we explain that a tale about frog queen is so similar in Russia, Germany, France, India, America and New Zeeland. As known for Propp the basic unit of tale was ‘a function’. So Propp formulated his hypotheses : 1) Functions are stable units of fairy tales, independent of who fulfils them or how dramatis personae realize them; 2) number of functions is limited; 3) the order of functions, their sequence is identical; 4) all fairy tales belong to the same genre. However functions do not follow immediately each other. When different persons pursue consecutively functions, the latter person has to know all what happened before he can enter. (How well this is a realized in a Wagnerian myth opera, Wagner whom Lévi-Strauss considered the first structural analyst of a myth!). Propp’s functions: absence interdiction violation reconnaissance delivery fraud complicity

18.6 Vladimir Propp |

385

villainy lack mediation, the connective moment beginning counter action departure the first function of the donor the hero’s reaction the provision, receipt of magical agent spatial translocation struggle marking victory the initial misfortune or lack is liquidated return pursuit,chase rescue unrecognized arrival the difficult task solution: a task is accomplished recognition exposure transfiguration: new appearance punishment wedding (quoted from Greimas 1966: 193–194)

The core of Propp’s heritage is certainly here, since later narratology most eagerly adopted the idea of segmentation into basic units, functions. Later they could be called differently like ‘narrative programs’ . . . and ‘later’ means the time after translation of Propp’s seminal work into American (1958) and French (1965). To what extent did Propp use the Finnish school of folkloristics for his achievement? Vilmos Voigt answered to my request by a letter: In Russia N. P. Andrejev appeared in the Folkore Fellows series, in which his two books have been published. I do not know where is his correspondence with Kaarle Krohn and Antti Aarne. Andrejev was a professor at St. Petersburg University, an old fashioned fairy tale type scholar. Probably he was the first who thought that one should make a catalogue of Russian folktale types. The Russkoe geograficheskoe obshchestvo (whose director was the famous orientalist Duke S. F. Oldenburg) founded a skazochnaja committee, a research committee for folk tales. It invited Propp to make a catalogue of fairy tale types. Propp got a grant but soon thought that Aarne’s system was outdated and when he had read through Afanasjev’s classical fairy tale collection, he realized that many fairy tales followed the same structure. This was the birth of Propp’s morphology. He wrote his own book three times. First it was a narrative story, what was really no morphology at all. Committee did not accept that writing. Then following V. M. Žirmunsky’s advice Propp wrote a short text with only schemes and diagrams. It was almost incomprehensible. Then emerged the well-known last version,

386 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch which was published in the book series of Russian literature and its morphology. Editor was again Žirmunsky. After the Second World War, they published Afanasjev’s three-part fairytale collection which has at its end the catalogue of fairytale types, following Aarne-Thompson in 1928, about 100 printed pages, and the writer was Propp. If we compare Aarne-Thompson type stores and Propp’s morphological diagrams, the division of texts is similar: but purpose was different. Accordingly Propp knew since the beginning how was the ‘Finnish’ analysis of fairy tale types, and he twice wrote such a catalogue – yet his own method of morphology was different. By the way, this background has been portrayed sufficiently in the dictionary of Enzyklopedie des Märchens. . . . This Encyclopedia has entries for Propp, Andrejev, Morphologie etc. In the 1960s the Russian folklorists like K. V. Chistov have underlined that Propp “was a deeply Soviet great scholar”, whereas the Westen folklorists and Isidor Levin expressed the opinion that the context of Propp’s life work was international. The rebirth of Propp’s Morphology was the idea of Roman Jakobson and the first English version appeared thanks to Thomas A. Sebeok. (Email letter from Voigt to the author in July 2013.)

Lévi-Strauss published his comments on Propp in his essay in Cahiers de l’Institut de science économique appliqué no 9, mars 1960 entitled “L’analyse morphologique des contes russes” and simultaneously in English in International Journal of Slavic Linguistics and Poetics 3, 1960. He starts it by saying that those exercising structural analysis have been often accused of formalism. This means that form is determined by its opposition to the matter which is alien to it. Whereas structure does not have any separate contents: it is the content put in a logical organization, which is conceived as a property of the real” (Lévi-Strauss 1973: 139). Lévi-Strauss praises the translators of Propp’s work who have done an immense service to the human sciences by their work. Lévi-Strauss then comments Propp and admits that his criticism of previous scholars is justified (Miller, Wundt, Aarne, Veselovsky): problem is that one can always find tales which belong at the same time to several categories because classification is based upon types of tale or themes which they enact. The distinction of theme again is arbitrary. The classification of Aarne provided an inventory of themes which is of big help but the segmentation is purely empirical, although belonging of one tale to one category is always approximate. As to Propp’s chain of functions Lévi-Strauss rather recommends to replace the linear line of Proppian functions ABCD . . . MNH . . . TUVWX by an algebraic matrix because very often one function is negation or conversion of another, say ‘departure’ and ‘return’ or ‘prohibition’ and ‘violation’ and so the story teller rather picks up his elements from a mathematical matrix like: w −w 1/w 1−w

−x 1/x 1−x x

1/y 1−y y −y

1−z z −z 1/z

18.6 Vladimir Propp

| 387

When Lévi-Strauss published this no one would believe that there would be a reaction on Propp’s side. No one could think that a scholar having published in 1928 would be still alive. However, Propp responded and thought that Lévi-Strauss had attacked him, and so he felt insulted. Lévi-Strauss in turn wrote a postscript in which he said that this had not been his purpose at all (this was published in the Italian version of Propp’s work Morfologia della fiaba. Torino: Einaudi, 1966). He stated that to his eyes the Propp’s work kept its imperishable value because it was the first in the line. Propp’s work was indeed celebrated by the structuralist movement by and large. For Greimas it was one of the starting points for his school and he launched the discussion in his Sémantique structurale in 1966. He paid attention like LéviStrauss that the list of Propp could be made more economic and as to actant and actors doing the functions one could distinguish what he called mythical actants model with six members: subject, object, sender, receiver, helper, and opponent. Nevertheless, the concept of an actant appears in his book much earlier than he speaks about Propp in the chapter À la recherche des modèles de transformation (Greimas 1969: 192). Also Greimas tries to reduce the number of functions. Yet, the History of Structuralism by François Dosse mentions Russian formalism rather passingly and only when it has impact on French structuralism. However, when Propp’s book appeared at Seuil in 1965 it became the source of inspiration for the whole structuralist movement. It had appeared in English in 1958 thanks to the initiative of Jakobson and effort of Thomas A. Sebeok, yet Lévi-Strauss had discovered it as early as 1960. Not only Greimas tried to improve Propp but also Claude Brémond in his Logique du récit tried to show that the functions were always following three phases: first there was a possibility for an action, i.e., virtuality, then one could choose either passage to act or not passage to act, and if positively, then achievement or non-achievement. Nevertheless, even this idea has been anticipated by Boris Asafiev in his intonation theory speaking about musical form as a process and stating that all music was based upon three phases: initium, motus and terminus, like in tonal music tonic, dominant and tonic – which could again serve as a new initium for next phase (like in Wagner’s opera as a Kunst des Überganges, where as the terminus serves a diminished seventh harmony from which the musical wave can go to any direction whatsoever). But there were also other scholars working further with Proppian model. If Lévi-Strauss had changed his linear change into an achronic matrix, this was elaborated further by Elli-Kaija Köngäs-Maranda and Pierre Maranda in their article on “Structural Models in Folklore” appeared in Midwest Folklore (Fall 1962). They list earlier studies on structure in folklore as Propp’s Morphology and Lévi-Strauss, Sebeok and Alan Dundes. The primary goal of all of them was to find out the

388 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch smallest operational units of structure. Aarne proposed it as ‘type’ 1910, Propp as ‘function’ in 1928; they were both content units without operational value. Then Thompson proposed motif in 1932 and Lévi-Strauss ‘mytheme’ in 1955 (study on Oedipus myth). The latter was a contentual structural unit consisting of a relation between subject and predicate. Ultimately, Dundes proposed in 1962 a motifeme, which was an act of a protagonist, taking into account its meaning in the whole fairy tale. Yet, for Kongas-Maranda the crucial problem was to find the opposed pairs and the mediator between them. This could be put in the simple formula A : B :: B : C. Lévi-Strauss’s scheme fx(a) : fy(b) :: fx(b) : fa−1(y) had to be understood as a formulation of the mediating process. Then Kongas-Maranda were able to portray different types of mediation. Starting from the analysis of a tsheremiss story by Thomas A. Sebeok, these were zero-mediator, unsuccessful mediator and successful mediator. When the structuralist fashion lost its attractiveness, what remained was the narratology, which could still consider Propp as its pioneer. Especially almost all canonical analyses of stories start with segmentation. For instance even in musical narratology this functions, like I have tried to show in my study of the G minor Ballade of Chopin with its modal grammar (Tarasti 1994). But it is as Ugo Volli has said about such use of Propp, that since Propp various authors have tried to extend the morphology to other narrative genres, like myth, legend, popular literature, and modern novel. But in order to do so it is necessary that analysis is brought upon a higher level of abstraction (Manuale di semiotica, Volli 2000: 111). It is hard to imagine any other type of systematic narrative study than just stemming from Proppian ‘functions’.

18.7 Mikhail Bakhtin Yet, there is another Russian formalist classic who became very influential in the West in the 1980s. This was Mikhail Bakhtin. His profound ideas on own/alien speech, dialogical imagination, polyphonic discourse in literature, ideologemes, and carnivalist culture had a major impact on Western intelligentsia. When now rereading Bakhtin this seems still to be quite evident. The originality of Bakhtin’s thought is still quite obvious when one returns to his own writings. As the background of many of his ideas, dialogism, etc. can be seen the culture of public disputes after revolution to which Bakhtin attended when he escaped from St. Petersburg to Nääveli. There local communists arranged public discussions or disputes on various general themes, such as Does God exist. Bakhtin was active according to the reviews in local newspapers, investigated by Prof. Erkki Peuranen, Jyväskylä University. Bakhtin even cried in one of them

18.7 Mikhail Bakhtin | 389

when he defended the God against the Marxist idea that he was mere invention of priests to maintain their power. These events may be interpreted as kernels to his later ideas on dialogue – and also of ideologeme, i.e., that there are now concepts, ideas, ideologies as such but only as enunciated by someone in a communication, i.e., dialogue with others. Later he tried to prove this by his example from literature, like Dostoevsky. Yet anyone who has written novels understands that the richness of a literary text is based upon the fact that writer does not only declare something but portrays in which situation, in which sense, in which manner, to whom the idea is propagated. Winfried Nöth in his Handbuch der Semiotik (2000: 95–97) emphasizes the undefinite, undetermined and continuous nature of signification in Bakhtin. He quotes from 1929: “Nothing is definite. The last word of the world and about the world was not yet announced. The world is open and free. All is in future and will also remain in future”. This way of thinking of meaning as a continuous process is related to Lévinas’s philosophy of unfinite, and also to the existential semiotics. In all these basic epistemic models the subject is going towards an unknown undetermined reality, X, may it be called Other or anything else. Augusto Ponzio has in his semiophilosophy and semioethics together with Susan Petrilli taken Bakhtin as one of his precursors. Ponzio tries to analyse the present globalized reality in Bakhtinian terms and also the life in the European Union. He sees Bakhtin as a philosopher and not only as literary theoretician (for instance Ponzio 1993: 107–138 and Petrilli & Ponzio 1999: 305–320). In fact Ponzio says “We take ‘our’ words, says Bakhtin, from the mouth of others. “Our” words are always semi-other. They are pregnant with the intentions of others before we use them ourselves as the materials and instruments of our own intentions. Consequently . . . our discourses and thoughts are inevitably dialogic . . . ” Yet, in the West it was perhaps Julia Kristeva who first introduced ideas of Bakhtin. She noted as early as in 1966 in her essay Le Mot, le Dialogue et le Roman, that what is involved is a ‘cosmogony’ in which ‘on ne connait pas la substance, la cause, l’identité en dehors du rapport avec le tout qui n’existe que dans et par la relation’ (op. cit.: 160). She speaks of Bakhtin’s intertextuality in ‘two texts which join, they contradict and relativize. The one who attends carnival is at the same time actor and spectator. She distinguishes epic literature which is monologistic from a dialogical one. In fact, we can notice like Kristeva the following cases: a) subject of utterance, enunciate coincides with the zero value of subject of enunciation: ‘he’ or proper name, The most simple narrative technique which gives birth to a story; b) it coincides the subject of enunciate with subject of enunciation: ‘me’. ‘I’; c) coincidence of subject of enunciate with the destinator: ‘you’; d) coincidence of subject of enunciation at the same time with subject of enunciation and destin-

390 | 18 Russian formalism in the global semiotics – Precursor of the European branch ator. Novel becomes a play with writing and tagging the dialogical nature of the book. Kristeva ends up with a scheme portraying these cases: Practice ‘Discourse’ Dialogism Correlational logics Syntagma Carnaval Ambivalence; Menippea;

God ‘History’ Monologism Aristotelian logics System Narrative Polyphonic novel.

If the word is the minimal unit in Bakhtin’s theory, there can be found two types: own word and alien word. Authoritarian word comes from the exterior and demands to be accepted, it penetrates into us independently whether we find it innerly convincing. The distinction between own and alien is very important in Bakhtin. We may think this coincides with existential semiotics and its categories of Moi/Soi. According to Bakhtin, the resistance to the alien, external world is of highest importance to the development of individual ideology and identity. The whole process of learning and education is after all: how the alien becomes own. How it is made into something ‘own’. Yet, surprising was in quite recent years the emergence of a special cultural psychological theory from Bakhtin’s ideas and their application to psychotherapy and cognitive and neurological brain studies. Hubert Hermans has created a theory of dialogical self entirely on Bakhtinian basis. He writes: “Dialogical self is inspired by both James’ 1890 classic distinction between I and me and Bakhtinian metaphor of the polyphonic novel. According to this theory ‘The I’ fluctuates among different and even opposed positions, and has the capacity imaginatively to endow each position with a voice so that dialogical relations between positions can be established . . . Self and society both function as a polyphony of consonant and dissonant voices.” These ideas lead Hermans to observation of two kinds of positions: one as intersubjective interchange and the other as dominance or social power. The one may ask how dialogical the brain is and scrutinize dysfunctions like schizophrenia as a ‘collapse of the dialogical self’. Psychologists studying ‘narrative structure in psychosis, confirm: “Theorists across discipline have described the dynamic and multifaceted nature of selfexperience, stressing that the self is inherently ‘dialogical’ or the product of ongoing conversations both within the individual and between the individual and others.” (p. 209). Moreover, Mikael Leiman from Joensuu University argues: “Semiotic position and Bakhtinian notions of the signs suggest modification of the concept of I-position. Person’s position reveals his or her subjective stance with regard to the addressee. The addressee . . . is an invisible third, is always seen to

18.7 Mikhail Bakhtin | 391

adopt a reciprocal stance, a counter-position. Thus instead of a dialogue between an I position (a voice) and another, each I position has dialogical relationship to its addressee. I positions are embodied in signs, and sign mediate changes between the positions”. Also Heikki Majava, a Finnish psychiatrist has developed a model of transference based upon two I positions, in the Bakhtinian sense. There, if one says in existential semiotics that dialogue can be a disturbance in communication in which the I tries to communicate his/her ideas, this disturbance is welcome and beneficent – it must be there as a particular ‘noise’ of the communication channel, albeit true that the other, the addressee remains an alien-psychic entity of which we can only hypothesize that he/she is something similar to the speaking subject. Thus almost unnoticed we glide with Bakhtin into most actual debate of the nature of the self and cultural communication. Altogether, we see that the heritage of Russian formalism is not only shared by the Tartu-Moscow school of cultural semiotics, albeit here in a privileged position; Bakhtinian reception takes place also directly all over the world. Many applying him hardly even know his background in the formalist movement, and some specialists even deny that he belonged to that school at all. There he is, however, put in the encyclopaedias of semiotics. Yet it is typical of contemporary schools of cultural theory and other to utilize these great figures as innovators but detach them from their ideational context. Of course we are not interested in Propp or Bakhtin in the first place as historic documents of early 20th century thought but due to the weight of their thought of its own. We read them as classics, who are never exhausted.

Chapter 19 Wilhelm Sesemann in the context of semiotics 19.1 Introduction We now know that Wilhelm Sesemann was the greatest philosopher in the history of Lithuania. Thorsten Botz-Bornstein study is the first “Western” treatise to take him seriously in that regard, and to explore carefully the relationships between Sesemann’s thought and the Russian and German philosophy of his time. As Botz-Bornstein observes, however, Sesemann’s thought comes at us from so many angles, it is difficult to define the “real” philosophy of this Baltic thinker. In Finland, interest in Sesemann’s work has stemmed mostly from its connection to semiotics. His name first surfaced here around 1982, when semiotics began to gain a foothold in our country, and the Semiotic Society of Finland began its annual meetings. The third of those, held in Jyväskylä in 1983, represented a notable expansion of Finnish semiotics onto the international scene. Among the featured speakers was Henri Broms (1985) and the great Franco-Lithuanian scholar, Algirdas Julien Greimas, who had lectured in Helsinki as early as 1979. Also featured was the Finnish psychiatrist and writer Oscar Parland (1912–1997), who later became an honorary member of our society. He and his brother, the Finnish poet Henry Parland (1908–1930), were nephews of Wilhelm Sesemann. When Henry was declared the “First Finnish semiotician”, interest began to grow in how and where he had gotten his ideas on semiotics. Oscar Parland, in lectures at meetings of the Finnish Semiotic Society, spoke about the Parland-Sesemann family history, and how Henry got his ideas about Russian formalism from his uncle, Sesemann. In those lectures, Oscar told breath-taking stories about Sesemann, his exile to Siberia, and his subsequent rehabilitation. The lectures were first published in Synteesi in 1991 and included in a collection entitled Oscar Parland 1991, Tieto ja eläytyminen: Esseitä ja muistelmia (Knowledge and Empathy: Essays and Reminiscences). At about the same time, Greimas, my former teacher in Paris, began to promote Lithuanian patrimony. He spoke of Sesemann having taught at Kaunas University when he was a student there, and told me about a study that Sesemann had written on aesthetics, which I determined to have translated into English. In our correspondence on the matter, Greimas mentioned a son of Sesemann living in Paris as an immigrant, but doubted that he would have been a pupil of his father. Hence any opinions about “Finnish” roots of Sesemann’s thought are speculative, and based on the internal content of his doctrine.

19.1 Introduction

|

393

Of course, an essential moment in the development of European semiotics was that of Russian Formalism, and the Preface to Sesemann’s Estetika was written by the formalist Žirmunsky, well-known for his studies in metrics. (My knowledge of that preface is limited to Žirmunsky’s mention of Yuri Tynianov, among the names of other Russian formalists.) Oscar Parland considered it obvious that Henry’s ideas about Russian Formalism came from their uncle, Sesemann, who had gotten them from Žirmunsky. In 1990, I commented on Sesemann in an article written (in both Finnish and English) for the Nordic art review, Siksi, from which I dare to quote: It would be tempting to draw connections between the neo-Kantian philosophy and epistemology of Sesemann and Greimas’s semiotics, but at least in practice there was no interaction between the two men. The fact that Greimas returned to the subject/object problem in his “third semiotic revolution” was due to quite different reasons than Sesemann’s philosophy. Nevertheless, some thoughts Sesemann had were quite close to those of Greimas. One of these was the differentiation between the concepts Wissen and Kennen. Since then, the French philosopher Vladimir Jankélévitch has spoken in the same manner about the difference between savoir and connaissance: the former denotes knowledge acquired from books; the latter, knowledge based on personal acquaintance. Perhaps Greimas’ modality of ‘know’ (savoir), should also be divided into those two types, according to his own categories of exteroceptive/interoceptive . . . . (Tarasti 1990b: 17)

Only a year after my article appeared, Oscar Parland’s (1991) Empathy and Knowledge was published, which contained a more detailed explication of Sesemann’s philosophy. In Parland’s view, the essential dichotomy – and common thread – in Sesemann’s thought is the distinction between objective and subjective knowledge (Gegenständliche und ungegenständliche Erkenntnis). Fundamental to objective knowledge is the separation between subject (perceiver) and object (perceived). To gain such knowledge thus requires a kind of reduction that attempts to bracket all subjective elements from the act of perception or sensation (Erkenntnis). In the act of conceptualization, the subject tries to dominate, take over, and assimilate the object, which appears as a transcendental entity to a subject that is alien to it. The subject grasps the object and detaches it from the Umwelt in which it has been embedded. Extracted from its “native” habitat, the object is set before the subject, to be observed, in terms of Kantian categories, as a “thing” (Gegenstand). Most important to the described process is the external appearance (Erscheinung) of the object, that is to say, the medium or phenomenon by which it appears to a subject. That process often involves violence – what Sesemann calls Vergewaltigen – to the object, particularly when such observation is directed to living entities or to psychic, spiritual, and similar phenomena. Objective knowledge alone (Erkennen)

394 | 19 Wilhelm Sesemann in the context of semiotics becomes less and less satisfactory, the deeper we proceed into the realm of psychic realities; the intellectual violence grows, causing distortions of knowledge to multiply:

subject

object

Figure 19.1: Subject/object relation in Sesemann

We can see in the above discussion a critique of Husserl – oft-mentioned in Sesemann studies – and an anticipation of Heidegger’s principle of Gelassenheit (letting things be), or in the semiotic terms of Charles Morris, “lettings things happen”. At the opposite pole lies non-objective (ungegenständliche) knowledge, or Wissen, such as that of realities connected with morals, religion, or aesthetic phenomena. This kind of knowledge differs most radically from the objective kind, in that it makes no clear distinction between subject and object. The subject is part of the reality that it experiences; and that experience necessarily includes the subject’s self-knowledge as well as the subject’s consciousness of itself (Erlebnis, personal experience). The subject recognizes itself in the object, and temporarily shifts to the latter’s side, yet without separating the object from its proper Umwelt. In this act the subject is “split” into two halves: one part of the subject remains as subject; the other part shifts to the object, with which it fuses:

Figure 19.2: The recognition of subject in object

Sesemann’s notion of Wissen has its counterpart in the so-called “Third semiotic revolution” sparked by Greimas, who after his hyper-objective, “linguistics phase” (e.g., Greimas 1966), began to figure subjective aspects into his semiotic theories, via the concept of modalities (e.g., Greimas 1973). He implicitly acknowledged as much in a speech given at the Kalevala symposium in Paris in 1985, when he said the ancient Finns were not so stupid as to have worshipped mere objects, stones, trees, and so on, but rather, the spirit in those objects. He moreover claimed to have more empathy with German-romantic ethnology than with that of positivists, which only gather things and classify them – an attitude also taken by Sesemann.

19.1 Introduction

|

395

In what follows, my assessment of Sesemann’s thought is based on copies of several of his studies, which were kindly sent to me by Greimas and Oscar Parland: Beiträge zum Erkenntnisproblem III: Das Logisch-Rationale (1930); Die logischen Gesetze im Verhältnis zum subjektbezogenen und psychischen Sein (1931); Estetika and Musu laiku gnoseologijai naujai besiorientuojant (1935a); and Zum Problem der logischen paradoxien (1935b). Those texts can be re-read in many ways, and BotzBornstein’s reading of them in the light of Lacan and Bakhtin seems completely justifiable: Oscar Parland tells us that Sesemann knew Freud and admired his treatise on dreams; and as mentioned above, Sesemann’s contact with Russian Formalism was real, given his personal friendship with Žirmunsky. We can also read Sesemann in the framework of ‘existential semiotics’ (e.g., Tarasti 2000). In my theories, the “classic” semiotic doctrines remain valid, especially that of Greimas, but influences also flow into it from German philosophy (Hegel, Kant, Jaspers, Heidegger) as well as from Kierkegaard, Sartre, de Beauvoir, Jean Wahl and others. That variety of sources mirrors the influences on Sesemann’s thought, and hence provides a suitable framework for my interpretation of his writings in terms of Greimassian and/or existential semiotics, to which Sesemann is shown to be a precursor. First of all, almost anywhere he uses the term “logical” we can replace it with the term “semiotical”. Sesemann always underlines the fact that he is studying the logical structure of the world and not its psychological content, as is the case with Greimassian as well as existential semiotics. Further, as a musicologist, I find interesting his analysis of der Schall, or “sound” (Sesemann 1931: 114). He, like Ernst Kurth, urges us to identify music not with printed notes but with Schall, which is equally translatable as “noise” (a radical anticipation of Futurism!). Once a sound has been emitted from its object, it creates its own universe: Daher vermag auch das Geräusch und insbesondere der Ton, als ein von aller Dinglichkeit losgelöstes Phänomen eine selbständige Existenz zu führen: worauf die Möglichkeit beruht in Gestalt der Musik eine eigenständige autonome Tonwelt zu schaffen. (ibid.) (Therefore sound, and especially the tone, as a phenomenon freed from all materiality, may lead an independent existence: on which basis rests the potentiality, in the form of music, for shaping an independent, autonomous tone-world.)

It is interesting that the chapter entitled Die logischen gesetze und das Daseinsautonome Sein starts with a question about the nature of ‘becoming’ (ibid.: 121): Is that modality established on logical principles? (“Ist das Werden den logischen Prinzipien unterworfen?”). That question brings to mind the time Greimas asked me to write an article for his Dictionnaire on the modality of ‘becoming’ (devenir,

396 | 19 Wilhelm Sesemann in the context of semiotics Werden), which was inserted into the otherwise rather static, atemporal categories of his system. Sesemann has this to say about ‘becoming’ (Sesemann 1931: 122): “Das Werden als Einheit von Sein und Nichtsein ist also das einzig, das wahrhaft Reale” (Becoming, as a unity of Being and Not-Being, is thus the only, the genuinely real). Sesemann discusses the problem of reducing ‘becoming’ to points of rest (Ruhemomenten), an issue one also encounters in using the Greimassian semiotic square, which is based on contrary relations between S1 and S2 and their negations, non-S1 and non-S2. Here Zeno’s paradox comes into play: we can try to temporalize the square by following the movement within it, among its various categories; but at the same time, the static, fixed points of reference remain in place. In that way, movement is conceived as spatialized (ibid.: 130): “Umdeutung der Dynamik der Bewegung in statisch räumliches Sein” (A new meaning of the dynamics of motion in static, spatial being). Pertinent in this context is the Bergsonian distinction, also mentioned by Sesemann, between “physical” and “phenomenal” (concrete) time. Sesemann notes that spatialisation also means objectification (Vergegenständlichung), which is not the same as conceptualization. According to Sesemann, we can study time only when we step into it: “. . . als man in ihr drinsteht oder vielmehr mit ihr geht, also soweit als man selbst zeitlich ist und diese Zeitlichkeit unmittlebar anschaut” (. . . to the extent that one steps into [time] – or, even further, goes with it – is the same extent to which one is temporal, and to which one perceives that temporality directly). Sesemann’s reflections on the essence of logical negation are precursors of ideas that Greimas incorporated into his semiotic square. The contradictory opposition must be specified as a contrary relation (ibid.: 138): “Wir haben nicht mehr a und non-a sondern a und b vor uns” (We no longer confront a and non-a, but both a and b). Sesemann deems such motion an aporia, i.e., an unresolvable paradox. Sesemann links the dialectics of ‘becoming’ to the notion of the possible: “. . . das Bestimmtwerden als Unbestimmtheit an einer Bestimmtheit oder als Bestimmtheit eines Unbestimmt-seins” (. . . determinate becoming as indeterminate becoming or as the determination of an indeterminate [state of] being). We find parallels to that view in existential semiotics, where we speak of three modes of signs: (1) presigns – inchoate signs, those which are only starting to become signs, and as such are not yet fixed; (2) act-signs, which are clearly determinable (bestimmt); (3) and post-signs. Presigns are located in the realm of possibility, and are therefore virtual (Tarasti 2000: 33). Sesemann likewise says that the concept of the possible is the foundation for the conceptual presentation of ‘becoming’. In a chapter on Werden und Identität, Sesemann asks if ‘becoming’ has identity, and concludes that it does. In doing so, he comes close to the Hegelian notion

19.1 Introduction

|

397

of an-sich-sein and für-sich-sein – or in my reformulation, an-mich-sein and fürmich-sein, the latter of which refers precisely to the identity of a subject. Sesemann then ponders the category of ideal-allgemeine (the ideally general), which equates to the notion of “transcendence” in existential semiotics. Sesemann criticizes the dominant school of thought, which commits to a conceptual realism that leads to objectification (Vergegenständlichung) of the general, and mistakenly takes the latter as an original phenomenon. To Sesemann, that is the pitfall of Husserl’s method (Sesemann 1931: 173). When first reading that passage in Sesemann, some twenty years ago, I noticed even then his distinction between the real and the possible (Wirklich/ Möglich). The real, as real, is always something concrete and actual – an actsign, in the parlance of existential semiotics – because it is real only insofar as it is active (wirksam). Therefore, it follows that the relation of the possible to the real is something concretely actual. The possible itself, in its primal given-ness, is concretely actual. It signifies the plenitude (Fülle) of possibilities which are concealed in a real, actual situation. Regarding this issue, Sesemann formulates a highly interesting axiom (ibid.: 175): “. . . das Allgemeine als Fülle der konkreten Möglichkeit ist ein konstitutives (wesentliches) Moment der Zeitlichkeit selbst in ihrem aktuellen Sein” (. . . the general, as a plenitude of concrete possiblities, is a constitutive [essential] moment of temporality itself in its actual being). To my mind, Sesemann’s comments bring up the notions of immanent and manifest, as they appear particularly in musical composition; for example, in the construction of a theme (possible, immanent) and the actual appearance of it (real, manifest). In existential semiotics, the same notions help describe how the transcendental becomes actual in Dasein, how the pleroma (fullness, plenitude) of the second act of transcendence might be interpreted more precisely as a plenitude of possibilities. When Sesemann ponders the relation between formal and transcendental logics, he provides semioticians with clues as to how signs, in transcendence, function as pre-signs of Dasein. Sesemann himself uses the term “pre-logical” (1930: 145), and describes the logical sphere as timeless. (In our theory, that would mean a transcendence that is anti-narrative and achronic.) He goes on to underline the act-like, processual nature of the logical, and here again, the term “logical” can be translated profitably into “semiotical”. I suppose this might be enough evidence of how Sesemann can be brought directly into past and present debates about semiotics and its epistemological foundations. Thorsten Botz-Bornstein’s profound and rich inquiry opens up paths leading to the core of Sesemann’s philosophy. Sesemann’s voice is again heard in the history of European and Lithuanian philosophy, as well as on the contemporary scene of thought and actuality.

Chapter 20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music I met Barthes twice in 1973 as a doctoral student and awardee of the French government in Paris. In fact he gave me an interview, and I remember one of my questions: which are to his mind the main trends of structuralist studies at the moment. He answered with certainty: structural linguistics, Marxism and psychoanalysis. But as we know he published in that year his epoch making booklet Le plaisir du texte in which he definitely left the academic or linguistic semiotics in favor of a more writerly activity. I also recall his elegant posture and gracious hands, certainly apt to piano playing. Roland Barthes was at that time one of the French structuralists which in the Nordic countries were mostly received via English translations – and Swedish ones (Mytologier). It is self-evident that this Barthes no longer was the Barthes of the Frenchmen, the original one. But anyone working in Paris was taken as French outside it. Just like of Greimas was said in Toronto: he is a very nice person but so damned French! And Greimas was after all Lithuanian! My own studies with Barthes were stopped with those interviews since when I revealed him that I was also in the seminar of Greimas, he lost his interest. Yet, Barthes’s Elements of Semiology, was much used as the best concise introduction to basic semiotic concepts. It represented the classical, Saussurean approach. It taught about such fundamental issues as syntagm/paradigm, metonymic/metaphoric and applied such rigorous concepts in a ludic manner to whatsoever topics, chosen not only from the high culture and sublime matters but as well as from lower spheres of life, those we call in aesthetics ‘lesser arts’. The fascination of the structural activity just appeared in this diversity of applied fields when it at the same time maintained its strictly disciplined manner of reasoning. This combination of course also manifested the very French episteme of playfulness, jeu. One of the new methods proposed by Elements of semiology, was the socalled commutation test, applicable to whatsoever sign system in order to clarify which were its basic, smallest signifying units. In musical discourse, one could change the E into E flat in the triad C–E–G and so change major into minor, i.e., noticing that this change of musical phonemes also caused the change in meaning: the cheerfulness of major was transformed into sadness of a minor. Moreover,

20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music

| 399

among non-verbal sign system Barthes dealt with gastronomic signs, with his famous approach to menus. Nevertheless, among his early essays particularly one was influential as a laconic presentation of the structuralist method, in which he spoke about ‘structural activity’ of man. In the early 1970s it inspired me to write a short Barthesian analysis on Pasolini’s movies Teorema and Oedipus. I quote: “At first sight it is hard to parallel Oedipus and Teorema by Pasolini. What common could have that myth of antiquity and the “experience of God” of five persons in an industrial society? Yet the joining factor can be found, namely by a structural analysis. Pasolini tries to yield a new type of vision of man, which could be called a structural man. Roland Barthes speaks about a structural activity, characterized by two phases: the destruction of the prevailing structure, and putting together a new structure, i.e. re-construction. Hence a structural man takes the given thing, analyses it into pieces and then reassembles it. In this activity something new emerges, which purely and immediately reflects the human nature. Pasolini’s movies precisely portray the emergence of such a type of man. Man can understand his nature only by de-struction of the norms he has internalized, which has been fed to him from the outside. In Teorema it is shown how the religious experience of five persons de-structures their bourgeois self-satisfactory world view. The visit of the young man in the house causes a chaos in each of them – thereafter they try to replace this chaos with their own new order. It is common to all Pasolini protagonists that they first deny their innermost essence. Persons in Teorema take the communication with a God difficult because they guess it will open new avenues in their lives. Yet each of them meet the God just by being their proper selves. However, the only one who is able to re-construct a new world view, establishing a harmony between individual and society, is the servant of the family. For Pasolini re-construction is above all a social event. Also the members of the capitalist bourgeois family “de-structure” and “re-structure” but their social situation, i.e. in Marxist terms, their objective class position forces them to resort to unreal surrogate solutions. The Tolstoyan turn of the father and the artistic creativity of the son are only mirroring their alienation and not genuine reconstruction. Thus their fate is a nihilist despair . . . Therefore only the servant in Teorema is able to enact the structural man in its full cogency and authenticity. She is taken at her home village as a saint, whose role is to heal sick people. Thus she is not driven out of her society and her solution is sincere re-construction. Oedipus has no possibilities to re-construction since his contradiction is more universal: the taboo of incest is the core in every society. Oedipus myth of course is like myths in general a rationalisation of the contradiction and not its solution. We found Pasolini’s interpretation of Oedipus when we apply to it the two phases of a structuralist activity. The object of de-struction is then the Freudian variant of the myth, to which supposedly the modern man connects the Oedipus myth. The Freudian myth is broken by a simple estrangement: all psychologization is avoided and the reality of myth is reified.

400 | 20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music For instance the sphinx and oracle are described with an ethnographic accuracy. If one wants to see Pasolini’s interpretation one has to be able to see through this colourful ethnological material . . . .”

That was written 40 years ago, but the essay displays the intellectual climate of that time in which the early Barthes wrote his semiological essays. This essay was known to us as a German translation by Günther Schiwy and therefore I used in Finnish the words destrukturierung and restrukturierung. In fact, the same happened with Mythologies a book from the early Barthes and much read in the North as Swedish translation. The structure of mythical sign system seemed to have impact on whatsoever topics to be mythologized. It was one of the starting points to my own study on Myth and Music; I again quote: “Roland Barthes has analyzed some modern myths and studied their specific structure using concepts and methods of semiotics. Myth is not determined, in the opinion of Barthes, by the content of a message, but by the manner in which the myth gives something meaning and form. Barthes, considers myth to be a semiotic system, meaning that in myth what is involved is a sign-system which in a certain sense is independent of any contents . . . . Myth sees in it only the original substance of its own sign-system. Whether it be literature, painting or music, myth subordinates it to the position of signifier. Thus any term used by myth allows two approaches: from the standpoint of the first sign system it is full of meaning, as it is the terminal point in this system. But from the viewpoint of mythical meaning it is exhausted when it becomes the first term, signifier, of the mythical system . . . . In all its abstractness Barthes’s theory will prove to be very useful in studying the connecting points between myth and music, especially the case in which myth subordinates music, retaining it as a substance in its own sign system. This theory is easily illustrated:; one may think, for example, of the futurist adoration of machines at the beginning of the twentieth century. Examples can be found in almost any futurist poetry, painting or music – such as Honegger’s mythologization of a train in Pacific 231, to cite only one. Almost any machine might serve as the substance, or signifier, of the myth while the signified is l’esprit nouveau, modernism, efficiency, productivity etc. or ultimately the nature-mechanical world view described by Jaspers, in which even the machines may achieve a mythical life”. (Tarasti 1979: 27)

Anyway, Barthes’s definition of myth and its structure was still connected with a certain type of ideology common to intellectuals of the period. Namely, his analyses of modern myths were all essentially iconoclast, breaking of myths, showing their illusory nature, and inserting them into the framework of capitalist society as a special device of the bourgeois class to mislead other classes. The signified, the “anti-subject” of Barthesian discourse was the Bourgeois class who replaced the original authentic meaning, signified with its own variant of it. Now, over thirty years later we can see this issue in another light. Must a semiotic analysis of myths always be iconoclast? Could we not imagine a positive, non-iconoclast analysis of myths. Such a study would serve the purpose of such

20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music

| 401

communities and identities which try to build their own value systems in their often postcolonial efforts to be heard, understood and accepted by the dominant groups and societies? If we think of any suppressed individual, community, group or nation – one does not need to make a list – it would be helpful to them. By a semiotic analysis they would be able to revive, build and maintain their proper ‘myths’ in their daily struggle of existence. We can now say that the intellectual attitude portrayed by Barthesian analysis a.o. has won, the media has questioned all the traditional values as a part of the globalized marketing culture of consumption, and so the structural activity of “destructure” has perhaps lead into results which were not intended by those who invented these approaches: namely ironization estrangement and banalization of historically authentic sign practices which now constitute the real resource for resistance. The very serious question is: Has semiotics participated in the trend which is ultimately leading to the death of all human sciences, which are replaced by more “exact”, “efficient”, and “positivist” methods in which any hermeneutic or existential understanding has been declared as something old-fashioned and outworn? Maybe Barthes is not the right person of the structuralist and semiotic movement to be posed such a question, since as we know, after the ‘semiological’ beginning, he turned to a more asystematic, ‘artistic’ manner of presenting his ideas. Accordingly, he took distance from Greimas and others, who until the end believed in an ‘efficient human science’ thanks to the exactness of semiotic methods. Among all the great semioticians of the 20th century Barthes is a rare case of being inspired by music and having written about music. Of course we cannot compare him to Lévi-Strauss, whose whole output radiates a musical orientation. But in the side of Greimas, Lotman, Eco, Kristeva, etc. who wrote about music almost nothing, Barthes often returned to his own musical tastes and inspirations. In Le plaisir du texte he emphasized the role of the reader. He said we have to become again aristocratic readers who read in a decelerated manner, slowly. Of course, here is no parallel to music: What could it mean to listen to a piece slowly? We cannot change the musical time. It is rather it which takes us into its possession; it is like a train going on its own rail with its own tempo while we are sitting on parallel rails in another wagon following the course of the first mentioned – which was the metaphor by Henri Bergson to illustrate listening to a melody. Yet, often Barthes’s literary studies inspired semioticians of music. I may mention as only example the study by the British scholar Robert Samuels of Gustav Mahler’s Sixth Symphony in which he adopted Barthes’s method of the codes from his S/Z. The author is fascinated by Barthes’s of idea of various superimposed codes which are used for reading and interpreting the text. Nevertheless,

402 | 20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music the shift from literary codes to musical ones is not entirely unproblematic, since in musical texts different codes need different technics of analysis. As a solution Samuels proposed that one takes from the arsenal of musical semiotics various devices for each code from Nattiez to Stefani. Hence his variant of the Barthesian method is the following: “At first, a certain sort of coding strategy on the part of the listener will be suggested; then potential signifying units for such a code will be identified as rigorously as possible; finally, the resulting structure will be examined as a semiotic phenomenon.” (Samuels 1995: 15)

Samuels’s second phase touches the obsession of earlier music semiotics, as it was represented by Jean-Jacques Nattiez and Nicolas Ruwet, namely the segmentation of musical texts. Barthes used in his S/Z his codes as criteria for segmentation, or rather each segment was systematically studied following his five codes. This is a reasonable method, but, however, when comparing this approach to the one by Greimas in his essay on Maupassant – I would say his equivalent to Barthes’s S/Z –, the advantage of semeanalysis is that a ‘seme’ can concern either one short phrase or even word as well as whole paragraphs and even chapters. Thus the text is not broken into discrete parts without connection. However, Barthes also admitted that we had two types of texts: writerly (scriptible) and readable (lisible): the first one could be certainly segmented according to formal syntactic criteria but the latter one was rather a phenomenal, continuous, processual case, which needed other type of analysis. As far as it was a musical text Barthes later said about it: Seule la métaphore est exacte, only metaphor is exact about music – thus joining to the Proustian paradigm of music descriptions. Distinction between writerly/readable texts occurs also in my own Existential Semiotics, I dare to quote again: “Thus the sign itself is no longer in focus: instead it is the dialogue, not only among people but between man and text (enunciate, utterance). The concepts of Roland Barthes, such as lisible/readable) and scriptible (writerly), contain this essential distinction. In a text that is only lisible one aims to forget the aforementioned dialectics and to merge with the enunciator inside the text. We read holding our breath. We listen as if enchanted. We look with eyes staring. But when we consider the text to be writerly (scriptible) we move to another degree of reality into a more semiotical consciousness. We see the text through the eyes of another text. We hear in some musical passage a reminiscence of Debussy. We see in this and that painting an allusion to Picasso. We read in this and that phrase a tinge of the Proustian mémoire involontaire, etc. Even life can be experienced as a text. The autobiography of Stefan Zweig The World of the Past (Die Welt von Gestern) is written in such a way that the phases of the writer are first depicted as written, scriptible, an orderly text. At the end, when one approaches the present time, the text glides into the Barthesian category of lisible . . . .” (Tarasti 2000: 9–10).

20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music | 403

Another theme which appears in Barthesian universe is the corporeality. Even here there are ideological reasons behind: the body was an untamed, subversive entity altogether, something which the “bourgeois ideology” could not totally subordinate. The body was the source of true meaning for Barthes, or at least more truthful than the ones stemming from socially determined codes. The juxtaposition: individual/society is looming at the background and there is no doubt on which side Barthes was standing. In his famous Leçon inaugurale he launches his provocative idea that language as such is a fascist institution. This means that language is always a tool of suppression and subordination. The mere fact of using a grammar in order to communicate, the Saussurean langue, is a fascist act to Barthes’s mind – because he follows here a very Rousseauan reasoning: Qui dit homme, dit langage, et qui dit langage dit sociéte. And it was the society which was the bad side to his mind. How can we understand this? It is paradoxical since one would rather be tempted to think that if language functions as Saussure has shown on the basis of arbitrariness, i.e., ever new meanings emerges in each level of articulation, then one should admit that this also guarantees the liberties to man for a redefinition on each next level of articulation of his/her existence – something like Kierkegaard proposed in his three stages of life and the discontinuous leaps between them. No, Barthes claims that any use of signs means falling into a trap of stereotypes; I am at the same time slave and master: I do not only repeat slavishly what was said but I also emphasize and foreground what I am repeating. Again comparing to Greimas: in his model such an implicit ‘fascist’ subordination of language – if he had said so! – would have been certainly the fact that there are modalities: if we have the main phrase it is subduing the subphrase, whose verb is thus put to a subjunctive mode reflecting this relation of subordination. That could well be seen metaphorically as a fascist phenomenon – however Greimas did not like metaphors (and neither too strong political engagements; an anecdote: his concept of embrayage is in English: engagement; once in a congress where there was talk about this notion, one scholar from Eastern Europe stood up and exclaimed: I am so glad that political engagement is finally accepted in semiotics!). However, Barthes’s solution to get out of the inherent fascism in language was literature; in which we can cheat the language, by the deviations from norms (so his view on aesthetics was essentially the same as by Eco, to whom it is the break of norms which constitutes the aesthetic value). But the other subversive technics is stemming from body. This aspect comes afore particularly in Barthes’s essays on music like The Grain of the Voice, Rasch, etc.

404 | 20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music The central pair of notions which we find in the first-mentioned is the distinction between phenotext and genotext. This has been of course borrowed from Julia Kristeva and her early idea on phénotexte/génotexte (who again got it from a woman scholar in Moscow, as Ivanka Stoianova has pointed out to me, oral communication). Phenotext of course meant the cultural codes of “civilized” style and manners, whereas in genotext the body speaks through these cultural codes and breaks them. In the vocal art of Dietrich Fischer-Dieskau one hears according to Barthes only the phenotext; the only singer who has grasped the Schubertian genotext is the French tenor Charles Panzera. In his singing one hears the body, the heart beats, muscles, the lunges. This Barthesian body is also essentially an erotic body. Fascinated by this distinction I tried to apply it also to other types of musical texts coming from purely instrumental music, like in the comparison of two interpretations of Chopin’s Nocturne No. 1 in B flat minor, by Arthur Rubinstein and Samson François (Tarasti 1994: 52). It was clear to me that Rubinstein was on the side of pheno- whereas François represented the geno-aspect of interpretation. If in Rubinstein melody was interpreted as written without pathetic accents, with nocturno genre as basis, emphasizing langue, then François was speech-like, with a lot of pathetic accents – quasi parlando as Barthes would have said – with a lot of entropy and surprise, varied touch, piece’s message as basis, emphasizing parole. This demonstrated that the Barthesian distinction functioned even outside the essentially corporeal vocal interpretation. One could even see, if one like, in my existential semiotics and its dichotomy of the spheres of Moi/Soi (see also Jacques Fontanille in his Séma et soma, Figures du Corps) a kind of Barthesian extension. Although I provide it with a Hegelian or philosophical tinge by stating that the Moi is the same as Being-in-Myself and Being-for-Myself whereas the Soi was the realm of Being-for-itself and Being-initself. If Moi, Being-in-and-for-Myself was the field of our corporeal ego with its kinetic energies and impulses – i.e., Barthes’s genotexte – then the Soi as the phenotext were the social norms as external demands and values intruding one’s Moi, bodily existence This dichotomy is quite essential in my theory of power and subjectivity, and the difference from Barthesian idea is that I try to see it rather as two instances of Being, than as qualities of any fixed text or object. In any case, in music, the existence of such corporeal signs is very evident, not only in the sense that we can speak about musical gestures, but in the sense that this modus influences the entire organisation of musical enunciation. In my treatise Signs of Music I tried to pose the question: Are corporeal signs iconic? And again I had to refer to Barthes:

20 Roland Barthes or the birth of semiotics from the spirit of music | 405

Are certain qualities of the male or female body iconically represented more or less directly by their appropriate signs? For instance are military rhythms and signs, galloping horses, and the like conventionally masculine? When Chopin exploits such musical devices, is that when his male body is “speaking” to us? Roland Barthes (1986) in his famous essay on Schumann, speculated similarly, that in the rhythmic quality of Rasch the Schumannian body starts to speak to us via its particular somathemes. Here, as with Barthes, this issue raises many questions . . . . (Tarasti 2002: 132–133)

In the light of existential semiotics this problem of bodily presence in music turns into the simple question: is the Moi present in the text when the codes, stylistic norms of the Soi are, so to say, shattering, negated, opposed? Then it would be that only at the moments of rupture or disturbance in the normal course of musical enunciation we can notice the presence and impact of the Moi – or the Barthesian “body”. I am not quite sure that this is true, because there are styles which are just based upon such ruptures, and which therefore do not any longer represent any deviation from the Soi in favor of the Moi. For instance, in Beethoven’s Fifth symphony, The Fate, in the opening motif we hear three beats and one accented longer note. Yet the essential thing here are not these notes as such but that those three beats are preceded by a pause of one eighth note – which causes that this figure as such is a deviation from a perfect Gestalt, i.e., a four-eighth-note-unit. How that gap of missing eighth note represented only by a pause is later filled is the basic narrative device of the whole piece, its individual grammar. It would be thus totally premature to infer that this pause would represent the principle of Moi, the Beethovenian “subject”, the genotext, disturbance in the whole text since the whole movement is built upon it following the norms and rules of the symphonic genre. It is, so to say, adopted and absorbed by the genre and is thus no longer a sign of any Beethovenian individual body behind the musical enunciation. To return to Barthes, his British interpreter Dr. Samuels made an interesting note on his method in the S/Z. Namely, perhaps the most significant aspect of the method employed in S/Z is that Barthes never uses it again. (Samuels 1995: 13). That is the true character of Barthes. The aspect which separates him from other more passionate structuralists. Their concept of an ideal science was contrarily a method which was so rigorous that it made no distinction who did the analysis, the master or the pupil: the result should be the same if the method was right. Here the artistic aspect of Barthes is again manifest. It would be very hard to imitate Barthesian discourse like the students often learn by repeating what the Master did. But he is our icon and idol and classic in semiotics in another way: first, by his exemplary attitude of uncompromising intelligence to whom any cultural expression was worth analyzing; and second, by his creative fantasy and imagination – which certainly also belongs to semiotics, the science we all exercise with different approaches.

Chapter 21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics Few efforts have been made to renew or even reflect upon the epistemological bases of traditional or “classical” semiotics, established (roughly) at the beginning of the twentieth century and continuing up to the present day. It seems that traditional semiotics has accepted the normative communication model – such as that elaborated by Shannon and Weaver to improve the efficiency of telecommunication – as the self-evident starting point for any semiotic research. It requires a semiotician with a philosophical mind to go beyond accepted truths and search out new avenues for the study of signs. Augusto Ponzio is one such scholar. Grounded in philosophy, he at the same time takes a keen interest in the worldly phenomena of our Dasein, and does so with the kind of encyclopaedic zest that characterizes the great semioticians of our time, from Roland Barthes to Umberto Eco. Ponzio’s version of semiotics is a fascinating combination of his roots in the line of Charles Morris/Ferruccio RossiLandi, Mikhail Bakhtin’s ideas on dialogue and, perhaps above all, the “existential” philosophy of Emmanuel Lévinas. Ponzio’s interest in what may be called sociosemiotics stems from the first source, his ideas on Russian formalism from Bakhtin, and his fundamental view of Otherness from Lévinas. It is tempting to argue that the common point for all these sources is the notion of subject as the primus motor of “semiosis”. Yet Ponzio turns the situation around: it is signs that constitute subjects, not vice-versa. In this aspect of his philosophy, he shows himself as a semiotician. I quote: “It is my contention that once a sign is produced it has a life of its own, independent from the person who generated it, continues using it or interprets it: such a modality of sign life is dialogic. From this point of view, sign dialogism constitutes a form of resistance, if not opposition, which to the person who uses signs is more than a means through which he manifests himself. Sign resistance is more properly designated as the semiotic materiality which comes to be added to the mere physical materiality of nonsigns as they are transformed into signs“. (Ponzio 1993: 2)

This comes close to John Deely’s idea that signs are not things. But Ponzio continues: “Sign objectivity or semiotic materiality constitutes the otherness of signs with respect to their producers and interpreters. The essence of the sign, its semiotic material, is what lies beyond the sphere of the subject . . . and figures as other” (ibid.).

21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics

|

407

Ponzio’s statements bring to mind the early phase of Greimas’s semiotics. In his Sémantique structurale, Greimas subordinated Georges Bernanos’s novel Journal d’un curé de campagne to a rigorous seme-analysis and ultimately reduced the whole novel into a Lévi-Straussian algebraic model depicting the “transformations” that constitute the Bernanosian universe. However, what was forgotten in such an extremely textual analysis was the idea of the story, which was clearly existential in nature. The tale’s concern with subjectivity was expressed quite cogently in Bresson’s film version of the novel. The young priest, in the novel and the film, faces a semiotic problem: he does not understand what kind of sign he is to his community, and this causes the failure of his idealistic “Christ” project. As Ponzio states: “Absolute otherness is an expression of the fact that we are signs” (ibid.: 3). Of course, we could put the problem in another way, and claim that it is about the alien psyche (Fremdseeligkeit). Ponzio, however, remains faithful to his sociosemiotic roots, and thinks in terms of signs themselves. For him, the resistant “materiality” of signs constitutes their crucial value to genuine human dialogue. It is signs and dialogue – i.e., semiosis – that determine the man, and not vice versa. Here Ponzio also shows his allegiance to structuralism, which held that the automatisms of sign systems force us to do and say things in a certain manner, if we want to communicate. Moreover, Ponzio’s confounding of signifier and opus connects him to a certain Marxist tradition: “Both the signifier and the opus contain a movement from the subject, the self, from the sphere of the same to the other”. But then intervenes the factor of ideology, central to Rossi-Landi, which inheres both in the “false consciousness” of the subject, and also in the signs themselves and in their usage: “Ideology is also false praxis”. Therefore semiotics cannot do, in a deeper sense, without the study of ideology. Semiotics can of course be exercised as the mere study of how signs function; but in doing so it remains dominated by existing practices without ever questioning their bases. Therefore, if semiotics wants to remain a science of the avant-garde – and in my view it should always be, paradoxically, a kind of “continuous avant-garde” – it cannot assert its “currency” simply by cataloguing what happens in the contemporary world, such as new innovations in communication technology, processes of globalisation, and so on. Semiotics must go further, and search out the often hidden ideological aspects of those objects, which range from mobile phones to urban spaces to military forces. There must be some intellectual moment in the semiotic discourse as such which makes it appealing in our times. Therefore we should not misunderstand Ponzio’s doctrine of material resistance of signs. We might well hear echoes of Sartre’s “semiotics is humanism” in the following declaration by Ponzio: “Before concerning us as specialists and

408 | 21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics experts, ideology concerns each and every one of us as human beings. This is particularly significant today in view of the fact that such concepts as the crisis of ideology or even the end of the era of ideology are now commonplace: in truth such expressions merely confirm that a given ideology is dominating over others, to the point of being represented as the modality of the existence of reality” (Ponzio 1993: 9–10). If on one hand Ponzio wants to preserve the idea of resistance of signs as a reserve against the dangers of subjectivism – the world is not just a creation of our mental, signifying acts – on the other hand he admits that, ultimately, it is the perpetually rebellious subject who powers the resistance against certain ideological practices. In his later study, Comunicazione (1999), Ponzio delves deeper into the essence of this fundamental notion of all semiotics. He starts from two premises: Communication is being, and being is communication. In making that determination he at once seems to expand the entire semiotic project into a kind of ontology. Biosemiotics, which the late Thomas A. Sebeok so strongly propagated from his own background as a zoosemiotician, claims that all organic being is ultimately communication – a claim that many philosophers found upsetting. One of them was the Finnish philosopher and elaborator of modal logics, Georg Henrik von Wright – a thinker that was highly respected by Greimas and that succeeded Wittgenstein as the Chair of Philosophy at Cambridge – who said he could not conceive of cells as in any way communicating. Evidently the problem lay in his relatively restricted understanding of the notion of “communication”. Namely, biosemioticians take a broader view of communication, seeing it not only as the transmission of messages with contents, but as a process and interaction between the organism and its Umwelt via two operations: Merken and Wirken (Jakob von Uexküll’s terms). The organism either accepts or rejects signs coming from its environment, which process forms the basis of its “identity”, “semiotic self”, or Ich-Ton. Ultimately, the “being” of this organism is totally determined by the operations of Merken/Wirken, which are further undergirded by the operations of acceptance/rejection – or to put it in philosophical jargon, affirmation and negation. Ponzio does not remain at the biological level, but moves onto the next one – that of anthroposemiosis. Here we encounter the facts of language and speaking, historical-social factors, and economic production. Here we might identify communication with production, such that to “communicate” means participating in the economy of production – exchange – consumption. The model of communication thus obtains a new configuration, which we may, like Ponzio, describe as communication-production. Of course, the notion of communicating via the exchange of objects is not at all new (think of Malinowski’s study of the bartering systems of Trobriand

21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics

|

409

Islanders or the notion of “exchange” advanced by Marcel Mauss). But, again, Ponzio does not stop here. He goes on to assert that not all being is communication, since the latter involves not only the category of being but also that of becoming. He argues that to communicate does not mean to “externalise” something that is first internal. Rather, communication begins with something “external” then moves inward, in a kind of autoaffirmation. By what principle does this kind of “communication” operate? Ponzio finds this question to be uninteresting, in the limited or regional ontological sense. What is interesting is that communication is being: “. . . if we want to venture into ontology, we can say: being is not communicating but communicating is being” (Ponzio 1999: 7). Can we be without communicating? Karl Jaspers asks a similar question: Why do we communicate? Why do we not prefer to be alone? For Ponzio this fact is not a matter of the subject’s decision or choice: we are in communication whether we want to be or not. Hunger comes first, then the act of seeking nourishment. Organism is communication. This brings us to the threshold of supremely fundamental questions. Certainly the major problem with classical semiotics, such as that of Greimas, has been its static nature, its categorial, Cartesian thought which remains alien to the world conceived as processes, temporalities, dynamism and action. My own efforts at expanding Greimassian theory have gone toward supplementing and refining his notion of being/doing with that of “becoming” (see my entry on “devenir” in Greimas & Courtés 1986: 67). This led me to deal also with his semiotic square, in which regard I was more interested in how we move from one corner to the other in the narrative process, than in defining the precise content of each logical articulation (i.e., s1, s2, non-s2 and non-s1). More recently I have tried to make his notion of “being” more subtle by stratifying it into at least four aspects: being-in-myself, being-for-myself, being-in-itself, being-for-itself – notions inspired by a certain philosophical thread that runs from Hegel to Sartre. The fact remains, however, that the only truly dynamic concept of standard semiotics has been the idea of communication. We can elevate it to the status of a first-principle, but in doing so we might risk universalizing what is ultimately nothing but a superficial and mechanical, Shannon-Weaver model of communication. The latter always goes in the same direction, from left to the right, describing some kind of transfer among its fixed “boxes” as the ultimate entities of communicative movement. Henri Bergson warned us early on about a view of temporality that reduces it to a chain of discrete shifts among designated entities. He used melody as an example: melodic motion is not only “chronological”, i.e., a chain of successive movements from pitch to pitch; it also projects a global, phenomenal quality in its aspect as duration. If Ponzio hesitates to explore more deeply the notion of “being” as “becoming”, I have recently found such investigation

410 | 21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics to be essential in theorizing appearance (Erscheinung) as a horizontal, temporal phenomenon. We now come to Ponzio’s concept of alterity, or Otherness, which stems from Lévinas. As semiotic animals we can conceive the states of the world as alternatives, as possibilities, we might say. It is the nature of man to think in terms of “otherwise” (altrimenti). Ponzio concedes that human behaviour cannot be understood exclusively in terms of communication, being, and ontology. Here we encounter the possibility of the Other: Questa capacità di animale semiotico, di portarsi al di lá dell’essere e del mondo della comunicazione lo rende assolutamente responsabile non solo della riproduzione sociale ma anche inscindibilmente da essa della vita dell’intero planeta. (Ponzio 1999: 10)

With that statement we have already traveled quite far from his starting point: the materiality of signs, which constitute human subjects. After all, because subjects are able to conceive and imagine alternatives, we are freed from the materiality of the sign and sign-practices, which we also have the capacity to change. Does this not constitute another type of resistance to the existing world and its ideologies of communication-production? This distinctively human situation – freedom from necessity – is reflected in Ponzio’s nicely formulated locution: the “right of unfunctionality”, diritto all’infunzionalità (ibid.: 30). I want to stop on this fascinating concept, since I think it is the core of Ponzio’s philosophy. Here also is where Ponzio’s philosophy comes close to existential semiotics, particularly its latest developments (see Tarasti 2006). Let me explain why. First of all, Ponzio’s notion of alterity, inherited from Lévinas, is almost identical to the concept of transcendence in my own theory. Man is a transcending animal, which simply means that we often use signs to speak about something which is absent, but present in our minds. We may go even further and ask, Isn’t every act of communication somehow transcendental? Even in communication between just two speakers – say, Saussure’s Mr. A and Mr. B – there is always a gap to be filled. When communicating we always run the terrible risk that the other, to whom we speak, does not understand us. We always engage with an alien psyche, knowledge of which we have only via abduction or inference (cf. Schütz & Luckmann 1994). The empty space between interlocutors always presents the possibility of rearticulation. If we are Greimassians, we might think that this gap is filled by modalities. In which case, we would be dealing with what Ponzio calls “relative alterity”. In contrast, “absolute alterity” surpasses even the modalities; it is a virtual universe, filled with such entities as values, ideas, presigns – anything that is not yet fixed in the sign-objects of communication or “production” processes of our

21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics

|

411

everyday world (Dasein). It is this absolute alterity which corresponds to my own conception of transcendence, which we can reach only via the acts of affirmation and negation. This is not the same as the “smaller” transcendences of our everyday communication, with which Saussure and Bakhtin are obviously concerned in their theories of human dialogue. Schütz and Luckmann (1994) speak of such quotidian exchanges as “middle” transcendences. But “major” transcendence pertains to the whole world of possibilities, which we can conceive and become aware of, and which constitute the sphere of spirit (Geist). According to Adorno, it was in this latter sphere that art, ethics, and truth originated, such that something non-material (Ungegenständlich) becomes actualized and objectified in our living world (see Adorno 1993). Ponzio’s “absolute alterity” equates to the major transcendence described by these other theories. “Relative alterity”, by contrast, is instantiated as a social position or role; e.g., professor, student, father, son, labourer, etc. For Hegel this signified being für-sich-sein, i.e., as determined by society, whereas an-sich-sein meant our being as such. I have extended Hegel’s notion by adding the principles of Moi/Soi (cf. Ricoeur, Fontanille), and subdividing those further into four categories: being-in-myself (our individual corporeal essence) and being-for-myself (our identities via habits), which together constitute the Moi; and being-in-itself (i.e., norms, abstract values existing in a society) and being-for-itself (the application of these norms in our behaviours, i.e., social practices), which together make up the Soi. This reasoning parallels that of Ponzio, whom I quote: L’alterità relativa è quella che fa la nostra identità, ma se per un ipotesi di “riduzione” togliamo tutte le nostre alterità relative che costituiscono a nostra identità, non resta piu nulla o persiste un “residuo” indipendente da esse? Ebbene, in contrasto a quanto questa forma sociale vuol farci credere, un tale residuo sussiste, un”’alterità” non relativa che fa esistere ciascuno di noi non semplicemente come individuo e quindi come rappresentante di un genere, di una classe, di un insieme, e come altro a – relativamente – . . . neppure come persona, termine di riferimento di quanto è “personale” , “appartenente”, “proprio” ma come unico, singolo, come assolutamente altro, non sostituibile, non intercambiabile, un genere a sè, sui generis. (Ponzio 1999: 31–32)

Is he talking here about the above-mentioned category of “being-in-myself”, i.e., our individual bodily – kinetic, gestural, pulsational, khoratic – existence before it becomes stabilized into what we call one’s identity? I think not. The absolutely Other, as the absolutely transcendental, cannot be trapped within the confines of the semiotic square, which portrays our subjective states within the world of Dasein, i.e., the world of signs, object and subject, including ourselves. Transcendence in its “major” form designates our ability to go beyond those states or “semiotic positions”. Now, Ponzio still supposes that this absolute Alterity is

412 | 21 The right of unfunctionality – Explorations in Ponzio’s philosophical semiotics unique and singular. And that is the problem: if there is transcendence or absolute alterity that is no longer limited to our corporeal existence as subjects, then what can it be, epistemologically speaking? How can we communicate with it? And is such communication even possible? The theologians do not speak in terms of transcendence, but rather of the supernatural, which only announces itself to us via revelation. If we are Kantian philosophers, however, and insist on speaking about transcendence as a philosophical principle, then we cannot avoid confronting the issue of proving its existence. One such proof has been offered by the Canadian philosopher Charles Taylor, in his study The Sources of the Self, who argues that, because certain behaviours take place in our world which cannot be reasonably understood except by supposing they refer to transcendence, then there must be transcendence (absolute Alterity). To pick up on my earlier reasoning: in my existential semiotics Ponzio’s idea of absolute Alterity, is totally compatible with the notion of Transcendence. At the same time, I admit that many problems remain open. In any case, I agree that Alterity in that sense is always beyond the relative alterity we encounter in our everyday life. I have suggested that the traffic between absolute Alterity (or transcendence) be portrayed by the notion of metamodalities. These are not quite the same as the primary modalities (will, can, must, know, believe, etc.). Rather, metamodalities are something like metaphors of the primary ones, based on the assumption that we are able to conceive the Cosmos, Alterity or Transcendence only via concepts stemming from, and entering into, our own world. The consequence which Ponzio draws from all this is simply: diritto all’infunzionalità – the right to stand on oneself, as a goal in itself, as an alterity that is non-relative (Ponzio 1999: 32). And when getting to the social semiotic, he says: “the right to unfunctionality assumes a subversive character – the unfunctional is human. And still, human rights do not discuss the right to unfunctionality. That would lead us to the humanism of identity. And it is the foundation of all rights of alterity” (ibid.). What does this mean? Certainly it comes close to the American Transcendentalists’ notion of quietism, or if we like, to the Heideggerian principle of Gelassenheit – or if we prefer to keep within semiotics, to Charles Morris’s world-view of “letting things happen” or movement “away from” (the related motions being “towards” or “against”). I would venture to guess that the Ponzian principle of “unfunctionality” would not always mean isolation or separation from the world, but rather first getting mentally freed or emancipated from it, but only in order to be equipped for fulfilling what the subject feels to be the demands of Absolute Alterity, which at the same time accounts for one’s accountability to other subjects – since our world is one of intersubjectivity and being with others.

Chapter 22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez Around November 7th 2007 the internet forum Musikeion became inundated with sorrow messages of the sudden passing away of the young Brazilian musicologist and composer José Luiz Martinez. They sounded incredible since José was born in 1960, familiar with Indian culture and meditation, vegetarian, and of a certain Iberian type of longevity. His colleague Professor Ricardo Monteiro later told about a sudden attack of illness which José met when he was leaving for a congress in Rio de Janeiro. The aforementioned Musikeion was a global discussion network, focusing particularly on Latin America and Brazil, created by José. It was launched in the context of the international research project Musical Signification, which José announced at a congress of the aforementioned project in Aix en Provence in 1998. Since I had the privilege to know José as early as from 1990 as his supervisor and older colleague, I wanted to write this small essay on José’s life and person such as it was seen from the other side of the world, from Finland, to which country destiny brought José for several years. These reminiscences are based upon the correspondence with José in the years 1990–2000. The story starts at the beginning of 1990 when in Helsinki, just after the celebration of the University’s 350th anniversary, a letter arrived from São Paulo, rua Dionisio da Costa. It began: “I am a Brazilian musician, very interested in music semiotics and developing research under tutorship of Prof. Lucia Santaella at Pontificia Universidade Catolica in São Paulo (PUC-SP). Graduated as a Music Bachelor I am going to get the Master’s degree in Semiotic and Communication in the beginning of 1991. I would like to discuss with you some points of my researchy and to ask you some questions about Helsinki University Department of Music . . . ”

And then he continued: “But first, I would like to present myself. I started studying classical music about 20 years ago (at the age of 10 years). My first instrument was the Guitar, in which I have reached a good level of ability . . . . Then, I worked on various kinds of musical activities, such as chamber music (ancient to contemporary) . . . The discovery of the contemporary music led me trying to write compositions . . . I wrote about 20 pieces, some of them were performed at new music festivals in Brazil. Nowadays I could introduce myself as a composer, guitarist and percussionist. Furthermore I have been more and more interested in theoretical issues in music. Soon I got a grant to develop research. My first subject was the art music of India . . . this research resulted in a book that I named: Classical Indian Music: Theory and Practice . . .

414 | 22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez However my interest reached also practice. . . I was enraptured by the sound of Tabla drums. Fascinated by the Indian music I tried to get a scholarship to study in India but I was not accepted for the Master’s . . . Actually, music semiotics is not only a personal choice, As you have written, music in the 20th century is a very wide field, displayed in a multitudinal of forms, styles and traditions. Their ways of signification are very particular, but I have not found a really complete signification theory designed for music. . . But I am quite disappointed (!) that few scholars have considered in depth the work of Charles Sanders Peirce. . . . Studies that borrow some Peircean concepts usually apply them to music in an isolated way (sometimes naively) . . . Nowadays I am trying to develop that which some day (I hope) could be a Peircean theory of musical semiosis . . . ”

At the end José asked for my opinion on these plans and some articles which I had written. On July 17, José wrote again: “I became very happy after reading your answer to my “long letter”. Your words sounded really optimistic to a third world student. I hope I could correspond worthily . . . I do am seriously interested in forwarding my studies abroad. There are three places that I think it would be ideal places – Helsinki University interest me specially . . . it looks me as a place to grow a strong base. The second place is, of course, some Indian University (I have a contact at Banaras Hindu University), where I could get first hand material as treatises and contact with living masters of classical Indian music. The third place is indeed Bloomington, as the ‘Mecca’ of all Peircean scholars. I was happily surprised when you indicated prof Lewis Rowell as an expert in Indian music. . . Well, Helsinki, India, Bloomington . . . it sounds really ambitious! Actually I do not have rich parents and I and my wife are making our living only through a state scholarship earned . . . It is possible but not easy, to get help from Brazilian institutions for the Doctoral research abroad . . . that is my hope.”

In fact, José realized later all what he planned as early as then: he came from São Paulo to Helsinki in order to become a PhD in Indian music – an example of truly international student mobility in our days. But also an illustration of extremely clear goals and strong determination. In the same summer José sent his paper Musica & Semiotica: Uma teoria peirceana for my reading; he had held it as a communication on Aug. 28, 1990 at the congress of Brazilian semioticians in Porto Alegre. To that theoretical foundation José in this speech had offered, i.e., how to apply Peirce’s sign categories to music, he remained faithful for his entire life. On Dec. 10, José’s “Finnish” plan was so far that he knew which documents he would need at the University of Helsinki and in Finland in order to apply for the grant of FAPESP. He asked for advice on whether he should concentrate theoretically in three cases of Peirce’s sign categories, i.e., musical signs in themselves, their relationships to the objects, or their relations to interpretants. As the second alternative he saw the study of semiotico-structural grounds of music: random-

22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez | 415

ness, functionality, and convention. At the same time, he kept the idea to study Indian music via Sanskrit sources. He also planned for composing studies at Sibelius Academy. On Dec. 18, José already had an invitation to the international doctoral seminar of musical semiotics in Helsinki, and he thought to study listening, performing and analysing of music according to Peirce’s logics. On March 6 José already knew that he would do musical semiotics just in connection to the Indian traditional music. He inquired about possible India specialists in Helsinki, of which I had mentioned to him Professors Simo and Asko Parpola. José later chose their courses. But an enormous amount of documents and applications were needed before all this became reality. We had spoken on the telephone but I always wanted to see in person a student before accepting him as doctoral student. On July 10, 1992 José could announce that the Brazilian Ministry had granted him an award for doctoral studies in Finland. Three days later he had received by mail the first issue of Acta Semiotica Fennica. In August José said that he would arrive in Finland at the beginning of September. Before this José attended São Paulo’s 28th Musica nova festival with a composition to the memory of John Cage in which an untuned tambura was tuned during 4󸀠 33󸀠󸀠 , pitches could be tones C, A, G and E. José arrived in Finland and found soon his home at Vironkatu, in that fivefloor turn of the century building in which the Department of Musicology had been settled since the 1960s. It became his fortress for years since he did not return home but four years later when his whole ‘project’ was completed. In Finland he met other difficulties, that is true, like continuous renovations of his visa at the Foreigners’ Office, for which one needed again reference letters. But José also utilized his stay in Europe and travelled with his wife Cisa a.o. in Greece and Germany (post card from Athens in Sept. 14, 1993). José sent at the beginning of June to me a copy of a letter from Lew Rowell, the leading American specialist of Indian music in which Rowell broadly commented on José’s ideas. Rowell discussed José’s theories on rasa and raga, two central genres of Indian classical music, which José wanted to study. The most important for Rowell was ‘insider’s perspective’ on Indian music – to the extent it is possible for a foreigner. In other words, Rowel said, emic information is better than etic for your purposes. But he also warned: You will not find Indian musicians and thinkers sympathetic to your project: it may even be better not to tell them what you have in mind. A more general problem may lie in the following: Peirce’s approach to analysis, as I understand it, is based on the recognition of oppositions. This is very foreign to the Indian way of thinking, which is inclusive – not exclusive . . . Indian logic has no difficulty in accepting propositions that both are and are not true.

416 | 22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez In August perpetual worries about visas now concerning José’s wife continued, and again we had to make telephone calls. In the meantime I visited Bayreuth and José greeted me by letter by saying: Hopefully Wotan inspired your trip! Otherwise José did not accept to call his professor by first name in the Nordic manner but called me systematically “Sir”. In 1994 José was already going to India and asked for recommendations for Professor Emerita Sarma to Banaras Hindu University. He intended to stay there as a visiting scholar. In March José introduced me to a paulista composer Mario Ficarelli who prepared a doctoral thesis on Sibelius’s symphonies. In Finland the Niilo Helander Foundation supported José. In July José wrote to be ready for India. He also answered to my questions about the notion of existence in Peirce. Peirce’s view radically differed from that of Sartre. The existing world was for Peirce a real world, that which is independent from our mind and thought. The best book written about it was by Ivo Ibri, in Portuguese, he said. In December José was already in India and now followed perhaps the most interesting part of our correspondence, José’s travel descriptions. He wrote on Dec. 12, 1994: “I have been in Delhi for almost three months now. I have to say, that I am very happy. Well, the city is indeed big and “intoxicating” as Lewis Rowell put it. I had almost forgotten how is the big city living style, so used I have got to the calmness and facilities of Helsinki. But, after the second month, I get into the Indian mood, and started enjoying everyday life, paying not too much attention to the difficulties. There are lots of pleasant situations, such as, the sight of an elephant walking slowly among the cars in the large avenues of New Delhi, or snake charmers playing not for tourists but in typical poor Indian areas. And, of course, wonderful concerts and dance recitals! You can guess that I am usually considered Indian by the people here. I am not even harassed by the tourist traps and their touts. I can go everywhere, even in the old town, and I feel safe. This would be a great advantage for an ethnomusicologist, but my Hindi is still too poor to follow the native speakers. I have Hindi class twice a week, though.”

José had met great musicians like Mrs. Mukerhjee, Mrs. Brhaspati and the Dagar brothers, famous drhupad singers. But he admitted having encountered one problem in his project. It had been difficult to collect signs that would support his theory. One source were the songs, from which he could draw musical meanings from texts – Mrs. Brahspati for instance told that lovers’ separation was expressed by leaps in the melody, and union was signified by melodies running in close intervals. But it would last years to gather such examples. Therefore José decided to put some key questions such as: Are there in Indian music instances of birdsong? Where, when, and how? Are there in Indian music instances of numerical or

22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez |

417

geometrical relations? Are there in Indian music instances of quotations or parodies concerning folk music, pop music, film music, or even Western music? Yet these concerned only the issue of icons. But José thought that indices and symbols were much easier to find. Altogether, Jose wanted to stay in India for a longer time in order to travel there and get more information about playing – although he first had to repeat only some basic figures. José wrote a kind of travel diary or essays entitled “Fieldwork” and asked where it could be published. I do not know if it has appeared anywhere but in any case it contains funny personal experiences. A.o. he tells about his visit at a tabla class by his teacher Probir: “To begin . . . we have to jump in the bus, since the driver rarely stops completely the decrepit vehicle, he merely slows it a bit. In the bus I am almost perfectly disguised as an Indian, thanks to my DNA heritage (a kind of artificial synthesis, since my parents have Portuguese and Spanish ancestors). However. my worst weakness is my quite poor Hindi, and my clothes, nothing special but still outstandingly neat and Western among the humble Indian urban buss travelers.

José tells that many musicians live in Lakshmi town, an area in New Delhi, in which rent is cheap. But the place’s name was ironic. Lakshmi is the goddess of fortune, wife of Vishnu, the dreamer and creator of the universe. “However, the area is very poor . . . In the street, walkable now, according to my guru-bhai (colleagues, disciple of the same teacher, Olivier), since during the rains they are full of mud and dejects, we meet cycle and scooter rickshaw, cows and buffaloes, among the small Japanese cars, and motorized vehicles of all kinds . . . ”

This is modern India, not the one of tourists. José also portrays his lessons and Probir asks him to forget everything from his previous style, since his fingers’ placement and attacks were not correct. At the end Probir asked him to bring a tape recorder. “My latent ethnomusicologist was surprised with the request, to which I promptly agreed. Probit checks the equipment ready, what a surprise! The tape supposed to be an ethnomusicological document is actually to work as a mirror of his tabla development. The tape had purely didactic purposes.” José is really happy for this opportunity to learn from original tradition, it is inestimable. But he had adventures during his return home from Probir’s. He heard a voice calling insistently: “Abhai-sahab, bhai-sahab” (brother-sir). Realizing that it meant him, José stopped and saw a policeman, with his chaqui clothes and a turban, indicating quite probably the man being a Sikh.

418 | 22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez “He starts speaking Hindi and I immediately make clear that I do not understand. Situation is strange and irregular. In a poor English the man asks me a few questions concerning my activities there. Soon people start to gather around me and I explain that I am merely a tabla student, and my teacher lives there. He seems to be satisfied and explains me that he is encharged of that area, so he has to make questions to strangers. The situation looks to be over and I restart my way . . . what a surprise when I am again called by the same policeman, just a few seconds after. Now I start to feel nervous and cannot the insistent question the policeman puts me: Cream name, cream name! It sounds me nonsense and I think perhaps he is actually questioning about some crime . . . ”

But then José starts to understand: “Cream – do you want to know what perfume I wear? Yes that was it!. Situation now is unbelievably comic. Relieved I tell the man which perfume brand I was wearing and thinking about the different weight Indian people probably puts on sense as smell, perhaps not as much important in the West, I continue . . . ”

In January José writes from Tanjore, Southern India, where he has seen beautiful old monuments, Buddhist, Hindu and Islamic. Then he is on a journey to Madras. On July 23, 1996 José is back again in Helsinki and lives in the center at Telakkakatu. Earlier he lived in Koivukylä, a suburb area, but once when returning home he was hit by a group of skinheads, lost his passport and pocket book. This made him move downtown. He had received prolongation to his grant from Brazil in order to continue to his defense in December. He was worried about the defense date, but Lew Rowell was arriving as his opponent. He planned it for December 7, just after the Finnish independence day, when his mother was going to visit him. José wished me a good trip to Brazil where I was going for a South American tourney. He said, after so many years you would not recognize the country as the same. On March 4 the Faculty of the Arts gave its printing permission for José’s thesis on the basis of the reports by Professors Erkki Pekkilä and Lew Rowell. Pekkilä said in his report that the candidate had become familiar with Indian music over ten years and studied it here, and thus he had intrinsic knowledge about it. But his work was not empirical description but theoretical contribution to the discourse of musical semiotics, as Pekkilä emphasized. Lew Rowell again said the dissertation was rich in ideas, brilliantly interpreted, and clearly organized. The candidate appeared to be equally at home in the intricate ideological distinctions of Peirce’s thought and the sensuous world of Indian music. In my experience, it is rare to find a work of scholarship that brings together such diverse fields of study in such a successful manner. José’s dissertation appeared in the series Acta Semiotica Fennica as volume V – but only some years later José still wrote (Jan. 14, 2000) that one

22 São Paulo, Helsinki, New Delhi – The life of José Luiz Martinez |

419

Indian publisher was interested in it, namely Motilal Banaridas. When José had visited New Delhi, he had noticed dozens of bookshops, all of them full of Indian publications in English and other languages, and crowded with people searching for books. I am sure that the book will be widely read there. Therefore he asked for copyrights from us – which were of course given to him. So José’s ideas have expanded even in India. On July 28, 1997 José sent a card from São Paulo, from rua Dionisio da Costa, where he had returned after his years of apprenticeship. The circle had been closed. Nevertheless, José did not stay outside the community of music semioticians. He attended as far as I know all major events of Musical Signification in various sides of Europe. Above all he created the internet discussion group Musikeion, which particularly oriented Brazilian music scholars to semiotics. José got a postdoctoral researcher post at São Paulo University, but obviously the life in Brazil with such a highly specialised field of study was not quite rosy. But with his gentle character, perfect mastering of himself in all situations, his seriousness, kindness, and mild temperament – which however contained a steely willpower to realize his plans – Jose managed his life. José’s unexpected passing away was a big loss to the international musical semiotics. It feels strange to remember now how only one day before he sent messages to his friends at Musikeion, who via Jose learned about international events. But if we believe in the old Indian myth and wisdom of “agasha” – i.e., that nothing disappears in the universe – then José’s memory will maintain still a long time – at least in the minds of those who had the joy to know him.

| Part VI: Practice

Chapter 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period 23.1 Introduction Any effort to portray the life of the semiotician since the gradual institutionalization of our discipline – with all its phases, turns, changes, stabilities – can be done only from a subjective point of view; all depends on who is viewing things and which position he/she occupies in the international semiotic movement. So, personally I have considered semiotics since the beginning, i.e., the moment I could join it, a great intellectual challenge – and adventure. Administration of semiotic issues is never an easy project: how could one manage, master, control people who are proper specialists in these fields knowing in advance how anyone is manipulated or guided. However, science is always also a social enterprise including communities and interaction. It is not only cerebral activity, it does not mean that one is closed into a monastery to write the chronicle of the world, like the monk Pimen in Boris Godunov’s first act. Also, some scholars are more inclined than others to organize and administer things. Greimas once told me that my case was rare, since I tried to be active both in organizing and publishing. For a professor getting involved in administration, especially in our days, also can be dangerous. Almost all colleagues whom I know and have done this transfer have adopted another identity altogether. They hardly say good morning to their former colleagues, they identify themselves with those politicians, administrators, and businessmen who nowadays crowd the University Boards. Since my experience stems from a position as a professor in the European Union I guess it is the same elsewhere in this territory. Often those colleagues are recruited to organization and administration whose cognitive forces have shrunk in science itself, and they want to show their competence instead by ruling others. That provides one with an illusion of a very important activity. This is a very general phenomenon anticipated in fact a long time ago by the American philosopher Josiah Royce when he argued that of three persons A, B, and C the most important is B, who is ‘only’ mediating, transmitting, managing between actors A and C. Yet, maybe organizing things is a kind of passion of the human mind à la Charles Fourier; it is an unavoidable trait in one’s nature if one is born with it. Anyway, I want to tell you here my ‘story’ and summarize my experiences on organizing semiotics during a rather long time in a human life. Now I have directed the IASS, the ISI at Imatra, and am chairing the international research project with

424 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period 600 members entitled Musical Signification and the Semiotic Society of Finland. All these semiotic corporations are completely different by their nature, structure and functioning. This is the empirical background and basis for my observations.

23.2 Beginning: Lévi-Strauss, Greimas . . . and Paris In fact, it all started very early. I was 22 years old when I happened to read a tiny book by Claude Lévi-Strauss entitled Myth of Asdiwal, as a Swedish translation. Suddenly a new world opened to me: this was for me! I had before studied philosophy and music, and just started, after military service, with social sciences; they had become fashionable among young intellectuals around the year 1968. LéviStrauss opened semiotics to me, but then it was called structuralism. However, I soon noticed that there was no semiotics at all yet in my surroundings. If I planned to write, speak or publish something about it, the first task was to create a surrounding community which would understand such issues. So was launched a reading circle or study group of young students of sociology, philosophy and arts at Helsinki University. It started to call itself a ‘structuralism group’. It convened almost weekly at my home. We read difficult French and Italian texts as Swedish translations, Umberto Eco’s La struttura assente as Den frånvarande strukturen, etc. Many of us had been active in student movements of those days with a Marxist orientation; for such members structuralism meant some disassociation from that type of intellectual analysis towards a more ‘modern’ approach. Also phenomena hitherto considered improper for an academic discourse were made acceptable by a structuralist approach, as Roland Barthes by his studies on modern myths had shown. On the other hand, also high culture phenomena such as Wagner, Goethe, etc. became open for a student of social sciences. Altogether a fascinating new world opened to young minds in the North. Yet, the first place where I saw organized semiotic teaching was in Paris, where I left for doctoral studies under direction of A. J. Greimas. As a Lithuanian he willingly accepted me in his famous seminars which often gathered 100–200 students of semiotics, particularly from Italy and Latin America. From the Nordic countries only Denmark was represented by several students and by me, the only one from Finland. The seminars were the regular basis for the whole future Paris school. They were not only students but teachers and scholars in general who came there to meet and talk about semiotic theories. That seemed to me an ideal body of semioticians. Nevertheless, I felt myself totally marginal, I did not make friends with any of the participants and also soon noticed that I very little understood what was said there. Therefore, I decided to translate into Finnish the Sémantique structurale

23.3 The Impact of Thomas A. Sebeok |

425

by Greimas in order to step into the system, so to say. I also followed lectures at Collège de France by Lévi-Strauss and by Michel Foucault; I twice met Roland Barthes, but when he heard I was in the seminar by Greimas he lost his interest. However, morally the most important and encouraging encounter in Paris for me was meeting with Claude Lévi-Strauss, the great idol of my young years. It was characteristic of Parisian life that it was possible even for a young 23-yearold student from the North to have an appointment with a great academician. It was helped by our common acquaintance, Professor Elli-Kaija Köngäs-Maranda, the Finnish anthropologist and colleague of Lévi-Strauss, who was then at Laval University in Canada. I particularly remember the following: when I said to LéviStrauss that the structuralism of such a small country like Finland could be only a reflection of such a center as Paris, he interrupted me: “No – the center is always where you are yourself!” My meeting of Parisian scholars was helped by a Bureau d’accueil for foreign visiting scholars which existed at that time at Blvd St. Germain; the lady there was most helpful and organized for me all these meetings. Under these conditions Paris, especially the address 10 rue Monsieur le Prince, the office of Greimas, became the center for my semiotic work. I knew that I could always meet him there on Thursday afternoon when he was having his reception. When I returned from Brazil from one year’s study journey in 1976, I passed by his room and he said: Vous êtes devenu un grand voyageur international. In 1978 I defended my thesis on Myth and Music at Helsinki University, not in Paris, although Greimas had been so kind to propose it, promising that he would check my French writing.

23.3 The Impact of Thomas A. Sebeok Immediately thereafter started the organizing of semiotics in Finland. In May 1979 there gathered at Helsinki University Department of Musicology six persons deciding to found the Semiotic Society of Finland. They were Henri Broms, Juhani Härmä, Osmo Kuusi, Erkki Pekkilä and me. I started to write regular membership letters. Later Vilmos Voigt, who soon became our honorary member – and who in fact had given as early as in 1973 the first course on semiotics at University of Helsinki – noticed that Finnish society was rare in the world since all its activities had been well documented since the beginning. The year 1979 was decisive in the organizing of semiotics in many senses. The IASS/AIS had its second world congress of semiotics in Vienna in the summer. It was preceded by a smaller precongress organized by Voigt and Hungarian semioticians, like Mihály Hoppál, in Budapest on semiotic methodologies. I left there with

426 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period my students; I had got my first post as associate professor of musicology at Helsinki University. The Vienna congress was the first really big congress I attended. It was opened by President Kirchschläger, and the old halls of Vienna University were filled with famous semioticians. I was introduced to Umberto Eco by Voigt. However, in Budapest I had met already an older (as it seemed to me) gentleman who looked like a mixture of Sigmund Freud and the Austrian Emperor, namely Thomas A Sebeok. This started a long friendship which has echoes precisely in semiotic organizations until now. Sebeok was from the Bloomington campus of Indiana University, to which he remained faithful through all his life. But his background was a Finno-Ugrian one, since he had studied the Tcheremiss mythology and language even by empirical field work at Volga in Russia after the war, and also made excursions to Finland and Lapland. He had published in 1947 a study book called Spoken Finnish for the US Army. He had chosen Finno-Ugrian studies as early as at Chicago University where his teacher recommended it as a test: if he could manage the Finnish language he could well become an anthropologist! So practically he spoke Finnish and knew leading Finnish linguists and folklorists of the time. This background was later often forgotten in the US and international semiotic circles. He was the organizer of the international semiotic movement more than anyone else. He created the platforms for others to appear, publishing series at Mouton, Indiana University Press, etc. Sebeok immediately took my thesis Myth and Music and published it as a reprint in his series Approaches to Semiotics. Then he invited me to attend in October 1979 three symposia in Bloomington: a Polish American symposium in logics with a Polish ten-person delegation led by Jerzy Pelc, the President of the IASS (I had met him as a student several times before at University of Helsinki during his guest lectures), the Charles S. Peirce Society symposium and the Annual meeting of the American Semiotic Society. This was also my first trip to the US. I was totally enchanted by the campus of Bloomington, in the deep Midwest of America, not only thanks to semiotics and the famous Research Center for Language and Semiotic Studies but also due to the famous School of Music. I remember the dinner at Memorial Union, with the presence of Umberto Eco, John Deely, Brook Williams, Beatriz Garza Cuaron and many others, hosted by the legendary Dean of the University, Herman B. Wells; with his enormous status he seemed to me like the symbol of all America and its good sides. One of the reasons for Sebeok’s success was that he enjoyed full support all his life from the direction of his university. Later experience has shown me that without such an establishment it is impossible to foster semiotics successfully. Upon invitation by Sebeok I then attended in consecutive years several annual meetings of the Semiotic Society of America, the next one in 1980 at Texas

23.4 Semiotics expands |

427

Tech University in Lubbock, then in Buffalo at SUNY and then in San Francisco, California. This was very important not only due to the contact with American scholars but also because I learned how to organize such meetings. The model of these conventions I could then move to my own Finnish symposia with their structure, business lunch meetings, elections, exhibitions, plenary speeches, etc. That was my school of organizing semiotics.

23.4 Semiotics expands I started to organize in Finland the annual meetings of the Finnish Semiotic Society. The first major one was realized at Jyväskylä University in Middle Finland, where I was holding my first chair of arts education in 1979–1983. This happened in the summer of 1983, and A. J. Greimas arrived there with a group of French colleagues such as François Delalande, Eric Landowski and Serge Martin. Greimas’s lecture Vers la troisième révolution sémiotique was videofilmed and is now available on DVD from the ISI, Imatra. This is noteworthy since there are not many film documents about him anywhere. (In fact Greimas had already in 1979 visited Helsinki University for the first time, but that was not filmed.) I have to mention here that sometimes I felt my position as a friend and colleague of Greimas and Sebeok at the same time rather awkward. As known, they were not on good terms. Sebeok called Greimas a ‘lexicographist’ and was opposed to his school absolutely and had an anti-French attitude altogether. Greimas, on the other hand, said once when I came from Bloomington to Paris: “Les américains n’ont pas fait beaucoup de progrès. Ils n’étudient que les chimpanzés”. Greimas was a little sorry that I had established such close contacts with Indiana University. But for Sebeok his Finnish connection was important. I was proud when I noticed that in his fax machine he had the direct line only to Eco and me in the first place. To defend Sebeok one has to say that in spite of all, he published English translations of Greimas’s works in his series. Via Sebeok I met also John Galman, director of Indiana University Press. He was an intellectual who favored semiotics. So the IU press became also my publisher together with whom we published some issues of Acta Semiotica Fennica, our international series which we had launched in Finland. In 1983 also the IASS had its third world congress in Palermo under Prof. Buttitta, which many Finns attended. Moreover, in the same year Sebeok organized in Estoril, Portugal his Advanced Studies Institute with the topic “Semiotics – Language of international scholarship” funded by NATO. In the same year Norma Tasca together with her husband, Minister José Seabra, had been establishing the Semiotic Society of Portugal; they were running a journal, Cruzeiro semiotico. Any-

428 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period way, in that summer course there were more teachers than students since it had been announced only in the magazine National Geographic. Itamar Even-Zohar, from Israel, and myself were the only persons from non-NATO countries. In these years we also established regular contacts with Estonia. I visited there for the first time in 1982 at a symposium in Tallinn organized by the Estonian Institute for Language and Literature. The main protagonist was then its vice-director Mart Remmel, an extremely intelligent mathematician and semiotician, interested in computers. It was not possible at that time to visit Tartu, a closed city under the Soviets; so the first time we met Yuri Lotman was in 1987 when he came for his visit to Helsinki University together with his student Igor Czernov. From his school we had had Boris Gasparov as lecturer of Russian language as early as in the times of our student structuralism group in the early 1970s. Later students of semiotics from Tartu often visited Helsinki with their teachers Peeter Torop and Kalevi Kull. Other Estonian intellectuals such as Aivo Lõhmus and the composer Leo Normet were also frequently with us. However, semiotics as a discipline to be taught was not in the mind of Lotman. He told me in Helsinki that he had almost no Estonian students. This was perhaps due to fact that KGB did not allow them to attend his courses. Lotman was persecuted by, among others, Endel Sõgel, the communist director of the Estonian Language Institute in Tallinn; he was isolated in Estonia as a Jew and as a Russian. Yet, one has to notice here that neither did Sebeok ever aim for MA or PhD programs in semiotics in his own Indiana University. He said that masters or doctors of semiotics would have no jobs in the US. So he was satisfied with his other international activities.

23.5 Imatra starts: Founding of the ISI Something very important happened in Finland in the organizations in 1986, when from a relatively unknown small town in our Eastern borderline, Imatra, came to Helsinki the director of the local Summer University, Pentti Rossi. Together with Henri Broms, Vice-President of our society, docent of Persian language and Head Librarian of the School of Business in Helsinki he organized days of ‘effective administration’ in Imatra. Next, Broms got the idea: why not do there a symposium on semiotics. The local Mayor, Kalervo Aattela, was in favor, and so in 1986 the first semiotic convention took place at the Imatra Cultural Center in its brand new white ‘palace’ of culture on the river Vuoksi, close to the rapids. The place which had been Finland’s most visited tourist attraction for centuries – when the whole Russian court of Catherine the Great would come from St Petersburg to see the waterfall – was again receiving international guests.

23.5 Imatra starts: Founding of the ISI

|

429

Sebeok was of course invited, and soon the State Hotel, Valtionhotelli, an art nouveau castle, became a center of semioticians as well. In this first semiotic congress in Imatra, there also participated the research group on musical semiotics called Musical Signification, which had been established in Paris in a direct broadcast at French Radio with six scholars: Costin Miereanu, François Delalande, Gino Stefani, Marcello Castellana, Luiz Heitor Corrêa de Azevedo and me. After this important radio program about musical semiotics I told Greimas about our plans to establish the Laboratoire européen pour les études en signification musicale – which title had been invented by Marcello Castellana, a Sicilian student of Greimas; he said: Take its organization to Finland! We here in Paris are a little Bohemian, it would not survive here. So I did and the first symposium in Imatra was attended by such eminent scholar of musical semiotics as Daniel Charles, Márta Grabócz, Ivanka Stoianova, Vladimir Karbusický, Jaroslav Jiránek and Iegor Reznikoff. Now the project has over 600 members and has held 13 international symposia in many European towns and 12 international doctoral and postdoctoral schools of musical semiotics at Helsinki University and Imatra. In the summer congress of 1987 the previous members of the Tartu-Moscow school met in Imatra in a commemorative symposium. Lotman could not come himself but instead many members living in diaspora came, such as Alexander Piatogorsky, Boris Oguibenin, Ann Shukman. Thomas Sebeok was of course also present and spoke about primary and secondary modeling systems. Also such famous scholars as Roland Posner and Masao Yamaguchi attended as well as Vilmos Voigt and Mihály Hoppál. Yet, alongside this meeting convened also for the first time the Nordic Association of Semiotics. This was the first all-Nordic symposium, for which especially the semioticians from Norway were active. The Dutch semiotician of translation Dinda L. Gorlée was there, and among founders of the association were Drude von der Fehr, Elena Hellberg, Sven Storelv, Jørgen Langdahlen, from Norway, Jørgen Dines Johansen, Svend Erik Larsen and Peter Brask from Denmark. A magazine was established also, entitled SEMIONORDICA. One of the decisive years in all these organizations was 1988. It was the year of founding of the International Semiotics Institute or ISI. The Canadian semiotician Paul Bouissac, who in Toronto was running his famous summer schools for structural and semiotic studies, which always lasted one full month, had got the idea to establish an institute to supervise the education of young semioticians and their teaching globally. There had to be a place where one could know everything that happened in semiotics in the whole world; a database from which students would learn where to go in order to specialize in diverse fields of semiotics. He had built a collegium of 44 scholars behind this enterprise, but it was certainly Sebeok’s

430 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period initiative which brought the founding meeting to Imatra. The candidates for the presidency of the ISI were Paul Bouissac and Roland Posner, but in the end I was elected. Finnish media followed this event closely; big articles were published in the main newspaper of the country Helsingin Sanomat, and it was mentioned in the news of TV channel 1. The international scholars who constituted the collegium were Lisa Block de Behar, Paul Bouissac, Maria Lucia Santaella Braga, José Romero Castillo, Igor Czernov, Jean-Claude Gardin, Beatriz Garza Cuaron, Dinda L. Gorlée, Claudio Guerri, Yoshihiko Ikegami, Jørgen Dines Johansen, Walter A. Koch, Alexandros-Phaidon Lagopoulos, You-Zheng Li, Dean MacCannell, Jacques Moeschler, Michael O’Toole, Rik Pinxten, Roland Posner, Debi Prasama Pattanayak, Monica Rector, Joëlle Rethoré, Fernande Saint-Martin, Thomas A. Sebeok, Ropo Sekoni, Ann M. Shukman, R. N. Sriwastava, György Szépe, Eero Tarasti, Terry Threadgold, Colwyn Trevarthen, Salvato Trigo, Patrizia Violi, Vilmos Voigt, Gloria Withalm and Masao Yamaguchi. Moreover, Peter Stockinger was nominated assistant to the President and Henri Broms director of the database. The goals of the Institute were defined as follows (the text written by Paul Bouissac): “First, it will establish an international database of all advanced teaching and research centers relevant to semiotics; the database should contain information on programs offered by other institutes and universities, conditions of admission, bursaries, grants and fellowships; second, it will facilitate mobility of the students; thirdly it will sponsor and organize interdisciplinary conferences workshops, courses and seminars in cooperation with the IASS.” In order to fulfil these tasks there were seven so-called regional centers for geographical areas. Australia, Eastern Europe, Japan and East Asia, Latin America, North America, Western Europe. Each center was supposed to gather information and send regularly to the ISI which was established in Imatra. Such was the ambitious plan. In fact, it was never literally enacted. The idea of regional centers proved to be not realistic, some data were gathered but the Imatra center did not receive information from regional centers as planned. However, when this was noticed, then the ISI started to function on its own, fulfilling the third paragraph of its goals, i.e., international symposia. In this manner Imatra became one of the well-known international centers of semiotic congresses and activities. It continued in these lines until the present. It had the summer congress every early June (it was moved from July in order to avoid coincidence with Urbino summer schools). In 2014 it was moved from Imatra to Kaunas Technological University where Dario Martinelli continues as its director. A little later, when the Toronto Semiotic Circle was no longer willing to continue their Summer schools for structural and semiotic studies, this institution was shifted to Imatra, whose summer congress, however, always lasted only one week. Canadian students of Marcel Danesi came often to these events. For the

23.6 IASS Continues |

431

Finnish audience the ISI started to organize winter schools in early February, amidst the hard Finnish winter. They became immediately very popular and expanded knowledge about the Institute in Finland, which was of course important for funding. The Ministry of Education started to fund the ISI upon the initiative of Minister Riitta Uosukainen, who was from Imatra. Also the City of Imatra continued funding under its Mayors Tauno Moilanen during ten years and Pertti Lintunen. The Institute survived the period of recession in the early 90s. Yet, it did not endure during the present crisis because its funding was finished by the Ministry of Education.

23.6 IASS Continues In the meantime, the IASS continued to function. When Cesare Segre left the Presidency the new President was elected, and he was Jerzy Pelc. After him Roland Posner got the post and held it for two four-year periods. During his time the secretariat was situated also in the German speaking area, namely in Vienna, thanks to Jeff Bernard and Gloria Withalm. They expanded remarkably the scope of the society, and specified its statutes. In addition to an Executive Committee consisting of national representatives from each country, 1–2 persons, it included professional institutes and others. An information bulletin was published regularly. The IASS saw the rise of new continents in semiotics, particularly Latin America. After my student time in Brazil in 1976, I visited again during a tour of Latin America in 1996 and lectured in Buenos Aires, Santiago de Chile, Lima and Santos and São Paulo. The width and scope of semiotics in Latin America was really outstanding. Also Mexico was tremendously active. IASS also started to foster congresses and symposia “under auspices of the IASS” and created formal criteria for such affiliation. The IASS general assemblies reflected the strong passions semiotics evoked among different groups, schools and scholars. In the Barcelona/Perpignan congress, which was the first two-city world congress in the history of the IASS, the assembly had to decide about the next place. Berkeley, California was elected under direction of Irmengard Rauch. When the Berkeley congress was held it was the first time the world congress took place outside of Europe. That was in 1988. Again the next meeting place had to be chosen. The Latin Americans and many others strongly supported Guadalajara as the congress site. Sebeok and some others proposed Helsinki. In the dramatic election Guadalajara won and so Latin America gained its first world congress. At the same time in Monterrey, Mexico, Pablo Espinosa Vera organized a convention he called the First World Congress of Semiotics and Communication, and was able to bring there a lot of semioticians

432 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period from Europe. Newspapers and media from Mexico City came and wrote extensively about the event. In fact, I do not know why the General Assemblies of this society always tended to be quite stormy and heavily debated. Often national and political interests were blended together with the scientific ones. But perhaps this was not so dangerous, since it showed the great interest people had in semiotics. They were passionately involved in the issue (at least during the congresses). Roland Posner was able to arrange the IASS congress next in Dresden, so it was back again in central Europe. In Dresden, the vote was for France and the University of Lyon, where Professors Louis Panier and Bernard Lamizet invited the congress to be held. The attendance during the 1990s was about 500–700 in each congress. All the time Semiotica appeared regularly thanks to Sebeok and his wife Jean Umiker-Sebeok and Mouton de Gruyter in Berlin. In the Posner time, vice-presidents were John Deely, Gérard Deledalle, Adrian Gimate-Welsh, Alexandros-Phaidon Lagopoulos and Eero Tarasti; secretary general was Jeff Bernard and Gloria Withalm as his assistant, the treasurer Magdolna Orosz and assistant treasurer Richard Lanigan. But at the Lyon congress in 2004 Posner’s two-year period expired and a new President was elected and also the Board. Under these conditions a new direction of the IASS was established. I became the President and the Vice-Presidents were as follows: Adrian Gimate-Welsh, Richard Lanigan, Youzheng Li and Jean-Claude Mbarga. The Secretary general became José M. Paz Gago and vice secretary Göran Sonesson, treasurer Susan Petrilli and vice treasurer John Deely. Semiotica editorship was moved to Toronto under Marcel Danesi. Now the Board was chosen and elected perhaps more in line with the geographical expansion of semiotics. Yet it is interesting to notice that no one seems to know until this day how many members there were in the IASS. Very few had paid any longer the membership fees, thinking of the advantages it would bring. However, there were unofficial lists, also provided by the ISI, of some 2000 addresses, which was used for messages and information. With the advent of the internet even this became unnecessary, with Göran Sonesson keeping the webpage and after the La Coruña congress in 2009, Priscila Borges in São Paulo. When I took on the direction of IASS in Lyon, I finally had the courage to propose that Helsinki and Imatra could organize the next world congress in Finland. This happened in 2007. The themes of these world congresses had been always very general, so that everyone could attend. Semiotics itself had exploded in so many directions and dimensions that no one could master or control its growth everywhere. There had been such titles as Man and his Signs. To my mind the titles had to be very common but also reflect in each case the host country and its traditions and orientations. In Finland we had just had a semiotic research

23.7 The World Congress in Finland |

433

project funded by the Finnish Academy on Understanding and Misunderstanding. Behind that was the lecture once given in 1983 Jyväskylä by the American linguist Walburga v. Raffler-Engel who had studied cross-cultural misunderstandings. As our congress patron we invited President Martti Ahtisaari; he wrote an epigram on our program booklet: “Semiotics studies all forms of communication. By analyzing cross-cultural misunderstandings it promotes the self-understanding of mankind”. These words well-suited Ahtisaari, the Nobel Peace Prize winner a year later.

23.7 The World Congress in Finland Now we were able to apply in Finland all that we had learned from organizing semiotic congresses for over twenty years already, but on a much larger scale. So what is needed for a world congress? First, you have to fix the theme and then the plenary speakers. Following the model once provided by the Vienna congress there was a series of lectures about Finnish culture. So we had Professor and Rector of Helsinki University, Ilkka Niiniluoto, to tell about philosophy in Finland; Vilmos Voigt introduced Finno-Ugric semiotics, Jaan Kaplinski from Estonia his views on communication and Pirjo Kukkonen on Finnish tango. The next problem was funding. The idea of a self-funding congress was impossible. So external funding was needed. It was given by sponsors such as the Academy of Finland, City of Imatra, European Social Funds, Finnish Cultural Foundation, Niilo Helander Foundation, Istituto Italiano di Cultura, Ministry of Education, Ministry of Foreign affairs, Nokia and State Provincial Office of Southern Finland. The Ministry of Foreign affairs provided remarkable funding to invite scholars from developing countries and particularly women (they helped us again for our summer congress in 2011). I mentioned the list above as an example for anyone organizing these kinds of conventions. Then we had to decide the congress site, and we agreed to do the event in two cities, first in Helsinki and then in Imatra. For the transportation to Imatra we hired one whole train. The railway station in Helsinki was one morning filled by a huge crowd, all semioticians going to the Imatra congress. One wagon was for a meeting of the Board of the IASS, which could work even during travel. Normally also, the world congress of semiotics has been invited to a buffet reception by the city. This happened in Helsinki as well. Yet the opening ceremony took place in the historic Solemnity Hall of the University of Helsinki with the symphony orchestra of the University which played Finlandia by Sibelius. Also eating is important as a part of the congress, since at lunch and dinner tables people meet each other unofficially and can talk about issues. In my mem-

434 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period ory of world congresses Lyon stands out as a landmark with its super delicious dinner tables. However, as to the behavior of semioticians at the buffet one would recommend a reading of Lévi-Strauss’s L’origine des manières de table. In Finland, Imatra offered its famous Carelian hospitality. Moreover, in order to do a world congress a big and motivated staff is needed. We had a committee of 17 persons including from the teachers’ side Pirjo Kukkonen, Dario Martinelli, Pekka Pesonen, Harri Veivo, Merja Bauters, Susanna Välimäki; others were students. The Helsinki congress was planned to be a ‘dancing congress’ with a ball at the Old Student House, but in fact rather few attended. Semioticians seem to like less formal togetherness. After the congress there still follows the editing of the proceedings. For years the proceedings of IASS congresses had not appeared as printed books. Thanks to the ISI we had a mechanism to produce such a thing, by two years’ hard work by its editors Paul Forsell and Rick Littlefield. The proceedings appeared in 2009 before the La Coruña congress, in three volumes. They did not contain plenary speeches since the speakers did not send their texts, probably thinking that they would never appear as books. I have thought that IASS has two major challenges in international semiotics: 1) to organize world congresses, 2) to keep publishing Semiotica. These two tasks have been fulfilled so far. Semiotica is the pride of its publisher Mouton, under the direction of Anke Beck and Marcia Schwartz. Danesi has as his assistants Andrea Rocci and Paolo Ammirante. In the Imatra General Assembly, in which also the membership criteria for different continents were discussed, the IASS received the invitation from its secretary general José María Paz Gago to convene in his home town La Coruña in Spain. Again a pre-meeting of the Board was organized and the place was confirmed to be a most suitable one. The theme of La Coruña was Communication of Culture/Culture of Communication. So the communication aspect of semiotics was emphasized. The meeting was planned to be held at the handsome congress palace in the harbor, but an economic crisis intervened and so it was held at the University Campus, which fortunately proved to be quite practical, with its several buildings side by side. Upon the initiative of Paz Gago the main outside plenary speaker was the writer Salman Rushdie. He spoke about the meaning of history, and tuned his whole speech in a humanistic manner so that it became a most appropriate message to all of the hundreds of semioticians gathered in the audience. The general assembly, when voting for the new Board, was again fairly stormy with several issues raised about the statutes, and about who was entitled to continue on the Board and who not. Also the Executive Committee brought their national problems on stage to be decided, which was of course not the task of the IASS assembly. Yet things were unresolved after the time of the first long meeting

23.8 From Italy to Bulgaria and Estonia |

435

had expired, and it had to convene again two days later. The new Board consisted of the same as earlier except for new Vice-Presidents, who were Paul Cobley, José Enrique Finol and Anne Hénault. So for the first time also the Paris school was included in the Board of the IASS. It was also decided that next congress would take place at Nanjing Normal University. The future Chinese hosts immediately invited the Board for a planning meeting to see the place. This was the first time many experienced China, its tremendous economic growth and also its growing and flourishing semiotic tradition. The soil had been prepared by, among others, the long-time work by You Zheng Li to introduce the classics of semiotics to China. After Nanjing the preparations for the next world congress to be held at Sofia by New Bulgarian University under Kristian Bankov, vice-rector of the University, had already been launched. The world congress in Sofia proved to be a great success, indeed. Paul Cobley was elected a new President and Kristian Bankov the Secretary General.

23.8 From Italy to Bulgaria and Estonia However, the events at the IASS are only the cover or umbrella for a most manifold development in our discipline on various continents. Here I deal with it only from the organizational point of view and insofar as I have been involved. In many European countries, semiotic master and doctoral programs have emerged, not only in Italy, which has always been the promised land of semiotics. As Umberto Eco said, Italy has a lot of semiotics since it is the same as communication. He had established at Bologna University the all-Italian doctoral program of semiotics, whose courses partly took place also in San Marino under Patrizia Violi and Patrick Coppock. In southern Italy Augusto Ponzio organized a lot of symposia together with Susan Petrilli and Patrizia Calefato. Studies for the doctorate were very well organized there. In Turin, Ugo Volli and Guido Ferrari were teaching semiotics, Omar Calabrese in Siena, Isabella Pezzini in La Sapienza, Rome, Prof. Abruzzese in Milano, and Gianfranco Marrone in Palermo. I was able to visit almost all of these places and meet their gifted students and learned teachers. In Bulgaria semiotics had been started in the early 1990s at the new Bulgarian University, a private academy, by Maria Popova and supported by the President of its Board, former Ambassador Bogdan Bogdanov. Sebeok visited it and so did John Deely and myself. Its most important tradition became the Early Fall Schools of Semiotics, earlier mostly and nowadays always held in Sozopol at the Black Sea. By cooperation with Italian and Greek semioticians it has grown a major educational project of young semioticians, visited by students even from Northern countries like Estonia and Finland. Its director Kristian Bankov is in fact a philosopher who

436 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period received his PhD at Helsinki University, but now he is interested in consumerism and applied semiotics. Such topics as advertising, media, marketing, sports fan clubs, etc. are indeed favored by young Italian, Greek and Bulgarian students. Strong support has been given by Turin University and its Professors Ugo Volli and Massimo Leone, the latter running also a new net magazine of semiotics, Lexia. In the meantime, in Estonia the teaching of semiotics was finally started by Peeter Torop and Kalevi Kull. Tartu University encouraged the memory of Yuri Lotman as the greatest Estonian scientist with a modernist statue in front of the Library in Tartu. The semiotic center of Tartu got the position of Center of Excellence and substantial funding. This happened all rather recently in the late 2000s and early 2010s. The Estonian case shows how important for organizing semiotics it is to have 1) support from the highest direction of the University, 2) a substantial national academic basis and tradition. In the latter sense Estonia could stand on the names of Lotman and Uexküll. The latter was remarkably helped by the late Thomas Sebeok, who considered biology as the key science of semiotics and the future. The son of Jakob v. Uexüll, Thure had continued biosemiotics, which joined with the work of Danish scholars became one of the new paradigms of semiotics altogether. Earlier they used to have their meetings also in Imatra, hosted by the ISI.

23.9 The Finnish Network University of Semiotics as an experiment In Finland a new phase of semiotics was opened when finally, at the third request, the European Union accepted to fund the National Network University of Finland under the guidance of the ISI. The funding was channelled via the Southern Carelian Board, and it was part of the so-called structural funding for unfavorable regions. This started in 2004 and meant rich years for the ISI for many years. 13 national universities joined the project whose aim was to educate PhDs of semiotics in each university in their already existing discipline, but the education and supervision taking place essentially at Imatra. The program included also studies on the Master level of semiotics. The Network University included also such peculiarities as the School of Defense, which under Prof. Aki-Mauri Huhtinen adopted semiotics in the training of officers. One doctoral thesis appeared on the notion of strategy. I had not heard that semiotics was used elsewhere in an army – except in Nanjing, where I met a teacher from its International University, which then proved to be a military academy and the teacher a general.

23.9 The Finnish Network University of Semiotics as an experiment | 437

Anyway, with this money from the EU it was possible to arrange a lot of teaching of semiotics in Imatra and also start a temporary chair of semiotics. Its first holder was Harri Veivo in 2004–2007 from literary studies at the University of Helsinki. The chair was situated at Helsinki University whose own semiotic study program thus gained a remarkable contribution. After this period the chair was moved to the University’s own budget as its temporary professor, whose holder is a Peirce scholar Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen. Besides Veivo, the Network University had two associate professors of semiotics, Dario Martinelli and Guido Ipsen. Still, in spite of this formal structure everything remained on a temporary basis and could change any time the situation would change. In fact, this has happened with the new University Law in Finland that privatized all earlier State Universities. It is still under discussion what impact it had on the science of a country that had thus far a flourishing academic life covering the whole country. Privatization again is a part of the huge epistemic change whose testimonies we all are and which means a total commercialization of all aspects of life. The Chinese Vice-President of the IASS You Zheng Li wrote the following recently: In our congress we will be engaged in many important topical discussions about the future of IASS and semiotics in general. Among many key issues one of the most significant is related to the general humanistic-academic situation in the world today. We are living in a completely commercialized world where the professional benefits become the top principle even in academia. In my opinion this could be the most serious problem: whereas in former times humanist scholars searched for truth, today they search for professional (individual and collective) profits. If so, any results in our practice could be used to continue our “profession”. The consequence must be that our scientific pursuits will be disconnected from the classical ideal for scientific truth. If scholars become businessman-like activists they could also adopt various means that are taken as proper within the commercial world. If we semioticians also follow such laws to search for our professional profits, what will happen to our semiotic future?

Most intelligent people in the world agree that something went wrong. Is it acceptable that all national, regional structures, traditions, jobs, cultures vanish during this enormous global process? It started when someone began to count everything. Such things, which were not earlier counted at all but taken as granted, were now being calculated, they got a price-tag. For instance, take facilities of the universities. Suddenly they were no longer property of the university but of the state. Then the university had to pay rent. But rent came from the state budget. The situation was crazy, with money moving from one pocket to the other. The normal teaching work became completely disturbed by constant evaluations, applications, competitions, all kinds of administrative operations for which the university needed to hire more and more specialists. Less and less money was left

438 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period for the basic functions of the whole academic system. This is the experience in Finland, and probably in the European Union it is the same.

23.10 SEMKNOW Yet, a new agent appeared in Finland in the field of semiotics when Lapland University in Rovaniemi entered the scene. This was thanks to its energetic young Rector Mauri Ylä-Kotola, who had had a philosophical education at Helsinki University, and now as a new Rector in Rovaniemi wanted to have there a lot of international activities. Imatra ISI, which had remained an independent private institute legally on the association basis had for years been looking for an affiliation with some university. This had been recommended earlier by Mrs. Uosukainen under her ministerial time in the 1990s. What made Rovanemi particularly interesting, was that despite its geographical place at a distance from even Helsinki, it had founded an agency called Finnbarents whose only task was to prepare EU applications. They had been successful, since 95 % of their projects had been accepted by Brussels. They had a Belgian agent, Miss Elke Kleutghen, who was from Brussels, and knew exactly what to do. So a new application for semiotics was made for a doctoral program in Europe under direction of Lapland and having three other partners: the New Bulgarian University and the universities in Sofia, Turin in Italy, and Tartu in Estonia. The first try to win the support failed around 2007, the time of our world congress. But a try was made again, and now with success. So started a project whose acronym became SEMKNOW. Its managers changed quickly. Now, when the three years’ planning is going to end and programs are opening in 2013 in every partner university, it’s managed by Irina Geraschenko. The project mission is defined as follows: “The aims of our doctoral program is to provide and develop high level semiotic expertise applicable to social and economic spheres thus being competitive on the labor market”. So the project is the answer to the challenge of new generations of semioticians having been educated until the MA level all over Europe, but without any special views toward a future job. Doctors of semiotics from many countries were writing to me and asking for work in Finland for instance, and even some with brilliant papers from the highest European universities. And the careers of many others, already doctors, had stagnated, and many had been forced to return to college or school as a teacher. So something had to be done quickly so that a whole generation of young semioticians would not feel lost and abandoned. In order to include efficiently the labor market orientation in the doctoral program, it was decided to make socalled company agreements with various enterprises and institutes, so that they

23.11 What do we want? |

439

were ready to receive SEMKNOW doctoral students for a fieldwork period. The agreement had no commitment from companies to really recruit these candidates, but one never knew what could happen. This was definitely on the agenda of the European Union, which had started to think of education only as preparation for a job. In any case, it was a pragmatic answer of semioticians to the challenges of our time. We have to be realistic, even if one were opposed to the total commercialization of life and culture, and even if one were supporting progressive phenomena such as “occupy” movements, ecology, indignant students, etc. The strong point in semiotics has been, through all times, its amazing capacity to adapt to different Umwelt conditions and changes of paradigms. This is why semiotics is still as fresh as ever – and not dead as Julia Kristeva was saying as early as in 1974. Another idea of SEMKNOW was that it would not focus on any particular school of semiotics but that the whole tradition of semiotics should be open to students. Now, the planning phase with a lot of meetings is almost over, and now starts what is called the implementation of the program. For this further funding is requested from Brussels. However, as everyone who has tried knows, this is possible only through professionally trained agents who master the very special EU jargon and bureaucracy. Accordingly, this very important pilot project, whose pioneer was in fact the Finnish Network University of Semiotics in 2004 – in which doctoral studies were experimented with on the national level – is now expanding its ideas into the international and pan-European scene. The idea is that, later, any European university fulfilling the criteria of SEMKNOW could join it. It has also been discussed under which terms double doctorates might be possible or at least co-tutored ones. And all this was initiated from the peripheral area of Lapland, which I myself had never even visited before this project started. But I comforted myself by the fact that I knew also a lot of Brazilians living in Rio or São Paulo who had never been in the Amazons. However, Lapland University is a completely modern university and a model example of how in a vastly smaller context such a utopian issue as semiotics can become a reality.

23.11 What do we want? Altogether, it seems to me that organizing semiotics, globally and nationally, is an endless task. In spite of all, however, I do not believe it to be a Sisyphean task. “Semiotics continues to astonish” as one fresh book has been entitled. How semiotics will survive in the present economic crisis all over the world is hard to anticipate. When university budgets are cut it depends on many things concerning on which list semiotics is put. If it is seen as what is fashionably called

440 | 23 Can Semiotics be organized? Observations over a 40-year period an ‘innovative’ science, it may have a chance. If not, it can still survive as an underground and marginal movement. It may remain as something that seems to be utopian, improbabilité infinie as Hannah Arendt said, as something which one day suddenly becomes a reality. In the present Internet revolution and with the Facebook age, semiotics has not lost one bit of its actuality. Someone just asked in the media, Why do we still need universities when what the professors say in their lectures can be much more easily discovered on the internet? This is obviously a crazy idea, since every society will need a place where young persons not yet mature, not yet knowing who they are and what they want, are kept. When the Japanese semiotician Masao Yamaguchi retired, he established in the remote countryside of his country a Buddhist meditation center and a semiotic university of his own. Might we think of the possibility of a semiotic university, which would teach people the principles of how to deal with the inundation of information, how to choose, select, and distinguish the essential from the unessential? Solomon Marcus recently argued that the majority of people live in a cultural slavery, but they do not know it. Should semioticians reveal it? This is a semio-ethical question. It is young persons’ right to be ignorant, their right is to be in the category of Ernst Bloch’s noch nicht, not yet, as he says in his Prinzip Hoffnung. Perhaps we semioticians also belong in the ‘not-yet class’, as perpetual students of our signs.

Literature Ablali et al. 2009. Vocabulaire des études sémiotiques et sémiologiques, sous la direction de Driss Ablali et Dominique Ducard. Paris: Honoré Champion-Presses universitaires de Franche-Comté. Adorno, Theodor. 1973. Ästhetische Theorie, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp; [In Finnish: Esteettinen teoria. Trans. by Arto Kuorikoski. Tampere: Vastapaino, 2006.] Afnan, Soheil M. 1958. Avicenna. His Life and Works. London: George Allen & Unwin. Ahonen, Pertti. 2003. Elämän työ epävarmuuksien maailmassa [The life work in the world of uncertainties]. Tampere: Tampere University Press. Almeida, Renato. 1974. A Inteligência do Folclore. 2a edicão. Rio de Janeiro: Companhia Editora Americana. Altman, Rick. 1999. Film/Genre. London: British Film Institute. Andrieu, Bernard and Gilles Boëtsch (eds.). 2008. Dictionnaire du corps. Paris: CNRS Editions. Apo, Satu. 1986. Ihmesadun rakenne [The structure and message of magic tales]. (Proceedings of the Finnish Literary Society 446.) Helsinki: Suomalaisen kirjallisuuden seura. Aron, Raymond. 1948. Introduction à la philosophie de l’histoire. Paris: Gallimard. Aron, Raymond. 1961. Introduction to the Philosophy of History. An Essay on the Limits of Historical Objectivity. Trans. by George J. Irwin. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Asafiev, Boris. 1977. Musical Form as a Process. 3 vols. Trans. by James Tull. Diss. Ohio State University. Aspelin, Kurt; Bengt A. Lundberg. 1971. Form och struktur. Litteraturvetenskapliga texter i urval. Stockholm: Bokförlaget Pan/Norstedts. Avicenna & al-Ghazali. 2001. Kaksi filosofia: Avicennan ja al-Ghazalin omaelämäkerrat [Two philosophers: The autobiographies of Avicenna and al-Ghazali]. Ed. by Jaakko Hämeen-Anttila. Trans. by Jaakko Hämeen-Anttila ja Taneli Kukkonen. Helsinki: Basam Books. Bacon, Henry. 2008. Ein aussergewöhnliches und vielseitiges Darstellungstalent: Romy Schneider in Viscontis Boccaccio 70 (Episode: Il lavoro) und Ludwig. In K. Moser (ed.), Romy Schneider. Film. Rolle. Leben. 95–115. Vienna: Verlag Filmarchiv. Bagh, Peter von. 2006. Aki Kaurismäki. Helsinki: WSOY. Bakhtin, Mihail. 1979. Kirjallisuuden ja estetiikan ongelmia [Problems of literature and aesthetics]. Trans. from Russian to Finnish by Kerttu Kyhälä-Juntunen and Veikko Airola. Moskova: Kustannusliike Progress. Bakhtin, M. M. 1981. The Dialogic Imagination. Four Essays. Edited by Michael Holquist. Translated by Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. Austin: University of Texas Press. Bakhtin, M. M. 1996. The Dialogic Imagination. Four Essays. Edited by Michael Holquist. Trans. by Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. (University of Texas Press Slavic Series No. 1.) Austin: University of Texas Press. Bankov, Kristian. 2000. Intellectual Effort and Linguistic Work. Semiotic and Hermeneutic Aspects of the Philosophy of Bergson. (Acta Semiotica Fennica IX.) Imatra: International Semiotics Institute. Bankov, Kristian. 2004. “Infinite Semiosis and Resistance”. In Eero Tarasti (ed.), From Nature to Psyche. Proceedings from the ISI Summer Congresses at Imatra in 2001–2002. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XX.) Imatra: International Semiotics Institute. Barker, Chris. 2008. Cultural Studies. Theory & Practice. Los Angeles, London etc.: Sage.

442 | Literature Barthes, Roland. 1957/2010. Mythologies. Edition illustrée établie par Jacqueline Guittard. Paris: Seuil. Barthes, Roland. 1970. S/Z. Paris: Editions du Seuil. Barthes, Roland. 1973. Le plaisir du texte. Paris:Seuil. Barthes, Roland. 1975a. Roland Barthes par Roland Barthes, Ecrivains de toujours. Paris: Seuil Barthes, Roland. 1975b. Rasch. Langue, Discours, Société. Paris: Seuil. Barthes, Roland. 1977. Image, Music, Text. Translated by Stephen Heath. New York: Hill and Wang Barthes, Roland. 1978. Leçon. Paris. Seuil Barthes, Roland. 1985. L’aventure sémiologique. Paris: Seuil. Bastide, Françoise. 1979. Le foie lavé – Approche sémiotique d’un texte de sciences expérimentales. Documents de recherche du Groupe de Recherche sémiolinguistique de l’Institut de la Langue Française. Paris : EHESS, CNRS, numero 7. Benedict, Ruth. 1951. Kulttuurin muodot [Patterns of culture]. Trans. by Kai Kaila; Helsinki: Porvoo. Bergson, Henri. 1938. La pensée et le mouvant. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Bergson, Henri. 1969. L’évolution créatrice. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Bergson, Henri. 1938/1975. La pensée et le mouvant. Paris: PUF. Bergson, Henri. 1939/1982. Matière et mémoire. Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France. Bloch, Ernst. 1985. Das Prinzip Hoffnung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Boss, Medard. 1953. Der Traum und seine Auslegung. Bern: Huber. Botz-Bornstein, Thorsten. 2006. Vasily Sesemann, Experience, Formalism and the Question of Being. Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi. Bouissac, Paul, Herzfeld, Michael, and Posner, Roland (eds.). 1986. Iconicity: Essays on the Nature of Culture. Festschrift for Thomas A. Sebeok on his 65th Birthday. Tübingen: Stauffenburg Verlag. Braudel, Fernand. 1973. Capitalism and Material Life 1400–1800. Transl. by Miriam Kochan. Original edition: Civilisation Matérielle et Capitalisme, 1967. London: Cox & Wyman. Brémond, Claude. 1973. Logique du récit. Paris: Seuil. Brent, Joseph. 1993. Charles Sanders Peirce. A Life. Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Brillat-Savarin, J. A. 1988. Maun fysiologia. Suuri ranskalainen gastronomian klassikko [Physiologie du goût., 1826]. Jyväskylä: Koko kansan kirjakerho. Broms, Henri. 1985. Alkukuvien jäljillä – kulttuurin semiotiikkaa [On the track of preimages – semiotics of culture]. Juva: WSOY. Burckhardt, Jakob. 1951. Maailmanhistorian näköaloja [Reflections on world history]. Suom. Eino E. Suolahti. Helsinki: Otava. Cauquelin, Anne. 2010. À l’angle des mondes possible. Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France. Chapman, John Jay. 1919. Portrait of Josiah Royce, the philosopher. The Outlook, vol 122 no. 9. 372 and 377. Cobley, Paul (ed.). 1996. The Communication Theory Reader. London and New York: Routledge. Cobley, Paul (ed.). 2001. The Routledge Companion to Semiotics and Linguistics. London and New York: Routledge. Cobley, Paul. 2002. Analyzing narrative genres. Sign System Studies 29 (2). Tartu: Tartu University.

Literature

| 443

Comte, Auguste. 1911. La philosophie positive. Resumé par Emile Rigolage (Jules Rig.). Tome deuxième. Paris: Ernest Flammarion. Condé, Gérard (ed.). 1981. Hector Berlioz: cauchemars et passions. Paris: J.-C. Lattes. Czernov, lgor. 1986. Johdatus Juri Lotmanin systeemiin [Introduction to the system of Yuri Lotman]. Punalippu 11. Petroskoi: Karjala-kustantamo. Dahlhaus, Carl. 1973. Zur Problematik der musikalischen Gattungen im 19. Jahrhundert. In Wulf Arlt, Ernst Lichtenhan, Hans Oesch, Max Haas (eds.), Gattungen der Musik in Einzeldarstellungen: Gedenkschrift Leo Schrade. Bern and Munich: Francke Verlag. Dahlhaus, Carl. 1985. Richard Wagners Musikdramen. Zürich; Schwäbisch Hall: Orell Füssli. Danuser, Hermann (ed.). 1988. Gattungen der Musik und ihre Klassiker. (Publikationen der Hochschule für Musik und Theater Hannover.) Laaber: Laaber Verlag. Darrault-Harris, Ivan and Jean-Pierre Klein. 2007. Pour une psychiatrie de l’ellipse. Les aventures du sujet en création. Limoges: Presses Universitaires de Limoges. Deely, John. 2001. Four Ages of Understanding: The First Postmodern Survey of Philosophy From Ancient Times to the Turn of the Twenty-First Century. Toronto, Buffalo (NY), London: University of Toronto Press. Deledalle, Gérard. 1995. John Dewey. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix. 1987. A Thousand plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia. transl. and foreword by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota Press. Dosse, François. 1991. Histoire du structuralisme. I. Le champ du signe, 1945–1966. Paris: Editions La Découverte Ducrot, Oswald & Tzvetan Todorov. 1972. Dictionnaire encyclopédique des sciences du langage. Paris: Seuil. Eagleton, Terry. 1996. Ideology. An Introduction. London and New York: Verso. Eco, Umberto. 1971. Den frånvarande strukturen, Lund: Bo Cavefors. Eco, Umberto. 1985. Matka arkipäivän epätodellisuuteen [Faith in fakes: travels in hyperreality]. Trans. by Aira Buffa. Juva: WSOY. Eco, Umberto. 1986. Art and Beauty in the Middle Ages. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Eco, Umberto. 1992. Les limites de l’interprétation. Traduit de l’italien par Myriam Bouzher. Paris: Bernard Grasset. Eco, Umberto. 1995. How to Travel with a Salmon & Other Essays. San Diego, New York: Harcourt Brace & Company. Eco, Umberto. 1997. Kant et l’ornithorynque. Traduit de l’italien par Julien Gayrard. Paris: Bernard Grasset. Einstein, Alfred. 1941. Greatness in Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Elias, Norbert. 1978. The History of Manners. The Civilizing Process: Volume I. New York: Pantheon Books. Elias, Norbert. 1997. Saksalaiset. Valtataistelut ja habituskehitys 1800- ja 1900-luvuilla [The Germans: power struggles and the development of habitus in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries]. Translated into Finnish by Paula Nieminen. Helsinki: Gaudeamus. Eschbach, Achim. 1983. Significs as a Fundamental Science. In Victoria Lady Welby, What is Meaning? Studies in the Development of Significance, ix–xxxii. (Reprint of the edition London, 1903, with an introductory essay by Gerrit Mannoury and a preface by Achim Eschbach.) (Foundations of Semiotics 2.) Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

444 | Literature Espagne, Michel. 1999. Les transferts culurels franco-allemands. Paris: PUF. Excousseau, J.-L. 1985. ‘Objectivité’ et ‘subjectivité’ dans les sciences physiques. Actes sémiotiques, Documents du Groupe de recherches sémio-linguistiques, EHESS, CNRS, Paris VII. 66. Fabbri, Franco. 1937/1996. Che genere di musica?, I generi musicali e i loro metalinguaggi. In Il suono in cui viviamo. Milan: Feltrinelli. Finol, José Enrique. 2004. Globalicazion y cultura. Estrategia simbolicas y vida cotidiana. Paper presented in Congress of the Spanish Society of Semiotics. Teneriffa: La Laguna. Firebird and Snow Maiden. Fabulous works from the collections of the State Tretyakov Gallery. Catalogue. Helsinki Art Museum Fisch, Max F. 1986. Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism. Eds. Kenneth Laine Ketner and Christian J. W. Kloesel. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Fontanille, Jacques s.d. Soma et séma. Figures du corps. Paris: Maisonneuve et Larose. Foucault, Michel. 1970. Les mots et les choses [The Order of Things. An archaeology of Human Sciences]. London: Tavistock Publications. Fricke, Richard. 1906/1998. Wagner in Rehearsal 1875–1876. The diaries of Richard Fricke. A translation by George R. Fricke, edited by James Deaville with Evan Baker. (Franz Liszt Studies Series 7.) New York: Pendragon Press. Frye, Northrop. 1957/1990. Anatomy of Criticism. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Fuják, Július (ed.). 2007. Convergences and Divergences of Existential Semiotics. Proceedings from symposium at Constantine the Philosopher University, April 12th 2007. Nitra: Faculty of Arts. Fuják, Július. 2011. Comprovisation – Notes on the validity of the notion. Musicologica 1. Prague: AMU. Furtwängler, Wilhelm. 1951. Keskusteluja musiikista [Concerning music]. Ed. Timo Mäkinen. Porvoo and Helsinki: WSOY. Gogol, Nikolai. 1835/1985. The Complete Tales of Nikolai Gogol. Vol. 2. Ed. Leonard J. Kent. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Goldmann, Lucien. 1956. Le dieu caché. Paris: Gallimard. Goodman, Nelson. 1976. Languages of art: An approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Greimas, A. J. 1966. Sémantique structurale. Paris: Larousse. Greimas, A. J. 1973. Toward a theory of modalities. In On Meaning: Selected Writings in Semiotic Theory. Trans. Paul Perron and Frank Collins. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Greimas, A. J. 1976. Maupassant. La sémiotique du texte: exercises pratiques. Paris: Seuil. Greimas, A. J. 1979. La soupe au pistou ou la construction d’un objet de valeur. In Du sens II: Essais sémiotiques. Paris: Seuil. 157–169. Greimas, A. J. 1980. Strukturaalista semantiikkaa. (Translated by Eero Tarasti from Sémantique structurale, 1966). Tampere: Gaudeamus. Greimas, A. J. 1983. Du sens. Paris: Seuil. Greimas, A. J.; J. Courtés 1979. Sémiotique. Dictionnaire raisonné de la théorie du langage. Paris: Hachette Université.

Literature

| 445

Greimas, A. J. and J. Courtés. 1986. Sémiotique: Dictionnaire raisonné de la théorie du langage, tome 2. Paris: Hachette. Grimm, Jacob. 1835. Deutsche Mythologie. Göttingen: Dieterich. Guerra Lisi, Stefania. 1996. Sinestesiarte nella Globalità dei Linguaggi. Bologna: Fuori Thema. Guerra Lisi, Stefania. 2003. Occhio di pino. Pinocchio, San Francesco, Italo Calvino. Roma: Edizioni Borla. Guerra Lisi, Stefania (a cura di). 2005. Contatto, Comunicazione, Autismo. Milano: Franco Angeli. Guerra Lisi, Stefania. 2010. Il Corpo matrice di Segni nella Globalità dei Linguaggi. Roma : Edizioni Borla. Guerra Lisi, Stefania; Gino Stefani. 2002. Arte e follia. Roma : Armando Editore. Guerra Lisi, Stefania; Gino Stefani. 2006. Prenatal Styles in the Arts and the Life. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XXIV.) Imatra/Roma: International Semiotics Institute/Università popolare di MusicArterapia. Guerra Lisi, Stefania; Giovanna Serazzi. 2003. Noi come Voi. Roma: Edizioni Arti Terapie. Habermas, Jürgen. 1987. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Band I. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Hämeen-Anttila, Jaakko. 2002. Jumalasta juopuneet: Islamin mystiikan käsikirja [Drunk on God: The handbook of Islamic mysticism]. Helsinki: Basam Books. Hardwick, Charles S. 1977. Semiotic and Significs: The Correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby. Bloomington (IN) and London: Indiana University Press. Hatten, Robert S. 1994. Musical Meaning in Beethoven: Markedness, Correlation, and Interpretation. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Hegel, G. W. F. 1838. Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte. Hrsg. v. Eduard Gans. Berlin: Verlag von Duncker und Humblot. Hegel, G. W. F. 1917. Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte. I. Band: Einleitung. Leipzig: Verlag von Felix Meiner. Hegel, G. W. F. 1989. Logiikan tiede I (alkulukuja). Trans. by E. Tarasti. Synteesi 1–2. “Der deutsche Geist.” 2–11. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Heidegger, Martin 1967. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag. Helbo, André. 1987. Theory of Performing Arts. Amsterdam, Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Hepokoski, James. 1993. Sibelius: Symphony No. 5. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hermans, Hubert (ed.). 2002. Theory & Psychology. Special issue: The Dialogical Self. Vol 12, number 2, April. Alberta: Sage Publications. Hoffmeyer, Jesper. 1993. Signs of Meaning in the Universe. Advances in Semiotics. Bloomington: Indianapolis. Indiana University Press. Huhtinen, Aki-Mauri (ed.). 2002. Sotilasjohtamisen tutkimuksen tieteenfilosofiset perusteet ja menetelmät [Scientifico-philosophical foundations and methods of studies in military leadership and management]. Helsinki: Maanpuolustuksen korkeakoulu [Finnish National Defense University]. Julkaisusarja 2, Artikkelikokoelma no. 9. Hume, David. 1748/1955. An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding. New York: Liberal Arts Press. Husserl, Edmund. 1995. Fenomenologian idea. Viisi luentoa [The idea of phenomenology. Five lectures]. Helsinki: Loki-Kirjat. Husserl, Edmund. 2000. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag. Inge Godoy, Rolf; Marc Leman (eds.). 2010. Musical Gestures. Sound, Movement, and Meaning. New York, London: Routledge.

446 | Literature Inwood, Michael. 1992. A Hegel Dictionary. The Blackwell Philosopher Dictionnaries. Oxford, Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers. Jacono, Jean-Marie. 1996. “Quelles perspectives sociologiques pour une sémiotique de la musique?”. In Eero Tarasti (ed.), Musical Semiotics in Growth. (Acta Semiotica Fennica 4.) Imatra, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, International Semiotics Institute. Jacono, Jean-Marie. 2008. “Une étrange absence – Jean-Jacques Nattiez à la sémiotique d’Eero Tarasti”. In Robert S. Hatten, Pirjo Kukkonen, Richard Littlefield, Harri Veivo, Irma Vierimaa (eds.), A Sounding of Signs. Modalities and Moments in Music, Culture, and Philosophy. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XXX.) Helsinki: Semiotic Society of Finland. Jakobson, Roman. 1975. Sémiologie, poétique, épistémologie. L’Arc 60. Paris-Marseille Jalava, Antti. 1981. Asfalttikukka [The asphalt flower]. Juva: WSOY. Jankélévitch, Vladimir. 1961. La musique et l’ineffable. Paris: Librairie Armand Colin. Jankélévitch, Vladimir. 1974. L’irréversible et la nostalgie. Paris: Flammarion. Jankélévitch, Vladimir. 1992. “Plongée dans un labyrinthe de mystère et d’angoisse.” Temoignaces et documents. In Gilles Macassar et Bernard Mérigaud, Claude Debussy: le plaisir et la passion. Paris: Gallimard. Jaspers, Karl. 1948. Philosophie. Berlin, Göttingen, Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. Jaspers, Karl. 1950. Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte. München: R. Piper & Co. Verlag. Johansen, Jørgen Dines. 1993. Dialogic Semiosis. An Essay on Signs and Meaning. Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Johansen, Jørgen Dines. 2002. Literary Discourse. A Semiotic Pragmatic Approach to Literature. Toronto, Buffalo, London: University of Toronto Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1968. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Stuttgart: Reclam. Karbusicky, Vladimir. 1985. Sechs Vorträge zur Semiotik und Kulturanthropologie der Musik. Helsinki 5.–13. September 1985. Manuscript. Karbusicky, Vladimir. 1992. Kulturwandel als Kodewandel: Zur Evolution musikalischer Gattungen. In M. Landsch, H. Karnowski, and I. Bystrina (eds.), Kultur, Evolution: Fallstudien und Synthese. Frankfurt am Main and New York: Peter Lang. Karsavin, Lev. 2003. Le poème de la mort. Traduction postface et apercu biographique par François Lesourd. Lausanne: Editions l’Age d’ Homme. Kaurismäki, Aki. 2003. Mies vailla menneisyyttä [The man without a past]. Helsinki: WSOY. Kircher, Athanasius. 1650. Musurgia universalis sive Ars magna consoni et dissoni in X libros digesta. Roma: Corbelletti. Kivi, Aleksis. 1973. Seven Brothers. Trans. by Alex Matson. Helsinki: Tammi. Knuuttila, Sirkka. 2009. Fictionalising Trauma. The Aesthetics of Marguerite Duras’s India Cycle. Helsinki: University of Helsinki. Knuuttila, Tarja. 2005. Models as Epistemic artefacts. Toward a Non-Representationalist Account of Scientific Representation. Doctoral thesis. University of Helsinki. Kokkonen, Joonas. 1992. Ihminen ja musiikki. Valittuja kirjoituksia, esitelmiä, puheita ja arvosteluja [Humans and music. Selected writings, presentations, speeches and criticism]. Jyväskylä: Gaudeamus. Köngäs-Maranda, Elli-Kaija; Pierre Maranda. 1962. Structural models in folklore. Midwest Folklore Fall 1962. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University. Kostka, Stefan. 1999. Materials and Techniques of Twentieth-Century Music. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Kowzan, Tadeusz. 1970. Littérature et spectacle dans leurs rapports esthétiques, thématiques et sémiologiques. Varsovie: Editions de Pologne.

Literature

| 447

Kowzan, Tadeusz. 1992. Spectacle et signification. Québec. Les Éditions Balzac. Kress, Günther and van Leeuwen, Theo. 2001. Multimodal Discourse. London: Hodder Arnold Publications. Kristeva, Julia. 1969. Zeemeiotikee. Recherches pour une sémanalyse. Paris: Seuil. Kristeva, Julia. 1999–2000. Le génie féminin. 3 vols. Paris: Fayard. Kukkonen, Pirjo. 2014. I språkets vida rum. Salens språk – Språkets sal. Volter Kilpis modernistiska prosaepos Alastalon salissa i Thomas Warburtons svenska översättning I Salen på Alastalo. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XLIV.) Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Kurkela, Vesa. 1989. Musiikkifolklorismi ja järjestökulttuuri [Musical folkloristics and organisational culture]. (Suomen etnomusikologisen seuran julkaisuja 3). Jyväskylä: Gaudeamus. Kuronen, Tuomas. 2011. Ritual in constructing strategic leadership mythologies. Doctoral dissertation. Helsinki: Aalto University. Kurth, Ernst. 1922. Grundlagen des linearen Kontrapunktes. Berlin: Max Hesse Verlag. Kuusi, Osmo and Elina Hiltunen. 2011. The Signification Process of the Future Sign. Journal of Futures Studies, September 2011, 16(1). 47–66. Laine, Kimmo; Matti Lukkarila, and Juha Seitajärvi (eds.). 2004. Valentin Vaala. Helsinki: Suomalaisen Kirjallisuuden Seura. Laine-Almi, Doris. 2000. “Tanssin kieli, vanha kieli” [The language of dance, old language]. Synteesi 1. Special issue on Body language. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Landowski, Eric. 1997. Présences de l’autre, Paris: PUF. LaRue, Jan. 1994. Guidelines for Style Analysis. Warren (Michigan): Harmonie Park Press. Leach, Edmund. 1970. Lévi-Strauss. Helsinki: Tammi. Leino, Eino. 1928. Tuomas Vitikka. (Kootut teokset 9). Helsinki: Otava. Lejeune, Philippe. 1975. Le pacte autobiographique. Paris: Editions Seuil. Leone, Massimo. 2014. Annunciazioni: percorsi di semiotica della religione. Rome: Aracne. Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1971. Totalité et l’infini. Essai sur L’extériorité. Paris: Kluwer Academic. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1947. Les structures élémentaires de la parenté. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1962 Anthropologie structurale. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1963. Structural Anthropology. Tr. Claire Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf. New York: Basic Books. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1964. Le cru et le cuit: Mythologiques I. Paris: Librairie Plon. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1973. Anthropologie structurale deux. Paris: Plon. Lidov, David. 1980. Musical Structure and Musical Significance (working paper). Toronto Semiotic Circle. Toronto: Victoria University. Lõhmus, Maarja. 2002. Transformation of Public Text in a Totalitarian System: A Socio-Semiotics Study of Soviet Censorship Practices in Estonian Radio in the 1980s. (Annales Universitatis Turkuensis Series B, vol 248.) Turku: Université de Turku. Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1948. Essays in the History of Ideas. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press. Luyken, Lorenz. 1995. “. . . aus dem Nichtigen eine Welt schaffen . . . .”: Studien zur Dramaturgie im symphonischen Spätwerk von Jean Sibelius. Kölner Beiträge zur Musikforschung. Kassel: Gustav Bosse Verlag. Mâche, François-Bernard. 1983. Musique, mythe, nature ou les dauphins d’Arion. Paris: Klincksieck. Malecka, Teresa and Malgorzata Pawlowska (eds.). 2014. Music as a Message of Truth and Beauty. Krakow: Academia Muzyczna w Krakowie.

448 | Literature Marc-Lipiansky, Mireille. 1973. Le structuralisme de Lévi-Strauss. Paris: Payot. Marrone, Gianfranco. 2007. Il discorso di marca. Modelli semiotici per il branding. Roma, Bari: Editori Laterza. Martinelli, Dario. 2010. Authenticity, Performance and Other Double-Edged Words. Essays on Popular Music. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XXXVIII.) Imatra: International Semiotics Institute. Helsinki: Umweb Publications. Martinelli, Dario. 2014. Lights, Camera, Bark! Representation, semiotics and ideology of non-human animals in cinema. Kaunas: Publishing House Technologija. Martinelli, Dario; Francesco Spampinato. 2009. La coscienza di Gino. Esperienza musicale e arte di vivere. Saggi in onore di Gino Stefani. Helsinki/Roma: Umweb Publications/Università di Roma Tor Vergata. Martinez, José Luiz. 1997. Semiosis in Hindustani Music. (Acta Semiotica Fennica V.) Helsinki and Imatra: International Semiotics Institute. Mbarga, Jean-Claude. 2012. L’essence du Camerounais. Théories et critiqe. Paris: L’Harmattan. Mead, George Herbert. 1938. The Philosophy of the Act. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Meyer, Leonard B. 1978. Explaining Music: Essays and Explorations. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Meyer, Leonard B. 1989. Style and Music, History and Ideology. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Michel, Régis. 1992. Géricault, l’invention du réel. Paris: Gallimard. Mirka, Danuta. 1997. The Sonoristic Structuralism of Krzysztof Penderecki. Katowice: Music Academy of Katowice. Morris, Charles. 1956. Varieties of Human Values. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Morris, Charles. 1971. Writings on the general theory of signs. The Hague and Paris: Mouton. Motiekaitis, Ramunas. 2011. Poetics of the Nameless Middle. Japan and the West in Philosophy and Music of the Twentieth Century. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XL.) Helsinki: Semiotic Society of Finland. Münster, Arno. 1982. Utopie, Messianismus und Apokalypse im Frühwerk von Ernst Bloch. (Suhrkamp Taschenbuch, Wissenschaft 372.) Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Münster, Arno. 1997. Le principe dialogique. De la réflexion monologique vers la pro-flexion intersubjective (Essais sur M. Buber, E. Lévinas, F. Rosenzweig, G. Scholem et E. Bloch). Paris: Kimé. Münster, Arno. 2007. Sartre et la morale. Paris: L’Harmattan. Mukařovský, Jan. 1978. Form, Sign and Function. Trans. by John Burbank and Peter Steiner. New Haven, London: Yale University Press. Murtomäki, Veijo. 1993. Symphonic Unity: The Development of Formal Thinking in the Symphonies of Sibelius. (Studia Musicologica Universitatis Helsingiensis 5.) Helsinki: Department of Musicology, University of Helsinki. Naudin, Jean-Bernard, Anne Borrel, and Alain Senderens. 1992. Zu Gast bei Marcel Proust. Der grosse Romancier als Gourmet. München: Wilhelm Heyne Verlag. Nignon, Édouard. 1995. Éloges de la cuisine française. Ligugé: Inter-Livres. Nöth, Winfried. 2000. Handbuch der Semiotik. 2. Vollständig neu bearbeitete und erweiterte Auflage. Stuttgart, Weimar: Verlag J. B. Metzler. Obolenski, Ruhtinatar Olga [Princess Olga]. 1931/1991. Herkkuja ruhtinattaren keittiöstä [Delicacies from the kitchen of a Princess]. Reprinted as Nuoren emännän herkkuleivosopas. Porvoo: WSOY.

Literature

| 449

Parland, Oscar. 1991. Tieto ja eläytyminen: Esseitä ja muistelmia [Knowledge and empathy: essays and reminiscences]. Juva: WSOY. Peirce, Charles S. 1955. Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Comp., tr., and introduction by Julius Buchler. New York: Dover. Pesonen, Pekka. 1987. Vallankumouksen henki hengen vallankumouksessa. Tutkielma Andrei Belyin romaanista ‘Peterburg’ ja sen aatetaustasta. [The spirit of revolution in the revolution of the spirit. A study of Andrei Bely’s novel ‘Peterburg’ and its ideological background]. (Slavica helsingiensia. Supplementum II.) Helsinki: University of Helsinki. Pesonen, Pekka; Timo Suni (eds.). 2001. Venäläinen formalismi [Russian formalism]. (Tietolipas 172.) Helsinki: Finnish Literary Society. Petrilli, Susan (ed.). 2007. Philosophy of Language as the Art of Listening: On Augusto Ponzio’s Scientific Research. Bari: Edizionio al Sud. Petrilli, Susan (ed.). 2009. Signifying and Understanding: Reading the Works of Victoria Welby and the Signific Movement. Berlin: Mouton. Petrilli, Susan and Augusto Ponzio. 1999. Fuori campo: I segni del corpo tra rappresentazione ed eccedenza. Milano: Mimesis. Pihlström, Sami. 2002. Linguistic Practices and Transcendental Arguments: Taylor and Wittgenstein. In Arto Laitinen and Nicholas H. Smith (eds.), Perspectives on the Philosophy of Charles Taylor. (Acta Philosophica Fennica 71.) Helsinki: Societas Philosophica Fennica. Pihlström, Sami. 2003. Naturalizing the Transcendental. A Pragmatic View. New York: Prometheus Books, Humanity Books. Pikkarainen, Esa. 2004. Merkityksen ongelma kasvatustieteessä. Lähtökohtia pedagogisen toiminnan perusrakenteen semioottiseen analyysiin [The problem of meaning in educational science. Starting points for the semiotic analysis of the fundamental structure of pedagogic action]. (Acta Universitatis Ouluensis E 69.) Oulu: Oulun yliopisto. Ponzio, Augusto. 1993. Signs, Dialogue and Ideology. Edited and translated from Italian by Susan Petrilli. Amsterdam. John Benjamins Publishing Company. Ponzio, Augusto. 1997a. Semiotica della musica: Introduzione al linguaggio musicale. Bari: Graphis. Ponzio, Augusto. 1997b. Elogio dell’infunzionale. Critica dell’ideologia della produttività. Rome: Castelvecchi; (2nd ed. Milan: Mimesis, 2005.) Ponzio, Augusto. 1998. La coda dell’occhio. Letture del linguaggio letterario. Bari, Graphis. Ponzio, Augusto. 1999. La comunicazione. Bari: Graphis. Porges, Heinrich. 1881–1896/1983. Wagner Rehearsing the ‘Ring’. An Eye-Witness Account of the Stage Rehearsals of the First Bayreuth Festival. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Post, Emily. 1945. Etiquette: The Blue Book of Social Usage. New York: Funk & Wagnalls. Propp, Vladimir. 1970. Morphologie du conte. Points. Paris: Editions du Seuil Ricoeur, Paul. 1967. Histoire et vérité. Paris: Editions du Seuil. Ricoeur, Paul. 1983. Temps et récit. Paris: Editions du Seuil. Ricoeur, Paul. 2000. La mémoire, l’histoire, l’oubli. Paris: Editions du Seuil. Rink, John. 2006. Musical Performance. A Guide to Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rossi-Landi, Ferruccio. 1973. Semiotik. Ästhetik, Ideologie. Munich, Vienna: Carl Hanser. Rossi-Landi, Ferruccio. 1976. Ideologies of linguistic relativity. (Approaches to Semiotics 4.) The Hague, Paris: Mouton.

450 | Literature Royce, Josiah. 1969. The Basic Writings of Josiah Royce. Ed. with Introduction by J. McDermott. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. Royce, Josiah. 1998. Metaphysics. Edited by W. E. Hocking, Richard Hocking and Frank Oppenheimer. New York: State University of New York Press. Runeberg, Johan Ludvig. 1948. Vänrikki Stålin tarinat [The stories of Ensign Stål]. Porvoo: WSOY. Ruskin, John. 1843–1860/1987. Modern Painters. Ed. and abridged by David Barrie. London: Andre Deutsch Ryan, Michael. 2010. Cultural Studies. A Practical Introduction. London: Wiley-Blackwell. Salmenhaara, Erkki. 1970. Tapiola. Sinfoninen runo Tapiola Sibeliuksen myöhäistyylin edustajana [Tapiola: The symphonic poem Tapiola as representative of Sibelius’s late style]. (Acta Musicologica Fennica 4.) Helsinki: Suomen Musiikkitieteellinen Seura. Salmenhaara, Erkki. 1979. Tutkielmia Brahmsin sinfonioista. [Studies in Brahms’s symphonies]. (Acta Musicologica Fennica 12.) Helsinki: Suomen Musiikkitieteellinen Seura. Salosaari, Kari. 1989. Perusteita näyttelijäntyön semiotiikkaan. I osa: Teatterin kieli ja näyttelijä merkityksen tuottajana [Fundamentals of the semiotics of acting. Part 1: The language of theatre and the actor as producer of meaning]. (Acta Universitatis Tamperensis ser A vol 262.) Tampere: Tampereen yliopisto. Salosaari, Kari. 2000. Eleellisyyden tutkimuksesta näyttelijäntyössä [On the gestural in acting]. Synteesi 1. 3–11. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Samuels, Robert. 1995. Mahler’s Sixth Symphony. (Cambridge Studies in Music Theory and Analysis.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sarajas, Annamari. 1962. Viimeiset romantikot [The last romantics]. Porvoo: WSOY. Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1943. L’Être et le neánt. Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique. Paris: Gallimard. Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2003. La transcendance de l’ego. Esquisse d’une description phenomenologique. Paris: J. Vrin. Schelling, F. W. J. 1977. Philosophie der Offenbarung 1841/42. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Scherer, Klaus. 2001. Le future des emotions. Le Monde, vendredi 23 novembre. 16. Schiller, Friedrich v. 1795/1978. Über naïve und sentimentalische Dichtung. Stuttgart: Reclam. Schiller, Friedrich v. 1795/1997. Briefe über die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen. Stuttgart: Reclam. Schiller, Friedrich v. 2000. Über die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen. Stuttgart: Reclam. Schlegel, August Wilhelm. 1994. Über Literatur, Kunst und Geist des Zeitalters. Stuttgart: Reclam. Schmitz, H. Walter. 1983. Victoria Lady Welby und die Folgen. In Zeitschrift für Semiotik 5 (1983). 123–138. Schmitz, H. Walter. 1984. Searle ist in Mode, Mannoury nicht: Sprech- und Hörakt im niederländischen Signifik-Kreis. In Zeitschrift für Semiotik 6 (1984). 445–463. Schmitz, H. Walter. 1985. “Victoria Lady Welby’s Significs: The Origin of the Signific Movement.” In Victoria Lady Welby, Significs and Language. The Articulate Form of Our Expressive and Interpretative Resources, ix–ccxxxv. (Reprint of the edition London, 1911, and of two articles by V. Welby.) Edited and introduced by H. Walter Schmitz. (Foundations of Semiotics 5.) Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Schmitz, H. Walter (ed.). 1990. Essays on Significs. Papers Presented on the Occasion of the 150th Anniversary of the Birth of Victoria Lady Welby (1837–1912). (Foundations of Semiotics 23.) Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

Literature

| 451

Schmitz, H. Walter. 1990. De Hollandse Significa. Een reconstructie van de geschiedenis van 1892 to 1926. Assen/Maastricht: Van Gorcum. Schmitz, H. Walter. 1995. Anmerkungen zum Welby-Russell-Briefwechsel. In Dutz, Klaus D. and Kjell-Åke Forsgren (eds.) 1995: History and Rationality. The Skövde Papers in the Historiography of Linguistics. 293–305. (Acta Universitatis Skodvensis. Series Linguistica 1.) Münster: Nodus Publikationen. Schück, Henrik. 1961. Yleinen kirjallisuudenhistoria [Allmän litteraturhistoria]. 1–12. Helsinki: Werner Söderström. Schütz, Alfred. 1974. Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt. Eine Einleitung in die verstehende Soziologie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [The Phenomenology of the Social World. Northwestern University Press.] Schütz, Alfred. 1993. Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt. Eine Einleitung in die verstehende Soziologie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Schütz, Alfred; Luckmann, Thomas. 1994. Strukturen der Lebenswelt I–II. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Scruton, Roger. 2005. Modern Culture. London: Continuum. Sebeok, Thomas A. 2001. Global Semiotics. Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press. Sesemann, Wilhelm. 1930. Beiträge zum Erkenntnisproblem III: Das Logisch-Rationale. Eranus Commentationes societatis philosophicae lituanae: Volumen primum. Sesemann, Wilhelm. 1931. Die logischen Gesetze im Verhältnis zum subjektbezogenen und psychischen Sein. (Eranus.) Sesemann, Wilhelm. 1935a. Estetika: Musu laiku gnoseologijai naujai besiorientuojant. (Eranus.) Sesemann, Wilhelm. 1935b. Zum Problem der logischen Paradoxien. (Eranus.) Showalter, Mary Emma. 1986. Mennonite Community Cookbook. Scottsdale, Pennsylvania; Kitchener, Ontario: Herald Press. Snellman, Johan Vilhelm. 1928. Kansallisuus ja kansallisaate [National identity and the idea of nationalism]. In Kootut teokset 9 [Complete Works 9]. Helsinki: Otava. Snellman, Johan Vilhelm. 1982. Persoonallisuuden idean spekulatiivisen kehittelyn yritys [The endeavour of the speculative development of the idea of personality]. Trans. by J. E. Salomaa. In J. V. Snellman: Teokset [Works] ll. Jyväskylä: Gummerus. Sonesson, Göran. 1992. Bildbetydelser. Inledning till bildsemiotiken som vetenskap. Lund: Studentliteratur. Souriau, Étienne. 1990. Vocabulaire d’esthétique, sous la direction de Anne Souriau. Paris: PUF. Souriau, Étienne. 2000. Vocabulaire d’esthétique. Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France. Spengler, Oswald. 1963. Länsimaiden perikato.Maailmanhistorian morfologian ääriviivoja [Untergang des Abendlandes]. Helsinki: Kirjayhtymä. Talvi, Jussi. 1989. Gastronomian historia [History of gastronomy]. Helsinki: Otava. Tarasti, Eero. 1979. Myth and Music (Approaches to Semiotics 51). The Hague: Mouton. Tarasti, Eero. 1988. Semiotics in the North the Tartu School continued in Finland. In Thomas A. Sebeok and Jean Umiker-Sebeok (eds.), The Semiotic Web 1987. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Tarasti, Eero. 1990a. Johdatusta semiotiikkaan [Introduction to semiotics]. Helsinki: Gaudeamus. Tarasti, Eero. 1990b. Scenes in the semiotic history of the Baltic countries. SIKSI 2. 12–18. Special issue, edited by Kimmo Sarje. Helsinki: Nordisk Kunstcentrum/Nordic Arts Center.

452 | Literature Tarasti, Eero. 1991. Sur l’authenticité et l’inauthenticité des arts. Degrés 68, numéro spécial sur sémiologie et pratiques esthétiques. Sémiotiques finlandaises. a–a26. Tarasti, Eero. 1994. A Theory of Musical Semiotics. Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press Tarasti, Eero. 2000. Existential Semiotics. (Advances in Semiotics.) Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Tarasti, Eero. 2001. Josiah Royce: amerikkalainen filosofiklassikko [Josiah Royce, a classic American philosopher]. Synteesi 3. 61–72. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Tarasti, Eero. 2002. Signs of Music. Berlin: Walther de Gruyter. Tarasti, Eero. 2004a. Arvot ja merkit. Johdatus eksistentiaalisemiotiikkaan [Values and signs. Introduction to existential semiotics]. Helsinki: Gaudeamus. Tarasti, Eero. 2004b. Valta ja subjektin teoria. [Power and Theory of Subject]. Synteesi 4. 84–102. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Tarasti, Eero. 2004c. Pariisin uudet mysteerit ja muita matkakertomuksia. [New mysteries of Paris and other travel stories]. (Suomen Semiotiikan Seuran julkaisuja 2.) Imatra: Imatran Kansainvälinen Semiotiikan Instituutti. Tarasti, Eero. 2005. Existential and Transcendental Analysis of Music. In Studi Musicali, Accademia nazionale di Santa Cecilia, direttore Agostino Ziino. 223–266. Firenze: Leo S. Olschki Editore. Tarasti, Eero. 2009a. Fondements de la sémiotique existentielle. Paris: L’Harmattan. Tarasti, Eero. 2009b. Fondamenti di semiotica esistenziale. Bari: Edizioni Giuseppe Laterza. Tarasti, Eero (ed.). 2009c. Communication: Understanding and Misunderstanding. Proceedings of the 9th Congress of the IASS/AIS at Helsinki/Imatra, 11–17 June 2007. Vols. 1–3. (Acta Semiotica Fennica XXXIV.) Imatra and Helsinki: International Semiotics Institute; Semiotic Society of Finland. Tarasti, Eero. 2012. Existential semiotics and cultural psychology. In Jaan Valsiner (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology. 316–343. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taruskin, Richard. 1997. Defining Russia Musically. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Tawaststjema, Erik. 1976. Sibelius, vol. 1. London: Faber and Faber. Tawaststjerna, Erik. 1978. Jean Sibelius, vol. 4. Helsinki: Otava. Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Tommila, Päiviö; Reitala, Aimo; and Kallio, Veikko. 1980. Suomen kulttuurihistoria [Finnish cultural history]. Porvoo, Helsinki, Juva: WSOY. Todorov, Tzwetan. 1972. Introduction à la littérature phantastique. Paris: Editions Seuil. Topelius, Zachris. 1926. Välskärin kertomuksia [Stories of an army surgeon]. Porvoo: WSOY. Topelius, Zachris. 1981. Maamme kirja [The book of our country). Porvoo: WSOY. Tshertkov [Chertkov], V. 1922. Tolstoin pako: [sen todelliset syyt] [The escape of Tolstoi: its true motives]. Trans. into Finnish by Arvid Järnefelt. Porvoo: WSOY. Tynianov, Iouri. 1977. Le Vers lui-même: problème de la langue du vers [Problema stikhotvornogo iazyka; 1924]; traduit du russe par Jean Durin, Blanche Grinbaum, Hélène Henry, Danielle Konopnicki . . . [etc.]; présentation par Léon Robel, Yvan Mignot, Henri Deluy. Paris: Union générale d’éditions. Uexküll, Jakob v. 1940. Bedeutungslehrew. Leipzig: Barth.

Literature

|

453

Uexküll, Thure v. 1993. Endosemiosis (together with Werner Geigges and Jörg M. Herrmann). Semiotica vol. 96-1/2. 5–51. Uspenskij, B. A.; Ivanov, V. V.; Toporov, V. N.; Pjatigorskij, A. M.; Lotman, Yu. M. 1973. Theses on the semiotic study of cultures (as applied to Slavic texts). In J. van der Eng and Mojmir Grygar (eds.), Structure of Texts and Semiotics of Culture. The Hague: Mouton. Vainiomäki, Tiina. 2012. The Musical Realism of Leoš Janáček. From Speech Melodies to a Theory of Composition. (Acta semiotica fennica XLI. Approaches to musical semiotics 15.) Helsinki: Semiotic Society of Finland. Valkonen, Markku. 1998. Kandinsky, Kalevala and the shamans. In Exhibition Catalogue, The Retretti Art Center, Punkaharju, Finland. Valkonen, Olli. 1998. Wassily Kandinsky’s early contacts with Finland. In Exhibition Catalogue, The Retretti Art Center. Vallgren, Ville. 1920. Guldranden. Helsingfors: Holger Schildts Förlagsaktiebolag. Vallgren, Ville. 1931. Minnen från mitt liv hemma och ute.Helsingfors: Mercators Tryckerie Aktiebolag. Vallgren, Ville. 1994. Pariisin Villen ruokasaarna. [The food catechesis of old man Ville]. Finnish trans. by Kyllikki Villa. Helsinki: Taide. (Originally published in Swedish as Wille-gubbens matkatekes. Helsingfors: Schildt, 1921.) Valsiner, Jaan. 2007. Culture in minds and societies. Foundations of cultural psychology. Los Angeles, London etc.: Sage. Valsiner, Jaan (ed.). 2012. The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vega, Carlos. 1967. Tradiciones musicales y aculturacion en Sudamericas. In George List and Juan Orrego-Salas (ed.) Music in the Americas. 220–250. (Interamerican monograph series Vol. 1.) The Hague: Mouton. Veivo, Harri. 2006. Verkosto P [Network P]. Synteesi 2. 39–43. Helsinki: The Semiotic Society of Finland. Voigt, Vilmos. 1973. Lectures on semiotics at the Folklore Dep. in the University of Helsinki. Voigt, Vilmos. 2013. Letter to Eero Tarasti by email, July 24, 2013. Volli, Ugo. 2000. Manuale di semiotica. Roma – Bari: Editore Laterza. Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2010. Sinne und Künste im Wechselspiel. Modi ästhetischer Erfahrung. Suhrkamp Taschenbuch, Wissensachfty 1973. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Wąsik, Zdzisław. 2014. Lectures on the Epistemology of Semiotics. (Philologica Wratislaviensia: Series Didactica. Vol. 1.) Wrocław: Philological School of Higher Education in Wrocław Publishing. Weiss, Peter. 1978. Ästhetik des Widerstandes. Roman. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. Welsch, Wolfgang. 1996. Vernunft. Die zeitgenössische Vernunftkritik und das Konzept der transversalen Vernunft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Wilson, Edward O. 1975. Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. Cambridge, Massachusetts. v. Wright, Georg Henrik. 1963. Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Zarcone, Thierry. 2009. Le soufisme. Voie mystique de l’islam. Paris: Gallimard. Zweig, Stefan. 1965. Ihmiskunnan tähtihetkiä [Sternstunden der Menschheit, 1927]. Porvoo, Helsinki: Werner Söderström Osakeyhtiö.

Index Aalto, Alvar 308, 309 Aarne, Antti 368, 385, 386, 388 Aattela, Kalervo 428 Abbot, Francis Ellingwood 324 Abruzzese, Alberto 435 Ablali, Driss 77, 441 Abu Ubaid 101 Ackte, Aino 310 Adler, Guido 87 Adorno, Theodor W. 7, 8, 28, 33, 39, 40, 42, 48, 74–76, 88, 89, 91, 95, 100, 103, 144, 158, 283, 294, 297, 372, 411, 441 Afanasyev 385, 386 Afnan, Soheil Muhsin 102, 441 Aho, Kalevi 161 Ahonen, Pertti 441 Ahtisaari, Martti 433 Airola, Veikko 441 Albeniz, Isaac 134, 220 al-Ghazali 441 Allen, Woody 219 Almeida, Renato 368, 441 Althusser 146, 150 Altman, Rick 81, 441 Ammirante, Paolo 434 Anderson, Benedict 182, 206 Andreyev, N. P. 385, 386 Andrieu, Bernard 441 Apo, Satu 441 Arendt, Hannah 3, 4, 21, 22, 31, 36, 103, 106, 183, 343, 440 Aristotle 100, 101, 221, 322 Arlt, Wulf 443 Aron, Raymond 177, 178, 441 Artaud, Antonin 214 Arwidsson, A. I. 317 Asafiev, Boris 74, 82, 84, 167, 226, 286, 289, 300, 369, 374, 387, 441 Aspelin, Kurt 368, 441 Augustine of Hippo (St. Augustin) 102 Austin, John L. 176 Avicenna (Ibn-Sina) 101, 102, 441

Bach, J. S. 74, 84, 90, 92–94, 284, 374 Bacon, Henry 246, 247, 441 Bądarzewska, Tekla 96 Bagh, Peter von 40, 441 Baker, Evan 193, 444 Bakhtin, Mikhail 30, 35, 72, 111, 144, 148, 184, 200, 206, 223, 226, 281, 349, 367, 368, 374, 388–391, 395, 406, 411, 441 Bankov, Kristian 105, 156, 157, 342, 435, 441 Barker, Chris 187–192, 194, 441 Barrie, David 450 Barthes, Roland 16, 63, 80, 84, 140, 144, 145, 187, 189, 191, 197, 216, 245–247, 249, 254, 255, 265, 277, 352, 367, 380, 398–406, 424, 425, 442 Bartók, Béla 94 Baryshnikov, Mikhail 230 Bastide, Françoise 270, 442 Baudrillard, Jean 45, 133, 139, 171 Bauters, Merja 434 Beauvoir, Simone de 4, 343, 395 Beck, Anke 434 Beethoven, Ludwig van 8, 10, 58, 82, 84, 86, 90, 91, 93, 94, 96, 138, 168, 195, 216, 218, 219, 223, 243, 283, 284, 286, 287, 290, 294, 296, 342, 361, 376, 382, 405, 444 Bellini, Vincenzo 84, 94 Bely, Andrei 362, 366, 371, 449 Benedict, Ruth 187, 189, 442 Benjamin, Walter 39 Berger, Peter L. 140 Bergman, Erik 88 Bergman, Ingmar 46, 373 Bergson, Henri 31, 105, 163, 167–170, 172, 174, 176, 337, 342, 401, 409, 441, 442 Berio, Luciano 84 Berlioz, Hector 87, 443 Bernanos, Georges 79, 116, 407 Bernard, Claude 270 Bernard, Jeff 431, 432 Bernard, Sarah 213 Berndtson, Gunnar 261

456 | Index Bernini, Gian Lorenzo 84 Bernstein, Leonard 295 Berruti, Massimo 3 Birdwhistle, Harrison 218 Bloch, Ernst 31, 40, 101, 107, 232, 440, 442, 448 Block de Behar, Lisa 430 Blok, Alexander 362, 366 Blume, Friedrich 97 Boëtsch, Gilles 441 Bogdanov, Bogdan 435 Bordron, Jean-François 77 Borges, Priscila 432 Borrel, Anne 448 Borromini, Francesco 84 Boss, Medard 65, 194, 199, 442 Botz-Bornstein, Thorsten 380, 382, 383, 392, 395, 397, 442 Bouissac, Paul 16, 219, 429, 430, 442 Boulanger 254 Boulez, Pierre 91 Bourdieu, Pierre 29, 32, 86, 139, 199 Bouzher, Myriam 443 Brahms, Johannes 375, 376, 450 Brask, Peter 429 Braudel, Fernand 178–180, 442 Bréal, Michel 5, 342 Brecht, Bertolt 150, 372 Brémond, Claude 34, 84, 289, 387, 442 Brent, Joseph 324, 442 Bresson, Robert 233, 407 Brhaspati 416 Brillat-Samarin, J. A. 68, 249, 251–253, 442 Britten, Benjamin 230 Broms, Henri 108 354, 392, 425, 428, 430, 442 Brontë, Charlotte 43 Brown, Ralph W. 339 Bruckner, Anton 95, 301 Brutus 226 Buber, Martin 208, 448 Buchler, Julius 449 Buffa, Aira 443 Bulgakov, Mikhail 372 Burbank, John 448 Burckhardt, Jakob 154, 442 Busoni, Ferruccio 117, 225

Buttitta, Antonino 427 Bystrina, I. 446 Caesar, Gaius Julius 226 Cage, John 58, 98, 127, 415 Calabrese, Omar 435 Calefato, Patrizia 435 Calvino, Italo 445 Camus, Albert 43 Capus, Alfred 252 Caravaggio, Michelangelo Merisi da 84 Carême, Antoine 253, 263 Carnap, Rudolf 169, 170, 172, 176 Carpelan, Axel 117 Carreño, Teresa 96 Cassirer, Ernst 140 Castellana, Marcello 429 Castillo, José Romero 430 Castrén, Matias Aleksanteri 314 Catherine the Great 428 Cauquelin, Anne 100, 101, 442 Celibidache, Sergiu 243 Céline, Louis-Ferdinand 43 Chapman, John Jay 323, 324, 442 Charles, Daniel 127, 429 Chausson, Ernest 45 Checca 216, 217 Chekhov, Anton 108, 361 Chertkov, Vladimir 107, 452 Cherubini, Luigi 342 Chesterman, Andrew 183, 199 Chistov, K. V. 386 Chomsky 62, 203, 325 Chopin, Fryderyk 94, 98, 167, 219, 220, 388, 404, 405 Cioran, Samuel D. 354, 355, 363, 364 Cobley, Paul 33, 80, 81, 342, 435, 442 Cocteau, Jean 43, 183 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor 321 Colette, Sidonie-Gabrielle 343 Collins, Frank 444 Comte, Auguste 271, 272, 346, 347, 354, 443 Condé, Gérard 87, 443 Coppock, Patrick 435 Corrêa de Azevedo, Luiz Heitor 429 Couperin, François 84, 224 Courtés, Joseph 77, 84, 270, 409, 443

Index |

Csinidis, Jean-Laurent 3 Cuaron, Garza 426, 430 Czernov, Igor 314, 428, 430, 443 Czerny, Carl 96 Dagar 416 Dahlhaus, Carl 86, 87, 89, 95, 97, 98, 286, 291, 443 Danesi, Marcel 247, 430, 432, 434 Danilevsky, Nikolai 354 Dante Alighieri 123 Danuser, Hermann 93, 94, 443 Darrault-Harris, Ivan 30, 443 Deaville, James 444 Debussy, Claude 117, 242, 297, 402, 445 Deely, John 52, 58, 59, 103, 105, 277, 326, 348, 382, 406, 426, 432, 435, 443 Delalande, François 427, 429 Deledalle, Gérard 321, 432, 443 Deleuze, Gilles 184, 185, 203–205, 443 Delyi, Henri 452 Derrida, Jacques 54, 56, 189, 276 Descartes, René 102 Dewey, John 30, 443 Diaghilev, Serge 92 Disney, Walt 149 Donizetti, Gaetano 342 Donskoi, Marc 130 Dosse, François 387, 443 Dostoevsky, Fyodor 111, 134, 144, 177, 374, 389 Ducard, Dominique 441 Ducrot, Oswald 71, 443 Dumézil, Georges 75, 195 Duncan, Isadora 214 Dundes, Alain 387, 388 Duras, Marguerite 446 Durin, Jean 452 Durkheim, Émile 139 Dutz, Klaus D. 451 Dvořák, Antonín 94 Eagleton, Terry 145, 146, 148, 443 Eco 3, 17, 39, 45, 56, 59, 63, 64, 70, 80, 89, 101, 109, 111, 140, 156, 163–166, 176, 179, 180, 184, 190, 194, 249, 294, 306,

457

326, 351, 368, 372, 401, 403, 406, 424, 426, 427, 435, 443 Edelfelt, Albert 263 Eggebrecht, Hans Heinrich 92 Eichenbaum, Boris 368 Einstein, Albert 342 Einstein, Alfred 342, 443 Eira, Maaria 241 Eisenstein, Sergei 369 Ekström, Pelle 261 Elgar, Edward 122 El Greco 8, 41, 168 Elias, Norbert 36, 46, 86, 153, 154, 165, 166, 178, 309, 443 Emerson, Caryl 441 Emerson, Ralph Waldo 3, 6, 105, 321, 441 Eng, Jan van der 453 Eronen, Ella 239, 240 Eschbach, Achim 443 Espagne, Michel 206, 207, 444 Espinosa Vera, Pablo 431 Euclid 101 Even-Zohar, Itamar 428 Excousseau, J.-L. 270, 444 Fabbri, Franco 99, 444 Farzaneh, M. F. 108 Fehr, Drude von der 429 Ferrari, Guido 435 Février, Jacques 214 Ficarelli, Mario 416 Finol, Enrique 155–157, 444 Finscher, Ludwig 93 Fisch, Max H. 105, 106, 321, 322, 344, 444 Fischer-Dieskau, Dietrich 404 Fiske, John 324 Flagstadt, Kirsten 239 Flaubert, Gustave 114 Floch, J. M. 81 Fludernik, Monika 72 Fontanille, Jacques 23, 24, 185, 270, 374, 404, 411, 444 Fontayn, Margot 230 Forman, Milos 44 Forsell, Paul 434 Forsgren, Kjell-Åke 451

458 | Index Foucault, Michel 58, 64–66, 76, 109, 116, 133, 134, 144, 151, 182, 184, 189, 193, 194, 312, 336, 425, 444 Fourier, Charles 423 France, Anatole 252, Franta, Vladimir 162 Freud, Sigmund 269, 395, 426 Fricke, George R. 444 Fricke, Richard 220, 444 Froelich, Carl 236 Frye, Northrop 73, 124, 359, 444 Fuják, Július 3, 444 Furtwängler, Wilhelm 239, 292, 292, 444 Gallen-Kallela, Akseli 117, 308–310 Galman, John 427 Gandhi, Mahatma 161 Gans, Eduard 445 Garbo, Greta 232, 245, 246 Gardin, Jean-Claude 430 Gasparov, Boris 370, 428 Gayrard, Julien 443 Geigges, Werner 453 Gentil, Jules 222 Geraschenko, Irina 438 Gergiev, Valery 243, 376 Géricault 159, 160, 448 Gide, André 43 Giere, Ronald 61 Gimate-Welsh, Adrian 432 Gingold, Joseph 310 Ginzburg, Carlo 180 Glinka, Mikhail 355, 374 Gluck, Chr. W. 87, 88, 93, 94 Goethe, J. W. von 17, 27, 79, 106, 120, 128, 134, 142, 192, 199, 274, 276, 282, 284, 374, 375, 424 Gogol, Nikolai 108, 255, 368, 444 Goldmann, Lucien 114, 115, 137, 144, 444 Goldoni, Caro 216 Goodman, Nelson 58, 444 Gorlée, Dinda L. 429, 430 Gould, Glenn 92, 234 Grabócz, Márta 429 Gray, Cecil 296 Gregorius Thaumaturgus 354

Greimas, A. J. 4, 5, 7, 10, 11, 16, 31, 39, 42–44, 52, 54, 66, 71, 76, 77, 81, 84, 109, 113, 115, 116, 120, 121, 126–128, 137, 140, 144, 147, 150, 162, 164, 179, 196, 202, 213, 216, 230, 233, 249, 251, 252, 254, 256, 257, 260, 265, 270, 271, 281, 291, 292, 295, 302, 308, 315, 321, 325–327, 329, 343, 348, 349, 351, 358, 359, 374, 378–380, 382, 385, 387, 392–396, 398, 401, 403, 407–409, 423–425, 427, 429, 444, 445 Grimm, Jacob 73, 445 Grinbaum, Blanche 452 Grossman, Leonid 374 Grundfest Schoepf, Brooke 447 Grygar, Mijmir 453 Guattari, Félix 203, 443 Guerra Lisi, Stefania 32, 84, 215, 221, 223, 230, 445 Guerri, Claudio 430 Guittard, Jacqueline 441 Habermas, Jürgen 33, 445 Hahn, Reynaldo 46 Habsburg dynasty 195 Hall, Stuart 184 Halm, August 292 Hämeen-Anttila, Jaakko 101, 243, 441, 445 Handel, G. Fr. 90, 93, 161 Hanslick, Eduard 370 Hardwick, Charles S. 342, 344, 348, 353, 445 Härmä, Juhani 425 Harnoncourt, Nikolaus 89 Hartmann 354 Hatten, Robert 287, 445, 446 Haydn, Joseph 86, 87, 93, 178 Heath, Stephen 441 Hegel, G. W. Fr. 3, 4, 21–24, 74, 103–106, 152–154, 157, 162, 167, 171–173, 175, 179–181, 188, 196, 199, 200, 273, 274, 307, 308, 321–323, 325–330, 332, 337, 338, 344–347, 354, 355, 357, 395, 409, 411, 445 Hedayat, Sadeq 108 Heidegger, Martin 3–5, 16, 21, 63, 100, 106, 125, 126, 128, 140, 164, 166, 170, 321, 326, 336, 395, 445

Index |

Heininen, Paavo 311 Helbo, André 215, 445 Hellberg, Elena 429 Hénault, Anne 45, 435 Henry, Hélène 452 Hensel, Fanny 96 Hepburn, Audrey 246 Hepokoski, James 301, 302, 445 Heracles 162 Herder, Johann Gottfried vom 197 Hermans, Hubert J. M. 30, 35, 390, 445 Hermes Trismegistos 354 Herrmann, Jörg M. 453 Herzfeld, Michael 442 Hesse, Hermann 375 Hiltunen, Elina 447 Hintikka, Jaakko 61 Hitchcock, Alfred 241 Hjelmslev, Louis 4, 327, 328 Hobbes, Thomas 274 Hocking, Richard 450 Hocking, W. E. 450 Hoffmann, E. T. A. 108 Hoffmeyer, Jesper 445 Hollo, J. A. 113 Holquist, Michael 441 Honegger, Arthur 400 Hope, Bob 239 Hoppál, Mihály 425, 429 Horowitz, Vladimir 221 Houser, Nathan 350 Hovenpitzer, Roman 224 Huhtinen, Aki-Mauri 155, 436, 445 Humboldt, Wilhelm 106, 197 Hume, David 11, 104, 125, 170, 445 Huntington, Samuel 138, 156 Husserl, Edmund 21, 33, 50, 57, 58, 105, 121, 163, 170, 176, 279, 394, 397, 445 Ibn Arabi 185, 186 Ibri, Ivo 416 Ikegami, Yoshihiko 430 Ingarden, Roman 10, 348 Inge Godoy, Rolf 445 Inwood, Michael 22, 272, 274, 446 Ipsen, Guido 142, 156, 437 Irwin, George J. 441

459

Isidoro 216, 217 Ivanov, Sergei 355 Ivanov, V. V. 453 Ivan the Terrible 307 Ives, Charles 304 Jacobson, Claire 447 Jacono, Jean-Marie 3, 446 Jakobson, Roman 72, 88, 115, 118, 171, 177, 249, 368, 369, 372, 380, 386, 387, 446 Jalas, Jussi 303 Jalava, Antti 310, 446 James, William 30, 321, 324, 337, 344, 352, 390 Janáček, Leoš 56, 57, 453 Jankélévich, Vladimir 95, 135, 221, 370, 393, 446 Järnefelt, Eero 310 Jaspers, Karl 3–5, 21, 38, 51–53, 100, 105, 106, 116, 121, 126, 141, 142, 176, 321, 395, 400, 409, 446 Jiránek, Jaroslav 184, 429 Johansen, Jørgen Dines 60, 74, 429, 430, 446 Johnson, Mark 27 Jolles, André 72, 73 Josephson, Ernst 261 Kafka, Franz 108 Kaila, Kai 442 Kajanus, Robert 117 Kalima, Eino 227 Kallberg, Jeffrey 98 Kallio, Veikko 307, 452 Kandinsky, Wassily 146, 203, 292, 369–371, 376, 453 Kant, Immanuel 3, 4, 7, 16, 21, 22, 24, 32, 39, 42, 54, 55, 59, 103, 105, 163, 179, 251, 272, 273, 275, 278, 322, 326, 344, 354, 357, 395, 442, 446 Kaplinski, Jaan 433 Karbusický, Vladimir 83–85, 429, 446 Karnowski, H. 446 Karsavin, Lev 52, 378, 379, 381, 382, 446 Karsavina, Tamara 382 Kašponis, Rimtautas 379, 382 Kätner 236

460 | Index Kaurismäki, Aki 40, 47, 235, 236, 261, 441, 446 Kent, Leonard J. 444 Khachaturian, Aram 368 Khayam, Omar 108 Kianto, Ilmari 312 Kierkegaard, Søren 3, 4, 22–25, 46, 103, 105, 192, 322, 348, 355, 395, 403 Kilpi, Volter 447 Kircher, Athanasius 98, 446 Kirchschläger, Rudolf 426 Kivi, Aleksis 158, 308, 309, 446 Klaus, Georg 61, 146, 448 Klein, Jean-Pierre 443 Klein, Melanie 30, 343 Kleutghen, Elke 438 Klinkenberg, Jean-Marie 78, 374 Kloesel, Christian J. W. 444 Knuuttila, Sirkka 446 Knuuttila, Tarja 60, 61, 446 Kochan, Miriam 442 Koch, Walter A. 430 Kokkonen, Joonas 308, 309, 311, 446 Köngäs-Maranda, Elli-Kaija 109, 387, 388, 425, 446 Konopnicki, Danielle 452 Kostka, Stefan 284, 285, 446 Kotilainen, Otto 304 Koussevitzky, Serge 219, 221 Kowzan, Tadeusz 215, 446, 447 Kress, Günther 79, 447 Kristeva, Julia 16, 109, 269, 275, 277, 326, 343, 389, 390, 401, 404, 439, 447 Krohn, Kaarle 368, 375, 385 Kukkonen, Pirjo 101, 433, 434, 446, 447 Kukkonen, Taneli 441 Kull, Kalevi 428, 436 Kuorikoski, Arto 441 Kupfer, Harry 107, 224, 373 Kurkela, Vesa 313, 447 Kuronen, Tuomas 200, 447 Kurth, Ernst 84, 90, 284, 292, 300, 395, 447 Kuusamo, Altti 226 Kuusi, Osmo 425, 447 Kyhälä-Juntunen, Kerttu 441

Laban, Rudolf von 214 La Bruyère, Jean de 27, 235 Lacan, Jacques 21, 336, 395 Lagopoulos, Alexandros-Phaidon 430, 432 Laine, Kimmo 241, 242, 447 Laine-Almi, Doris 242, 447 Laine Ketner, Kenneth 444 Laitinen, Arto 449 Lakoff, George 222 Lakshin, Vladimir 108 La Mettrie, Julien Jean Offroy de 183 Lamizet, Bernard 432 Landowski, Eric 40, 53, 156, 427, 447 Landsch, M. 446 Langbehn, Julius 205 Langdalen, Jørgen 429 Lanigan, Richard 432 Larsen, Svend Erik 429 Larsson, Carl 261 LaRue, Jan 288, 294, 447 Launis, Armas 317 Laurell, Axel Adolf 330 Laurinen, Tuomas 161 Leach, Edmund 191, 447 Leander, Zarah 226 Le Clézio 11 Le Corbusier 204 Leeuwen, Theo van 447 Lehto, Otto 44 Leibniz 59, 100, 102, 163, 322, 344 Leiman, Mikael 390 Leino, Eino 240, 312, 313, 447 Lejeune, Philippe 78, 79, 447 Leman, Marc 445 Lenin, V. I. 145 Leone, Massimo 436, 447 Lepik, Peet 111 Lermontov, Mikhail 355 Lesourd, François 446 Levas, Santeri 301 Levin, Isidor 386 Lévinas, Emmanuel 106, 349, 389, 406, 410, 447, 448 Lévi-Strauss, Claude 4, 28, 39, 56, 75, 76, 109, 112, 116, 140, 154, 165, 184, 187, 191, 194, 200, 205, 206, 231, 249, 252, 254, 265, 269, 283, 326, 368, 370, 384,

Index |

386–388, 401, 407, 424, 425, 434, 447, 448 Lewin, Kurt 34, 35 Li, You-Zheng 430, 435, 437 Lichtenhan, Ernst 443 Lidov, David 285, 287, 297, 447 Lifar, Serge 242 Ligeti, György 84, 88, 289, 297 Lindberg, Magnus 161 Lintunen, Pertti 429 Lippmann, Léontine 354 List, George 453 Liszt, Ferenc 286, 444 Littlefield, Richard 434, 446 Locke, John 57, 125, 276 Lõhmus, Aivo 428 Lõhmus, Maarja 149, 447 Lönnrot, Elias 309 Lorenz, Max 237–239 Lossky, Vladimir 383 Lotman, Yuri 4, 41, 62, 64, 68, 72, 76, 81, 111, 116, 117, 120, 124, 126, 138, 140, 156, 179, 215, 249, 254, 271, 281, 306, 307, 309, 314, 326, 346, 368, 401, 428, 429, 436, 443, 453 Lotze, Hermann 321 Lovejoy, Arthur 202, 283, 294, 447 Luckmann, Thomas 41, 46, 50, 53, 71, 140, 208, 353, 410, 451 Ludwig II of Bavaria 179, 236, 237, 246, 247, 441 Lukkarila, Matti 447 Lundberg, Bengt A. 368, 441 Luyken, Lorenz 287, 288, 294, 447 Macassar, Gilles 446 MacCannell, Dean 430 Mâche, François-Bernard 447 Macie, John 11, 12 Magnani, Anna 239 Mahler, Gustav 95, 117, 219, 283, 294, 301, 401, 450 Majava, Heikki 391 Mäkinen, Timo 444 Malecka, Teresa 447 Malevich, Kazimir 369 Malinowski, Bronisław 408

Manet, Édouard 257 Mann, Thomas 117 Mannerheim, C. G. E. 35 Mannoury, Gerrit 443, 448 Mao Zedong 225 Maranda, Pierre 109, 446 Marc-Lipiansky, Mireille 39, 448 Marcel, Gabriel 4, 21 Marcus, Solomon 55, 440 Marrone, Gianfranco 80–82, 435, 448 Martin, Serge 427 Martinelli, Dario 430, 434, 437, 448 Martinet, André 81, 190, 204 Martinez, José Luiz 413–419, 448 Martucci, Giuseppe 92 Marx, Karl 103 Marx, Wolfgang 97 Massumi, Brian 443 Matson, Alex 446 Maupassant, Guy de 402 Maurois, André 108 Mauss, Marcel 200, 222, 232, 409 Mayakovsky, Vladimir 368 Maximus the Confessor 354 Mbarga, Jean-Claude 201, 432, 448 McDermott, John J. 322, 323, 450 Mead, George Herbert 30, 308, 334, 448 Medici, Maria di 130, 145 Mendelssohn, Felix 283, 295, 297 Mérigaud, Bernard 446 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 4, 321 Mersmann, Hans 85 Meyer, Friedrich Gottlob 313 Meyer, Leonard B. 86, 178, 287, 313, 448 Meyerhold, Vsevolod 214 Michel, Régis 448 Miereanu, Costin 429 Mignot, Yvan 452 Mill, J. S. 361 Miller 386 Minkus, Léon 242 Mirka, Danuta 289, 448 Mitford, Nancy 138, 197, 349 Moeschler, Jacques 430 Moilanen, Tauno 431 Molière 110 Monelle, Raymond 88

461

462 | Index Monroe, Marilyn 233 Monteiro, Ricardo 413 Montesquieu 27, 129 Monteverdi, Claudio 94 Morozoff, Ivan 252 Morpurgo-Tagliabue, Guido 370 Morris, Charles 33, 75–77, 81, 136, 138, 140, 308, 394, 405, 412, 448 Morris, G. S. D. 321 Moser, K. 441 Motiekaitis, Ramunas 448 Mozart, W. A. 51, 58, 86, 87, 93, 94, 96, 178, 224, 225, 250, 287, 297, 342, 376 Muhamedov, Irek 230, 241, 242 Mukařovský, Jan 78, 368, 448 Mukerhjee 416 Münster, Arno 184, 208, 448 Munthe, Axel 261 Murail, Tristan 161 Murtomäki, Veijo 292, 293, 448 Musil, Robert 188 Mussorgsky, Modest 225, 295, 310 Napoleon Bonaparte 159, 178 Nattiez, Jean-Jacques 295, 402, 446 Naudin, Jean-Bernard 448 Neruda, Pablo 134, 259 Nestroy, Johann 240 Nieminen, Paula 443 Nietzsche, Friedrich 138, 184, 378 Nignon, Édouard 68, 251–253, 259, 263, 448 Niiniluoto, Ilkka 433 Nikolai II (Russian Emperor) 252 Normet, Leo 428 Nöth, Winfried 16, 57, 58, 124, 128, 144, 150, 389, 448 Obolensky, Olga 256, 448 Occam, William 57, 59 Oesch, Hans 443 Oguibenin, Boris 429 Oldenburg, S. F. 385 Onur, Zeynep 188 Oppenheimer, Frank 450 Orosz, Magdolna Orrego-Salas, Juan 453

Osolsobě, Ivo 225, 373 O’Toole, Michael 430 Pacius, Friedrich 96, 264, 311, 312 Palestrina, Giovanni Pierluigi da 84, 93, 284 Palo, Tauno 241 Panier, Louis 432 Panula, Jorma 221 Parland, Henry 380, 392, 393 Parland, Oscar 31, 192, 380, 382, 392, 393, 395, 449 Parpola, Asko 415 Parpola, Simo 415 Pascal, Blaise 115, 137 Pasolini, Pierpaolo 399, 400 Paul, Adolf 117 Pawlowska, Malgorzata 447 Paz Gago, José María 432, 434 Peirce, C. S. 4, 6, 11, 22, 25, 55, 56, 58–60, 63, 71, 105, 106, 115, 120, 124, 127, 134, 140, 156, 163, 168, 171, 277, 281, 321–324, 326, 329, 330–332, 337–342, 344–347, 349, 351, 353, 356–358, 362, 366, 414–416, 418, 426, 437, 442, 445, 449 Peirce, Jem 324 Peirce, Juliette 324 Pekkilä, Erkki 418, 425 Pelagius 354 Pelc, Jerzy 426, 431 Pellonpää, Matti 235 Penderecki, Krzysztof 448 Perron, Paul 444 Perry, Ralph Barton 324 Pesonen, Pekka 354, 375, 434, 449 Peter the Great (Russian czar) 381 Petrilli, Susan 136, 156, 342–344, 346–350, 352, 353, 389, 432, 435, 449 Peuranen, Erkki 72, 388 Pezzini, Isabella 435 Piatigorsky, Alexander 429 Pierce, Alexandra 218 Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko 437 Pihlström, Sami 123, 152, 449 Plato 122, 277, 343 Pikkarainen, Esa 163, 176, 177, 449 Pinxten, Rik 430

Index |

Plisetskaya, Maya 230 Poe, Edgar Allan 108 Ponzio, Augusto 80, 111, 136, 139, 141, 147, 156, 184, 349, 389, 406–412, 435, 449 Popova, Maria 435 Popper, Karl 62, 100 Porges, Heinrich 220, 449 Posner, Roland 16, 104, 429, 430–432, 442 Post, Emily 257, 449 Poulenc, Francis 290 Poussin, Nicolas 159, 160 Prasama Pattanayak, Debi 430 Presley, Elvis 247, 248 Probir 417 Prokofiev, Sergei 221, 368, 370 Propp, Vladimir 71, 158, 368, 376, 378, 384–388, 391, 449 Proust, Marcel 36, 46, 53, 91, 108, 109, 117, 134, 138, 146, 167, 213, 222, 250, 252, 259, 326, 378, 446 Ptolemy 101 Pushkin, Alexander 355 Pyatigorsky, A. M. 453 Racine, Jean 11, 115, 137 Rachmaninov, Sergei 219 Raffler-Engel, Walburga von 135, 182, 433 Rameau, J. Ph. 94 Ratner, Leonard 88 Rauch, Irmengard 431 Rautavaara, Einojuhani 285 Rector, Monica 430 Reimas, Olavi (Unto Kalervo Eskola) 240, 241 Rein, K. G. T. 326 Reitala, Aimo 307, 452 Rembrandt 168 Remmel, Mart 299, 428 Renoir, Jean 221, 233, 235, 241, 257 Rethoré, Joëlle 430 Réti, Rudolph 285, 292 Reybrouck, Mark 219 Reznikoff, Iegor 429 Ricoeur, Paul 18, 166, 177–181, 185, 277, 411, 449 Rigolage, Emile 443 Rimsky-Korsakov, Nikolai 376 Rink, John 219, 449

463

Rinne, Pärttyli 51 Robel, Léon 452 Rocci, Andrea 434 Rosen, Charles 244 Rosenzweig, F. 448 Rossellini, Roberto 233 Rossi, Pentti 428 Rossi-Landi, Ferruccio 146–149, 406, 407, 449 Rossini, Giachino 84 Rouget, Gilbert 368 Rouget de l’Isle 161 Rowell, Lewis 414–416, 418, Royce, Josiah 22, 105, 106, 321–326, 328, 330–341, 345, 346, 352, 423, 442, 450, 452 Roye, Katharine 323 Rubinstein, Arthur 219, 220, 234, 404 Rumi, Maulaana 243 Runeberg, J. L. 240, 311, 312, 450 Rushdie, Salman 31, 434 Ruskin, John 105, 124, 125, 259, 260, 334, 345, 346, 355, 450 Russell, Bertrand 30, 103, 125, 328, 342, 443, 451 Ruwet, Nicolas 402 Ryan, Michael 196, 198, 450 Saariaho, Kaija 161 Saint-Martin, Fernande 430 Salieri, Antonio 342 Sallinen, Aulis 308, 309 Salmenhaara, Erkki 296, 297, 299, 302, 376, 377, 450 Salomaa, E. 451 Salonen, Esapekka 303 Salosaari, Kari 201, 215–219, 228, 234, 246, 303, 450 Samson, Jim 98, 404 Samuels, Robert 401, 402, 405, 450 Sand, George 138, 343, 414 Santaella Braga, Lucia 413, 430 Sarma 416 Sapir, Edward 146 Sarajas, Annamari 312, 450 Sarje, Kimmo 451

464 | Index Sartre, Jean-Paul 3, 4, 6, 21, 23–25, 40, 43, 64, 106, 108, 152, 185, 199, 321, 395, 407, 409, 416, 446, 450 Saussure 4, 5, 10, 18, 21, 32, 47, 53, 56, 58, 70, 77, 109, 176, 191, 269, 326, 403, 410, 411 Schelling 3, 4, 6, 27, 67, 105, 273, 274, 450 Schenker, Heinrich 220, 284, 292, 300 Scherer, Klaus 146, 450 Schiller, Friedrich v. 39, 42, 43, 272–276, 303, 450 Schlegel, A. W. 275, 278, 450 Schlegel, Friedrich 276 Schmidt, Anna Nikolaevna 366 Schmitz, H. Walter 342, 450, 451 Schiwy, Günther 400 Schneider, Romy 246, 246, 441 Scholem, G. 448 Schönberg, Arnold 117, 286, 293, 326 Schopenhauer, Artur 105, 107, 260, 357 Schrade, Leo 443 Schubert, Franz 93, 286, 306 Schück, Henrick 110 Schumann, Clara 96 Schumann, Robert 84, 93, 94, 96, 198, 234, 290, 405 Schütz, Alfred 41, 46, 50, 53, 71, 184, 208, 353, 410, 411, 451 Schütz, Heinrich 93, 94, 451 Schwartz, Marcia 434 Scriabin, Alexander 84, 91, 295, 371, 376, 382 Scruton, Roger 190, 197, 451 Scudéry, Madeleine de 75, 109, 110 Seabra, José 427 Searle 176, 216, 448 Sebeok, Thomas A. 4, 15, 16, 42, 56, 62, 63, 111, 124, 134, 230, 259, 278, 306, 328, 349, 384, 386, 387, 388, 408, 425–432, 435, 436, 442, 451 Seeger, Anthony 28, 225 Seeger, Pete 248 Segre, Cesare 431 Seitajärvi, Juha 447 Sekoni, Ropo 430 Sellars, Peter 373 Senancour, Étienne Pivert de 79

Senderens, Alain 448 Serazzi, Giovanna 445 Sesemann, Vasily 382, 442 Sesemann, Wilhelm 127, 378, 380, 382, 383, 392–397, 442, 451 Shakespeare, William 226 Shannon, Claude Elwood 118, 406, 409 Shostakovich, Dmitry 368 Showalter, Mary Emma 256, 451 Shukman, Ann 429 Sibelius, Jean 91, 95, 117, 145, 283, 286–288, 290, 292–304, 308–311, 314, 376, 415, 416, 433, 444–448, 450, 452 Šklovsky, Viktor 368, 372, 383 Smith, John E. 447 Smith, Nicholas H. 449 Snellman, J. W. 28, 103, 307, 308, 310, 315, 325, 326, 329, 330, 449, 451 Socrates 194 Sõgel, Endel 428 Solovyov, Mikhail 364 Solovyov, Vladimir 6, 325, 354–366, 382 Sonesson, Göran 80, 432, 451 Sormunen, Markku 205 Souriau, Anne 451 Souriau, Étienne 43, 50, 213, 214, 218, 221–223, 234, 449, 451 Spampinato, Francesco 448 Spengler, Oswald 106, 199, 205, 451 Spinoza, Baruch 273 Sriwastava, R. N. 430 Stanislavsky, Konstantin 214 Stefani, Gino 32, 84, 87, 139, 215, 221, 223, 230, 402, 429, 445, 448 Steiner, Peter 448 Stigell, Robert 261 Stockhausen, Karlheinz 84, 285 Stockinger, Peter 430 Stoianova, Ivanka 289, 292, 293, 296, 404, 429 Storelv, Sven 429 Strauss, Richard 117, 243, 302 Stravinsky, Igor 74, 84, 92, 221, 290, 297, 369, 370, 375, 381 Strindberg, August 263 Sukhova, Natalia 47 Suni, Timo 375, 449

Index |

Suolahti, Eino E. 442 Syberberg, Hans-Jürgen 236, 237 Szépe, György 430 Tähti, Annikki 236 Taine, Hippolyte 113–116 Talvela, Martti 310 Talvi, Jussi 254, 255, 451 Tarasti, Eero 4, 5, 9, 11, 15, 72, 89, 145, 153, 164, 168, 198, 216, 234, 274, 291, 307, 329, 331, 346, 353, 357, 375, 388, 393, 395, 400, 402, 404, 410, 430, 432, 441, 445, 446, 451–453 Taruskin, Richard 153, 381, 382, 452 Tasca, Norma 427 Tati, Jacques 235 Taylor, Charles 123, 124, 152, 181, 276, 278, 29, 295, 332, 412, 449, 452 Tawaststjerna, Erik 117, 287, 295, 296, 303, 314, 452 Tchaikovsky, Piotr 95 Thomas Aquinas 163 Thompson, Stith 386, 388 Thoreau, Henry David 3 Threadgold, Terry 430 Tietjen, Heinz 238 Todorov, Tzvetan 71, 73, 74, 124, 452 Tolstoi, Alexei 371 Tolstoi, Leo 43 107, 108, 136, 142, 158, 180, 452 Tomashevsky, Boris 368, 375, 376 Tommila, Päiviö 307, 452 Topelius, Zachris 309, 314–316, 452 Toporov, V. N. 453 Torop, Peeter 111, 428, 436 Trevarthen, Colwyn Trigo, Salvato 430 Trubetskoy, Yevgeny 363, 380, 381 Tull, James 441 Turgenev, Ivan 31 Turkka, Jouko 308, 309 Tynyanov, Yuri 82, 368, 374, 393, 452 Uexküll, Jakob von 15, 24, 51, 52, 62, 66, 103, 113, 118–120, 140, 200, 278–281, 289, 300, 408, 436, 452, 453 Uexküll, Thure von 15, 66, 120, 281, 436, 450

465

Ulanova, Galina 230 Umiker-Sebeok, Jean 432, 451 Uosukainen, Riitta 431, 438 Uotila, Aukusti 261 Uotinen, Jorma 192 Uspensky, B. A. 306, 310, 453 Vaala, Valentin (Valentin Ivanoff) 240, 241, 447 Vainio, Jan Mikael 161 Vainiomäki, Tiina 56, 453 Valentinus 354 Välimäki, Susanna 434 Valkonen, Markku 453 Valkonen, Olli 453 Valnetov, Mikhail 365 Vallgren, Ville 114, 257, 261–265, 453 Valsiner, Jaan 27, 34, 35, 67, 76, 184, 188, 206, 207, 452, 453 Vattimo, Gianni 164 Vega, Carlos 86, 453 Veivo, Harri 45, 434, 437, 446, 453 Vélasquez, Diego 65, 312 Verdi, Giuseppe 167, 224, 225, 342 Verlaine, Paul 261, 374 Veron, Eliseo 150 Veselovsky, Alexander 384, 386 Victoria (Queen of England) 342 Vierimaa, Irma 446 Villa, Kyllikki 453 Villa-Lobos, Heitor 94 Villard, Pierre 257 Violi, Patrizia 430, 435 Visconti, Luchino 236, 246, 441 Voigt, Vilmos 368, 375, 385, 386, 425, 426, 429, 430, 433, 453 Volli, Ugo 119, 144, 279, 388, 435, 436, 453 Voltaire 102 Vuori, Harri 161 Wagner, Cosima 220, 343 Wagner, Richard 16, 53, 84, 90, 92, 93, 107, 117, 118, 134, 161, 184, 192, 220, 224, 226, 236–238, 257, 286, 295, 373, 384, 387, 424, 444, 449 Wagner, Winifred 238 Wagner, Wolfgang 373

466 | Index Wahl, Jean 4, 127, 395 Waldenfels, Bernhard 453 Wallenius, Otto 261 Wąsik, Zdzisław 453 Waugh, Evelyn 167 Weaver, Warren 118, 406, 409 Weber, Carl Maria von 96, 283 Webern, Anton 293 Wecksell, Julius 226 Weiss, Peter 158–160, 453 Welby, Victoria Lady 56, 342, 343–353, 366, 443, 445, 449–451 Wells, Herman B. 426 Welsch, Wolfgang 41, 333, 453 Weston, Judith 247 Whorf, Benjamin Lee 147 Williams, Brook 426 Williams, Raymond 197 Willis, Paul 187, 188 Wilson, Edward O. 269, 453 Wiora, Walter 97

Withalm, Gloria 430–432 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 449 Wodehouse, Pelham Grenville 257 Worburton, Thomas 447 Wright, G. H. von 56, 61, 107, 172–174, 183, 195, 408, 453 Wundt, Wilhelm 333, 354, 386 Yamaguchi, Masao 430, 440 Ylä-Kotola, Mauri 438 Yli-Salomäki, Aki 161 Zarcone, Thierry 453 Ždanov, Andrei 368, 375 Zeffirelli, Franco 373 Zholdak, Andriy 373 Ziino, Agostino 452 Žirmunsky, Viktor 375, 380, 382, 385, 386, 393, 395 Zola, Émile 114, 261 Zweig, Stefan 402, 453