Ideas of Education: Philosophy and Politics from Plato to Dewey 2012047750, 9780415582520, 9780203817544

1,134 130 3MB

English Pages [306] Year 2013

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Polecaj historie

Ideas of Education: Philosophy and Politics from Plato to Dewey
 2012047750, 9780415582520, 9780203817544

Table of contents :
Cover
Title Page
Copyright Page
Table of Contents
List of contributors
Credit list
Introduction: education and political theory
1 Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education
2 Aristotle’s educational politics and the Aristotelian renaissance in philosophy of education
3 Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era
4 Medieval theories of education: Hugh of St Victor and John of Salisbury
5 Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia
6 Teaching the Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on education
7 Locke on education and the rights of parents
8 Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education
9 Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment
10 Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education
11 Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability between mankind and the nation: Fichte and Schleiermacher on higher education
12 Education and utopia: Robert Owen and Charles Fourier
13 Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education
14 J. S. Mill on education
15 Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England
16 Idealism and education
17 ‘Affection in Education': Edward Carpenter, John Addington Symonds, and the politics of Greek love
18 John Dewey: Saviour of American education or worse than Hitler?
Index

Citation preview

Ideas of Education

There has always been a strong relationship between education and philosophy – especially political philosophy. Renewed concern about the importance and efficacy of political education has revived key questions about the connections between the power to govern and the power to educate. Although these themes are not always prominent in commentaries, political writings have often been very deeply concerned with both educational theory and practice. This invaluable book will introduce the reader to key concepts and disputes surrounding educational themes in the history of political thought. The book draws together a fascinating range of educational pioneers and thinkers from the canon of philosophers and philosophical schools, from Plato and Aristotle to Edward Carpenter and John Dewey, with attention along the way paid both to individual authors, such as Thomas Hobbes and Mary Wollstonecraft, as well as to intellectual movements, such as the Scottish Enlightenment and the Utopian Socialists. Each thinker or group is positioned in their historical context, and each chapter addresses the structure of the theory and argument, considering both contemporaneous and current controversies. A number of themes run through the volume: • • • •

an analysis of pedagogy, socialisation, schooling, and university education, with particular relation to public and private life, and personal and political power; references to the historical and intellectual context; an overview of the current reception, understanding, and interpretation of the thinker in question; the educational legacy of the theories or theorists.

This book will be of interest to students, researchers, and scholars of education, as well as to students and teachers of political theory, the history of political thought, and social and political philosophy. Christopher Brooke is Lecturer in Politics at the University of Bristol, UK. Elizabeth Frazer is Official Fellow and Tutor in Politics at New College, Oxford, and Lecturer in Politics at the University of Oxford, UK.

This page intentionally left blank

Ideas of Education Philosophy and politics from Plato to Dewey Edited by Christopher Brooke and Elizabeth Frazer

First published 2013 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2013 C. Brooke and E. Frazer The right of the editors to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ideas of education : philosophy and politics from Plato to Dewey / edited by Christopher Brooke and Elizabeth Frazer. pages cm Includes bibliographical references. 1. Education—Philosophy. I. Brooke, Christopher, 1973- editor of compilation. II. Frazer, Elizabeth, editor of compilation. III. McPherran, Mark L., 1949- Socrates, Plato, Eros and liberal education. LB14.7.I34 2013 370.1—dc23 2012047750 ISBN: 978-0-415-58252-0 (hbk) ISBN: 978-0-203-81754-4 (ebk) Typeset in Galliard by Cenveo Publisher Services

Contents

List of contributors Credit list Introduction: education and political theory

vii xi 1

C H RI S TO P H E R BRO O KE A ND EL IZA BET H FR AZ ER

1 Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education

6

M ARK L. M C P HERRA N

2 Aristotle’s educational politics and the Aristotelian renaissance in philosophy of education

21

RAN D ALL CU R REN

3 Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

38

G . RE Y D AM S - S CH IL S

4 Medieval theories of education: Hugh of St Victor and John of Salisbury

52

B RI AN D . F I TZ GERA L D

5 Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

66

J O H N M . PARRIS H

6 Teaching the Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on education

83

TERES A M . BEJA N

7 Locke on education and the rights of parents AL EX TU CKN ES S

103

vi

Contents

8 Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

115

PATRI C K RIL EY

9 Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment

129

R YAN PATR ICK H A NL EY

10 Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education

145

E L I ZAB ETH FRA ZER

11 Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability between mankind and the nation: Fichte and Schleiermacher on higher education

160

AL EXAN D E R S CH MIDT

12 Education and utopia: Robert Owen and Charles Fourier

178

D AVI D L EO P O L D

13 Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education

194

RU TH WATT S

14 J. S. Mill on education

209

AL AN R YAN

15 Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

224

LAU RA S C HWA RT Z

16 Idealism and education

237

AN D REW VINCENT

17 ‘Affection in Education’: Edward Carpenter, John Addington Symonds, and the politics of Greek love

252

J O S EP H I N E CRAWL EY Q U INN A ND CHRIS TOPHER BR OOK E

18 John Dewey: saviour of American education or worse than Hitler?

267

RI C H ARD PRING

Index

285

Contributors

Teresa M. Bejan is a Mellon Research Fellow in the Society of Fellows in the Humanities and a visiting lecturer in the Department of Political Science at Columbia University. She holds a Ph.D. from Yale University and an M.Phil. from Cambridge. Her principal research interests lie in early modern AngloAmerican political thought, particularly concerning issues of toleration, education, and civility. Her article on Roger Williams recently appeared in History of European Ideas. In 2014, she will join the Department of Political Science at the University of Toronto Mississauga as an Assistant Professor. Christopher Brooke is Lecturer in Politics in the School of Sociology, Politics and International Studies at the University of Bristol and the author of Philosophic pride: Stoicism and political thought from Lipsius to Rousseau (Princeton, 2012). Randall Curren is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Rochester, in New York, Chair of Moral Education at the University of Birmingham, and Professor at the Royal Institute of Philosophy, London. He is author of Aristotle on the necessity of public education (2000) and editor of The Blackwell companion to the philosophy of education (2003) and the journal Theory and Research in Education. Brian D. FitzGerald is a D.Phil. candidate in Medieval History at Lincoln College, Oxford. His doctorate is on scholastic and humanist debates about prophecy and divine inspiration, and recent publications include articles on Hugh of St Victor’s theory of history and on Franciscan mysticism. Among his research interests are medieval intellectual history, medieval literary theory, and the classical tradition. Elizabeth Frazer is Official Fellow and Tutor in Politics at New College, Oxford, and Lecturer in Politics at the University of Oxford. Her research interests include the problems of political education, and normative theories of politics.

viii

Contributors

Ryan Patrick Hanley is Associate Professor of Political Science at Marquette University. His research in the history of political philosophy focuses on the Scottish Enlightenment. He is the author of Adam Smith and the character of virtue (Cambridge, 2009) and editor of the Penguin Classics edition of Adam Smith’s Theory of moral sentiments (2010) and the forthcoming Princeton guide to Adam Smith. David Leopold is University Lecturer in Political Theory at the University of Oxford, and a Fellow of Mansfield College, Oxford. He has interests in both contemporary political philosophy and the history of political thought. His publications include an edited volume (co-edited with Marc Stears), Political theory: methods and approaches (Oxford, 2008), and a monograph, The young Karl Marx. German philosophy, modern politics, and human flourishing (Cambridge, 2007). Mark L. McPherran is Professor of Philosophy at Simon Fraser University. He is the author of The religion of Socrates (Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), and numerous articles, including: ‘Socratic religion’ in The Cambridge companion to Socrates (forthcoming); ‘Medicine, magic, and religion in Plato’s Symposium’ in Plato’s Symposium: issues in interpretation and reception (CHS/Harvard, 2006); ‘Platonic religion’ in A companion to Plato (Blackwell, 2006); and ‘The piety and gods of Plato’s Republic’ in The Blackwell guide to Plato’s Republic (Blackwell, 2006). He is currently the Director of the Annual Arizona Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. John M. Parrish is Associate Professor of Political Science at Loyola Marymount University and studies political theory, political ethics, and the history of political thought. He is the author of Paradoxes of political ethics: from dirty hands to the invisible hand (Cambridge, 2007). He is currently engaged (with co-author Alex Tuckness) in a book-length study of the historical development of mercy as a political concept. Richard Pring was Director and Professor of Educational Studies at the University of Oxford, 1989–2003, and Lead Director of the Nuffield Review of Education and Training for England and Wales, 2003–9. His most recent book was recently published by Routledge, The life and death of secondary education for all. Josephine Crawley Quinn is University Lecturer in Ancient History in the Classics Faculty of the University of Oxford and a Fellow of Worcester College. Her current work concentrates mainly on the Phoenician world and the cultural history of North Africa, and she co-directs the Tunisian-British excavations at Utica.

Contributors

ix

G. Reydams-Schils is Professor in the Program of Liberal Studies at the University of Notre Dame, USA, and holds concurrent appointments in philosophy and theology. She specialises in the traditions of Platonism and Stoicism. She is the author of Demiurge and providence: Stoic and Platonist readings of Plato’s ‘Timaeus’ (Brepols, 1999) and The Roman Stoics: self, responsibility, and affection (Chicago, 2005). She is the editor of Plato’s ‘Timaeus’ as cultural icon (Notre Dame, 2003), and of a collection of essays on Stobaeus (Brepols, 2011). She also directs the Notre Dame Workshop on Ancient Philosophy. Patrick Riley is Oakeshott Professor of Political Philosophy Emeritus at the University of Wisconsin-Madison and Lecturer in the Department of Government at Harvard University. He is the author of several books on modern political thought, including Will and political legitimacy (Harvard, 1982), The general will before Rousseau (Princeton, 1986), and Leibniz’ universal jurisprudence (Harvard, 1996), and editor of The Cambridge companion to Rousseau (Cambridge, 2001). Alan Ryan teaches at Princeton and is Emeritus Professor of Political Theory at the University of Oxford. He has written extensively on J. S. Mill, Bertrand Russell, and John Dewey, and is the author of Liberal anxieties and liberal education (1998) and, most recently, The making of modern liberalism and On politics (both 2012). Alexander Schmidt is a Junior-Professor of Intellectual History at Friedrich Schiller University, Jena. He is the author of Vaterlandsliebe und Religionskonflikt: politische Diskurse im Alten Reich 1555–1648 (Brill, 2007). His articles have appeared in The Historical Journal, History of Political Thought, Modern Intellectual History, Francia, and elsewhere. He is currently writing a book about Enlightenment debates concerning the promotion of sciences and letters. Laura Schwartz is Assistant Professor of Modern British History at the University of Warwick. She is the author of A serious endeavour: gender, education and community at St Hugh’s 1886–2011 (Profile, 2011) and Infidel feminism: secularism, religion and women’s emancipation in England, 1830– 1914 (Manchester, 2013). She is currently working on a history of ‘Feminism and the Servant Problem’. Alex Tuckness is Professor of Political Science at Iowa State University. He is the author of Locke and the legislative point of view (Princeton, 2002). His articles have appeared in a variety of journals including the American Political Science Review, Journal of Political Philosophy, American Journal of Political Science, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Journal of Politics, and Journal of

x

Contributors the History of Ideas. He is currently engaged (with co-author John M. Parrish) in a book-length study of the historical development of mercy as a political concept.

Andrew Vincent is Honorary Professor at Cardiff University and Emeritus Professor of Political Theory at Sheffield University. He is a political theorist specialising in political philosophy, ideologies, human rights, and philosophical idealism. Recent publications include Comparative political thought: theorizing practices (with Michael Freeden, 2012) and British idealism: a guide for the perplexed (with David Boucher, 2011). Ruth Watts is Emeritus Professor of History of Education at the University of Birmingham. She has published much on the history of education and gender. Her books include Gender, power and the Unitarians in England, 1760–1860 (Longman, 1997) and Women in science: a social and cultural history (Routledge, 2007), for which she won the History of Education Society Anne Bloomfield Book Prize in 2010. She is an honorary life-member of both the History of Education and the International Standing Conference for the History of Education (ISCHE), Chair of the Martineau Society, and a member of the Women’s History Network in Britain.

Credit list

McPherran, M. L. (2010) Socrates, Plato, erôs and liberal education, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 527–541. Curren, R. (2010) Aristotle’s educational politics and the Aristotelian renaissance in philosophy of education, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 543–559. Reydams-Schils, G. (2010) Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 561–574. FitzGerald, B. D. (2010) Medieval theories of education: Hugh of St Victor and John of Salisbury, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 575–588. Parrish, J. M. (2010) Education, Erasmian humanism and More’s Utopia, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 589–605. Bejan, T. M. (2010) Teaching the Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on education, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 607–626. Tuckness, A. (2010) Locke on education and the rights of parents, Oxford Review of Education, 36, 627–638. Riley, P. (2011) Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 573–586. Hanley, R. P. (2011) Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 587–602. Frazer, E. (2011) Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 603–617. Leopold, D. (2011) Education and utopia: Robert Owen and Charles Fourier, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 619–635. Watts, R. (2011) Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 637–651. Ryan, A. (2011) J. S. Mill on education, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 653–667. Schwartz, L. (2011) Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 669–682. Quinn, J. C. & Brooke, C. (2011) ‘Affection in education’: Edward Carpenter, John Addington Symonds and the politics of Greek love, Oxford Review of Education, 37, 683–698.

This page intentionally left blank

Introduction Education and political theory Christopher Brooke and Elizabeth Frazer

This book collects together specially commissioned chapters which cover a series of political philosophical theories of education: Plato and Socrates, Aristotle, the Roman Stoics, the Scholastics Hugh of St Victor and John of Salisbury, Erasmus and More, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, the Scottish Enlightenment, Macaulay and Wollstonecraft, Fichte and Schleiermacher, the Utopian Socialists, Owen and Fourier, Martineau and the Unitarians, J. S. Mill, nineteenth-century British feminists, the Idealists, Symonds and Carpenter, and Dewey. The initial intellectual impetus for our project was the observation that political and social theories and philosophies inevitably are imbricated with some theory of or, more modestly, ideas about, education. So we asked contributors to place accounts of pedagogy, curriculum, socialisation, schooling, university and scholarship into the context of political and social philosophy and theory, considering the relationships between education and the concerns about public and private life, political and personal power, as they had been understood by prominent thinkers and groups of intellectuals. The close relationship between educational and political theory may, of course, come as news to some scholars and theorists in both disciplines. Disciplinary specialisation and departmentalisation mean that the academic study of education and of political theory or philosophy can proceed in mutual disregard or even ignorance of one another. In any case, the place of the one in relation to the concerns of the other varies tremendously, and certainly cannot be determined in advance of close textual and theoretical study. Further, there will invariably be interpretive dispute about the structure and coherence of any thinker’s work, and therefore about how the themes of education and political power relate therein. Let us take as an example a thinker whose work is not covered by any of the contributors to the present volume, because he is outside our timeframe. John Rawls in his 1971 book A theory of justice says rather little about the education of young people, although he does not say nothing.1 The paucity of his direct engagement with the theme, though, is of course consistent with the interpretation that actually education must be a critical contributor to a Rawlsian just society. Exactly what its contribution is, however, is a matter of interpretation and dispute between critics and philosophers.

2

Christopher Brooke and Elizabeth Frazer

Like those of other systematic political thinkers, Rawls’s model relies on a balance between four factors. First is the rational or philosophical justification of certain patterns and standards of conduct. The idea is that participants in the society and state will be rationally motivated to behave in desirable ways, simply because of the truth or validity of proposals that they should behave in those ways. Second are the institutional and structural incentives that constrain and urge citizens and rulers to conduct themselves in particular desirable ways. The idea here is that people behave appropriately not so much because they are convinced of the independent rightness of appropriate behaviour, but because the institutions of reward, taxation, and punishment of the society make such behaviour instrumentally rational. Third is the cultivation of a culture of values and standards which governs individuals and groups, as it were, informally. The norms of conduct to strangers, friends, and kin, the values that are celebrated in cultural forms like music, food, and sociability, are a necessary element of a social system that is stable and just. Fourth and finally, there is the overt socialisation of individuals with a specific emphasis on socially oriented and state-endorsed education, in particular of young people. Just and stable societies educate individuals to be the kinds of characters who participate appropriately in the just society. Exactly how the balance between rational motivation, structural incentives, culture and education, is, can be, and should be, struck and maintained is a problem that looms large in the now legendarily voluminous literature on Rawlsian political theory.2 Commentators argue about what Rawls himself actually thought about this question, and critics wonder whether Rawls’s solution, or any solution that is consistent with Rawls’s theory, is really valid or feasible. A Rawlsian worry about education, especially of young people, is that socialising, disciplining, incentivising, and acculturating individuals to be ‘the right kind of individual’ for the society can seem to be an unjustifiable, or, worse, sinister, imposition of society’s values on what ought to be autonomous individuals. Others worry that it is an unwarranted intrusion on what should be the prerogative of parents, or cultural community. For others, the idea that a just society can be established and maintained simply by incentivising adults, engaging in philosophical argument about right and wrong, and promoting a public culture is evidently inadequate: education, of children and adults, must be a necessary condition of any project of social and political stability. Many theorists and thinkers from the ‘political thought’ canon, of course, say a good deal more about education, as such, than did Rawls. For many, a treatise on education is a prominent part of the work – for instance, Erasmus, Locke, Rousseau, Wollstonecraft, Fichte, and Dewey. For others – for example, More, Hobbes, or Carpenter – ideas about education are much more interwoven with the general social or political philosophy. In some cases, essays explicitly addressing educational policy and philosophy can be put into the context of more general social and political theory, as in the cases of Mill and Fichte. In other cases, an intellectual and political position has its origins in struggles over education; this is true for the Unitarians, for example, and, arguably, a good deal

Introduction

3

of feminist thought and action. Either way, problems of interpretation regarding the exact place of education in the theory arise. How, exactly, we should read and understand works or remarks on education in relation to those on epistemology, political power and governmental legitimacy, ethics and metaphysics is invariably contentious. The ‘philosophy of education’ raises the same kind of conundrums and disputes as have been rehearsed with reference to other branches of philosophy. For some, philosophy consists of an enquiry into metaphysics and epistemology, or into the nature of being, what there is, and our understanding or knowledge of it. Some philosophers accordingly treat works that are ostensibly about ‘ethics’ or ‘politics’, or about ‘education’ or ‘science’, as ‘really’ about knowledge and existence, and hence about the human condition. The question whether we treat philosophical analysis of education and politics (and ethics, science, etc.) as autonomous fields of study with their own concepts, methods (and nowadays of course departments, conferences and journals), or as derivative of some more fundamental philosophical enquiry, is one with which our project engages. Our discussion of Rawls’s political philosophy earlier treats ‘education’ as one element in a theory of state and social stability and justice – one that is analytically distinct from truth, economic rationality, and culture. That it is analytically distinct from these others does not in itself settle the question of its necessity, nor its sufficiency, as a critical element of a theory. Nor does analytic distinctiveness imply that education is wholly autonomous from economy or culture. But denial that it is wholly autonomous does not licence the view that it is simply derivative, an epiphenomenon, or some kind of reflex. And analogous considerations apply to the question of the philosophies of education, politics and epistemology and metaphysics. Commentators and critics ask whether we should treat Rousseau’s Emile separately or together with The social contract and the Discourse on inequality; or whether we should read Locke’s Essay on human understanding, his Two treatises of government, and Some thoughts concerning education separately, in the context of distinct philosophical enterprises, or together as part of ‘the same’ problem.3 These questions then – how philosophy of education relates to other kinds of philosophical enquiry, and the place of education in particular in relation to other elements in philosophy and theory of state and social, public and private, political and personal power – are at the basis of our project. From the Stoic philosophers, to utopian experimenters, we meet, in the chapters that follow, a range of philosophical analyses of the relationship between education and the self, and the society, the polity, values, and knowledge. The term education itself, of course, covers a wide range of processes and concerns. The chapters here show how focus shifts over time and from thinker to thinker. Analyses variously focus on the purposes and methods of scholarship; the nature of a ‘university’ or a ‘school’; the rearing and socialisation of children; and the learning and politicisation aspects of religious observance. For some of the philosophers and thinkers considered here, education is connected above all to questions of equality and autonomy. Some focus on the relationships internal

4

Christopher Brooke and Elizabeth Frazer

to education itself – between students, between teacher and pupil; others consider education, and the institutions within which it proceeds, in terms of their effects on polity and society. We have decided to present the chapters in the traditional chronological order, although in the course of the project we considered some alternative schemes. The historical order naturally conduces to a reading of changes over time, and across intellectual and political contexts, in how education is conceptualised. This way of putting it signals dissent from some recent methodological positions in the history of ideas. It has been argued that an idea in its local context, formed as it is in response to very specific questions and problems, can hardly be treated as the ‘same idea’ as that which is denoted by the same word in a context many centuries distant.4 Notwithstanding the undoubted value of interpretive caution, about stability of meaning, about the nature of intellectual influence, and about the ‘development’ of ideas over time, we work on the basis that the past, distant though it may be, is never completely left behind by those who come after. It might be that the situations of educators like Socrates, Aristotle, or the Stoics, mean that their view of education as a public concern is dramatically different from the view that education, including the education of girls, must be a matter of public interest as that is articulated by Catharine Macaulay and Mary Wollstonecraft in the eighteenth century. But the contrasts can be overemphasised, for eighteenth-century thinkers were well aware of the concepts, analyses, and arguments of the classics, and used them as resources in their own thinking. Macaulay, for example, defended ‘stoicism’ at length, and modelled herself (in portraits and sculpture) as a Roman woman. Rousseau’s Emile can be read as a complex dialogue with both Plato and Seneca. Similarly, a particular understanding of the nature of medieval scholarship and education in the universities – critically constructed as ‘scholasticism’ – was an important counter in the fashioning of a new idea of the relationship between state sovereignty and education in the work of Hobbes, and after him Locke and Rousseau. These ‘conversations’ across time are an important aspect of our project. We don’t think of the transformation of ideas across time as teleological – developmentally directed to a greater understanding. But nor do we think of ideas as occurring purely locally, in specific historical contexts. History is not just one great philosopher, with her or his ideas of education and politics, in relation to their own time and place, after another. The transformation of ideas across contexts and across time is a matter of contestation, rejection, inspirational refashioning, and reinvention. From the point of view of some philosophers of education and historians of educational thought, this collection of essays might look incomplete. Important eighteenth-century educationalists such as Johann Pestalozzi, or nineteenthcentury figures like Maria Montessori, should surely figure in a collection of essays entitled ‘Ideas of Education’. We have to say that our intentions from the outset in this project have been to explore the relationship between thought about public and private power, politics and government and about education, and that our approach has been unabashedly based on a traditional canon.

Introduction

5

So Rousseau is here, but Pestalozzi not; Mill is in, but not Montessori, simply because Rousseau and Mill are among the standard list of significant political thinkers, and our question about the place of education in their schemes is clearly posed. This is not to say that we here offer a complete canonical guide. A larger reader or encyclopaedia would encompass a much longer list of thinkers than ours. The chapters published here are not encyclopaedic, either, in their approach or format. We asked contributors to consider the nature of educational ideas as well as their place in the broader context of the theory and philosophy of the individual or group in question, and to consider, where appropriate, the educational legacy or continuing salience of the work. But we also asked for independent views of the theme and treatments of the subject. The results are gratifyingly non-standard, although we have tried to achieve a certain uniformity in the provision of dates, references, allusions to critical disputes, and to changes in the reception of the theories in question, in order to help interested readers who wish to pursue their study further.

Notes 1 Rawls, 1999: two sentences in §17, one in §39, and a paragraph on instruction in moral autonomy in §78. 2 Some notable contributions in this framework are Gutmann, 1987; Callan, 1997; Brighouse, 1998; Levinson, 1999; Macedo, 2000. 3 On Rousseau, see Bloom’s introduction to Emile in which he warns against treating; it as a book ‘for teacher training schools’: Rousseau, 1979, p. 4. On the question of the relationship between Locke’s Treatises and the epistemology, see Waldron, 2002, pp. 50ff. 4 Skinner, 2002, p. 86.

References Brighouse, H. (1998) ‘Civic education and liberal legitimacy’, Ethics, 108, 719–745. Callan, E. (1997) Creating citizens: political education and liberal democracy (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Gutmann, A. (1987) Democratic education (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Levinson, M. (1999) The demands of liberal education (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Macedo, S. (2000) Diversity and distrust: civic education in a multicultural society (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Rawls, J. [1971] (1999) A theory of justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Rousseau, J.-J. [1762] (1979) Emile, or on education (ed. A. Bloom) (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Skinner, Q. [1969] (2002) Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas, in: Visions of politics vol. 2 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Waldron, J. (2002) God, Locke, and equality: Christian Foundations in Locke’s Political Thought (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

1

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education Mark L. McPherran

Introduction Although modern educators and educational theorists often credit Socrates and Plato for their ground-breaking contributions to educational methods, theory, and reform, they often misunderstand them. They also commonly relegate them to the history of education, rather than seeing them as still relevant to the theory and practice of teaching at secondary and post-secondary levels. This is understandable, especially if one has some understanding of the current state of secondary and post-secondary teacher education.1 There are several useful outlines of the nature and uses of Socrates’ (469–399 BCE) notorious ‘Socratic Method’ – and many contemporary discussions of the logical side of its several puzzling aspects.2 There are also several good outlines of Plato’s (428/427–348/347 BCE) educational theory – especially as it is deployed in his portrait of the perfect city in his Republic.3 In this paper, I want to focus on a more neglected topic, namely, the non-logical, psychologicallyastute pedagogical methods of Socrates, mentioning briefly what Plato did with that inheritance. It has been said that the first axiom of Socratic teaching is ‘Start where the students are’ (Swardson, 2005, p. 178). Given where some students really are these days, however, this will strike some of us as a very challenging invitation. For although Aristotle (384–322 BCE) may have been right in his own time and place that ‘It is easy to get starting points with men of good upbringing’ (Nicomachean Ethics, Bk I, 1095b7-8), such points are now harder to find in the post-everything era of the present – even among the very best of the breed. For although undergraduates may not actually believe that four-sided triangles exist, some very bright ones are nevertheless willing to assert that very possibility until one can per impossibile prove otherwise. Others seem not to have any committed beliefs on philosophical topics to appeal to in discussion. So even though the Socratic method – the elenchos – is frequently presented as a relatively theory-free teaching device, suitable for use in all disciplines from art to law to engineering as a way of testing student knowledge claims, it needs always to be recognised that its subjects must at least possess a commitment to the law of noncontradiction for the game to even get going. Moreover, the effective use of the

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 7 elenchos requires a full consideration of the psychological, cultural, and ethical factors surrounding the relationship between the elenchos-wielder and his or her interlocutor.

Socrates and his methods One of the best and most time-honoured ways to approach such topics is to turn to the fountainhead of the elenchos: Socrates, as represented to us by Plato. In such dialogues as the Charmides and Gorgias, for example, we find Socrates operating as a subtle diagnostician of Charmides’ (446–403 BCE) attraction to intemperance and Callicles’ (450/445–404/403 BCE) attraction to tyrannical hedonism, as part of his inquiry into the nature of the virtues. Indeed, Socrates’ examinations are portrayed as being so attentive to the specific characteristics of each individual interlocutor that Socrates and Plato have been credited with being the inventors of scientific verbal psychotherapy, beside whom ‘Gorgias [485–380 BCE] and Antiphon [479–411 BCE] are mere prehistory’ (Entralgo, 1970, p. 137; cf. p. 126). However, once we begin to study the methods of Plato’s Socrates we must confront a host of puzzles generated by the way Socrates relates his elenctic method to a revolutionary moral theory, and to his equally revolutionary religious commitments. Modern sensibilities can likewise be disconcerted by Socrates’ seemingly antidemocratic tendencies, and by his disingenuous and cruel use of shame, irony and erôs in the pursuit of his therapeutic, educational mission.4 Modern educators must ask themselves: Ought we really to risk the ire of the Dean, let alone law suits and so on, in order to model ourselves as modern day Socrateses grilling and publicly humiliating our own reluctant Alcibiadeses (451–404 BCE)?5 I wish here to explore briefly several of these puzzles and difficulties in an attempt to begin to locate the nature and place of Socratic and Platonic pedagogical methods and their use of erôs as they might be deployed in the modern classroom. It was Socrates who allegedly ‘first called philosophy down from the sky’ (Cicero, Tusculan Disputations, 5.4.10) by investigating not the nature of the physical cosmos, but rather, the human virtues of courage, temperance, piety, justice, and wisdom, and their contribution to human happiness, human flourishing; that is, eudaimonia. The basic elements of Socrates’ revolutionary moral theory (later developed by Plato, Aristotle and others) can be summarised like this: 1 Every kind of creature desires/aims by nature to achieve that kind’s particular good (e.g., acorns ‘aim to be’ successful oak trees). 2 Thus, every person aims to achieve the human good for him or herself (every person desires to be an agathôs; a good, successful person). 3 A person is not his or her body, but is, rather, a soul (psuchê) = a rational mind (nous). 4 The human good is eudaimonia (‘happiness’ in an objective sense; human flourishing, ‘success’ – ‘being well’ and ‘doing well’). All other goals such as

8

5 6 7

8

Mark L. McPherran health and wealth are subordinate at best and only insofar as they promote eudaimonia (they are not what eudaimonia consists in). The means to the human good are the virtues (aretai: ‘excellences’); the canonical virtues being: courage, temperance, piety, justice, and wisdom. The virtues are kinds of craft-knowledge (of how to produce virtuous actions). Knowledge of the virtues is best obtained by means of philosophising (beginning with the elimination of the conceit that one already has such knowledge when one does not). Thus, the happiest life belongs to the philosopher.

The philosophising mentioned in item (7) most closely associated with Plato’s Socrates is the elenchos. The general pattern of an elenchos is roughly this: 1 the advancement of a moral proposition p by some interlocutor, 2 prodded by Socrates, the interlocutor admits that he or she holds moral propositions q and r, 3 through the assistance of Socrates, the interlocutor concedes that q and r entail not-p, 4 whereupon Socrates claims that p has been shown inconsistent with the interlocutor’s belief-set and 5 hence, that the interlocutor does not have the expertise that led him or her to advance thesis p as something that they know as a matter of their expertise (see, e.g., Euthyphro, 7a-8b; G. 475a-d). There is no clear scholarly consensus on how Socrates’ method was actually supposed to work – whether it is as negative as this summary implies, whether it is more positive than that, or whether, actually, there can be said to be any such thing as ‘the Socratic method’ or, rather, whether Socrates’ questioning of his interlocutors was not always ad hoc and not ‘methodical’ at all. Whatever the correct account of the elenctic method might be, we have no reason to believe that Socrates was the first to use it. He was preceded by other thinkers in cultivating the systematic use of the procedure. That explains why, when Aristotle assessed Socrates’ contributions to the development of philosophical methodologies, he did not mention the elenchos per se as a Socratic innovation but picked out instead Socrates’ introduction of the search for definitions of universal ethical terms and inductive or epagogic argumentation (arriving at a general claim by adducing examples) (Metaphysics, 1078b). Plato and Xenophon (430–354 BCE) also focus on epagogic reasoning as an innovative, distinguishing mark of Socratic methodology when they have Socrates’ interlocutors complain that Socrates prattles on far too much about ‘his favorite topics’ (Memorabilia, 1.2.37) – blacksmiths, cobblers, cooks, physicians and other such banal craftspeople – in order to generate and test general analogical principles concerning the alleged craft of virtue (McPherran, 2007). This overall approach to ethics has been both criticised and defended by recent commentators. In this article I aim to respond critically to these controversies in

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 9 a way that will help us to appreciate more fully the groundbreaking and perennially relevant aspects of Socratic and Platonic teaching, beyond their mere logical forms.6 Socrates, and other ancient philosophers’ positions can be characterised as ‘eudaimonistic’, meaning that philosophical analyses and understandings, and ethical decisions and conduct, should be both justified and explained by reference to human flourishing (or ‘happiness’). This position can be criticised in the same way that modern consequentialism can – it can be said to suffer from the flaw of ‘ethical egoism’. That is to say, it implies the general rule that one ought to take one’s own self-interests as the overriding guide in one’s moral decision-making (Vlastos, 1991, p. 177). Against this, though, Socrates can also be interpreted as not endorsing any such egoistical, self-serving point of view. After all, the argument goes, in Socrates’ case it was piety, not eudaimonistic reasoning or justification that motivated and explained his own philosophising and teaching (Vlastos, 1991, p. 177). According to his own account, as told by Plato in the Apology, he received a report that the Delphic oracle had said that ‘Socrates is the wisest of the Athenians’, and it is for this reason that he became a ‘street philosopher’, buttonholing and deflating the presumptions of all those interlocutors who laid claim to exact knowledge of the virtues (Apology, 20e-23b). Socrates had already arrived at a partial definition of piety according to which it involves not so much close attention to the correct performance of religious rituals as to serving the gods by improving the state of our souls by means of philosophising. Since piety as a virtue is then a means to the personal end we all seek – namely eudaimonia – then we serve ourselves even by serving others just insofar as we labour to improve their own intellectual grasp of the virtues, and thus, their own possession of eudaimonia (McPherran, 1996). This is a plausible interpretation of the story. However, I do not believe it is sufficient either to square eudaimonistic reasoning with piety and refute an egotistical account, or as a complete account of Socratic philosophy and education. It must be acknowledged that in the Apology Socrates certainly tells the story this way. An overly-enthusiastic Chaerephon went to the Delphic Oracle to ask if anyone was wiser than Socrates (Ap., 20c-23c) and got the response, ‘No one is wiser’ (21a5-7). This report, however, was at odds with Socrates’ own conviction that he possessed no great knowledge of the virtues, and so he was provoked to conduct a long interpretive effort that would somehow preserve Apollo’s veracity. The result is the thesis that the god actually meant that Socrates is wisest by best grasping his own lack of genuine, divine wisdom concerning the virtues. This, in turn, is taken to mean that Apollo has – like a general – stationed Socrates in Athens, ordering him to philosophise and examine himself and others (28d10-29a2). And since one ought always to obey the command of a god at all costs, Socrates is obliged to philosophise regardless of any dangers (29d; cf. Republic, 368b-c). Despite their scepticism and outrage, then, Socrates’ jurors should ‘know well’ (Ap., 30a5) that the Oracle’s pronouncement marked a turning point in his life so profound that he now philosophises under a unique divine mandate (29c-30b, 33c).

10

Mark L. McPherran

Attractive though Socrates’ account is, many scholars who have found his uncompromising allegiance to rational philosophy attractive have been just as repelled by his grounding it on such shady religious origins. This puzzlement is legitimate, at least insofar as Apollo’s response to Chaerephon’s question is clearly and explicitly descriptive (describing the nature of Socrates’ wisdom), not prescriptive (telling Socrates what to do with his wisdom). In any case, it would appear that well before Chaerephon’s trip to Delphi Socrates had already been pursuing a life of refutational philosophy – that is what prompted Chaerephon’s long and difficult journey in the first place. Hence, the pronouncement of the Oracle could not have been what initiated his philosophical career. No wonder, then, that some have found Socrates’ ‘derivation’ of his alleged divine obligation to philosophise as analogous to pulling a rabbit from a hat: a rabbit concealed within the hat by the magician himself (Vlastos, 1991, p. 171). Why does Socrates not end his interpretive quest after discovering the god’s meaning in saying that he is the wisest, but rather go on to try to convince his hapless interlocutors via the elenchos that they lack the expert knowledge they originally lay claim to? In particular, why do this when he knows that public refutation brings shame to his interlocutors, shame that breeds in turn the kind of hostility that will eventually land him in court on trial for his life (Ap., 22e-23a)? (Even now such responses plague the life of the ‘disrespectful’ Socratic teacher.) In any case why does Socrates give the slightest hoot about what these ignoramuses believe about themselves? We can imagine Socrates offering several plausible reasons. First, we are told in the dialogue Crito that Socrates loves – has philia for – Athens in the way that a child loves his or her parents (e.g., Crito, 49e-52d). Socrates has even fought and risked his life for Athens. And since a politician – or any citizen for that matter – stands to harm Athens if he acts out of an unaware, hubristic assumption that he possesses sufficient wisdom to counsel the city, Socrates must for reasons of natural affection and filial piety attempt to convince that person of their lack of wisdom. Socrates chooses a politician as his initial candidate for testing by the elenctic method (Ap., 21 b-c). Secondly, Socrates does indeed declare that the demands of piety require him to serve the gods by convincing the politician of his or her ignorance. But it is important to note that the story of the Oracle is the story of how Socrates in particular came to realise his unique status as Apollo’s missionary, a divine gift to Athens, set upon her as a gadfly, scourge and midwife who – unlike all other Athenians – is under an obligation to philosophise free of virtually all the mitigating or restraining factors present in the case of other people. His story simply is not our story since we lack his unique philosophical gifts, and it is certainly not the story of harmful bumblers like Euthyphro or ill-intentioned Sophists like Thrasymachus whose defeat by the Socratic method is reported in the Republic. Neither Apollo nor the demands of prudential self-interest require of any other Athenian – nor of any of us moderns – that they or we step outside the boundaries of the pressing project of promoting our own eudaimonia. This is made clear by Socrates’ comparison of himself to a soldier who has been stationed at a

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 11 battle-post by a general (Ap., 28d-29a) – that is, he is acting under orders, and hence, not simply out of a philanthropic impulse. That is also what explains Socrates’ willingness to override his normal inclinations to live a fairly normal human life (Ap., 23b, 31a-c). Third, moreover, there is no general principle inherent in the virtue of piety that must force us to look beyond our own personal good. We can satisfy the demands of piety that we attempt to instantiate goodness in the universe just insofar as we look to improving our own souls or minds. We need not go off trying to play would-be Socrateses to our unreceptive, possibly anti-intellectual, neighbours. From their perspective, after all, it is unclear whether or not the relentlessly-examined life is all that worth living. So it seems as though I must only pursue the project of coming to know the virtues, and need not be distracted from that aim by the incessant demands of all those potential objects of my charity. There is no obvious link between say, being a dutiful professor of the humanities and staying past office hours for the sake of tardy students. If all this is right, then I suggest that we must look elsewhere for a way to save Socratic moral theory – and our own students – from the ‘spiritual toxins’ of ethical egoism. We need to know what to say to students who ask sceptically about the value of self-examination and liberal education, especially in view of the pleasures of self-deception and the pain self-examination can involve. We will receive guidance on this if we look to Socrates’ and Plato’s conceptions of love – both philia and erôs – and their relation to the inherent presuppositions of Socrates’ and Plato’s educational methods. Elenchos, philia, and erôs I begin with a famous and – for some modern students – scandalous scene from Plato’s Charmides. Returning after a long absence from his service in the heavy fighting at Potidaea, Socrates seeks out the pleasures of a familiar gymnasium. After recounting items of recent military news (Charmides, 153b-d), Socrates then asks whether there are any young men distinguished for their wisdom, their physical beauty, or both – instantly introducing the topic of the mind and the body, and implicitly their relation. When young, handsome Charmides is then presented to him as just such a specimen, Socrates fastidiously insists that before Charmides allows Critias (460–403 BCE) and himself to admire his physique he must first strip off his entire body so as to display his soul. Socrates then also confesses that he is no judge of physical beauty, since ‘almost all young persons appear to be beautiful in my eyes’. Nevertheless, Socrates proceeds to join the mob in a more than cerebral appreciation of Charmides. First, Socrates jostles with the others on his bench – toppling the end-man off sideways – in order to make a place for Charmides next to himself. Then, once seated, Charmides’ close physical proximity causes Socrates to lose first his ‘previous bold belief in his powers to converse naturally, and then – when Socrates is presented to Charmides as a physician with a cure for his morning headaches – Socrates becomes further unsettled by Charmides’

12

Mark L. McPherran

full gaze. Finally, suddenly glancing past Charmides’ cloak at the no-doubt manly chest within, Socrates loses his last vestiges of control, becoming suddenly inflamed with an attraction more than mental. Feeling ‘frozen like a fawn before a powerful hungry beast’, Socrates experiences a virtual loss of self and becomes – even to himself – mere flesh (Xenophon, Mem., 1.3.11-15). This image is very familiar to readers of Plato, but it is also deeply complex, signalling both expected and unexpected claims. First, the way in which Socrates’ behaviour contradicts his claimed impartiality to physical beauty amounts to an admission that even he does not possess full self-knowledge. Nevertheless, we are still reminded that we are in the presence of Socrates-the-hero-of-self-control, since instead of casting himself in the expected ancient role of an erastês – an older lover – Socrates withdraws inside himself, assuming instead the passive stance of a young erômenos – a young beloved (Xenophon, Mem., 1.3.11-15). Plato thereby also gives us a peek into Socrates’ cloak and soul, providing a direct view of his erôs, and an indirect gauge of its intensity. For, knowing as we do the almost superhuman self-control that Socrates brings to any encounter, the fact that he, the master-steersman of all conversations, is brought to speechlessness – barely able to avoid the clutches of the beast beside him – allows us to infer that within Socrates there exists an equally superhuman erôs (Cicero, On fate, 5.10; Tusc., 4.37.80). Socrates is, of course, able to recover his composure, and then responds to Charmides’ request for a headache-cure by claiming that he possesses a leaf and charm that will heal him. He next goes on to subtle diagnosis of both Critias’ and Charmides’ characters. Critias is revealed to be a plotter of the sort who is willing to deceive even his own cousin, Charmides, despite the fact that he is obliged to serve as his guardian (Plato, Charmides, 155a). Moreover, he is shown to have irresponsibly failed to detect the most likely cause of Charmides’ headache: namely, over-indulgence in wine (especially improperly-mixed wine) – brought on, one suspects, by Charmides’ status as the current beau of the ball. Charmides in turn fails to see that knowledge of Socrates’ medicinal charm might be reserved to those who are qualified to apply it, since its non-harmful application to a patient may well require prior training and expertise in both diagnosis and the application of magical charms. Finally, by the conclusion of the dialogue (176a-d) the tables have been entirely turned. The experience of undergoing repeated interrogations at the hands of Socrates has had the effect of turning Charmides into just another one of Socrates’ suitors, with Socrates having replaced him as the new beau of the ball. For Charmides – and Critias as well – are presented as having become convinced that Socrates possesses charms of exactly the sort they have experienced; namely, mental gymnastics to match the physical ones surrounding them. So beguiling is this sort of argumentative encounter for them that they now desire to be charmed in this fashion every day, and so intense is their desire for such an association with Socrates – and so free of the restraints that kept Socrates’ own attraction to Charmides in check – that they are willing to plot and use force to obtain it (176a-d).

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 13 There is little dispute that Plato (and Xenophon) are eager to reveal the erotic side of Socrates. Part of this project is driven, I suspect, by a desire to explain and so justify Socrates’ disingenuous and cruel use of erôs in the pursuit of his educational mission. That is, he often flatters his interlocutors and students, letting them believe that he finds them interesting on the basis of their bodily as well as their intellectual or psychological charms, and then – as he takes them through the process of self-examination via his notorious method of questioning – they suddenly find that the tables have been turned. The importance of their bodies has been dismissed and it is now they who are infatuated, and shamefully so, since Socrates is the ugliest man in Athens. Plato gives voice to this process of reversal with the speech he attributes to the Alcibiades of his famous dialogue on erôs, the Symposium (212c-223b). We find the same reversal in Xenophon (Mem. 3.11), in the charming and illustrative story of a beautiful courtesan named Theodotê – a hetaira, not an everyday pornê – who ‘was ready to keep company with anyone who pleased her’. Socrates visits her and begins by flattering her, but by the end of his investigation into the exact nature of her vocation, she demands that he ‘come to see her often’ for more useful conversation. However, Socrates demurs, saying that he is too busy with his many other girlfriends to whom he is teaching what he terms ‘potions, spells, and magic love wheels’. ‘Lend me your magic love wheel, then, that I may draw you to me’, she begs; to which the Socratic reply is ‘But, I don’t want to be drawn to you; rather, I want you to come to me’ (my emphasis). And, so, the scene concludes with Theodotê exclaiming: ‘Oh, I’ll come alright: but just make sure that you welcome me when I do!’ Just as in the Charmides, Socrates has turned the tables: the object of erôs has become the subject of erôs, but the erôs is no longer what it was for in the first instance. Desire for the beautiful body has been replaced by a desire for the beautiful words and arguments that only a knowledgeable – that is, beautiful – soul can produce. The big joke is that Socrates and Theodotê are comparable to each other, as neither of them have any visible means of support and so count on the generosity of their ‘friends’ (Plato, Ap., 38b). Both are also, of course, proposing seductions – though of radically different sorts, one intellectual and one with a strong corporeal element. What is more interesting, though, is that it has taken Socrates only a very few ironic, argumentative moves to turn a professional seductress into an eager lover of whatever it is that she now thinks she can obtain from the founder of Western moral theory. If she goes to him thinking that she will increase her profit-line by attending to him, we can be sure that Socrates will soon be having her inquiring into her own, limited conception of what it is to truly ‘profit’. But what useful lesson are we lesser mortals to take away from all this? This, I think. We have wondered how to find a way out of the self-absorbed attitude that moral eudaimonism can appear to take as a given. Western culture began in its Grecian childhood and that is where most of us still start off as children (if, that is, we are raised in a loving home and supportive culture) – namely, with a robust sense of self that takes itself to be at the centre of a universe whose central

14

Mark L. McPherran

purpose was to bring our glorious little selves into existence. Alas, those unlucky enough never to transcend that childhood point of view at a reasonable pace then go on to cause us and themselves a wide range of troubles. The healthy trick, as parents know, is to nurture the nascent self without becoming too entangled in its pain as it begins the long journey toward a rational and psychologically-integrated understanding of its proper place in a universe much larger than any self can yet adequately comprehend. There are many key events in this often-painful unfolding, running the gamut from being weaned and toilet-trained to encountering one’s first unexpected schoolyard snub or grade B, to one’s first job, or war, or death, or mid-life crisis. But Socrates seems to know that chief among these things is love. The Socratic theory of love that we can locate within his general moral theory goes something like this. Socrates holds that the desire for self-knowledge is a natural feature of eudaimonistic self-love and self-regard: we can only best achieve eudaimonia by understanding and harmonising our own belief-systems, since we must employ our beliefs in our everyday deliberations as to how we must act in respect of both ourselves and others so as to obtain and maintain eudaimonia. In a social system that derives from our natural constitution, we begin with an acquaintance with the rewards and demands of parental and closeacquaintance philia that alert us to the needs and existence of others. However, these others rarely demand full reciprocity or any abrupt reorientation of our self-centred desires and projects. But at some point in our early lives something very odd and even frightening makes its presence known to us, something very much beyond our rational control and hence normal sense of self. This is the fierce desire for direct acquaintance with and possession of a beauty that is at once both material and yet always just a bit beyond our actual grasp. Yet as every popular music station attests, despite its many attractions this initial form of erotic intimacy is in itself just as much an obstruction to what we take to be our eudaimonia as it is its fulfillment. That sort of beauty cannot be made our own by simply snuggling up to it (Plato, Symposium, 175c-e). It resists acquisition by its very nature and by virtue of its possessing a will of its own. Nevertheless, from the Socratic point of view the many failures of this form of erôs are precisely its central function in the psychological economy of a human life. Rough as it may sound, romantic erôs is for Socrates and Plato only the prelude to a larger life and kind of love for those who can bear to see this. So it seems that what interlocutors such as Alcibiades complain of is that Socrates is able to take the natural desire for close contact with beauty – and all other forms of passionate, erotic desire – and redirect, rechannel, a good measure of it towards desire for intellectual beauty as it is manifested in the soul of the virtuous human being. This is the move that takes us away from ourselves and toward others, because I simply cannot examine and improve my belief-system – and hence, my means of obtaining eudaimonia – without attempting to see how others see me and assess my own beliefs. It is only by engaging with others at the deepest levels of my own self that I have any hope of becoming more intellectually, psychologically beautiful in a way that goes beyond mere appearances.

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 15 Philia by itself in its first instances is insufficient to break through the safe boundaries of the familiar. Absent erôs, we almost always become friends with people like ourselves and those to whom we are bound – as Vlastos says – by ‘blood or fortune’. Philia is more ‘up to us’ than not, and so we pick and choose and reject our friends when we are more or less in our right minds. But erôs has the delightful but also terrifying power to immobilise the rational will and put us into close association with those outside our normal circle of potential associates; those to whom we might well never of our own rational accord have drawn close. Then as now the phenomenon of infatuation has the positive power to break through the narrow circle drawn by our self-regarding eudaimonistic impulse by making us keenly aware of the existence and needs of another – so much so that we can lose ourselves and all our boundaries in the Beloved, if only for a very brief moment. This is again, then, one of the benefits the experience of unrequited erôs can bring: one’s sense of entitlement and worth can receive just the lashing it requires when such central and powerful desires are thwarted. To escape the bonds of self-love and acquire genuinely friendly philia seems to require that we become somehow motivated or forced to include the selfinterests of others within the bounds of our own self-interest (cf. Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, Bks 8, 9). The only way we can begin to want what is good for the sake of another without mixed motivations is by finding ourselves able to place ourselves within the position of the other. Yet to learn to see how a situation looks from the vantage point of another we must begin to see the other as relevantly similar to ourselves. That is precisely what erôs can lead us to see as we attempt to come to terms with the otherness of a beloved. This very same thing is what effective use of the Socratic method in the necessary quest for selfunderstanding requires: I cannot teach or philosophise in a fully successful fashion without trying to put myself into a student’s psychological position so as to see what crucial premise it is that is driving that person to a puzzling or opposing conclusion. We see Socrates do this with Euthyphro when he is able to elicit Euthyphro’s belief in warring gods so as to show that it is at odds with Euthyphro’s own other beliefs (Plato, Euthyphro, 5d-11b). But once I do begin to reposition myself, I will be hard-pressed not to see how very similar my own self is to the selves of others. And this understanding, plus whatever natural psychic drive to remain rationally-self-consistent we already have, can generate that fellow-feeling of brotherly and sisterly affection we call philia – that is, for Socrates at any rate. From that vantage point, then, we can begin to see that our love of self translates into love of wisdom which then translates into love of others. I am suggesting, then, that the Socratic method can yield good results for those who use it in examining others. As I engage with others in my attempt to secure psychic beauty – thereby doing myself a good – I will realise that I have an intrinsic interest in including others within the sphere of my conception of what a eudaimôn life is. Eudaimonia consist entirely in the process of acquiring, possessing and manifesting the only true good – wisdom (Euthydemos, 277d-282e). That process strictly requires a full valuation of another individual as a potential bearer of wisdom. Hence, I

16

Mark L. McPherran

have complete motivation for regarding another’s essential interests as part and parcel of my own as well. If I desire – as I must – to possess the sort of genuine beauty I spot in another, then the only way I can satisfy that desire is by pursuing a self-educational project that looks beyond the borders of what I conceive myself to be at present. Trying to obtain wisdom and beauty for myself alone – as I might try to obtain all the food on the table just for myself – is incoherent if that project requires that I discover and value its presence in others, and then generate it in others. The being well and doing well of eudaimonia must, it seems, simply include the state of loving well. It is Socrates’ position here that since due to erôs one simply must have a desire for friendship, and since to have friends one must have the self-control bestowed by the virtues, and since self-control requires the psychic harmony that the elenchos can instil, one can come to see that one’s desires need to be redirected so that the primary beloved becomes philosophy (or, liberal learning, if you like). But as many of his aporetic, elenctic encounters demonstrate, there is a bootstrapping problem here insofar as being logically led to see this need for a love of consistency requires that one already have a love of consistency. For example, in Euthyphro Socrates can only get the discussion on track by offering friendly help and unwarranted flattery (Plato, Eu., 11a-e). It is thus an extra-logical skill possessed by Socrates that allows him to redirect his interlocutor’s erôs away from transient and inconstant objects of love – whether they be people or activities or material goods – and towards a love of elenctic self-examination. On close analysis, it turns out that when it comes to the elenchos, style and substance are inseparable. Now, let us ground this view of Socratic philia, erôs, and self-examination in a concrete elenctic encounter. Socrates’ examination of Callicles in Plato’s Gorgias is ideal for this purpose. A key theme of the Gorgias is its emphasis on the need for the psychic harmony of belief consistency that the elenchos can expose and provide. Socrates’ examination of Callicles, for example, offers us a case of a split personality characterised as ‘Callicles not agreeing with Callicles’. Here Socrates emphasises the value of internal harmony, saying that it is better to be in contradiction with the vast majority of people than to be at odds with oneself (Plato, Gorgias, 482b). This section of text also connects the importance of possessing psychic harmony with erôs and with the value of having harmonious relations with others. At 481c Socrates notes that he and Callicles have the common experience of being in love with two loves, Socrates with Alcibiades and philosophy, and Callicles with Demos and the demos. Callicles, however, is entrapped by his two loves into continual inconsistency. Whenever he is with Demos, he says what Demos wants to hear, even if it is at odds with his own views. Whenever he is in the Assembly, he says whatever will win approval, even if it is at odds with his own views. Socrates, by contrast, is a constant lover, always preferring philosophy to Alcibiades (Plato, Gorgias, 481d-482b). Since, unlike Alcibiades, Demos and the demos, philosophy always says the same things about the same things, Socrates is able to maintain a relatively harmonious soul by loving the constant,

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 17 psychologically-consistent things that philosophy says (such as that ‘doing what’s unjust and not paying the penalty for it is the ultimate evil’). However, by speaking of his two loves, he indicates that despite the fact that philosophy is his special darling (482a4), he is able to maintain a constant love for another, even someone as internally inconstant (and yet brilliant) as Alcibiades (a man who is at one moment drawn to Socrates and at another repelled) (Plato, Symposium, 216b-c). This same point is present at the conclusion of Socrates’ argument against Callicles at 507c-508a. Here Socrates supports the worth of justice and selfcontrol by maintaining that without them a person cannot be a partner to another person, and hence, will be unable to be a friend to another. The clear assumption is that friendship is in some way valuable, though how it is valuable is left up to us as a problem. Here, I think, the answer is that erôs is being treated in the Gorgias as a distinct and basic psychic force. As we saw before, from the Socratic perspective regarding the true self that we all have, one must simply have loves to have eudaimonia; the question then becomes what one ought to love. Socrates’ love of philosophy as his central beloved over and above other people involves the love of logical consistency that the elenchos requires and cannot itself supply (Woolf, 2000, p. 32). It is Socrates’ position here that since due to erôs one simply must have a desire for friendship, and since to have friends one must have self-control, and since self-control requires the psychic harmony that the elenchos can instill, one can come to see that one’s desires need to be redirected so that the primary beloved becomes philosophy.

Plato and education In his middle and late periods Plato developed positive methods of philosophising (for example, dialectic), but it seems that he retained the elenchos as a way of purging the mind of false beliefs before beginning the process of instilling positive doctrine (for example, Sophist, 229d, 231b). The shame of refutation experienced by Socrates’ interlocutors and the shame of erotic failure that he exploits are both merely means that Socrates will use in the service of his overarching educational and therapeutic project. We are all bidden to join in this project just insofar as we are able to recognise that we cannot do otherwise given that genuine eudaimonia is our unavoidable goal. Twenty-first century students commonly find Socrates’ and Plato’s analogies between everyday infatuation and passionate intellectual longing to be a strained one at the very best, and also find these teachers’ worries about everyday erôs to be quaint and perhaps even a bit pathological. This is because, sad to say, overlysexualised cultures like ours trivialise genuine erôs. However, with just a bit of work on teachers’ parts, students can come to appreciate the force of what Plato says about learning in his Republic: A real lover of learning strives by nature for what is … He does not linger over each of the many things that are believed to be, but keeps on going,

18

Mark L. McPherran without dulling his erotic passion or desisting from it, until he grasps what the nature is of each thing itself with the part of his soul that is fitted to grasp a thing of that sort because of its kinship with it. Once he is drawn near to it, has intercourse with what really is, and has begotten understanding and truth, he knows, truly lives, is nourished, and – at that point, but not before – is relieved from his labor pains. (490a9-b7).

This is precisely why it is more important than ever to have high school and college students confront texts such as the Symposium: for such texts give them the language and the theories that will allow them to confront and integrate the great forces that those years unleash, and whose long-term consequences can be more than devastating. I should here make some brief relevant points about Plato’s larger, positive educational theory. As Plato sees it, education is not something that can be simply instilled in a manner analogous to ‘putting sight into blind eyes’ (Plato, Republic, 518b-c). On the contrary, the educator grants that sight is there, though not turned in the right way or looking where it should look, and contrives to redirect it appropriately (518d). Education, then, is the craft concerned with ‘this very turning around … with how this instrument [by which we learn] can be most easily and effectively turned around, not of putting sight into it’ (518d). The instrument in question, here, is our rational element (580d). That element, together with appetite (439) and spirit (thumos; 439e, 581a-b) constitutes the entire embodied human soul. As a result, education cannot accomplish its task of reorienting reason without reorienting the whole soul, any more than an eye can be turned around except by turning the whole body (518c). So although Platonic educational practice is primarily targeted on reason, it must also concern itself with appetite and spirit. And, as I have here argued, we can now see that it must concern itself also with love. The lesson of Plato’s dialogues is that we must somehow lead students to desire to come to visit us (and each other), as Socrates does with Theodotê. This must be instead of us chasing after them and their often transitory, job-oriented goals. We can try to grasp just what it is they think they desire, and then connect it as best we can in our teaching styles with a desire for the subject matter at hand, the argumentative skills that subject involves, and even, perhaps, the psychic harmony that must be a component of their actual, genuine, inchoate Desire.

Acknowledgements Previous versions of this chapter have been presented at the Socrates or Rousseau? Ancient and Modern Perspectives on Liberal Education conference, The Daniel Webster Program, Dartmouth College, November; Vancouver Island University, September 2009; and the University of San Francisco, March 2010. My thanks to my audiences for their comments. I am also grateful to my colleague at USF, Marjolein Oele, for her comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.

Socrates, Plato, erôs, and liberal education 19

Notes 1 A recent (tough-minded) article on the current state of the liberal arts in the United States is Slouka (2009). 2 See, e.g., Scott (2002). 3 See, e.g., Reeve (2010). 4 Erôs is most commonly observed at work in those who are sexually infatuated with a beloved, whereas friendly affection (philia) can be had for friends and family. On Socrates’ use of irony, Vlastos (1991), ch. 1; for his use of shame, Brickhouse & Smith (2010), pp. 53–62, and Sanderman (2004). 5 Slouka (2009) argues that ‘upsetting people is arguably the very purpose of the arts and perhaps the humanities in general’. 6 My argument in these paragraphs is engaged in particular with Vlastos (1991).

References Aristotle (1933/5) The Metaphysics. 2 vols, Loeb Classical Library (London, Heinemann). Aristotle (1934) Nicomachean Ethics (trans. H. Rackham) (London, Heinemann). Benson, H. (2000) Socratic wisdom (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Brickhouse, T. & Smith, N. (2002) The Socratic Elenchos? In: G. Scott (ed.) Does Socrates have a method? Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s dialogues and beyond (University Park, PA, Pennsylvania State University Press), 145–157. Brickhouse, T. & Smith, N. (2010) Socratic moral psychology (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Cicero (1927) Tusculan disputations (trans J.E. King) Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Entralgo, L. (1970) The therapy of the word in classical antiquity (eds and trans. L.J. Rather & J.M. Sharp) (New Haven, CT, Yale University Press). McPherran, M.L. (1996) The religion of Socrates (University Park, Pennsylvania State University Press). McPherran, M.L. (2007) Socratic epagôgê and Socratic induction, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 45(3), 347–364. Plato (1953 fp 1871) Gorgias (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. II of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Charmides (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. I of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Euthyphro (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. I of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Euthydemus (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. I of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1930–1935) Republic (trans. P. Shorey) 2 vols, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Sophist (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. III of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Phaedrus (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. III of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1953 fp 1871) Symposium (trans. B. Jowett) in Vol. I of Dialogues of Plato (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Reeve, C.D.C. (1989) Socrates in the Apology (Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company).

20

Mark L. McPherran

Reeve, C.D.C. (2010) Blindness and reorientation: education and the acquisition of knowledge in the Republic. In: M. McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic: a critical guide (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Sanderman, D. (2004) Why Socrates mocks his interlocutors, Skepsis, 15, 431–441. Scott, G. (ed.) (2002) Does Socrates have a method? Rethinking the Elenchos in Plato’s Dialogues and beyond (University Park, Pennsylvania State University Press). Slouka, M. (2009, September) Dehumanized: when math and science rule the school, Harper’s Magazine, 32–40 (Available online at: http://www.harpers.org/archive/ 2009/09/0082640). Swardson, H.R. (2005) Socratic teaching under postmodern conditions, The Philosophical Forum, 36(2), 161–182. Vlastos, G. (1989) Socratic piety. In: J. Cleary (ed.) Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy, v(5), 213–238. Vlastos, G. (1991) Socrates: ironist and moral philosopher (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). Vlastos, G. (1994) Socratic Studies (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Woolf, R. (2000) Callicles and Socrates: psychic (dis)harmony in the Gorgias, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 18 (Summer), 1–40. Xenophon (1923) Memorabilia (trans. E.C. Marchant) in Vol. IV of Xenophon in 7 vols. Loeb Classical Library (London, Heinnemann).

2

Aristotle’s educational politics and the Aristotelian renaissance in philosophy of education Randall Curren

Introduction The only extended discussion of education in the Aristotelian corpus is in Book VIII of the Politics, where Aristotle advocates that schooling be publicly provided and ‘one and the same for all’ (VIII.1 1337a23). Isolated remarks about education appear in earlier books of the Politics, and a few can be found in the Nicomachean Ethics and elsewhere. With enough effort, these scattered passages can be understood in relation to one another and in light of the overall plan of the Nicomachean Ethics (NE) and Politics (Pol.).1 The former concerns ethics, obviously enough, and the latter concerns ‘legislative science’ (nomothetikê), but they are closely related to each other as parts of the larger enterprise Aristotle calls ‘political science’ (hê politikê epistêmê or hê politikê; NE I.2, X.9; Adkins, 1991). As Aristotle conceives it, the general aim of political science is to determine the truth about human happiness (eudaimonia) – ‘the highest of all goods achievable by action’ (NE I.4 1095a15-20) – and to guide societies (Pol. IV.1 1288b21-89a7, III.8 1279b12-25; NE VII.11 1152b1-2) and households (NE X.9 1180a25 ff.) toward happiness.2 A central claim about happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics is that it requires the possession and exercise of intellectual and moral virtues, and a central related feature of the Politics is its identification of education that cultivates these virtues as the primary tool of statesmanship (Pol. VIII.1). Education is as important to Aristotle’s conception of a political community as it is to Plato’s, though Aristotle would seem to have had less patience with spelling out the details. A revival of interest in Aristotle’s ethics was well underway in the 1970s (see Cooper, 1975; Barnes et al., 1977; Rorty, 1980), and a revival of his politics followed (see Keyt & Miller, 1991; Yack, 1993; Miller, 1995), yielding more integrated readings of the texts and topics that span them (see, e.g., Cooper, 1999; Curren, 2000; Kraut, 2002; Roberts, 1989, 2009). An Aristotelian renaissance in philosophy of education has meanwhile developed largely as an offshoot of the virtue ethics movement associated with the revival of Aristotle’s ethics. This has arguably done much to advance our understanding of moral development and education (see Pincoffs, 1986; Carr, 1991; Carr & Steutel, 1999; Curren, 2002a; Kristjánsson, 2007), and to reestablish

22

Randall Curren

human flourishing as a theorised aim of education (White & White, 1986; Kupperman, 1987; Hirst, 1998; Strike, 2003; Brighouse, 2006; Nussbaum, 2006; Curren, 2009a). Apart from and substantially prior to the virtue ethics movement, interest in Aristotle’s account of practical reason yielded a significant literature on teacher competence and curriculum (Schwab, 1969; Green, 1976; Fenstermacher & Richardson, 1993). The limitation of an Aristotelian renaissance largely independent of scholarship in ancient Greek philosophy is not inconsequential, however. Opportunities have been missed and mistakes have attracted a substantial following. My aim in this paper is to survey Aristotle’s educational thought, noting some interpretive controversies, commenting on related developments and missed opportunities in contemporary educational thought, and questioning the Aristotelian credentials of a major body of recently influential work in philosophy of education. The work I will question concerns the nature of teaching and denies that phronêsis (practical wisdom, good judgment) has for Aristotle the ‘universal’ element, or element of systematic knowledge of principles, he says it has (Dunne, 1997; McLaughlin, 1999; Smith, 1999; Maclntyre & Dunne, 2002; Dunne & Pendelbury, 2003; Hogan & Smith, 2003; Carr, 2005). It deploys this understanding of phronêsis, together with some related claims about crafts and practices, to defend the professional autonomy of educators against managerial encroachment. I shall challenge the Aristotelian credentials of this work, but also suggest how a more accurate understanding of Aristotle’s philosophy of education can be harnessed to much the same end. The universal element in phronêsis was obscured by some of the interpretations of the 1980s, sometimes in constructing particularist forms of virtue ethics, but to say that phronêsis ‘ is concerned not only with universals but with particulars, which become familiar from experience’ (NE VI.8 1142a13-15; cf. 1141b14-16) is to assert unequivocally that it is concerned with universals.3

Political science The Nicomachean Ethics and Politics are records of lectures intended to equip Aristotle’s students with the universal element of phronêsis, or a systematic understanding of the human good and how to promote it.4 Students must have been ‘well brought up in good habits’ (NE I.4 1095b6) and be experienced ‘in the actions that occur in life’ (I.4 1095a3) in order to grasp ‘the facts’ that are the ‘starting-points’ of ethical and legislative inquiry. A good upbringing and experience of life provide a student with true moral beliefs (‘facts’), but these are just the starting points. True virtue (arête; see Curren, 1996a) and the systematic knowledge required to promote virtue and happiness require more, and Aristotle aspires to provide what is required. His course in ethics is presented as an opportunity to progress dialectically from the possession of ordinary, unsystematic, true or mostly true ethical beliefs to a systematic, reasoned body of ethical knowledge (epistêmê) resting in an account of human nature and well-being (see Reeve, 2000, pp. 21–27, on dialectic and the first principles of sciences).

Aristotle’s educational politics

23

The student’s antecedent beliefs are to be worked into a coherent, interconnected, and grounded whole – the ethical knowledge required for phronêsis. There is, thus, in the very framing of Aristotle’s project and its audience, an announcement of his practical philosophy as both a science intended to guide practice and a curriculum for all who would aspire to happiness in their own lives or the lives of others – the curricular prerequisites of phronêsis. He follows Plato in frequently invoking the role of medical science (epistêmê) in medical practice as a guiding analogy for the role of political science in human affairs (NE I.13 1102a7-25; II.2 1104a5-9; III.3 1112b12-15; X.9 1180b13-29; Pol. I.9 1257b25-32; II.8 1268b33-39; see also Jaeger, 1957; Lloyd, 1968). The reference to medicine at the end of the Nicomachean Ethics (X.9) is especially telling: But individuals can be best cared for by a doctor or gymnastic instructor or anyone else who has the universal knowledge of what is good for every one or for people of a certain kind … And surely he who wants to make men, whether many or few, better by his care must try to be capable of legislating, if it is through laws that we can become good. For to get anyone whatever – anyone who is put before us – into the right condition is not for the first chance comer; if anyone can do it, it is the man who knows, just as in medicine and all other matters which give scope for care and practical wisdom. (1180b13-29) Educating is described here as a form of care, an art (technê) comparable to medicine or gymnastic instruction, grounded in a science (epistêmê), namely the hê politikê epistêmê he offers his own students.5 A technê is indeed a form of science or knowledge in Aristotle’s scheme of things (Met. I.1 981b7-10, XI.7 1063b35-64a18; Top. VI.6 145a15-18), politics itself being referred to as both a technê – a master art or architektonikês – and an episteme, and as determining ‘which of the sciences should be studied,’ who should learn them, ‘and up to what point they should learn them’ (NE I.1-2 1094a1-b2). Aristotle does say, famously and having just identified his topic as political science, that ethical matters are ‘only for the most part true’ (NE I.3 1094b21). This has created some puzzlement about how he could claim to establish ethics and politics as sciences, consistent with his declaration that strictly speaking a science can only pertain to what ‘does not admit of being otherwise’ (NE VI.3 1139b18-24). Yet, Aristotle does speak less strictly of scientific knowledge of ‘what holds always or for the most part (hôs epi to polu)’ (Met. VI.2 1027a19-21), or what holds true by a necessity qualified by the indeterminateness of the matter in which objects of concern to some sciences are embodied (see Reeve, 2000, pp. 27–42). Aristotle identifies sciences as systematic bodies of truths pertaining to the nature of unchanging objects of knowledge (NE VI.3 1139b20-25); ethics pertains to the nature, function and varieties of the human psyche (i.e., the varieties of character, which do or do not fulfill that function), and politics pertains to the nature, function and varieties of the polis (i.e., the varieties of political constitution, which do or do not fulfill that function). Structurally, these

24

Randall Curren

are sciences not unlike logic, as Aristotle invented it, logic being the science pertaining to the nature, function and varieties – varieties that do or do not fulfill the function of preserving truth – of syllogisms. Ethics and politics take unchanging natures as their enduring objects of knowledge and they elaborate systematically the domains of truths that come to rest in the comprehension of those natures. What is true invariably of the natures may be true ‘only for the most part’ of the embodied creatures and cities (polises) that are the focus of practical concern; the latter may fail to be true to their natures for reasons more or less systematically diagnosable through insight into the qualities of their ‘matter’, a theme sounded repeatedly through the middle books of the Politics in observations about the difference the characteristics of a population make to a city’s fulfillment of its function (Pol. IV-VI). Having noted these general features of Aristotle’s vision of political science, we can now best approach the substance of his educational views through an ordered survey of the large moving pieces of his ethical-political theory. To this end, we must now consider the moral and intellectual virtues, how they are acquired and how they are related to one another; the happiest kind of life and the role of virtue in achieving it; the nature of a political community; Aristotle’s theory of constitutions and the ‘best possible’ society described in Book VII of the Politics; the context these provide for the account of education in Book VIII of the Politics.

The virtues In the final book of the Nicomachean Ethics (X.9), Aristotle observes that reasoned arguments alone are not enough to make people good. Many people are not moved by arguments based on what is admirable or appropriate (kalon), because they lack even a conception of what is kalon, having never been exposed to it (1179b4-15). He goes on to say that ‘nature’ (i.e., traits one is born with), habituation (training in doing the right things) and teaching must all be favourable in order for a person to become good, so there is little chance of becoming good if one does not grow up under good laws. We learn in Books VII and VIII of the Politics that those laws should, among other things, provide schooling that is public and ‘the same for all’ (VIII.1 1337a23-24). Book VIII opens with the remarkable suggestion that ‘No one will doubt that the legislator should direct his attention above all to the education of youth’ (1337a10-11) – remarkable because public or state-sponsored education was unknown in his world apart from some military training. It reflects a conviction that societies have a fundamental, collective duty – a duty falling on governments – to enable the young to develop into good and flourishing adults. The laws should regulate birth and early training in order to ensure the healthy development of the body and the desiring part of the psyche, all with an eye to the development of ‘reason and mind’ (VII.15 1334b15-17). Aristotle says this sequence of development is ‘natural’, but he regards the fulfillment of a person’s intellectual potential as something rare and difficult to achieve.

Aristotle’s educational politics

25

Aristotle defines moral virtues as dispositions to feel and be moved by our desires or emotions neither too weakly nor too strongly, but in a way that moves us to act as reason would dictate, and to take pleasure in doing so (NE II.2-6). Intellectual virtues are defined as capacities or powers of understanding, judgment and reasoning that enable us to attain truth (NE VI.2 1139b11-13). Treating the moral virtues as states of the irrational part of the psyche, he regards them as laying a necessary foundation for the development of intellectual virtues. Having distinguished the moral and intellectual virtues in this way, Aristotle says the former mainly arise as a result of habit and the latter mainly arise as a result of teaching (NE II.1). The understanding of his conception of moral development often goes no farther than the associated idea that we become brave by repeatedly doing the right thing in the face of danger and become cowardly by repeatedly fleeing or cowering in the face of danger. Yet, there are two very important further aspects to Aristotle’s conception of moral virtue and its development. The first is that ‘habit’ cannot mean thoughtless, unguided repetition (Sherman, 1989). The conduct in question must be shaped in all its details towards what is desirable. This requires supervision to ensure that the learner does the right thing, and coaching that leads her through progressive mastery of various nuances of what she is doing, calling her attention to aspects of it she will not have perceived nor had any language to describe. Supervision and coaching enable learners to progress and become self-directed in their practice and habits. The second overlooked aspect of Aristotle’s conception of moral development is that the moral virtues are both a necessary step towards, and only completed by, the acquisition of the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom or good judgment (VI.12 1144a29-37; VI.13 1144b7-20 and 30-32; Curren, 2000, pp. 202–204). Aristotle asserts a unity of virtue thesis, which holds there are interdependencies between the possession of good judgment and the possession of moral virtues. No moral virtue is a true virtue unless it is guided by good judgment, and no one can develop good judgment without first possessing natural or habituated forms of the moral virtues. Moral virtues are dispositions of desire, emotion and perception that lead us to choose and do what it is reasonable for us to choose and do, all the while perceiving our choices and actions to be reasonable. Moral virtues thereby establish the ends we aim at, while good judgment enables us to achieve those ends. Virtue that is merely habitual might suffice in familiar circumstances, but it will not reliably guide us to the right or best act. A true virtue is supposed to be good without qualification, so it must be guided by good judgment which prevents its possessor from going astray in challenging circumstances. The unity of virtue thesis also holds that in order to have good judgment one must possess all the moral virtues. The possession of good judgment is only possible if one perceives the world accurately in all its moral particularity, and according to Aristotle our perceptions are largely shaped by what we have experienced as normal. The ways we have habitually acted and the ends we have habitually pursued will seem to us acceptable and good. An aspect of the formation of (habitual) moral virtues or vices is thus the habituation of

26

Randall Curren

corresponding perceptions, accurate or inaccurate. Since good judgment requires accurate perceptions, it also requires the possession of the moral virtues pertaining to different spheres and aspects of conduct. By Aristotle’s lights, good practical judgment (phronêsis) subsumes particular cases, well perceived, under universal principles acquired through teaching. Perceiving the particulars well requires virtue, as we have seen, but also experience and discussion that enables one to benefit from the perceptions of others. Learning the universal principles begins, as we have seen, with the acquisition of true ethical beliefs in the course of a sound moral upbringing, and it proceeds through a study of political science that refines and shapes those beliefs into a systematic, interconnected whole – a ‘scientific’ understanding of human affairs.

Human flourishing Aristotle employs a whole battery of arguments in Books I and X of the Nicomachean Ethics and Book VII of the Politics to show that the highest good and happiest life for human beings is a life devoted to intellectual inquiry or ‘contemplation’ as its highest aim.6 The most intuitive of his reasons is that what is most satisfying is putting our greatest gifts, our intellectual capacities, to good use. As he says in NE I.7, the highest good for human beings is activity that exhibits virtue of the ‘best and most complete’ kind, or in other words sophia, the wisdom that pertains to intellectual inquiry or ‘contemplation’ (1098a16-18). Another argument compares the two strongest candidates for being the highest good: the life that takes contemplation as its highest end and the life that takes statesmanship or political leadership as its highest end. The contemplative life qualifies as the highest good for human beings, because it is not only desirable for itself (being intrinsically satisfying), but aims at nothing beyond itself (NE X.7. 1177a16-18; Pol. VII.3 1325b14-32). The political life cannot qualify as a highest good, because the activity of statesmanship aims at something beyond itself – ideally, the well-being of the statesman’s society. In aiming at something beyond itself it is not ‘complete’ in itself, and the virtue it exhibits is not ‘complete’. The political life may be a happy life for some, if it genuinely exhibits the virtue of practical wisdom – the second best and most complete human virtue – but it cannot constitute the best kind of life or highest good for a human being. Once one recognises that Aristotle identifies only two kinds of lives as genuinely happy, the contemplative life being the happiest and the political life being happy ‘in a secondary degree’ (NE X.8 1178a9), it is easy to understand his deepest argument for believing that only someone who possesses moral virtue can be happy. It is intrinsic to both of these kinds of lives that they involve the exercise of intellectual virtues which, according to the unity of virtue thesis, cannot be possessed by someone who lacks the moral virtues (Kraut, 1989). The accurate perceptions associated with the moral virtues are required for both phronêsis and sophia, since both are concerned with truth, including truths about human affairs.7 Understanding this sheds light on Aristotle’s idea in Politics

Aristotle’s educational politics

27

VII that the training of the irrational psyche should aim at ‘reason and mind’. It should prepare the way for the acquisition of the intellectual virtues, whose exercise is central to a happy life, by ensuring that a person’s perceptions of what is good and appropriate are not corrupted by growing accustomed to doing bad or inappropriate things.

Political communities Aristotle’s Politics begins with an account of the origin and growth of polises (politically autonomous cities), and his famous claim that human beings are ‘political animals’ (politikon zôon). What this means is not that human beings naturally engage in political activities, but that they are gregarious, need to live together in cities in order to live the best kind of life, and are equipped by language to live as a community consciously organised in pursuit of the best kind of life (I.2 1252a8-53a30; Miller, 1995, pp. 30–45). As Aristotle conceives it, a political society should be a mutually beneficial partnership to which everyone freely consents (Pol. I.13 1259b37-60a2; III.3 1276a8-16, III.4 1277b8-30, III.6 1297b17-22, VII.2 1324a24-25, etc.). As a partnership in pursuit of the best kind of life, a political community must be socially unified, collectively governed, of one mind in its conception of the best kind of life, and egalitarian. A true political community is unified by friendship, and friendship requires at least a semblance of equality (VII.8 1328a35-36; II.4 1262b7-10, etc.). Yet, existing societies are not unified, Aristotle says. His concern, like Plato’s, was how societies might become more peaceful, stable and secure against the factional conflict that ensured most governments in their world were short-lived. In the Republic, Plato imagined a scheme for common rearing of children in which parents would not even know whose child was whose. He imagined that, in this way, rivalries between families might be restrained and a stronger sense of civic community might emerge. In Book II of the Politics, Aristotle rejects this scheme. He agrees that a society must be unified by friendship to be secure against factional conflict, but he thinks a more promising way to accomplish this is through civic institutions that nurture friendships bridging all social groups. The most important of these civic institutions is common schools – public day schools – in which a city’s diverse children ‘grow up together’ at least a few hours a day (V.9 1310a12-25). It is through education that societies can be unified and made into a community, Aristotle advises (Pol. II.5 1263b37-38; see Curren, 2000, p. 131 ff, 2002c). Aristotle goes on (in Pol. III) to elaborate an account of constitutions and the proper forms of political rule, distinguishing the true, just or legitimate forms of constitution from those that are corrupt, unjust or illegitimate. As one would expect, the former aim at the common good and operate on the basis of consent, while the latter aim only at the good of the rulers and rely on force (III.6 1279a17-22). The former promote partnership in living well, hence mutual trust and goodwill, while the latter may seek to divide and enfeeble the populace in order to prevent unified and effective resistance to its rule. Just regimes are based

28

Randall Curren

upon a rule of law, which no one is above, and their laws are worthy of respect. Unjust regimes are by contrast ‘lawless’ or ‘unconstitutional’, and the unjust requirements they announce as laws have no claim to being obeyed. Of the just forms of constitution, polity is the best that can be attained by most societies, and it is for that reason the goal towards which the reform of actual societies should aim. It is both a ‘mixed’ constitution, which provides forms of direct participation for citizens of all social classes, and a ‘middle’ constitution, dominated by a large middle class. This is just because it respects the right of all citizens to participate (Pol. III.9 1280a9-b7; NE V.3 1131a24-28), and it is beneficial because moderation of wealth is conducive to living well and a large middle class serves as a bulwark against destructive political polarisation. Kingship is Aristotle’s theoretically ideal system, but he dismisses it as ‘unattainable’, leaving an ideal form of aristocracy as the best constitution that might be possible in highly favourable circumstances. Aristotle regards an ordinary aristocracy, or rule in the common interest over willing citizens by a few who are genuinely the best (aristoi), as a legitimate form of constitution.8 In Book VII of the Politics, he imagines a constitution in which all of the citizens rule and possess the true virtue required to live the best kind of life. This would be an ideal aristocracy in which all of the citizens are voluntary partners in living the best kind of life. Since the citizens would be partners in this, they must have leisure from productive activities so they can acquire the highest virtue and make activity in accordance with it the dominating concern of their lives. Those who engage in productive activity, namely artisans, traders and farmers, would be necessary to the political society but not members of it. They might be resident aliens at best, maybe slaves but not citizens, though dealings with them should still be based on mutual benefit. (It goes without saying that Aristotle has no plausible account of how slavery could benefit the slave.) Citizens would share in ruling and being ruled, and land holdings would be divided among the citizens, assuring the moderation of wealth conducive to equal citizenship and a life of virtue. Three institutions are mentioned as conducive to virtue and the social unity necessary to a true community: common meals or dining clubs, common religious observances and common schools. In the closing chapters of Book VII, we come to matters of childbirth, childcare and the training of habits and schooling, where (as we have seen) everything should aim at the proper development of the rational element of the psyche – the ‘best part’ in human nature, the flourishing of which is intrinsic to living the best kind of life. Since this ‘ideal aristocracy’ is to be a society of virtuous equals living in partnership in pursuit of the best kind of life, every citizen must receive an education in virtue, and should receive it in the context of common schools in which all citizen children are educated together.

Education Two ideas dominate the opening of Book VIII of the Politics. One is that education is a prerequisite for the practice of virtue, and is thus a matter of public concern (1337a20-21). The foregoing makes this easy enough to understand: the

Aristotle’s educational politics

29

proper aim of politics is to enable citizens to live the best kind of life. In order to live such a life, a person must be virtuous. The development of virtue depends on a variety of things beyond a person’s control. To educate someone is to train and teach him so he acquires the moral and intellectual virtues, develops the good judgment needed for prudent self-governance and participation in political rule, and learns to take pleasure in the excellent activities with which a good life is occupied. It makes perfect sense that Aristotle says in VIII.5 that the main concern of education is to ‘cultivate … the power of forming right judgments, and of taking delight in good dispositions and admirable actions’ (1340a15-19). He says elsewhere that to be educated is to be able to form a sound judgment of an investigation or exposition, a person of ‘universal education’ being one who is able to do this in all or nearly all domains of knowledge (Departibus animalium 639a1-5). Note well that education is a preparation for leisure ‘spent in intellectual activity’, according to Aristotle (VIII.3 1338a10-11). It is not a preparation for work, as is so often now assumed. Greek education in gymnastikê (athletics) and musikê (music, poetry and narratives – the ‘Arts of the Muses’) was from the beginning a preparation for leisure (see Curren, 1996b). The knightly warriors of Athens who originally received it spent their daytime leisure in athletic contests and their night-time leisure at drinking parties where they entertained each other with music and recitations. The subsequent democratisation of Athens and invention of group lessons altered this ‘old education’, in part by introducing the commercially useful arts of reading, writing and arithmetic. Leisure was, in any case, not equated with mere amusement. It was contrasted with productive labour in such a way that public service – even military service – was generally considered a use of leisure, or time not spent in satisfying material needs. For Aristotle, leisure provided the opportunity to flourish as a human being or to pursue what is intrinsically, not just instrumentally, good. Education should include ‘necessary’ practical arts, according to Aristotle (VIII.1 1337b3-9), but it should focus on what is ‘liberal’ or conducive to spending one’s leisure in activities that express the best in human nature or best and most complete virtue. Aristotle’s lengthy discussion of music emphasises its capacity to shape character and judgment (VIII.5-7). Yet, he notes that even music becomes illiberal or ‘mechanical’, if it is pursued in order to entertain others (making it an activity that is not complete in itself) and is pursued in such a way that it interferes with the development and exercise of virtue (VIII.6 1341a4-b19). He is not specific about what counts as ‘necessary’ practical arts, but he probably has in mind what is necessary to meeting one’s material needs and exercising virtues that involve the use of external goods. His model is probably a landowner of moderate means who needs to read, write, draw and use arithmetic to prudently manage his farm. The second dominating idea at the opening of Politics VIII is that citizens should be moulded ‘to suit the form of government’ or constitution (1337a11-19). The character of citizens matters to preserving constitutions and also to their quality. The better the character of the citizens, the better the constitution, Aristotle says. This is somewhat puzzling, since everything I have

30

Randall Curren

attributed to Aristotle suggests that constitutions should be made to suit the needs of the citizen, not the other way around. Moreover, Aristotle says that it is only in the best constitution that the virtues expected of a citizen fully coincide with the virtues of a human being as such (Pol. III.4 1277a1-4). Only the best kind of society fully enables the development of independent good judgment and encourages the universal expression of that judgment in public and private life. Since the proper aim of any political society is to enable citizens to develop and exercise the best and most complete human virtue, it is not clear how it could be legitimate for any government to educate citizens to have any virtues that deviate from these. What are we to make of this? First it is important to realise that Aristotle says a great deal in the middle books of the Politics about the measures that actual regimes should take to preserve themselves. He identifies injustice as the most important general cause of political instability, and his advice to governments has the effect of encouraging reforms that will make them both more just and longer lasting (V.1 1301a36b4; Curren, 2000, p. 100 ff.). To the extent that defective regimes adopt his proposed reforms, they will come to approximate polities and have the best form of constitution most societies could hope to have. Public education is introduced in this context as the most valuable of the reforms that can be adopted. Like other reforms, it will not leave a deficient system as it is, but will instead both stabilise and improve it. Indeed, Aristotle says quite explicitly in Politics V.9 that the education that ‘suits’ a constitution is not the kind of education preferred by the rulers of an unjust system (1310a12-25). It is education compatible with a more balanced and moderate system that better serves the interests of all citizens. A critic might object at this point that education should not support anything less than an ideal system. Aristotle’s implicit answer is that the best course in human affairs is to proceed through incremental reform transacted through public consultation and shared governance. Education that prepares everyone to employ independent good judgment in shared governance is progress. Second, it must be recognised that in order for constitutions to ‘suit the needs of the citizen’, citizens must have certain desirable qualities. A constitution (politeia) is not, as Aristotle understood it, simply a blueprint for a form of government, but a functioning political system whose actual patterns are heavily determined by the characteristics of the people involved. Moulding the constitution in such a way as to enable citizens to live the best kind of life requires measures to ensure that citizens are prepared to treat each other with mutual respect and friendly regard for each other’s well-being. It requires that citizens have fellow citizens who will in a variety of ways allow them the satisfaction of fulfilling their human potential.

The contemporary import of Aristotle’s philosophy of education Understood within the larger context of his philosophy of human affairs, Aristotle’s philosophy of education offers valuable starting points for addressing

Aristotle’s educational politics

31

several topics of enduring interest. One must surely count among these his account of the virtues and their development, his conception of what is good for human beings, his ideas about the relationships between virtue, law, and education, and his defence of public education. I noted at the outset that Aristotle’s account of the virtues has been fundamental to a major movement in moral theory and the related broad swath of scholarship on moral development and education. Neo-Aristotelian approaches restored a measure of plausibility to the philosophy of moral education by defending roles for both habituation and critical reason, in an era when neo-Kantian notions of stimulating children to clarify and self-impose their own values had dominated the landscape. They have arguably enriched and advanced debate by arguing that habituation, perception, emotion, and judgment are developmentally interrelated, and by confronting puzzles concerning the relationship between habituation and autonomous good judgment (Peters, 1981, pp. 45–60; Curren, 2000, pp. 205–212; 2006; Kristjánsson, 2007, pp. 31–48). They have also arguably provided the basis for more plausible accounts of the role of motivation in moral learning, by addressing desire and perception. The Aristotelian notion that governments and schools should make human well-being or flourishing their central aim has also had some arguably salutary influence, through arguments that contest to some degree the value neutrality of liberalism (see White & White, 1986; Kupperman, 1987), views that hold the chief purpose of education is to develop human capabilities or promote flourishing (Brighouse, 2006; Nussbaum, 2003, 2006), and conceptions of education that make initiation into ‘practices’ definitive of, or essential to, its nature (Hirst, 1998; MacIntyre & Dunne, 2002; Strike, 2003; Curren, 2009a). Some such ‘practice’ oriented views treat the ‘goods’ made accessible to learners through initiation as purely internal to the practices, and others are ambiguous as to whether these goods are purely internal. My own view, which is arguably the most authentically Aristotelian, is that the framework of justification we need to guide education is one that identifies what is good for human beings and on that basis identifies practices worthy of perpetuation through schools (Curren, 2009a, pp. 52–54). We must, of course, set aside Aristotle’s idea that there is one best life for human beings, but there is nevertheless much to be said for his idea that what is most satisfying in life is experiencing the development and selfdirected employment of our abilities. It is an idea which must, however, be placed within a wider and empirically grounded understanding of human needs and happiness. Other aspects of Aristotle’s philosophy of education have been all but ignored, presumably because his Politics is a more daunting work than the Nicomachean Ethics, and one more burdened with unattractive features. These are not trivial obstacles, but there are nevertheless some themes in – and just below the surface of – the Politics that are important for contemporary educational debate. The most important of these is Aristotle’s ‘developmental’ view of reason, and its bearing on the relationships between law and education.9 If reasonableness is a human quality that develops by degrees and needs assistance to develop, and an

32

Randall Curren

ethic of respect for people as rational beings requires dealing with people as much as possible through truthful and reasoned instruction and persuasion and as little as possible through force and violence (see Curren, 2000, p. 21 ff., 2002a), then the foundations of law and government rest more crucially on adequate education for everyone than we generally realise. The legitimacy of a government and a rule of law will rest on conscientious education that prepares everyone voluntarily to accept the reasonable expectations of law on the basis of their independent good judgment. This is a much more extensive educational task than it may at first seem, largely because ongoing consent to new legislation is transacted through participation in the public life of a democracy, for which citizens must be prepared. This is arguably the strongest argument for public education and equitable provision of education to be found in the Politics, and one that remains compelling.10 In the foreground of the Politics are concerns about equity in enabling all the members of a society to live well, the need for civic education to promote intelligent cooperation in the enterprise of shared governance, and the value of schooling different kinds of children together so they may learn to know and respect each other as equals. These are still important concerns, and wealth and poverty matter to all of them today, just as they did in Aristotle’s world. His was not a multicultural world in the way ours is, but the patterns of conflict that concerned him are perennial. Aristotle is often invoked in the communitarian literature, a literature very sympathetic to calls for separate and culturally homogeneous schooling, but the Aristotelian course in these matters would be to hold onto the common school ideal to the extent we can productively approximate it. The educational literature of teaching and phronêsis that I referred to at the start of this paper seems to have been directly inspired by the work of Alasdair MacIntyre, a central figure in the communitarian movement, though he has himself repudiated its central claims (MacIntyre & Dunne, 2002). Of all the Aristotelian strands in philosophy of education, this is perhaps the most active and influential at present. I shall close with a critique of its central claims, and note how a more authentically Aristotelian argument might be brought in defence of the professional autonomy of educators. Kristján Kristjánsson has offered a detailed critique of the body of work in question, referring to its shared commitments as the phronêsis praxis perspective (PPP) (Kristjánsson, 2007, pp. 157–173). I will not rehearse his arguments, which are essentially on target, but will instead offer a much briefer critique based on the sketch of Aristotle’s views I have provided.11 According to PPP, teaching is not an art (technê) comparable to medicine and gymnastic instruction, as Aristotle implies in Nicomachean Ethics X.9. It is said to be not a productive art (like medicine) or practical science (like political science) that aims at something beyond itself, but a ‘practice’ (praxis) engaged in for itself and nothing beyond itself. In Aristotelian terms, this would make teaching an activity that qualifies as a highest end. If teaching were nothing more than engaging in contemplation with students for the sheer pleasure of it, this might make sense, but Aristotle’s account of education presents a very different conception of

Aristotle’s educational politics

33

teaching. The activity of teaching is unequivocally understood to aim at something beyond itself, namely the formation of students, just as the art of politics, to which education is subsidiary, is understood to aim at the formation and thereby happiness of citizens. Notice that if the activity of teaching did qualify as a highest end for Aristotle, it would qualify by reason of expressing the virtue of contemplative wisdom or sophia. According to Joseph Dunne and those who have followed him in adopting PPP, the virtue expressed in teaching is phronêsis, which is correct but not helpful to their view. A crucial further element of PPP is the claim that phronêsis is not grounded in any body of science or ‘theory’.12 Having already seen in some detail the error in this, what remains to be said of this claim is that it is presented as: (1) a way to dissolve puzzles concerning how theory can guide practice; (2) a way to establish that: education is a distinctive practice with an integrity of its own, and that this entitles that practice to a decisive measure of autonomy in carrying out its work. (Hogan & Smith, 2003, p. 166, italics added; cf. Blake et al., 2003, p. 7; Dunne, 1997, p. 364 ff.) I have not found in the paper this is quoted from, or in any related works, an actual argument for the claim that the integrity of educational practice entitles educators to professional autonomy. Supposing the activity of teaching were a practice engaged in for itself and nothing beyond itself, what is quite unclear is why anyone would be entitled to engage in that activity with other people’s children, at other people’s expense, free of external constraint, guidance and expectations. As much as I find PPP both un-Aristotelian and philosophically irreparable, I do sympathise with the desire to shield teaching and learning from the unrelentingly instrumentalist and controlling pressures of the age. I also sympathise with the intuition that Aristotelian resources can be put to good use in this endeavour. The argument I have made in my own work on academic leadership (writing here not of schools, but of universities) is that: an academic institution’s mission cannot be understood in a purely or even dominantly instrumental sense, because the goods belonging to the enterprise of higher education are in large measure internal to the practices of inquiry and learning; i.e., internal to the unimpeded activities of academic communities themselves. If institutions of higher learning do not initiate students into forms of inquiry and other practices (such as the arts) that are more intrinsically rewarding than what they could devote themselves to without a higher education, then they will have failed. … A good institution of higher learning is like a good political system [that enables people to flourish as human beings] … It is governed in a way that enables it to be a community or partnership in unimpeded pursuit of academic goods, which is to say an institution in which people drawn to the value of such work are able to flourish in doing it. (Curren, 2008, p. 351)

34

Randall Curren

This is no argument against accountability or demands that teaching serve ends beyond the initiation of students into practices that offer intrinsic rewards, and it would be inconsistent with Aristotle’s philosophy of education if it were. What it is, and can be, is a defence of the view that institutions that leave no room for intrinsically rewarding teaching and learning are not educational institutions, whatever we may call them.13

Acknowledgements I owe thanks to the Spencer Foundation for facilitating my work on the larger project of which this essay is a part, and to Deborah Modrak and an anonymous referee for their comments on an earlier draft.

Notes 1 This was indeed my purpose in Aristotle on the necessity of public education (Curren, 2000). The present article relies fundamentally on interpretive arguments developed in detail in that work. For some points of clarification and philosophical expansion, see Curren 2002a, 2002b, 2002c, 2006 and 2009b. The translations quoted in this paper are from the Revised Oxford Translations in Barnes, 1984. 2 For an account of Aristotle’s audience, see Bodéüs, 1993. 3 See Sherman, 1989, for a particularist reading, and compare Reeve, 1992 and 2000, which take Aristotle at his word. 4 For what is known about Aristotle’s school, the Lyceum, see Lynch, 1972. 5 ‘Art’ is a more idiomatic translation of technê in some contexts, and ‘craft’ is more idiomatic in others. Contemporary usage commends medical ‘arts’ but Socrates’ understood virtue as a ‘craft’, a form of knowledge resting in definitions of the virtues; politics as soul ‘craft,’ but the ‘art’ of governing. 6 For a comprehensive defence of this reading and consideration of the leading alternatives, see Kraut, 1989. Kraut argues that it is the unity of the virtues that makes moral virtue internally (psychically) essential to a happy life. 7 An alternative, ‘inclusive ends’ interpretation of eudaimonia and its dependence on moral virtue attributes to Aristotle the view that a happy human life – unlike a god’s life – essentially involves virtuous participation in a human community. The texts typically cited include NE 1097b11, 1140b7-11, 1177b27-28, 1178b5-8 and 1179a22-32 (see Depew, 1991; Miller, 1995, pp. 346–357; Roberts, 2009, pp. 9–10), but they are hardly decisive. What seems true is that: (1) virtue is essential to enjoying intimate good friendship, which Aristotle identifies as the greatest ‘external’ good; (2) widespread virtue with respect to others is essential to a city capable of enabling one to live well. 8 ‘Ordinary’ aristocracy is, of course, itself an ideal. Most so-called aristocracies are actually oligarchies ruled by persons of wealth posing as ‘the best’ or most virtuous. 9 It is important to recognise that one can dismiss the idea that development occurs in stages, with the emergence of reasoning trailing behind the formation of desire, yet still hold that the development of reasonableness is incremental, dependent on factors and efforts beyond the learner’s control, and may remain incomplete (as it is in much of our prison populations; see Curren, 2002a). Stables, 2008 is not the first work to argue in one way or another that Aristotle is wrong because children are already rational and do not require the formative care we imagine. These arguments focus on circumscribed forms of rationality and fail to acknowledge the incremental nature and gradual, socially mediated development of good judgment and capacities of self-management. See Purdy, 1992, for a powerful, virtue-centred refutation of such arguments.

Aristotle’s educational politics

35

10 A great deal of Curren, 2000 is devoted to establishing this. 11 There is of course substantial overlap between my critique and Kristjánsson’s, as well as points of divergence. In the interest of brevity I must leave it to interested readers to consult his splendid book for themselves. It corrects other abuses of Aristotle’s ideas in the moral education literature, which I won’t address. 12 Dunne writes, in a characteristic passage, that ‘the great significance of Aristotle lies in the fact that he ... set limits to the sway of techne and, through his novel conception of phronesis, provided a rich analysis of the kind of knowledge that guides … characteristically human – and therefore inescapably ethical – activity (praxis)’ (Dunne & Pendlebury, 2003, p. 200). He asserts a few lines later that phronêsis is irreducible ‘to general propositions’ (p. 201). It being a virtue, this can scarcely be denied, but it does not at all follow that the universal principles that inform good practical judgment will never, in the circumstances discerned, point clearly to a course of action. Dunne’s rejection of ‘technique’ rests on a form of contextualism about judgment that Aristotle did not hold. 13 On intrinsic rewards in learning, the damaging consequences for students of administrative pressures on teachers, and the value of theory in guiding good practice, see Pelletier & Sharp, 2009; Ryan & Niemiec, 2009a, b. The empirically grounded theory in question incorporates a form of eudaimonism broadly inspired by Aristotle’s account of well-being. Aristotle’s philosophy being a naturalistic one with aspirations to science, it is entirely within the spirit of his project to wed contemporary applications of it with empirical research (see Curren, 2006, pp. 465–468).

References Adkins, A. W. H. (1991) The connection between Aristotle’s Ethics and Politics, in: D. Keyt & F. Miller (eds) A companion to Aristotle’s politics (Oxford, Blackwell), 75–93. Barnes, J. (ed.) (1984) Complete works of Aristotle (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Barnes, J., Schofield, M. & Sorabji, R. (eds) (1977) Articles on Aristotle 2: ethics and politics (London, Duckworth). Blake, N., Smeyers, P., Smith, R. & Standish, P. (eds) (2003) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education (Oxford, Blackwell). Bodéüs, R. (1993) The political dimensions of Aristotle’s Ethics (Albany, State University of New York Press). Brighouse, H. (2006) On education (London, Routledge). Carr, D. (1991) Educating the virtues (London, Routledge). Carr, D. & Steutel, J. (eds) (1999) Virtue ethics and moral education (London, Routledge). Carr, W. (2005) Philosophy and education, reprinted in: W. Carr (ed.) The RoutledgeFalmer reader in the philosophy of education (London, Routledge), 34–49. Cooper, J. (1975) Reason and the human good in Aristotle (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Cooper, J. (1999) Reason and emotion: essays on ancient moral psychology and ethical theory (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Curren, R. (1996a) Aretê, in: J. J. Chambliss (ed.) Philosophy of education: an encyclopedia (New York, Garland), 29–30. Curren, R. (1996b) Paideia, in: J. J. Chambliss (ed.) Philosophy of education: an encyclopedia (New York, Garland), 439–440. Curren, R. (2000) Aristotle on the necessity of public education (Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield).

36

Randall Curren

Curren, R. (2002a) Moral education and juvenile crime, in: S. Macedo & Y. Tamir (eds) Nomos XLIII: moral and political education (New York, New York University Press), 359–380. Curren, R. (2002b) Public education and the demands of fidelity to reason: a response to Dwyer, Feinberg, Hourdakis, Pendlebury, Robertson, Strike, and White, The School Field, 13, 79–105. Curren, R. (2002c) Civic education in the liberal and classical traditions, The School Field, 13, 107–119. Curren, R. (2006) Developmental liberalism, Educational Theory, 56, 451–468. Curren, R. (2008) Cardinal virtues of academic administration, Theory and Research in Education, 6, 337–363. Curren, R. (2009a) Education as a social right in a diverse society, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 43, 45–56. Curren, R. (2009b) Academic standards and constitutive luck, in: R. Talise & M. Eckert (eds) A teacher’s life: essays for Steven M. Cahn (New York, Lexington Books), 13–32. Depew, D. (1991) Politics, music, and contemplation in Aristotle’s ideal state, in: D. Keyt & F. Miller (eds) A companion to Aristotle’s Politics (Oxford, Blackwell), 346–380. Dunne, J. (1997) Back to the rough ground: practical judgment and the lure of technique (Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press). Dunne, J. & Pendelbury, S. (2003) Practical reason, in: N. Blake et al. (eds) The Blackwell guide to philosophy of education (Oxford, Blackwell), 194–211. Fenstermacher, G. & Richardson, V. (1993) The elicitation and reconstruction of practical arguments in teaching, Journal of Curriculum Studies, 25, 101–114. Green, T. (1976) Teacher competence as practical rationality, Educational Theory, 26, 249–258. Hirst, P. (1998) Education, Knowledge and Practices, in: P. Hirst & P. White (eds) Philosophy of education: major themes in the analytic tradition, vol. 1 (London, Routledge), 384–395. Hogan, P. & Smith, R. (2003) The activity of philosophy and the practice of education, in: N. Blake, P. Smeyers, R. Smith & P. Standish (eds), 165–180. Jaeger, W. (1957) Aristotle’s use of medicine as model of method in his ethics, The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 77, 54–61. Keyt, D. & Miller, F. (eds) (1991) A companion to Aristotle’s Politics (Oxford, Blackwell). Kraut, R. (1989) Aristotle on the human good (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Kraut, R. (2002) Aristotle: political philosophy (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Kristjánsson, K. (2007) Aristotle, emotions, and education (Aldershot, Ashgate). Kupperman, J. (1987) Perfectionism and educational policy, Public Affairs Quarterly, 1, 111–119. Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968) The role of medical and biological analogies in Aristotle’s ethics, Phronesis, 13, 68–83. Lynch, J. (1972) Aristotle’s school (Berkeley, University of California Press). MacIntyre, A. (1981) After virtue (Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press). MacIntyre, A. & Dunne, J. (2002) Alasdair MacIntyre on education: in dialogue with Joseph Dunne, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 36, 1–19. McLaughlin, T. (1999) Beyond the reflective teacher, Educational Philosophy and Theory, 31, 9–25. Miller, F. (1995) Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle’s Politics (New York, Oxford University Press).

Aristotle’s educational politics

37

Nussbaum, M. (2004) Women’s education: a global challenge, Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 29, 325–355. Nussbaum, M. (2006) Frontiers of justice (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Pelletier, L. & Sharp, E. (2009) Administrative pressures and teachers’ interpersonal behaviour, Theory and Research in Education, 7, 174–183. Peters, R. S. (1981) Moral development and moral education (London, George Allen & Unwin). Pincoffs, E. (1986) Quandaries and virtues (Lawrence, Kansas University Press). Purdy, L. (1992) In their best interest? The case against equal rights for children (Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press). Reeve, C. D. C. (1992) Practices of reason: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Reeve, C. D. C. (2000) Substantial knowledge: Aristotle’s metaphysics (Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing). Roberts, J. (1989) Political animals in the Nicomachean Ethics, Phronesis, 34, 185–204. Roberts, J. (2009) Aristotle and the politics (London, Routledge). Rorty, A. (ed.) (1980) Essays on Aristotle’s ethics (Berkeley, University of California Press). Ryan, R. & Niemiec, C. (2009a) Autonomy, competence, and relatedness in the classroom, Theory and Research in Education, 7, 133–144. Ryan, R. & Niemiec, C. (2009b) Self-determination theory in schools of education: can an empirically supported framework also be critical and liberating? Theory and Research in Education, 7, 263–272. Schwab, J. (1969) The practical: a language for curriculum, School Review, 78, 1–23. Sherman, N. (1989) The fabric of character: Aristotle’s theory of virtue (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Sherman, N. (ed.) (1999) Aristotle’s ethics: critical essays (Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield). Smith, R. (1999) Paths of judgement: the revival of practical wisdom, reprinted in: W. Carr (ed.) The RoutledgeFalmer reader in philosophy of education (London, Routledge), 206–218. Stables, A. (2008) Childhood and the philosophy of education: an anti-Aristotelian perspective (London, Continuum). Strike, K. (2003) The ethics of teaching, in: R. Curren (ed.) A companion to the philosophy of education (Oxford, Blackwell), 509–524. White, J. & White, P. (1986) Education, liberalism and human good, in: D. Cooper (ed.) Education, values and mind: essays for R. S. Peters (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul), 149–171. Yack, B. (1993) The problems of a political animal (Berkeley, University of California Press).

3

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era G. Reydams-Schils

Introduction In the first two centuries of the Roman imperial era, the study of philosophy constituted the crowning educational experience, in the sense of being both a privilege and a capstone. Only an elite among the elite studied philosophy, and only then after mastering a curriculum consisting of grammar (reading, writing and literature) and rhetoric. The ongoing cultural rivalry between rhetoricians and philosophers could be intense, even though a Stoic such as Seneca (c. 4 BCE–65 CE) clearly turned his rhetorical training to his advantage in order to convey his views more forcefully, especially in his letters and consolations. This tension was acknowledged in Seneca’s comments about his father’s misgivings about philosophy (Ep. 108.22), in the exchanges between Marcus Aurelius (121–180 CE, Med. 1.7) and his rhetoric teacher Fronto (c. 100–170 CE, De eloquentia (Haines/van den Hout), Ad M. Caes. 3.15 (1.100 Haines, p. 48 van den Hout)), and in the concerns of Epictetus (c. 55–135 CE, Diss. 3.23.3338), who, like Seneca (Ep. 40), warned that rhetorical flourishes should not cloud a philosopher’s expression.1 For Romans, Latin was the linguistic medium for rhetoric (even though rhetoric could also draw from Greek models). Philosophy, on the other hand, was most often expressed in Greek, even in the reflections that the emperor Marcus Aurelius addressed to himself. Seneca consciously departed from this model by not merely rendering Greek idiom, as had Cicero (106–43 BCE) and Lucretius (early to mid-first century BCE) before him, but also developing his philosophical views in Latin terms (Inwood, 2005, pp. 7–22). As the following discussion of the views of Seneca, Cornutus (fl c. 60 CE), Musonius Rufus (fl c. 30–100 CE), Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius will demonstrate, these later Stoics could look back on a considerable legacy established by the founders of the school in the Hellenistic period: Zeno (334–262 BCE), Cleanthes (331–232 BCE), and especially the prolific Chrysippus (c. 280–206 BCE). The earlier Stoics had often framed their views in a conscious rivalry with Plato and his successors, and also claimed Socrates for their own purposes. During the Roman Republic, Stoics such as Panaetius (c. 185–110 BCE), who spent part of his life in Rome and belonged to the entourage of Scipio Africanus

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

39

the Younger, and Posidonius (135–51 BCE), who went on an ambassadorship to Rome, directly infused Roman culture with their ideas; and Cicero, though not a Stoic himself, demonstrated a familiarity with many Stoic views. Not all the Stoics of the Roman imperial era taught philosophy or directed a philosophical school. (For a good overview of Stoicism in the imperial era, see Gill, 2000, 2003.) There is evidence of teaching activity on the part of Cornutus and Musonius Rufus, but not much information about its structure. Cornutus appears to have also taught topics pertaining to grammar as well as philosophy. Epictetus directed a school in Epirus. Other Stoics were engaged in a wide range of practices. Seneca progressively devoted more time to philosophy as he grew older, addressed others who had interests and concerns similar to his, and also wrote tragedies; Marcus Aurelius’ writings were addressed to himself, and it is not clear whether he intended his reflections for a wider audience; and Manilius’ work (first century CE) belongs within the tradition of didactic poetry. Cleomedes’ astronomical treatise on the heavens is a rare example of a Stoic technical treatise from this period (c. 200 CE),2 as is the Elements of ethics by a certain Hierocles (fl. 100 CE), to which we will return below. Although the works of Seneca, Cornutus, Musonius Rufus, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius engage the topic of education at the relatively advanced level of philosophy, they also provide some insights into pre-philosophical education. The writings of Seneca and especially Marcus Aurelius give us clues about how they themselves were educated. The entire first book of Marcus Aurelius’ Meditations, for instance, consists of an overview of the people who shaped him, including his teachers. Stoic philosophy itself, in turn, had its own curriculum, often conveniently divided into the three areas of logic, the study of nature (or physics, as the ancients called it), and ethics, though in the work of the authors examined here, ethics is the dominant strand of inquiry. Yet in the final analysis, in the view of these later Stoics, philosophy cannot be reduced to a curriculum or even a purely intellectual activity, but rather is meant to inform all human actions and to transform so-called ‘ordinary’ life from within existing social structures and responsibilities. The following discussion will examine these thinkers’ views regarding pre-philosophical education, the three branches of philosophy, and the ultimate goal of philosophical education.

Pre-philosophical education: Cornutus and Seneca From the writings attributed to Cornutus it appears that he worked in grammar and rhetoric (areas to which the Stoics also devoted attention) as well as philosophy. He taught, among others, the poets Persius (34–62 CE) and Lucan (39–65 CE). The topic of his sole preserved text, Introduction to Greek theology, sits right at the intersection of literary studies and philosophy. The work stands in a tradition of allegorical interpretations of poetry (primarily but not exclusively Homer and Hesiod) through etymologies of divine names, which, when interpreted correctly, were believed to reveal the proper ‘philosophical’ view of the gods.

40

G. Reydams-Schils

As the opening line and final paragraphs of this work indicate, it is intended to provide a young pupil (paidion) with the correct understanding of the nature of the universe, or physics, necessary to reinterpret mythological accounts. The Stoics considered theology the highest branch of physics, and Panaetius and Posidonius are said to have started their course of instruction with physics (Diogenes Laertius 7.41). Cornutus’ work is a physics textbook – but it is also plausible that it was meant to ease the transition from literary studies and rhetoric to philosophy, and thus either to prepare the ground for a potential interest in ‘higher’ philosophical studies or to prevent the worst misconceptions. The correct view of the gods would, it was assumed, yield the right attitude towards them: reverence with respect for traditional practices, yet also genuine piety without superstition.3 According to Cornutus, there were ‘philosophers’ even among the men ‘of old’, who had begun the tradition of clothing their insights in symbolic language. Both of these points, however, were a matter of debate within the Stoic tradition, as reflected in one of Seneca’s letters (Ep. 90). Though the Stoics agreed that the first generations of human beings had more direct access to the truth, they differed in their views about the extent of this knowledge and whether it was pre-philosophical. They also disagreed over when the practice of ‘hiding’, or, if viewed as a negative outcome (e.g., Cicero De natura deorum 2.63; 70–71; Plutarch Stoic. rep. 1039F), losing true meanings in poetry, mythology, and other media, such as paintings and cult practices, had started. In this context, Cornutus seems to present a strong endorsement of the allegorical method. To what extent the earlier Stoics engaged in full-fledged ‘allegorising’ is unclear. (For the best current overview of the debate, see Ramelli, 2003, esp. pp. 31–41.) We do know that the early Stoics Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus shared Cornutus’ interest in etymologies of divine names that presumably revealed true insights about nature and the divine. Cicero’s On the nature of the gods provides invaluable information about this practice, notably about Chrysippus’ work of the same name, but in a context, it has to be noted, that is very critical of Stoicism (1.40-41). Seneca goes even further than Cicero in disapproving of this mode of interpretation, thereby also asserting his independence vis-à-vis his Stoic predecessors (Ben. 1.3.2-4). In his criticism of the allegorising method, Seneca uses the three Graces as an example. (We have an instance of just such allegorising of the Graces in Cornutus 18.4-20.5 Lang. Thus Seneca may also have been indirectly criticising his contemporary.) Looking for hidden meanings in specific names, genealogies, and attributes of the gods in myths, poetic renderings, and art is not unique to the Stoics, he claims, but constitutes a broader cultural practice. His main complaint against allegorising is three-fold. First, such interpretations vary according to the views of any given interpreter. Second, poets are not reliable witnesses: often they simply make up names to suit their taste or to accommodate metrical constraints. Most importantly, this kind of analysis of poetry and of cultural artifacts is of no real use in instilling the right attitude and behaviour, he holds, making explicit

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

41

the ethical implications of one’s views of the divine. Capitalising on a well-attested cultural tension between the Greek and Roman traditions, Seneca claims that one could expect such an overly subtle approach from a Greek like Chrysippus. But this subtlety belies Chrysippus’ usual acumen and is out of keeping with his ability elsewhere to state his points lucidly and succinctly. Perhaps Chrysippus’ acumen is so finely pointed, Seneca scoffs, that it gets blunted and turns against itself, pricking rather than piercing (Ben. 1.4.1). Seneca’s famous Letter 88 on ‘liberal studies’ (liberalia studia), which also mentions the key Greek notion of ‘encyclical education’ (egkuklios paideia, 23), builds on this criticism within a larger assessment of the curriculum that normally preceded the study of philosophy. Homer can be turned into a Stoic, Epicurean, Peripatetic or Academic, he complains, depending on who is interpreting him; if all of these doctrines can be read into Homer, none is really present. Even if Homer was a philosopher, he became so independently of his poetry. In this letter, Seneca plays on the connection between artes liberales and liberae. Traditionally ‘free studies/arts’ meant those forms of knowledge that are appropriate for politically free men and do not aim at moneymaking or usefulness. (Seneca lumps painting and sculpture, which promote luxury, together with wrestling and athletics and ranks these activities lower than the ‘liberal arts’, 18–19.) But the only study that makes human beings truly free, he claims, is that which pursues wisdom and virtue, two notions inextricably connected in Seneca’s mind. Among the traditional liberal arts, he discusses grammar, literary studies, music, arithmetic, geometry, and astronomy. (One can see traces here of the curriculum of the so-called trivium and quadrivium, which goes back to Plato’s educational programme in his Republic (Hadot, I., 2005).) According to Seneca, these forms of knowledge are helpful only to the extent that they are propaideutic, in the sense of preparing the soul for the reception of virtue (20), and that one limits one’s efforts to the strictly essential rather than being carried away by a flood of useless tidbits of information (36–41). He denounces such excessive interests as motivated by pleasure and thus intemperate. Mathematics often concerns itself with practical purposes, as when arithmetic serves the purpose of managing one’s wealth, or geometry is needed for fixing the dimensions of an estate. But even forms of mathematics that are devoid of such practical concerns are at best auxiliary sciences, and thus do not belong within philosophy, or physics in the philosophical sense. Mathematics, he argues, must always borrow its first principles from other forms of knowledge, whereas philosophy investigates causes and laws of natural phenomena and hence probes much more deeply (24–28). If the goal of philosophy is to instill virtue and to make us better human beings, as Seneca holds here, then not even all of philosophy as included in the tradition will qualify as ‘free’. There are plenty of thinkers, Seneca complains, who have either vied with scholars of grammar and geometry in the pursuit of useless knowledge or who have undermined the possibility of knowledge altogether (42–46). Ultimately, he maintains, all forms of knowledge that do not

42

G. Reydams-Schils

teach us how to live well (42–43) in the context of a universe that is rationally ordered, or prepare the ground for this outcome, are superfluous.

Philosophy: logic, physics, ethics In his letter on ‘liberal studies’, Seneca also alludes to the division of philosophy into logic, physics, and ethics (24), which was central for the Stoics (though not unique to them). But most writings by the later Stoics tend to focus on ethics in action – on how to lead the good life and face challenges. As a result, many commentators have tended to consider their accounts mere popular moralising; scholars such as Paul Veyne have even gone so far as to claim that in the Roman imperial era, Stoicism lost its initial critical edge and innovative perspective by conforming itself to prevailing social customs and practices (Veyne, 1987, p. 45). Rather than endorsing an unreflective conformism, however, these accounts have a much more complex hermeneutical status and represent a conscious choice and a very specific mode of doing philosophy as well as engaging critically with prevailing norms, a point to which I will return below. This mode of philosophy by no means implies that knowledge of the more technical and theoretical aspects of Stoicism was no longer available in this era or that the later Stoics no longer cared about it. The technical aspects of Stoicism were still present in doxographies, compilations of the views of different schools of thought and philosophers, such as the work by Diogenes Laertius (probably early third century CE). Such compilations offer insights into the circulation of Stoic works and ideas in all three areas of physics, logic, and ethics. In addition, critics of the Stoics such as Plutarch (c. 46–120 CE), Galen (129–199/217 CE) and Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. late second to early third century CE) reveal that the debate about core Stoic tenets, and Chrysippus’ teachings in particular, was very much alive in this period. It may be that later Stoics tended not to focus on theory in part because they wanted to move beyond these controversies rather than get bogged down in them, as seems to have happened with earlier Stoics in their debate with the sceptical Academy. If so, the ‘grid’ of the structure and connections between different technical terms and notions that we find in doxographical sources, as developed primarily by Chrysippus, may not be the best lens through which to interpret these later accounts, even though they reveal many connections with earlier Stoic doctrine. Rather, the apparent differences may be mostly a matter of focus. Cleomedes’ exposition on astronomy, Manilius’ didactic poem, and Seneca’s own Naturales quaestiones attest to a continued interest in advanced Stoic physics. In his other writings, Seneca also likes to demonstrate occasionally that he ‘has the goods’, so to speak, including a decent knowledge of the Stoic tradition and key technical distinctions in it and other currents of thought (as in Letters 94 and 95, on the use of general doctrine and precepts, or Letter 58, on being, and Letter 65, on causality). But these expositions may have been little more than fingerexercises, just as a skilled orator may occasionally reveal the tools of his trade, both to refresh his skills and establish his credibility. As readers, we should avoid

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

43

the anachronism of considering such passages more ‘philosophical’ than others (Reydams-Schils, 2007).4 The writings of the Stoic Hierocles demonstrate how misleading the scholarly view of these Stoics’ work as simply popular moralising can be. Praechter, evaluating Hierocles’ thought only on the basis of passages preserved in Stobaeus containing ‘how to’ guidelines for dealing with the gods and one’s socio-political relationships (1901: v), considered him simply an ‘ordinary soldier in the army of Stoicism’. But shortly afterwards von Arnim edited a papyrus with fragments from a more theoretical work by Hierocles on ethics (Elements of ethics) that now constitute our best evidence on the highly sophisticated Stoic notion of ‘appropriation’ (oikeiôsis), which stipulates that by nature and from birth, animals and human beings come equipped with a self-awareness and self-love that guides them towards self-preservation (von Arnim, 1906). This notion brings together insights from both physics (how nature works) and ethics (how human beings should lead their lives) and clearly demonstrates that later Stoics such as Hierocles still had a good grasp of the technical aspects of Stoicism. (The core texts for present purposes are Cicero De finibus 3.16-25, 62-68, Seneca Ep. 121.) These Stoics had more than a mere awareness of doctrine. They also apparently still had access to extensive writings by their predecessors, notably by Chrysippus. According to the Vita Persii (32.35-33.40 Clausen), Cornutus inherited from Persius’ library about 700 scrolls of Chrysippus’ works. And although such sessions are not recorded in the extant evidence of Epictetus’ teachings, the expositions do mention that Epictetus’ approach partly relied on the writings of his Stoic predecessors, especially those of the prolific and systematic Chrysippus. Epictetus thus practised ‘commentary’ as a pedagogical method by reading philosophical works together with his pupils (sunanagnôsis, as this was called (Hadot I., 2005, second edition, revised and expanded: p. 423)). Either the teacher would comment on the passages read or students would be asked to do so (as mentioned in Diss. 1.10.7-13; 1.26; 4.9.6; this would become the dominant mode of teaching in later Platonism). Yet it is very striking that whenever Epictetus mentions this pedagogical method, he more often than not sounds a cautionary note, claiming that it does one no good whatsoever to be able to interpret and understand Chrysippus’ works, or those of other thinkers for that matter, unless one can also put these insights into practice and show how one has changed for the better as a result of one’s reading (as in Diss. 1.4.5-17, 17.13-18, 2.16.34, 17.34-40, 19.5-15, 23.44, 3.2.13-18, 9.20-22, 21.6-7, 24.81). According to Epictetus, merely interpreting philosophical expositions and showing off one’s erudition is no different from the immersion of a scholar of literature in trivial details that are meant to dazzle (Diss. 2.19.5-15; Ench. 49), and we have already seen how little Seneca also valued this kind of erudition. Presumably Epictetus would measure his own success as a teacher by the actual moral progress of his pupils, not by their ability to parrot his teachings, a point to which I will return below. What holds for reading philosophical treatises in these later Stoic accounts also holds for the study of logic and physics. Although logic and physics do belong

44

G. Reydams-Schils

within philosophy, these branches of knowledge can create similar pitfalls as the other forms of knowledge to which students would have been exposed earlier in their lives. There is a right and a wrong way of engaging in these inquiries, these authors make clear; the wrong way entails studying them for their own sake and indulging in technical details. As the art of reasoning, and more specifically of demonstrations and syllogisms (for which both Zeno and Chrysippus were famous, or notorious, depending on one’s perspective), logic is indispensable to virtue: someone who is fundamentally confused in his thinking about what the good is cannot be expected to live the virtuous life. (On the study and importance of logic in this era, see Barnes, 1997; Crivelli, 2007; Giavatto, 2008.) For this reason both Musonius Rufus and Epictetus are very severe with students who wish to bypass logic altogether or downplay its importance. When Epictetus once replied to his teacher Musonius Rufus that making a mistake in a logical problem was not as bad as burning the Capitol and one of Epictetus’ students in turn said that it was not like killing one’s father, both received the same reply: in logic, such sloppiness would in fact be the equivalent of those odious deeds (Epictetus Diss. 1.7.32-33; cf. also Ench. 52). Another important pedagogical technique related to logic is the use of theses and demonstrations. Musonius Rufus provides a glimpse of how this worked in his teaching of ethics (1 Hense/Lutz), as in his example of the counter-intuitive thesis that pleasure is not a good. If we start, Musonius says, with the generally accepted premise that every good is desirable, and then add a second equally accepted one that some pleasures are not desirable, the conclusion that pleasure cannot be considered a good clearly follows. By this method, one moves from that which is more obvious to that which is harder to grasp. Yet, Musonius points out, a teacher should use only as many arguments and proofs as necessary to make the point, taking into account the pedagogical needs of his pupils: the gifted ones will need fewer arguments, while those who are dull, either because of a weaker disposition or a wrong upbringing, will need more evidence for the point to register. Yet the most convincing example, he claims, is a teacher who acts consistently with his words (see also 5 Hense/Lutz, discussed below). Here Musonius agrees with Epictetus that theorising, or drawing the right conclusions, is easier than practice, that is, living according to these insights (Diss. 1.26.3-4). Physics appears to play a minimal role in Musonius Rufus’ approach. Whereas Chrysippus famously defined the goal of human life as living according to nature, which included the nature both of individual human beings and of the universe (Diogenes Laertius 7.88), Musonius Rufus does not draw much attention to the universal dimension (17 p. 89 Hense) but tends to focus on human nature as different from that of the animals and the gods. Musonius does leave room for the notion of Zeus as the ‘ensouled law’ (nomos empsuchos 16 p. 87 Hense) and depicts humans as citizens in Zeus’ city (i.e., the universe) (9 p. 42 Hense), but does not spell out the philosophical implications of this position. Marcus Aurelius, in contrast, states emphatically that physics, like logic, is indispensable for the pursuit of philosophy, because views that are not based on

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

45

the correct science of nature cannot hold their own. He argues that in order to make progress one needs a strong theoretical foundation and the self-confidence that results from the correct knowledge applied to each particular case (10.9). Yet a prominent, and often debated, feature of Marcus Aurelius’ writings is that he appears to leave open how exactly the universe is governed, tending instead to list alternatives, most often pitting the Stoic view of Providence against the Epicurean randomness of colliding atoms with a disjunctive ‘either ... or’ structure. (Annas, 2004 and Cooper, 2004 are representative of the debate on this issue; see also Giavatto, 2008.) His strategy appears to be a double one. First he holds that regardless of one’s view of the universe, there are certain tenets about attitude and behaviour to which one should always cling. And in some cases, he uses an a fortiori approach: if an Epicurean can manage to be content with his lot, how much more should a Stoic be so, given his or her belief that a god has made everything good? By this approach, one could argue, Marcus Aurelius puts physics in what he sees as its proper place, as subservient to ethics. Marcus Aurelius is not the only later Stoic to use these strategies, though they do loom largest in his reflections. Seneca, in one of his letters (16.4-6), leaves open whether an inexorable fate, a god, or chance rules the universe (though Stoicism assumes a connection between the first two possibilities – i.e., fate supposedly reflects the divinely imposed order of the universe). But the actual course he recommends to his addressee, namely, firmness of resolve, does not depend on any specific theory of the universe. Epictetus adopts a similar strategy, saying, ‘Why should I care whether existing things are compounded from atomic or incomposite elements, or from fire and earth? Isn’t it enough to learn the essence of good and bad ... to run our lives using these as rules; and not to bother about those things that are beyond us?’ (fr. 1 Oldfather, trans. Long). In On benefits (7.1), Seneca does not leave any doubt that it is much preferable to have a few maxims of practical philosophy at hand that will make us better and happier than a vast storehouse of recondite knowledge about nature and its hidden causes. But it is in the preface to the third book of his Naturales quaestiones that he solves the riddle of this quasi-sceptical approach to the study of nature. Physics and moral self-improvement are meant to reinforce each other, and only the physics that serves this mutual relation is worth pursuing. Understanding ourselves correctly implies understanding our place and role in the universe, how we relate to the divine principle, and to other human beings in the universal community. In the final analysis, according to the later Stoics, it is not just logic or physics in the philosophical curriculum that are subservient to the correct way of life. So, too, is talking about rather than practicing ethics. As Musonius Rufus (5 Hense/ Lutz) and Epictetus claim, one can hold discussions and write as much as one wants about the good life, but anyone with philosophical interests is ultimately judged by the same standard as a physician, a sailor or a musician: it is what one accomplishes that matters. Musonius Rufus and Epictetus hereby also quietly subvert certain upper-class assumptions about the value of philosophy, as exemplified in Seneca’s letter on the liberal arts discussed above (88). (Musonius

46

G. Reydams-Schils

Rufus, after all, taught the slave Epictetus.) Paradoxically, Musonius Rufus and Epictetus turn Seneca’s notion of freedom on its head: even though they agree with Seneca that only virtue makes one truly free, they use the parallel of the arts and vocational training to underscore that philosophy, too, has to prove itself in its results. Or, as Epictetus puts it: The builder does not come and say: Listen to me lecturing on building. He gets his contract for a house, builds it, and shows that he has the craft. You should act in the same sort of way: Eat like a human being, drink like a human being, and so too, dress, and marry, and father children, and play your roles as citizen; put up with abuse, and an inconsiderate brother, father, son, neighbor, fellow-traveler. Show all this to us, so that we can see what you have really learnt from the philosophers. (Diss. 3.21.1-6; trans. Long)

The role of philosophy, the goal of life When Musonius Rufus locates the ideal relationship between teacher and pupil in an agrarian setting and recommends farming or being a shepherd as the best way of life for a philosopher, who should work with his own hands just like anybody else (11 Hense/Lutz), it is obvious that we are dealing with a very specific concept of philosophical education, and one that sets itself in conscious opposition to the Platonic and Aristotelian traditions. Musonius Rufus argues that if work is balanced with leisure for study and discussion, this mode of interaction is the best because the teacher simultaneously sets an example by putting his principles into action and displaying virtue in his way of life (cf. also Seneca Ep. 6.6). To understand what is behind Musonius Rufus’ recommendations, we need to see how theory and practice relate to each other in Stoicism, and especially in the later accounts. ‘Philosophy’, Musonius Rufus claims, ‘is nothing else than to search out by reason what is right and proper, and by deeds to put it into practice’ (14-end Hense/Lutz, cf. also 4, on philosophy as the art of becoming a good human being). A Platonist or a follower of Aristotle would agree that philosophy should serve the good life. But for all the points of contact with these other traditions, the Stoic understanding of the good life is fundamentally different from that of a Platonist or Aristotelian. The crucial point here is not even that the Stoics in general would consider all forms of philosophical knowledge, including logic and physics, to be virtues (SVF 2.35). After all, Plato and Aristotle’s notions of virtue (which, one has to remember, in its original context is closer to our term ‘excellence’) are also capacious, including the virtues pertaining to reason. Rather, the difference is that Stoics do not have a hierarchical notion of virtue, seeing logic, physics, and ethics as mutually entailing each other in one continuous and dynamic whole. (Cf. Hadot, P., 1979, 1991; Gourinat 2008. Other core texts here would include Diogenes Laertius 7.130 and SVF 3.280.) What sets especially later Stoicism apart is the view that all theory, including what we would call theory or philosophising about ethics, must serve an ethics

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

47

in action. Theory and practice are inextricably intertwined, but with an emphasis on practice. Generally speaking, for Platonists contemporary to the Roman Stoics and later, the good life consists primarily, if not always exclusively, of the contemplation of and the mind’s reunion with a higher, intelligible realm, or theory in that sense. Interpreters of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics disagree about which of two conceptions of the good life he endorses. According to one conception, the good life consists of the exercise of practical reason in a life of political and social activity. According to the other, it consists of the exercise of theoretical reason through contemplation. To the Stoics, positing pure thought (or even a higher state) as the goal of life and as ‘practice’ (cf. Aristotle Politics 1325b) would make little sense, not in the least because they do not recognise a transcendent intelligible and noetic dimension to reality. For them, with their unified view of virtue, in which all virtues entail each other, wisdom as the excellence of reason always constitutes moral virtue and being engaged in the world.5 Small wonder, then, that the later Stoics put so much emphasis on training (meletê, askêsis, as in Musonius Rufus 6 Hense/Lutz) as the indispensable bridge between theoretical insights and practice.6 This notion, which has connections with the Socratic and Cynic traditions, encompasses much more than Aristotle’s habituation, which is meant to shape the lower, irrational aspects of the soul (as in Nicomachean Ethics 2). The Stoics, with the potential and debated exception of Posidonius, do not accept irrational aspects of the soul as existing independently from reason. Hence training and habituation involve a human being’s entire disposition, including the process of learning to use one’s reason correctly. The Stoic notion of the good has this feature in common with its Platonic and Aristotelian counterparts that it is a radical departure from ordinary conceptions of happiness, and thus it is not easy to implement against prevailing practices, weaknesses in one’s own disposition, and bad habits. Therefore, according to this view, pupils need all the help they can get to make these insights sufficiently their own or to acquire the right ‘disposition’ (ethos, as in Musonius Rufus 5 Hense/Lutz) for putting them into practice under all circumstances. To this end, Musonius Rufus (6 Hense/Lutz) stipulates exercises for both body and soul, but holds that of the two, the care of the soul is the most important. He establishes an explicit connection between the exercises of the soul and demonstrations (1 Hense/Lutz): the training of the soul, he claims, involves having ready at hand (procheirous) the demonstrations concerning true (as opposed to apparent) good and evil, becoming accustomed (ethizesthai) to making the correct distinctions, and practising (meletan) the avoidance of true evil and the pursuit of true good. (Diogenes Laertius (6.70) attributes the same distinction between two types of exercises to Diogenes the Cynic (fl. mid-fourth century BCE, on this topic cf. Goulet-Cazé, 1986); cf. also Clement of Alexandria Strom. 7.16.) Here askêsis, it has to be noted, has not yet acquired its later connotations of ‘asceticism’, though frugality and the endurance of hardships are recommended for the sake of self-control and temperance, which are essential if one does not want to be swept off one’s feet by the pull of the wrong values (as in Musonius

48

G. Reydams-Schils

Rufus 18-20 Hense/Lutz). For instance, Epictetus urges his students ‘on occasion, when you are very thirsty, [to] take cold water into your mouth, and then spit it out, without telling anybody’ (Ench. 47). But a good Stoic, as Seneca reminds us, is also capable of putting affluence and easier conditions to good use (De vita beata 20.3-end). For the later Stoics, ethics in action means showing one’s mettle in ordinary, everyday life circumstances and in society, among one’s given socio-political obligations. For this reason, students are not meant to form settled attachments to a school, as increasingly happened, for instance, with the inner circles of the schools of Platonism. The knowledge and training acquired through education has to be portable and to become fully interiorised, ‘digested’, as it were (Epictetus Diss. 3.21.1-3; Ench. 46; Seneca Ep. 2.2-4, 84, De beneficiis 7.2.1). Thus Seneca and Epictetus show their own independence towards their Stoic predecessors and do not extol a Zeno, Cleanthes or Chrysippus above all others. ‘We Stoics’, Seneca claims, ‘are not subjects of a despot: each of us lays claim to his own freedom’ (Ep. 33.4). If Chrysippus took the liberty to disagree with his teacher Cleanthes, ‘Why, then, following the example of Chrysippus himself, should not every man claim his own freedom?’ (Ep. 113.23). Epictetus and Musonius Rufus also play down their own importance as philosophers (as in Diss. 1.16.20, 1.2.35, 3.1.36, 3.7.1, 3.8.7)7 – even though they do, on occasion, mention the benefits of studying under their guidance.8 Students are told sternly not to show off their philosophical knowledge (e.g., Epictetus Diss. 1.26.9) and that external trappings, such as a certain dress code, do not make the philosopher (as in Epictetus Diss. 3.12.16, 3.14.4, 3.23, 4.8.15-16); Musonius Rufus (16 Hense/Lutz). Many of the accounts preserved in Epictetus’ Discourses explicitly address the challenge of the transition from the school to everyday life (as in 4.1.132-143, 4.5.37, 4.12.12; cf. also 1.29.34-35, 2.9.15-16, 2.10.29-30, 2.16.2, 3.3.17, 3.20.18). As they point out, it is quite a bit easier to display the correct attitude and behaviour among like-minded people and peers than to hold on to what one has learned outside the school environment (Diss. 2.16.20-21). And if Epictetus devotes so much attention to this topic, it is precisely because his pupils are meant to return to their regular lives. In the long run, and over the course of an entire lifetime, according to this view, teachers are there only to point the way (as Seneca and Epictetus indicate Chrysippus had done for them). It is self-education and monitoring one’s own progress as one goes through different situations in life that are to do the bulk of the work. Modes of such ongoing training include reading and excerpting philosophical works, refreshing one’s memory of key tenets so as to have these ready at hand (as the etymology of ‘manual’ or Epictetus’ Encheiridion implies), engaging in conversations with others, witnessing one’s conversations with oneself, contemplating the order of the universe or writing. Although Seneca is not a teacher in the same sense as Musonius Rufus and Epictetus, he increasingly focused on philosophical writings towards the end of his life and mapped out his own moral progress and challenges, along with summaries and advice for his addressees and audience. Marcus Aurelius’

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

49

reflections, many of which were jotted down during military campaigns, are the clearest example of writing as ongoing training, especially if originally intended primarily for himself and not for a broader audience. (Epictetus attributed this kind of writing even to Socrates allegedly training himself in the art of refutation, raising objections and coming up with counter-arguments, Diss. 2.1.32-33, 2.6.26-27, as rightly noted in Döring, 1974, p. 218 n. 2.) In those reflections, we find the most powerful man in the then known world, as measured by conventional standards, warning himself against completely identifying himself with his public role. ‘Make sure’, he tells himself, ‘that you are not turned into a Caesar’, without leaving space for the self to continue groping for that which truly matters. In the course of interpreting Homer and Virgil, being trained in delivering speeches, and acquiring other forms of learning, all the way up to one’s philosophical education, one should aim towards ‘a holy disposition and acts that serve the common good’ (6.30), as Marcus Aurelius succinctly rendered the purpose of human life.

Notes 1 During the later period known as the Second Sophistic, the rivalry becomes all the more pronounced, with Dion of Prusa (also known as Chrysostom), Apuleius and Maximus of Tyre clearly straddling the divide. 2 Even though the dates suggested for Cleomedes range from the first century BCE to the fourth century CE, a dating of ‘some time around 200 CE’ has been proposed as likely by Alan C. Bowen and Robert B. Todd, 2004, pp. xi–xii, 2–4. 3 Cf. Boys-Stones, 2007, who emphasises a strong strand of ethical pedagogy in his work, which also reflects on the political and civic aspects of human communities. 4 On the point that texts such as Epictetus’ Encheiridion and Marcus Aurelius’ Meditations are as ‘philosophical’ as Chrysippus’ treatises, see Sellars, 2009, esp. pp. 126–128, 165–166, 167–175. Pace Brennan, 2005, who uses a stereotypical distinction between Chrysippus as ‘one of the greatest thinkers of all time’ and Epictetus as ‘one of the greatest talkers’ (p. 10). 5 Here my approach differs from P. Hadot, 1998, p. 216, repeated by Sellars, 2007 and 2009, esp. p. 145 (summary statement), who stipulate that there is a practical side to physics and logic as well. While I do not take issue with this claim as such and the implication that there are appropriate exercises in logic and physics, I would also emphasise that physics and logic are practical precisely to the extent that they serve a human being’s correct understanding of the good and its implementation in life, that is, ethics in action. 6 P. Hadot, 1995, is still the seminal work on this topic, but my focus here is on what is distinctive in the later Stoic tradition; cf. also Hijmans, 1959; Sellars, 2009, esp. pp. 107–166. Xenophon does not hesitate to attribute this notion to Socrates (Mem. 1.2.19). 7 On this aspect of Epictetus, who prefers to see himself as a ‘trainer of the young’, see Diss. 2.19.29-34, cf. Long, 2002, pp. 121–125. Thus when Musonius Rufus speaks as one man in exile to another, he presents his arguments as addressed to himself as well as to his addressee (9 Hense/Lutz), and when he counsels a youth who has a conflict with his father over the study of philosophy, he does not insert himself between the son and the father to bring about a transfer of authority (16 Hense/Lutz). On this topic, cf. also Bénatouïl, 2009, especially pp. 134–155, and G. Reydams-Schils, ‘Authority and agency in Roman Stoicism’, forthcoming.

50

G. Reydams-Schils

8 Even though Epictetus explicitly distances himself from the practice of doctors advertising for patients, Diss. 3.23.27. See Musonius Rufus 17 Hense/Lutz; Epictetus Diss. 1.11, addressed to a Roman official merely passing through, and 2.19.29-34.

References Primary Aristotle (1996) The politics and The constitution of Athens (S. Everson ed.) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Arnim, H. A. von (1903) Stoicorum veterum fragmenta (4 vols) (Leipzig, Teubner). Cicero, M. T. (1914) De finibus (H. Rackham ed.) (London, Heinemann). Cicero, M. T. (1933) De natura deorum; Academica (H. Rackham ed.) (London, Heinemann). Clement of Alexandria (1882) Stromata in: The writings of Clement of Alexandria (W. Wilson ed.) (2 vols) (Edinburgh, T & T Clark). Cornutus, L. A. (1881) Theologiae Graecae compendium (C. Lang ed.) (Leipzig, Teubner). Diogenes Laertius (1925) Lives of eminent philosophers (R. D. Hicks ed.) (2 vols.) (London, Heinemann). Fronto, M. C. (1928) The correspondence of Marcus Cornelius Fronto (C. R. Haines ed.) (2 vols.) (London, Heinemann). Fronto, M. C. (1954) Epistulae (M. P. J. Van den Hout ed.) (Leiden, Brill). Epictetus (1925) The Discourses as reported by Arrian, the Manual, and fragments (W. A. Oldfather ed.) (2 vols.) (London, Heinemann). Hierocles (1906) Ethische Elementarlehre (H. von Arnim ed.) (Berlin, Weidmann). Marcus Aurelius (1930) Meditations (C. R. Haines ed.) (London, Heinemann). Musonius Rufus (1905) Reliquiae (O. Hense ed.) (Leipzig, Teubner). Musonius Rufus (1947) Musonius Rufus: The Roman Socrates (C. E. Lutz ed.) (New Haven, Yale University Press). Plutarch (1976) Moralia, vol. XIII: Part 2: Stoic Essays (H. Cherniss ed.) (London, Heinemann). Probus, M. V (1959) Vita Persii in: A. Persi Flacci et D. Iuni Iuvenalis saturae (W. V. Clausen ed.) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Seneca (1917) Epistles (R. M. Gummere ed.) (3 vols.) (London, Heinmann). Seneca (2011) On Benefits (M. Griffin & B. Inwood, eds.) (Chicago, University of Chicago Press).

Secondary Annas, J. (2004) Marcus Aurelius: ethics and its background, Rhizai: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 1.2, 103–119. Barnes, J. (1997) Logic and the imperial Stoa (Leiden, Brill). Bénatouïl, T. (2009) Les Stoïciens III: Musonius, Épictète, Marc Aurèle (Paris, Les Belles Lettres). Bowen, A.C. & Todd, R.B. (2004) Cleomedes’ lectures on astronomy. A translation of the heavens with an introduction and commentary (Berkeley, University of California Press). Boys-Stones, G. (2007) Fallere sollers: the ethical pedagogy of the Stoic Cornutus, in: R. Sorabji & R. W. Sharples (eds) Greek and Roman philosophy 100BC-200AD, Volume 1 (London, Institute of Classical Studies), 77–88.

Philosophy and education in Stoicism of the Roman imperial era

51

Brennan, T. (2005) The Stoic life: emotions, duty and fate (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Cooper, J. (2004) Moral theory and moral improvement: Marcus Aurelius, in: Knowledge, nature and the good (Princeton, Princeton University Press), 335–368. Crivelli, P. (2007) Epictetus and logic, in: A. Mason & T. Scaltsas (eds) The philosophy of Epictetus (Oxford, Oxford University Press), 20–31. Döring, K. (1974) Sokrates bei Epiktet, in: K. Döring & W. Kullman (eds) Studia Platonica. Festschrift für Hermann Gundert (Amsterdam, Grüner), 195–226. Giavatto, A. (2008) Interlocutore di si stesso: la dialettica di Marco Aurelio (Hildesheim, Olms). Gill, C. (2000) Stoic writers of the imperial Era, in: C. Rowe & M. Schofield (eds) The Cambridge history of Greek and Roman political thought (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 579–611. Gill, C. (2003) The school in the Roman imperial period, in: B. Inwood (ed.) The Cambridge companion to the Stoics (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 33–58. Goulet-Cazé, M.-O. (1986) L’ascèse cynique: un commentaire de Diogène Laërce VI 70–71 (Paris, Vrin). Gourinat, J.-B. (2008) Les éclipses de la phronèsis dans le stoïcisme de Cléanthe à MarcAurèle, in: D. Lories & L. Rizzerio (eds) Le jugement pratique. Autour de la notion de phronèsis (Paris, Vrin), 167–197. Hadot, I. (2005) (2nd edn, revised & expanded), Arts libéraux et philosophie dans la pensée antique (Paris, Vrin). Hadot, P. (1979) Les divisions des parties de la philosophie dans l’Antiquité, Museum Helveticum, 36, 201–223. Hadot, P. (1991) Philosophie, discours philosophique, et divisions de la philosophie selon les Stoïciens, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 45, 205–219. Hadot, P. (1995) Philosophy as a way of life: spiritual exercises from Socrates to Foucault (trans. A. Davidson) (Oxford, Blackwell). Hadot, P. (1998) La philosophie antique: une éthique ou une pratique? in: Études de philosophie ancienne (Paris, Les Belles Lettres), 207–229. Hijmans, B.L. (1959) Askesis: notes on Epictetus’ educational system (Assen, Van Gorcum). Inwood, B. (2005) Reading Seneca: Stoic philosophy at Rome (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Long, A.A. (2002) Epictetus. A Stoic and Socratic guide to life (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Praechter, K. (1901) Hierokles der Stoiker (Leipzig, Dieterich). Ramelli, I. (2003) Anneo Cornuto, Compendio di teologia Greca (Milan, Bompiani). Reydams-Schils, G. (forthcoming) Authority and agency in Roman Stoicism. Reydams-Schils, G. (2007) Review of B. Inwood Reading Seneca: Stoic philosophy at Rome, Phoenix, 6.11-2, 186–189. Sellars, J. (2007) Stoic practical philosophy in the Imperial period, in: R. Sorabji & R. W. Sharples (eds) Greek and Roman philosophy 100BC-200AD, Volume 1 (London, Institute of Classical Studies), 115–140. Sellars, J. (2009) (2nd edn) The art of living: the Stoics on the nature and function of philosophy (London, Duckworth). Veyne, P. (1987) The Roman Empire, in: P. Veyne (ed.) A history of private life: from pagan Rome to Byzantium (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press).

4

Medieval theories of education Hugh of St Victor and John of Salisbury Brian D. FitzGerald

Introduction The medieval roots of our contemporary universities are well known. Rather less familiar is what thinkers of the time actually considered education to be. The two theorists examined here – Hugh of St Victor (c.1096–1141) and John of Salisbury (c.1120–1180) – represent only the twelfth century, but there are good reasons for turning to this period in particular for an assessment of medieval education. Intellectually, the twelfth century saw heightened activity, especially in Paris, where Hugh taught and John studied. The old cathedral schools were proving incapable of absorbing the influx of new texts and ideas (including, for instance, techniques of textual analysis and the translations of Aristotelian logical writings) or of satisfying the growing desire for instruction in these by students who were driven both by enthusiasm and by a recognition of the career advancements that education could bring within the Church. In this period, before groups of masters and teachers became formalised entities recognisable today as universities, before the methods and aims of scholasticism spread, both Hugh and John understood the need for systematic statements about what learning should be and how it should be done. Hugh’s Didascalicon (written in the late 1120s) and John’s Metalogicon (in 1159), besides reflecting the twelfth-century fashion of Greek-sounding titles, are their major pedagogical statements. Medieval scholars had, of course, long been aware of earlier visions of education: the writings, for instance, of Cicero and Quintilian, though incompletely known in the Middle Ages, encouraged reflection on the liberal arts – what was the relationship between wisdom and eloquence? Did studying these arts improve people’s lives? For Christian thinkers, whose search for wisdom revolved around the figure of Christ, whom they believed was Wisdom incarnate, there was often uncertainty about their relationship to the old pagan arts and forms of schooling. What place did a liberal arts education have for a Christian when all that was necessary for salvation could be found in the Bible? Twelfth-century scholars could find authority either for an ascetic rejection of worldly wisdom, as in Athanasius’ Life of St Anthony, or for a more positive monastic appraisal of secular letters, as in the writings of Cassiodorus (c. 490–585) or Alcuin (c. 735–804). One of the reflections on these questions

Medieval theories of education

53

most influential for medieval education was Augustine of Hippo’s De doctrina christiana, written at the beginning of the fifth century. In this paper, I hope to show how Hugh and John, drawing on, and responding to, both classical and Augustinian ideas, offered re-statements of pedagogical purpose and method which were significant in their own day and important for any consideration of the history of educational theory.

Hugh of St Victor: Didascalicon Hugh’s origins are obscure, but in the second decade of the twelfth century he arrived at the Abbey of St Victor in Paris, home to a community of Augustinian canons. By 1127, Hugh was a master at the school there, and, within six years, its head. Rooted in the traditional monastic form of reading and education that emphasised sacra pagina, the study of and meditation on Scripture, the abbey masters were nonetheless engaged with the intellectual energy of Paris. Hugh’s Didascalicon reveals the influences of both of these currents. The Didascalicon is, first and foremost, a text about how to read. There are two things, Hugh tells us in his preface, by which a person ‘advances in knowledge … – reading and meditation’ (1961, p. 44). The Didascalicon treats only of reading, but he wants to emphasise that education is not comprised of study alone; reading begins, but by no means completes, a process of understanding and learning. The Didascalicon’s goal, though, is to ensure that the first step is taken properly. To teach his readers how to study, Hugh believes they ought to know what to read, the order in which to read it, and how to read it (p. 44). Out of this project emerges Hugh’s effort to order all knowledge, both sacred and secular. Underlying such an ordered system is a belief in the unity of all knowledge, the interrelationship of the liberal arts, and their importance for an understanding of the divine. Thus, while understanding how to read is the stated goal of the text, Hugh presumes a still higher purpose for this activity, which he reveals in the opening line of Book One: ‘Of all things to be sought, the first is that Wisdom in which the Form of the Perfect Good stands fixed’ (1961, I.1, p. 46). For Hugh, this Wisdom is ultimately Christ, though he speaks about it here as an inner illumination, one which reveals to people what they truly are. What one must do above all is follow the classic doctrine: ‘Know thyself’ (I.1, p. 46). Knowledge, ultimately, leads to self-knowledge, and this learning process is necessary because man has ‘forgotten his origin’ (I.1, p. 46). Hugh refers here to original sin, and all of his pedagogical concerns must be seen in the light of his belief in human involvement in a narrative of creation, sin and redemption. This pursuit of wisdom reminds the self of its true origins in God, as a creature made in God’s image and likeness. The Didascalicon therefore proposes a programme of spiritual restoration for fallen man: ‘we are restored through instruction, so that we may recognise our nature and learn not to seek outside ourselves what we can find within’ (I.1, p. 47). By opening the paths to wisdom, education is ultimately not only an epistemological endeavour, but a moral and spiritual one as well.

54

Brian D. FitzGerald

In this, Hugh draws on Augustine’s belief in the ethical component of reading, highlighted in De doctrina christiana. The first three books of De doctrina discuss Christian education with the aim of interpreting Scripture and its revelation of God’s wisdom. While Hugh rarely cites them explicitly, it is their concerns which he is reworking, less for exegetical than for pedagogical purposes (Sweeney, 1995, p. 63).1 Augustine believes that ‘all teaching is teaching of either things or signs’ (1995, p. 125).2 All words for Augustine are signs that point to things they represent, as the word ‘sheep’ represents the animal. Instruction in the arts helps a student understand unfamiliar signs and therefore the literal meaning of the words of Scripture. Classical liberal arts education, then, must be put at the service of the interpretation of Scripture, the definitive Christian text containing all necessary teaching. This is to appropriate classical learning for a Christian purpose, as in Augustine’s famous analogy (1995, p. 67) of the Israelites despoiling the Egyptian treasures for their own ends on the way to the Holy Land (an image not quite as negative as Jerome’s well-known comparison of secular learning to the captive woman of Deuteronomy (21:10-3), who might be wed only after she had been shorn of all her hair) (1996, 70.2). In the Scriptural text, though, there are meanings beyond the literal at work, which, for Augustine, cannot be accessed by classical education and to which those pagan arts are in strict subservience. These spiritual meanings are revealed by God through sacred history and Christian truth. So, for instance, the word ‘sheep’ in the Book of Genesis signifies the animal, but the sheep which Abraham sacrificed was a thing that also pointed ahead to Christ’s sacrifice (Augustine 1995, p. 14). Understanding the relationship between literal and allegorical meanings will prevent one from going astray in the interpretation of Scripture. For Augustine, the ability to interpret Scripture is connected to one’s moral capacities. In the first place, reading something literally (e.g., the Song of Songs) that in reality points to a different spiritual meaning (and vice versa) could be disastrous for one’s abilities to understand and to live out God’s word. Furthermore, Augustine extends the ethical implications of reading to every choice a person makes in life: every created thing – not just those in the Scriptural narrative – points as a sign to its Creator (1995, p. 141). We have continually to interpret the world, recognising its ultimately contingent nature, refusing to let our desires settle on worldly things while lifting them continually towards God. All of our choices are therefore acts of interpretation, fraught with moral and spiritual dimensions, about the true meaning of things. This is Hugh’s belief as well, but Hugh is far more systematic than Augustine, and his plan for Christian education not only goes beyond De doctrina’s scope but, in the process, alters some of its emphases.3 Hugh’s first concern is what to read. Mindful, like Augustine, that wisdom is the goal of education, Hugh classifies all learning under the heading of Philosophy, using, as Jerome Taylor notes (1961, p. 8), an Aristotelian four-fold division containing all the arts (by which Hugh means a form of knowledge comprised of rules and precepts). His scheme is as follows: 1) theoretical – theology (contemplation of God and spiritual substances), physics (natural philosophy) and mathematics (the quadrivium

Medieval theories of education

55

of arithmetic, music, geometry and astronomy); 2) practical – solitary (ethics), private (household economics) and public (civil); 3) logical – the trivium (grammar, dialectics, and rhetoric) and 4) mechanical (containing seven arts, including agriculture, medicine, and hunting).4 Hugh justifies his four-fold scheme by pointing out that the contemplation of truth (the theoretical) and the practice of virtue (the practical) are the two means of restoring the divine image within (1961, I.8, pp. 54–55); humans need, in addition, the verbal arts of logic to comprehend and assess those higher arts (II.17, pp. 71–73). Furthermore, since the intention of all human pursuits ‘ought to regard either the restoring of our nature’s integrity, or the relieving of those weaknesses to which our present life lies subject’ (I.4-5, pp. 51–52), Hugh includes the fourth type of art, the mechanical. He not only recognises clearly the significance of the traditional seven liberal arts, but he also attempts an ordering of all conceivable human arts. Even the lowliest, at the most physical level, has a part to play in spiritual restoration. Although Hugh distinguishes knowledge of the mechanical arts (scientia) from the understanding which ultimately comes through the higher arts (intelligentia), his treatment of the mechanical is, as Paul Rorem points out, ‘a comprehensive affirmation of daily life in the world at large’ (2009, p. 26).5 As Hugh unfolds his pedagogical system, his discussion of the order in which to read and how to read them reveals another difference from Augustine. To aid in his readers’ philosophical quest, Hugh spends the first three books of the Didascalicon explaining how the arts are to be learned through secular writings; the second three books go on to discuss the continuation of learning via sacred texts. Hugh certainly distinguishes between secular and sacred writings – he emphasises the truthfulness of the sacred – but the Didascalicon does not focus on this difference.6 Because all of the arts are ‘philosophical’, secular arts have standing on their own terms as part of the search for wisdom and the ethical and spiritual regeneration of those who study them (Hugh, 1961, II.3, II.18, pp. 63, 73). Augustine’s suspicion of secular texts and his subjugation of secular arts to the status of Scriptural aids are absent here. Hugh specifically encourages the study of certain arts of which Augustine is suspicious (notably, drama and astronomy), but more important is the basis on which he includes them. For Augustine, the secular is an instrument of Biblical exegesis; for Hugh, it is more integrally and naturally an instrument of the very process of human renewal. Hugh follows Augustine’s lead in appropriating pagan treasures, but he incorporates them into the Christian life to a far greater extent.7 Hugh’s discussion of textual analysis seems rather straightforward – begin with the basic sense of the words and then look for the deeper meaning. But, unusually for the twelfth century, he uses this method for both sacred and secular texts: first the letter (the literal meaning), then the sense (sensus) or particular figures of speech and finally the deeper meaning (sententia) (III.8, VI.8-12, pp. 91–92, 147–150). This parallel further highlights the underlying unity of sacred and secular learning. It also points to Hugh’s consistent awareness of the need for firm foundations. This is particularly evident in his insistence that, when

56

Brian D. FitzGerald

reading the Bible, one must begin with its historical books – ultimately, it is an account of deeds done in time, and any hidden spiritual significations in the text must be grounded in reality (V.3, p. 121). As with ‘the construction of buildings’, the loftier meanings are built upon basic foundations: the humble meaning and syntax of sentences shape and support any deeper understanding, and the basic events of sacred history provide both support for, and constraint on, interpretation (VI.2-3, pp. 135–138). It is in this spirit that Hugh utters his most famous remark: ‘Learn everything; you will see afterwards that nothing is superfluous’ (omnia disce, videbis postea nihil esse superfluum) (VI.3, p. 137). Hugh does not intend by this to promote an insatiable appetite for reading anything that comes along;8 instead, it is a reminder of the ethical implications of how one reads. For both Hugh and Augustine, reading is a moral act: as Eileen Sweeney notes, ‘the soul’s path towards salvation itself [is] made symmetrical to the path of reading’ (1995, p. 62). Augustine laid out his programme of Christian education for the purposes of Scriptural exegesis, and he saw interpretative skills primarily as a way of growing out of disordered selfishness and learning to recognise that everything points beyond itself to something greater. Hugh agrees on this goal: the movement within a text from literal to figurative and spiritual, like the movement from the study of words in the trivium to the study of things in the higher arts, and from secular to sacred writings, mirrors the soul’s growth from an understanding of worldly things to a recognition of their relationship to the divine (Sweeney, 1995, p. 75). For Hugh, though, unlike Augustine, this spiritual process begins long before one is interpreting Scripture’s deeper meanings. All education contributes to the rebuilding of sinful humanity, for Hugh is more optimistic about people’s natural potential for drawing upon the things of creation to remake that lost image in their present life. The process of renewal begins even with the lowliest of arts. Hugh’s well-ordered programme thus requires a student who is able to order himself along the way, for at the beginning of the whole endeavour lies humility, a willingness to proceed step-by-step, from the lowest to the highest, all the while recognising that the ‘instability of our life’ means that ‘we are forced often to review the things we have done’ and often repeat them (1961, V.9, p. 133). One must also recognise that, as Hugh noted at the beginning of his book, even this process of reading is only a stage, for lectio must always point beyond to meditatio and then to operatio, the living out of the growth of love and virtue within.9

John of Salisbury: Metalogicon John left his native Salisbury for Paris in the 1130s, where he studied for twelve years under such luminaries as Peter Abelard, William of Conches, and Gilbert of Poitiers. Unlike Hugh, however, John chose to enter into political service after his ordination, and he then trained at the papal court before returning to England in 1154 to serve as secretary to the Archbishop of Canterbury, a post which entailed numerous political and diplomatic duties. It was while serving in

Medieval theories of education

57

this office that John finished both the Metalogicon and his political treatise, the Policraticus. The Policraticus was by far the more popular of the treatises in John’s day, but the Metalogicon, which appeared in 1159, had a circulation among contemporary intellectuals and has proven of lasting significance as a reflection on education. Compared to Hugh’s Didascalicon, the Metalogicon is decidedly more focused in scope – it treats only the components of logic, or the trivium: grammar, rhetoric and dialectic. John does not disagree with Hugh’s basic principle about the pedagogical goal of wisdom, but he discusses only the first stages of that search. He sets out to promote the study of the trivium’s verbal arts (all three of which he calls logic), and to ensure that they are studied correctly (1962, I.10, p. 32). In its stated purpose, the Metalogicon is clearly Victorine in spirit – much as Hugh insists on the significance of even the lowest arts for the philosophical quest, so does John defend the very foundations of education. As will be clear, however, John’s interest in the uses of that education differs from Hugh’s. John’s first point is one of basic pedagogy. The Metalogicon’s source of inspiration is someone he calls Cornificius, who has been a critic of the teaching of logic (current scholarly consensus is that John’s description of this detractor is a composite portrait of several different opponents). Against the ‘Cornifician’ claim that the verbal arts should not be taught because reason and eloquence are gifts of nature which education cannot alter, John states his case firmly for the mutual interaction of talent and instruction: nature needs to be cultivated or it will deteriorate (1962, I. 8, pp. 28–31). For John, this means not merely knowing the principles of the trivium or the rules of eloquence but practising them. He cites numerous instances of schoolmasters who neglect to have students act on what they have been taught (II.10, 17, pp. 95ff, 111ff). Here, his approach differs from Hugh, for whom treating ‘by means of the art’ rather than ‘of the art’ is far too complex and leads to reading things out of proper order. It is sufficient for Hugh if students understand the rules (1961, III.5, 89–90). John is decidedly more pragmatic. In this regard, a key feature of John’s pedagogical theory is the role of the Aristotelian habitus: knowledge is not truly possessed until it becomes fixed through regular practice. As Cary Nederman has pointed out (1989, pp. 270, 275–277), this principle (which John could have derived indirectly, from authors such as Cicero and Boethius) underlies John’s claims that nature grants only the capacity for knowledge. Instruction that is active as well as informative must then do its work. This is why John rejects not only the Cornifician disdain for the trivium but also the opposite error of over-intellectualisation. He is critical of the fad for dialectics he has seen among some of his former instructors (a trend which would certainly continue among the schoolmen of the next century). Those who elevate dialectics above all else will fail to reach wisdom, not so much because they do not study the other arts but because they have forgotten the relationship of their studies to life (1962, II.7-9, pp. 88–95). Debates about the tension between subtilitas (subtlety or precision) and utilitas (usefulness) were

58

Brian D. FitzGerald

ongoing in the twelfth century, and John here prefers the latter, seeing wisdom in pragmatic terms: It is easy for an artisan to talk about his art, but it is much more difficult to put the art into practice. What physician does not often discourse at length on elements, humours, complexions, maladies, and other things pertaining to medicine? But the patient who recovers as a result of hearing this jargon might just as well have been sickened by it. (II.9, p. 94) The same is true of moral philosophers who cannot embody ethics in their own lives.10 One of John’s overriding concerns regards eloquence’s relationship to wisdom and, like Hugh, he has an Augustinian precedent in De doctrina christiana. While Hugh drew primarily upon the themes of the first three books of that work, John’s interest in the concrete uses of the verbal arts is the focus of Book IV. Augustine recognises rhetoric has a purpose in promoting the truth when used well, but he worries about its misuses (1995, p. 119). Book IV, where he discusses how to present Scripture’s meanings to others, reveals that underlying ambiguity. Augustine, like John, focuses on specific uses of eloquence rather than mastery of its rules (p. 201), but he is wary of the study or use of any rhetoric detached from a Scriptural context. This, for him, is eloquence without wisdom, and he refers to Cicero’s own warning ‘that wisdom without eloquence was of little value to society but that eloquence without wisdom was generally speaking a great nuisance, and never beneficial’ (p. 203). For Augustine, wisdom comes from reading Scripture, and his concern is the eloquence required for preaching to unfold Scripture’s message to others and to move them to follow it (pp. 227–233). John’s own discussion of this relationship is not focused on preaching but, as befits a diplomat, on the interactions that occur in civil life. Eloquence without wisdom – the mistake made by addicts of dialectic – is a mere ‘hodgepodge of verbiage’ (sartago loquendi), words that are useless or harmful in their emptiness (1962, I.3, p. 16). But wisdom without eloquence – the mistake of the Cornificians – is equally problematic: any knowledge we have is futile unless it can be assessed with dialectic, expressed with grammar, and used via rhetoric to influence others (I.7, pp. 26–27). Only with eloquence can one pursue the goal of building up human happiness. This goal reveals a reworking of Book IV of De doctrina christiana in the same manner that Hugh reworked the first three books. Like Hugh, John rejects a pessimistic notion that man’s post-lapsarian nature limits his capacities and knowledge (Nederman, 1988, pp. 11–12). John intends a more immediate remedying of human weakness than Augustine, though he urges the development of happiness within a context more secular than both Hugh and Augustine. In positing the trivium’s powers, John retains an Augustinian awareness of human weakness and disorder, and yet he believes that it is natural and beneficial for humans to live within social bonds. John follows what Nederman calls the

Medieval theories of education

59

Ciceronian tradition (placing it between Augustinian pessimism and Aristotelian optimism about natural sociability) – society may be natural, but people need to be awakened to this nature through reason and persuasion (1988, pp. 4–6).11 Unlike Hugh, for whom the maxim ‘Know thyself ’ is the basis for spiritual regeneration ultimately aimed at the contemplative’s encounter with the cosmic source of Wisdom, John’s emphasis is on renewal of the human community. For John, too, then, the way one studies is a mirror of moral development. Human nature neither limits one’s abilities to learn nor one’s abilities to build up the bonds of human society – people need to be drawn out through practice in both learning well and living virtuously. Studies do not make people good, John notes, but they do help them both ‘to receive and to impart knowledge’, which precedes virtue (1962, I.21, p. 61). There is room for grace, but it must build upon a developed nature. John’s pedagogical ethics contain one further element. He combines his optimism about the powers of education with a moderate scepticism (rare in his time) regarding man’s ultimate capacities for certain knowledge.12 People are, he says, ‘imprisoned within the petty dimensions of our human capacity’ and therefore must be moderate in their claims of truth (II.20, p. 127). In the end, with sensation as its foundation, knowledge consists mainly of ‘probabilities’ (III.10, p. 201) such that human perfection means ‘having a good concept of many things’ (III.3, p. 157). John’s sense of the probabilistic is a major reason why he spends so much of the Metalogicon discussing the proper uses of dialectic and promoting in particular its Aristotelian forms: rational powers are useless without the verbal arts to bring them to life, and Aristotelian logic seems to him a particularly suitable technique for assessing probable truths in a world which is otherwise reliant on sense data (Keats-Rohan, 1987, pp. 4–5). This technique’s moderate methods are a good way of using both reason and persuasion in the attempt to improve human society.

Education and politics As is clear from the Didascalicon, Hugh’s interest in education is ultimately a spiritual one. He does, in fact, speak of politics, classifying it as a practical science along with ethics and economics. Not simply a theoretical knowledge, what these sciences teach requires virtuous actions to achieve – political science, for instance, trains rulers how to act with regard to their subjects’ welfare (1961, II.19, p. 74). Hugh is one of the first twelfth-century thinkers to articulate a specifically public sphere of practical knowledge and to point to ‘the interrelated educative nature of ethics and political science’ (Nederman, 1996, p. 577). Nonetheless, he wrote no treatises on the subject; only when we turn to John of Salisbury and his Policraticus – often considered the first complete work of political theory in the Latin Middle Ages – can we see explicit connections between the pedagogical, the ethical, and the political. John clearly conceived of an intimate link between the Policraticus and the Metalogicon: finished in the same year (1159), the pedagogical precepts he lays

60

Brian D. FitzGerald

out in the one are the guiding principles of his political thought in the other.13 One of the most significant of these is John’s distinction between sacred and secular: just as he emphasised a clearly secular purpose for the liberal arts, so does he articulate separate spheres for Church and State. Spiritual concerns are ultimately the most important: John uses the familiar image of the political community as an organism, a body, and declares the clergy its soul (1990, V.2, pp. 66–67). The Church, therefore, must orient the community towards promoting the salvation of its members. The secular ruler, though, has an independent purpose, to cultivate human society through the renewal of a just community on earth. Such a renewal is a contribution to the Church’s goal, but it is not merely that: temporal goodness and happiness have significance in their own right. Both secular and sacred, therefore, have roles to play, and good governance in either realm requires awareness of the limits of each.14 Not only does John argue for a balanced relationship between body and soul, but he also insists on harmony among the different corporal members. He takes the traditional analogy of the state as body and greatly expands it, describing in detail the role of head (prince), heart (senate), senses (judges), etc. One important feature to note is John’s treatment of the peasantry as a distinct group who are by no means insignificant: they are ‘the feet … for whom it is all the more necessary that the head [the prince] take precautions, in that they more often meet with accidents … and those who erect, sustain and move forward the mass of the whole body are justly owed shelter and support’ (V.2, p. 67). Nederman (2002, p. 82) argues that John (perhaps influenced by the Didascalicon) is drawing out the political implications of Hugh’s valorisation of mechanical labour. Just as Hugh’s classification of knowledge gives the mechanical arts a crucial role to play in support of a person’s pursuit of virtue and wisdom, so do John’s mechanical citizens improve the material well-being of a state and thus are by no means unimportant to the larger goals of either individual or communal flourishing. Indeed, another major feature of John’s body politic is that all its parts, including the lowest, exist in a reciprocal, rather than subordinate, relationship with the other members: ‘The health of the whole society will only be secure and splendid if the superior members devote themselves to the inferiors and if the inferiors respond likewise to the legal rights of their superiors’ (1990, VI.2, p. 126). Each group has responsibilities, but it is ultimately the task of the ruler, the head, to maintain within the body this reciprocal balance, a prerequisite for the common good. The prince’s power comes from God, and thus the prince becomes a divine image, so long as he does not act unjustly. But the purpose of his power is to ‘bring about the utility of each and all, and … arrange the optimal condition of the human republic, so that everyone is a member of the others (alter alterius membra)’ (IV.1, pp. 28–29). The tyrant abuses this power and threatens the balance by ignoring the principles of equity (aequitas), which seeks to give to each person what is owed. John’s description of the causes of tyrannical behaviour reveals the intimate connection he sees between ethics and politics. Much of the Policraticus is a

Medieval theories of education

61

critique of the numerous distractions at the secular courts: hunting, gambling, and music, among others. Lamenting the rulers’ dissolute lifestyle, John expresses the hope that, having attained years of discretion, they would allow serious affairs of state to take precedence of their own diversions. The state would then feel a surge of strength course through its entire frame and the appearance of perfect harmony would impart charm and it would attain the perfection of an exquisite beauty … if there be no confusion in its various functions. (1938, I.4, p. 26) John’s conception of political power is ‘an entirely personalised one’ (Nederman, 2005, p. 60), so individual vices take on far greater significance. The first chapter of the Policraticus provides an Augustinian framework for such corruption: ‘the soul is tricked by a multiplicity of allurements into a captivity in which, alienated from itself, inner goodness decays as the desires are extended to the deceptions of various external things’ (1990, I.1, p. 9). Those distractions weaken the individual by distorting their judgment and preventing the habitus of virtuous action to develop. But, they also weaken the state, for a leader who lacks inner and outer harmony transmits this imbalance to the community he governs. The soul that extends itself without restraint in its desire for external pleasures will be just as unrestrained in its desire for power.15 It is not surprising, therefore, to see John call flattery the worst possible vice. Embodying all that the Metalogicon fought against, flattery abuses eloquence by directing it towards pleasing deception rather than wisdom. Its profusion of nonsense distorts the prince’s knowledge of himself and his relationship to the other members of society, loosening the moderation necessary for harmony. The ruler who is unable to assess the proper relationship of words to life throws off the restraints of humility and turns to tyrannical excess (IV.7, pp. 46–49). The imbalance created in the flattered ruler is so grave, in fact, that John proclaims, ‘him whom it is permitted to flatter, it is permitted to slay’ (III.15, p. 25). The extent to which he actually considered tyrannicide justifiable has been debated; nonetheless, such a statement leaves no doubt about his belief in the link between pedagogy and politics.16 Underlying this link is John’s epistemology, which highlights one further element in his political thought. His philosophical scepticism promoted an education that recognises most truths as probabilistic; to achieve a harmonious body politic, its members, and especially its rulers, must recognise the same thing. Liberty, says John, is a prerequisite for virtue; the latter cannot be pursued without the ability to make free choices: ‘to the extent that one is free the virtues are effective’ (VII.25, p. 176). Like a classroom where students do practice exercises, these choices are part of the rooting of knowledge in habitual action, but they also include the possibility of mistakes, to which others must be tolerant. A ruler’s wise restraint and moderation in his own life is a good sign that he will recognise the importance of granting freedom and support to other members of

62

Brian D. FitzGerald

society as they pursue virtue (Forhan, 1992, p. 109). A flattered tyrant is far less willing to listen to critics. Therefore, John insists, ‘it is always permitted to a free man to speak to persons about restraining their vices’ (1990, VII.25, p. 180). The wise use – and the wise reception – of eloquence are crucial elements in a political system that cultivates virtue not only through mutual support, but also through mutual toleration of each others’ liberties. Those are the necessary foundations for building up the bonds of human society.

Conclusion Both Hugh and John, therefore, propose systems where the humble search for wisdom and truth underlies all learning, and where the process of education is a model for how one lives. Augustine, too, understood this to be education’s function, and Hugh and John are clearly indebted to him. Nonetheless, they are not as willing as Augustine (or indeed as predecessors like Cassiodorus or Alcuin) to subordinate everything so firmly to Scripture. For Hugh, a comprehensive vision of the divine presence within the natural world leads him to seek a legitimate and proper place for all forms of knowledge, balancing the new and the old, the sacred and the secular. All these forms contribute to his systematised search for wisdom, marked by the concerns of contemplation: to gain greater awareness of the divine image within. John, on the other hand, places the arts at the service neither of Scripture nor of contemplation but of society, for it is in the realm of utility and action that he primarily envisions the operation of wisdom. Knowledge in pursuit of virtue must be grounded in the practical and the probable. In pedagogy, this means defending the traditional trivium to keep each art in its proper place, while encouraging the latest developments in logic because of their epistemological benefits. In politics, it means articulating the distinct responsibilities of each member for the other to prevent the distortions that weaken communal harmony, while promoting a liberty that requires humble toleration. Jerome Taylor notes that a particular concern of twelfth-century thinkers was ‘the relationship of the entire order of nature to the divine’ (1961, p. 12). For Hugh and for John, education develops man’s natural capacities, making him more aware of who he is and what he is called to be, as image of God or as social creature. Both the contemplative and the politician see education at the heart of humanity’s spiritual renewal. In the following century, as the Paris schools were incorporated as a university, the concerns of Hugh and John did not lose their significance. Indeed they became more acute: the translation of Greek and Arabic texts continued apace, requiring absorption by intellectuals; university curricula became both more organised and more narrowly specialised; and dialectic assumed a greater role in theological and philosophical discourse. Thirteenth-century scholastic philosophers and theologians were certainly concerned with the role of education in spiritual and social renewal, but, by the fourteenth century, the condemnation of scholastic pedagogy and specialised training by Italian humanists such as Petrarch indicated the perception of a lost balance and purpose. Schooling, with its

Medieval theories of education

63

distinctions and disputations, seemed dominated by arid subtilitas, its ethical and civic relevance more and more distant. In the Didascalicon and Metalogicon, though, it is clear that one does not need to wait for the Renaissance to see the answers that would address humanist interests: the need to integrate the classical and Christian traditions, the significance of the verbal arts, and the role of education in transforming not only the intellect but the soul. Augustine had already shown how important solutions to these issues were for medieval Christians, and Hugh and John continued his work while transforming it. Their twelfth-century statements offer insight into the earlier pedagogical traditions while pointing forward to the questions and debates of the centuries to come.

Notes 1 See also Zinn (1995) for the presence and absence of De doctrina christiana in the Didascalicon. 2 See Markus (1996) for an excellent discussion of this aspect of Augustine’s thought. 3 See Sweeney (1995) for a more detailed comparison of the two works. 4 For a discussion of 12th-century divisions of the arts, see Taylor (1961), pp. 7–17. 5 Cf. Hugh (1961) I.8, p. 55. 6 Zinn (1995) describes Hugh’s later development of a more refined distinction between sacred and secular. 7 Sweeney (1995, pp. 63–65) offers more detailed comparisons. 8 Cf. Hugh’s critique of this attitude (1961, V.7, p. 130), as well as Augustine’s rejection of curiositas, e.g. in Confessions X.35. 9 Harkins (2009, pp. 275–276) discusses the significance of this idea for Hugh’s works after Didascalicon. 10 Two influential precedents for a discussion of this relationship – between a person’s moral statements and moral actions – with regard to preachers are De doctrina christiana Book IV and Gregory the Great’s Regula pastoralis. 11 For a discussion of the classical and early medieval sources for this concept, see Kempshall (2008). 12 Augustine treats this sort of scepticism in De magistro and Contra Academicos. 13 There is no complete English translation of this work. In this paper, I quote the partial versions by Pike (the 1938 edition) and Nederman (the 1990 edition). 14 Nederman (2005, p. 60) notes that, in his discussion of tyranny, John spends nearly as much time on ecclesiastical tyrants as secular ones, for members of the clergy could just as easily attempt to upset the balance of power between body and soul. 15 Wilks (1984) gives a more detailed explanation of this relationship. 16 For more on the debates about John’s attitude towards tyranny, see Nederman (2005), pp. 60–62.

Further reading For the Didascalicon, the best current translation is (1961) The Didascalicon of Hugh of St Victor: a medieval guide to the arts (trans. J. Taylor) (London, Columbia University). Taylor’s introduction is an excellent discussion of the text in its historical context. The critical edition is (1939) Hugonis de Sancto Victore Didascalicon de studio legendi (ed. C. H. Buttimer) (Washington, DC, Catholic University). The latest comprehensive discussion of Hugh’s thought is by Paul

64

Brian D. FitzGerald

Rorem (2009) Hugh of St Victor (Oxford, Oxford University Press), and a good overview can also be found in Patrice Sicard (1991) Hugues de Saint-Victor et son école (Turnhout, Brepols). For a contemporary thinker’s meditation on the significance of the Didascalicon, see Ivan Illich (1993) In the vineyard of the text: a commentary to Hugh’s Didascalicon (Chicago, University of Chicago). The English translation of the Metalogicon is (1962) The Metalogicon of John of Salisbury: a twelfth-century defense of the verbal and logical arts of the trivium (trans. D. McGarry) (Berkeley, University of California). The critical Latin edition is (1991) Ioannis Saresberiensis Metalogicon (eds J. B. Hall & K. S. B. Keats-Rohan) (Turnhout, Brepols). Keats-Rohan has also done a critical edition (1993) of Books I–IV of the Policraticus (Turnhout, Brepols). The remainder can be found in C. Webb’s 1909 edition. A recent overview of John’s life and works, with a helpful bibliography of scholarship since 1984, can be found in Cary Nederman (2005) John of Salisbury (Tempe, Arizona Center for Medieval & Renaissance Studies). David Luscombe provides a summary of scholarship before 1984 in (1984) The world of John of Salisbury (ed. M. Wilks) (Oxford, Blackwell). Among the numerous considerations of 12th-century thought and education, several important ones, with references to Hugh and John, are R. W. Southern (1982) The Schools of Paris and the School of Chartres, in: R. Benson & G. Constable (eds) Renaissance and renewal in the twelfth century, 113–137, and (1970) Medieval humanism (Oxford, Blackwell); C. S. Jaeger (1994) The envy of angels: cathedral schools and social ideals in medieval Europe, 950–1200 (Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania); S. Ferruolo (1985) The origins of the university: the schools of Paris and their critics, 1100–1215 (Stanford, Stanford University); and M.-D. Chenu (1997) Nature, man and society in the twelfth century (trans. J. Taylor & L. Little) (Toronto, University of Toronto). For Augustine’s De doctrina christiana, the critical edition is R.P.H. Green (1995) Augustine: De doctrina christiana (Oxford, Oxford Early Christian Texts). A collection of scholarly essays about the text can be found in D. W. H. Arnold & P. Bright (eds) (1995) De doctrina christiana: a classic of western culture (Notre Dame, IN, University of Notre Dame). The influence of the work is assessed in E. D. English (ed.) (1995) Reading and wisdom: the De doctrina christiana of Augustine in the Middle Ages (London, University of Notre Dame).

References Augustine (1992 [397]) Confessions (trans. H. Chadwick) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Augustine (1995 [c. 426–7]) On christian teaching (ed. & trans. R. P. H. Green) (Oxford, Clarendon). Forhan, K. L. (1992) The not-so-divided self: reading Augustine in the twelfth century, Augustiniana, 42, 95–110. Harkins, F. (2009) Reading and the work of restoration: history and scripture in the theology of Hugh of St Victor (Toronto, Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies).

Medieval theories of education

65

Hugh of St Victor (1939 [c.1127]) Hugonis de Sancto Victore Didascalicon de studio legendi (ed. C. H. Buttimer) (Washington, DC, Catholic University). Hugh of St Victor (1961 [c.1127]) The Didascalicon of Hugh of St Victor: a medieval guide to the arts (trans. J. Taylor) (New York, Columbia University). Jerome (1996 [Epistle 70 composed 397]) Sancti Eusebii Hieronymi epistulae (ed. I. Hilberg) (Vienna, Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften). John of Salisbury (1938 [1159]) Frivolities of courtiers and footprints of philosophers, being a translation of the first, second, and third books and selections from the seventh and eighth books of the Policraticus of John of Salisbury (trans. J. Pike) (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota). John of Salisbury (1962 [1159]) The Metalogicon of John of Salisbury: a twelfth-century defense of the verbal and logical arts of the trivium (trans. D. McGarry) (Berkeley, University of California). John of Salisbury (1990 [1159]) Policraticus (trans. C. Nederman) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). John of Salisbury (1991 [1159]) Ioannis Saresberiensis Metalogicon (eds J. B. Hall & K. S. B. Keats-Rohan) (Turnhout, Brepols). Keats-Rohan, K. S. B. (1987) John of Salisbury and education in twelfth century Paris from the account of his Metalogicon, History of Universities, 6, 1–46. Kempshall, M. S. (2008) The virtues of rhetoric: Alcuin’s Disputatio de rhetorica et de virtutibus, Anglo-Saxon England, 37, 7–30. Markus, R. A. (1996) Signs and meanings: world and text in ancient Christianity (Liverpool, Liverpool University). Nederman, C. (1988) Nature, sin and the origins of society: the Ciceronian tradition in medieval political thought, Journal of the History of Ideas, 49, 3–26. Nederman, C. (1989) Knowledge, virtue and the path to wisdom: the unexamined Aristotelianism of John of Salisbury’s Metalogicon, Mediaeval Studies, 51, 268–286. Nederman, C. (1996) The meaning of ‘Aristotelianism’ in medieval moral and political thought, Journal of the History of Ideas, 57, 563–586. Nederman, C. (2002) Mechanics and citizens: the reception of the Aristotelian idea of citizenship in late medieval Europe, Vivarium, 40, 75–102. Nederman, C. (2005) John of Salisbury (Tempe, Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies). Rorem, P. (2009) Hugh of St Victor (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Sweeney, E. (1995) Hugh of St Victor: the Augustinian tradition of sacred and secular reading revised, in: E. D. English (ed.) Reading and wisdom: the De doctrina christiana of Augustine in the middle ages (London, University of Notre Dame), 61–83. Taylor, J. (1961) Introduction, in: (trans. J. Taylor) The Didascalicon of Hugh of St Victor: a medieval guide to the arts (New York, Columbia University), 3–39. Wilks, M. (1984) John of Salisbury and the tyranny of nonsense, in: M. Wilks (ed.) The world of John of Salisbury (Oxford, Blackwell), 263–286. Zinn, G. (1995) The influence of Augustine’s De doctrina christiana upon the writings of Hugh of St Victor, in: E. D. English (ed.) Reading and wisdom: the De doctrina christiana of Augustine in the middle ages (London, University of Notre Dame), pp. 48–60.

5

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia John M. Parrish

Introduction Of the various classical theories of education surveyed in this volume, the contribution of the humanists of the Northern Renaissance – of what came to be known as ‘Erasmian humanism’ – may well be the least familiar to modern students of education. There is some irony in this. The name of Desiderius Erasmus (1466– 1536), though scarcely remembered today beyond the university, was in his own day synonymous with learning and the pursuit of knowledge. The most famous of his associates, Thomas More (1478–1535), is better remembered, but mainly for his martyrdom, and perhaps secondarily for coining the term ‘Utopia’ – but not as a leading exemplar and promoter of the Erasmian humanist approach to learning and knowledge. Other leading Erasmian humanist figures, such as Guillaume Budé or Juan Luis Vives, are now remembered almost exclusively by historians. Yet the contribution made by Erasmus and his circle to the theory and practice of education was as influential as perhaps any of the approaches surveyed in this collection. In the first section of this paper, I will outline the main features of the Erasmian strain of Renaissance humanism, pointing out the main components of that tradition which carried implications for the philosophy of education. In the second section, I will explore in greater detail two specific works of Erasmus – his treatises on The education of a Christian prince (1515) and his later work On the education of children (1529). In the last section I will show how Thomas More’s Utopia (1516), perhaps the most enduring literary achievement of Erasmian humanism, displays the educational philosophy of the movement in such a way as to bring out its larger implications for moral and political theory and practice. Finally, in the paper’s conclusion, I will briefly consider the contemporary legacy of this tradition for educational theory and reform.

Erasmian humanism as an educative movement The idea of education, in its broadest sense, resided at the heart of the intellectual movement we now know as Northern or Erasmian humanism. Erasmus himself, the figure whose name the movement would come to bear, was the

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

67

paramount scholar of his age, and the circle he led was deeply committed to the idea of the liberating power of learning. Its leading lights were men such as Guillaume Budé (1467–1540), Jerome Busleyden (c. 1470–1517), Ulrich von Hutten (1488–1523), Beatus Rhenanus (1485–1547), Juan Luis Vives (1493–1540) and of course Thomas More, among the most significant literary talents and intellectual innovators of their age. (See further Bietenholz & Deutscher, 1985–87.) In some ways the Erasmian movement was a continuation of the particular orientation towards learning sparked in the Italian Renaissance; yet in other respects Erasmian humanism struck out in its own distinctive direction, in ways that were to have consequences particularly for the Protestant Reformation (Phillips, 1949; Kristeller, 1961; Spitz, 1988). From the Renaissance in Italy, the Northern Humanist movement inherited an orientation towards both historicism and the rhetorical arts, emphasising the importance of context in the pursuit of learning (Kristeller, 1961). Among the most important reasons for this change was the re-emergence in late medieval Italy of the ancient city-state forms of government (Skinner, 1978, vol. 1). Confronted simultaneously with the differences between their forms of government and those of their feudal contemporaries on the one hand, and with the similarities between their practices and those of the ancient city-states on the other, leading intellectuals of the Italian Renaissance came to stress the significance of time and historical context in a fashion uncharacteristic of prior medieval thought (Kristeller, 1961; Skinner, 1978, vol. 1). This awareness led Lorenzo Valla (1406–1457), for example, to employ self-consciously historicist methods in order to debunk the fraudulent ‘Donation of Constantine’ document which had helped to validate the papacy’s claim to temporal supremacy (Valla, 1922). The humanists’ emphasis on context derived also from the revival in the late medieval world of awareness about the ancient past. One antecedent of this change was the rediscovery of Aristotle during the thirteenth century, an event which led Thomas Aquinas and his followers to apprehend some of the differences between their age and that of the pre-Christian past (Skinner, 1978, vol. 1, ch. 3). While Aquinas and other scholastics focused on trying to reconcile these differences in order to show the innate compatibility of Christian doctrine with Aristotelian philosophy, later Renaissance figures (including Erasmus and his colleagues) drew a different lesson from the encounter with the ancient past. In this way most of the leading figures of Renaissance humanism came to define their project in explicit opposition to scholasticism. In particular, they criticised the scholastics’ emphasis on speculative philosophy and dialectical logic, which they saw as impractical and pedantic (Augustijn, 1991). These Renaissance thinkers, influenced by the ancient texts they had recently rediscovered (and most particularly by Cicero), came to emphasise the importance of rhetoric as opposed to philosophical logic, and to see the study of literature and oratory, rather than philosophical disputation, as the most worthy scholarly pursuits (Cameron, 1990, p. 148). This also led them to diminish their focus on the recent medieval past and reach back to those ancient sources where rhetoric

68

John M. Parrish

and practical ethics had held the place of honour now reserved for dialectic and speculative philosophy. To a significant degree, the Erasmian movement followed these trends of the Italian Renaissance. Yet within the Erasmian movement these Renaissance orientations combined in rather different ways than they had in Italy. To begin with, the Erasmian movement was consistently a more self-consciously pious undertaking than was true (broadly speaking) of the Italian Renaissance. Most Italian humanists were practising Catholics and some were devout – but their faith did not move to the centre of their work and in particular of their pursuit of learning with quite the consistency that we find in the Erasmian circle (Hexter, 1973, pp. 62–82; McConica, 1991, ch. 4). As with the Renaissance’s revival of the ancient past in general, so too specifically in the area of religion the Erasmian humanists urged a return ad fontes (that is, ‘back to the sources’), replacing contemporary scholastic disputations as the principal texts of scholarship with an attention to the ancient classical, Biblical, and Patristic sources. The emphasis on rhetoric and historical context led these humanists to stress the knowledge of Greek as well as Latin grammar and literature as indispensable to true scholarly learning, and this commitment to the study of language filtered down to each level of educational attainment. In Erasmus, in particular, we find a deliberate revival of the idea of ‘baptising the classics’, derived in part from Erasmus’s beloved St Jerome and in part also from the more developed account offered by St Augustine (Boyle, 1981). This drew in turn on two features of the earlier Italian Renaissance which we have already noted: first, its fascination with and admiration for the intellectual achievements of antiquity; but second, and to some degree opposed, its sense of the historical distance between those practices and the fundamentals of the Christian faith. Following the advice of Augustine and Jerome, the practice of these humanists was to be like the Israelites leaving with spoils of their Egyptian (that is, pagan) captors: they were to take what was useful from pagan society, and abandon what was not (Augustine, 1997, pp. 64–67). Thus the Erasmians, more self-consciously than the Italian humanists, came to see scholarship as an undertaking possessed of its own distinctive form of piety. They upheld the ideal of ‘Christian scholarship’, in which one’s scholarly labours were governed by standards of accuracy that were often critical of conventional religious practice, yet pursued a fundamentally religious purpose: the illumination of God’s truth and the performance of Christ’s ideals in the contemporary world (Harbison, 1956). As a consequence of these factors, Erasmian humanism – in a pronounced and deliberate contrast to the scholastic tradition – focused its attention persistently on the practical, ethical conclusions to be drawn from its religious foundations. Eschewing the speculative concerns of scholastic theology, Erasmian humanism emphasised instead the ‘philosophy of Christ’, exemplified in the challenging but practical moral teachings of (for example) Jesus’s Sermon on the Mount (McConica, 1991, ch. 4). This emphasis found reinforcement in the larger Renaissance orientation toward the elevation of the rhetorical arts over deductive

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

69

logic. Rhetoric was the superior skill because of its practical benefits – it was able not only to identify morally correct conclusions but to move its audience to undertake appropriate practical action in response (Spitz, 1990, p. 207). These commitments of the Northern humanist movement – to antiquity and historical context, to a more Biblically-centred and practically-oriented form of piety – sharply influenced the movement’s approach to the issue of education. In tune with the broader spirit of the Renaissance, Erasmian humanism conceived of education as a method for cultivating human potential and dignity to the fullest possible extent. In keeping with their emphasis on practical piety, these humanists viewed the educative process as not merely the pursuit of knowledge but rather the engendering of virtue through knowledge. The preceding has offered a sketch, necessarily brief and broad, of the general attitudes toward education which arose in the Renaissance in general and among the Northern humanists in particular. In the next two sections, I want to illustrate how those attitudes emerged in the writings of two of the key figures of the movement: Erasmus himself, whose specific writings on education are the focus of the next section, and Thomas More, whose employment of these educational ideas in his literary masterpiece Utopia are the subject of the following section.

Erasmus on education Turning now to Erasmus’s own main texts on education, I want to focus my attention on three issues, each of which is both central to Erasmus’s own educational theory and has been deeply influential on subsequent educational practice. These are: first, his persistent emphasis on the importance of early childhood education; second, his argument that methods of education which amuse and delight students are more effective than those which emphasise coercion and fear; and third, his insistence that the moral dimension of education – an explicit concern with directly cultivating the pupil’s development of virtue and good character through the educative process itself – is not only a legitimate but indeed an indispensable element of the teacher’s task. If there is a single theme most frequently emphasised in Erasmus’s educational writings, it is the importance of early childhood education. It is never too early to begin the process, Erasmus argues, for ‘we can never begin too soon with something that can never be finished’ (De pueris instituendis (hereafter DPI); Collected works (hereafter CWE) v. 26, p. 343). Early education is necessary because of the centrality of learning for human life, for what it means to be human. Repeatedly Erasmus emphasises that someone who lacks education or the desire for wisdom ‘is less than human’ or ‘has no humanity at all’ (Colloquies, ‘The abbot and the learned lady’, CWE v. 39, p. 502; DPI, p. 298; see also DPI p. 301; De recta pronuntiatione (hereafter DRP), CWE v. 26, p. 369). This belief commits Erasmus to promote public responsibility for providing universal education to citizens, for ‘children of commoners are human beings just as much as those of royal family’ (DPI, p. 334). Just as the public takes responsibility to train its soldiers or its church choir members, so too should appropriate training ‘be

70

John M. Parrish

provided by the authorities for those who are to give the young people of the nation a sound education based on humane ideals’ (DPI, p. 333). Parents should therefore begin thinking about providing their children’s education from the moment of conception, for the child’s earliest experiences will have immense consequences for later life (DPI, pp. 309, 319, 323). Several factors make children especially well suited to early learning, in contradistinction to (sixteenth-century) conventional wisdom. First, very young children are exceptionally impressionable, giving them a good memory and a natural aptitude for learning (DPI, p. 297, p. 320). Erasmus stresses this from the first sentence of the De pueris: If you follow my advice … you will see to it that your infant son makes his first acquaintance with a liberal education immediately, while his mind is still uncorrupted and free from distractions, while he is in his most formative and impressionable years, and while his spirit is still open to each and every influence and at the same time highly retentive of what it has grasped; for we remember nothing in old age as well as what we absorbed during our unformed years. (DPI, p. 297) Repeatedly, Erasmus invokes the metaphors of wax, clay and dye wool to illustrate the impressionability of young children (Parallels, CWE v. 26, p. 163; DPI, pp. 305–306, 318–319). In particular, Erasmus points out, very young children are well suited to the acquisition of language, in part because of their natural urge (shared with monkeys) to imitate (DRP, p. 369; DPI, pp. 319–321, 336). So remarkable is this capacity in young children, Erasmus claims, that ‘a German boy could learn French in a few months quite unconsciously while absorbed in other activities’ (DPI, p. 320). Adults avoid learning Latin and especially Greek because of its difficulty; early education is the remedy. And given the centrality of the rhetorical arts to the humanist programme, it is not surprising to find Erasmus claiming that language acquisition is the gateway to ‘intellectual judgment and a mastery of all the branches of knowledge’ (DPI, pp. 320–321). Not every method is suitable to early childhood education, so the instructor must be discriminating. Human flourishing in general depends on three factors, according to Erasmus: nature (i.e., natural character); method (i.e., education); and practice. These form ‘three strands [which] must be intertwined to make a complete cord: nature must be developed by method and method must find its completion in practice’. Thus our natural character is not all-determining; and likewise practical experiences by themselves are not sufficient to supplement it; education or ‘method’ plays the crucial intermediary role. Diverse methods work best with diverse students, just as various methods work best at varying stages of children’s development (DPI, pp. 316, 335–338; Erasmus, Education of a Christian prince (hereafter ECP), p. 12). What links these methods together, distinguishing which method is appropriate at each stage, is the importance of alluring the student to the enjoyment of

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

71

study. This partly involves an accommodation to the frailties of human nature. ‘As physicians do not always prescribe the most efficacious remedies for patients but make some allowance for their cravings’, Erasmus explains, ‘so likewise I thought it well to allure the young – who respond more readily to pleasing than to strict or harsh treatment – with this kind of bait’ (Colloquies, ‘The usefulness of the Colloquies’, CWE vol. 40, p. 1097). It cannot all be fun and games, of course – at some stage, all students must discipline and master themselves so as ‘to find delight in things productive of utility rather than pleasure’ (Colloquies, ‘The art of learning’, CWE v. 40, p. 394). Yet at the same time Erasmus insists that ‘there is nothing which prevents usefulness from going hand in hand with pleasure, and integrity with enjoyment’ (DPI, p. 338). Indeed, this is how we should expect to achieve the most effective results in education. It is easier to go downhill than uphill, easier to sail a ship with the wind and tide than against them – and likewise ‘it is also easier to be taught in a discipline that agrees with our personal inclinations’ (DPI, pp. 316–317, 336). Each individual has their own unique nature, including natural aptitudes for certain subjects – mathematics, theology, language – and ‘we take in most easily the work for which nature designed us’ (DPI, p. 316). In such situations, the educator must accommodate what he is in any event powerless to overcome, and help each individual talent ‘to follow its own spontaneous inclinations’ (DPI, p. 336). The process of alluring begins with the teacher himself. According to Erasmus, it is an absolute ‘prerequisite’ for the learning process to work effectively ‘that the teacher must be liked’, and this is because ‘we learn best when we have the desire to learn; and it is from those whom we like and respect that we learn most eagerly’ (DPI, p. 324). Consequently, the teacher selected should be someone ‘who is able to encourage [the student] by a kind and charming manner, and not someone who will alienate him by a hard demeanor’ (DPI, p. 298; see also pp. 325, 334, 338).1 The same principle further applies to the instructor’s methods of encouragement and correction. The instructor should seek to encourage students where he can, though always ‘with sincerity and on valid grounds’ (ECP, p. 13). To encourage students, he should also design his lessons specifically so as to avoid any unnecessary difficulties for students to encounter, and when a difficulty is unavoidable he should ‘smooth and soften it with an agreeable style of speech’ (ECP, p. 13; DPI, p. 341). When correction is necessary, as it will sometimes be, he should correct the student privately and with ‘a touch of pleasantness in manner’ (ECP, p. 13; DPI, p. 332). Above all, Erasmus returns repeatedly to condemn the harsh and widespread use of corporal punishment in education. Contrary to conventional wisdom, Erasmus insists, coercive practices such as the use of fear and especially beatings in education are unhelpful, unprofitable and unnecessary (Colloquies, ‘Off to school’, CWE, v. 39, p. 114; DPI, pp. 325, 327–328, 331, 333–334). Such tactics are opposed to the free spirit of education, and will drive students either to rebellion or to despair; ‘and once this hatred has been implanted in young minds, the disgust with education will remain through the years of adulthood’ (DPI, p. 325; cf. pp. 326, 331; CWE, v. 26, pp. 327, 331).

72

John M. Parrish

Instead, Erasmus warmly recommends the employment of games and amusements in the educative process. Practically nothing ‘is learned better than what is learned as a game’, Erasmus asserts, and consequently the teacher’s task is ‘to give the course of study the appearance of a game’ (Colloquies, ‘Usefulness’, p. 1098; DPI, p. 341). Children will always be open to anything that can be presented as a game, because ‘play and childhood go naturally together;’ and so if children can be persuaded to ‘think of their activity as play rather than exertion’, the battle is largely won (DPI, p. 341). In addition, educators can employ students’ competitive instincts to motivate them to excel: the desire for praise and fear of shame will drive them to greater achievements, and the teacher, Erasmus somewhat coldly states, ‘should exploit these motives to advance their education’ (DPI, pp. 332, 339–340). Early childhood education matters to Erasmus not only because of the unique capacity of young students for certain kinds of learning, but equally if not more importantly because of its moral dimension.2 Children must be ‘fashioned and instructed from earliest infancy … for true virtue’, Erasmus argues (‘Panegyric for Archduke Philip of Austria’, ECP, p. 143; cf. ECP, p. 54). Failing to take advantage of the blank slate provided by the raw impressionability of youth will invariably result in the child’s eventual moral degeneration (DPI, p. 306). Without this moral dimension of education, other aspects of learning are of limited value (DPI, p. 319). Here, Erasmus again employs his redefinition of ‘philosophy’ to include the ‘philosophy of Christ’: for since a philosopher is ‘someone who rejects illusory appearance and undauntedly seeks out and follows what is true and good’, it follows that ‘being a philosopher is in practice the same as being a Christian; only the terminology is different’ (ECP, p. 15). This also helps to situate in proper context the famous openness of Erasmus’s circle to at least a limited degree of education for women. Though no member of the Erasmian movement went so far as to encourage universal education for women equal to that received by men, it was nevertheless the case that a few women judged exceptionally able were encouraged to attain learning in the humanist style and were praised when they succeeded. Perhaps the most conspicuous instance was the case of Thomas More’s daughter Margaret, who attained literacy not only in English but also in Latin and even Greek and who served as the model for the female character in Erasmus’s colloquy, ‘The abbot and the learned lady’. This openness to education for women is somewhat surprising in Erasmus’s case, since in other respects he was hardly inclined to view women as equal to men in their capacity for learning: for example, he consistently uses the male pronoun only in referring to teachers, and he has some quite unkind things to say about females assigned to serve as teachers (as at DPI, p. 325). Nevertheless, the belief that some women are suitable pupils for a humanist education is clearly sincere and important to Erasmus. This commitment to women’s education is best understood, however, in the context of the movement’s larger commitment to the idea that knowledge is the path to moral virtue. We can see this illustrated in Erasmus’s discussion of Thomas More’s home ‘school’ for his three daughters and son. Describing

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

73

More’s school, Erasmus observes approvingly that More’s experiment has changed his mind to favour providing women with a full humanist education (Erasmus, Letter 1233 to Guillaume Budé, CWE, v. 8, p. 296). Yet the rationale for this experiment is not based on a gender-free view of human equality; it is grounded rather in a deeply gendered perception of women’s appropriate roles in society – and the utility of humanist learning specifically for their good performance of these roles (Erasmus, Letter 1233, p. 296). ‘For two things in particular are perilous to a girl’s virtue, idleness and improper amusements’, Erasmus states, ‘and against both of these the love of literature is a protection’ (Erasmus, Letter 1233, p. 297).3 Thus the education of women is desirable because it is education in moral principles, according to Erasmus’s understanding of the morality of gender roles. Central to Erasmus’s idea of moral education is the need to inoculate the student against the contagion of popular opinion. In ‘The abbot and the learned lady’ Erasmus’s spokesperson (the lady) states that the public is ‘the worst possible authority’ on moral conduct, and that popular custom is ‘the mistress of every vice’ (Colloquies, ‘Abbot’, p. 503). This is perhaps the principal reason why early education is so important: those who delay a child’s education are postponing his learning ‘to an age when his mind will already be less receptive and more subject to grave temptations (which by that time, in fact, may have entangled him completely in their brambles)’ (DPI, p. 299; cf. ECP, pp. 10–11);4 for to inculcate good habits we must first unteach bad ones – and this is far more difficult than teaching virtue in the first place (DPI, pp. 312–313). Instead, the learned lady advises, we should ‘accustom’ ourselves to what is truly virtuous: ‘then the unusual will become habitual, the unpleasant enjoyable, the apparently unseemly, seemly’ (Colloquies, ‘Abbot’, p. 503). The most important element in moral education is therefore habituation, for ‘small acts of goodness, habitually repeated, amount to great virtue’ (DPI, p. 318). Once again, early childhood education is the key to bringing this to fruition. ‘It is the young who most easily acquire the good’, Erasmus argues, ‘since they possess that natural flexibility which enables them to bend in any direction, are not as yet enslaved by bad habits, and are readily inclined to imitate whatever is suggested to them’ (DPI, p. 318). Throughout, Erasmus assumes the correctness of the Socratic notion that virtue is in principle teachable. Since human beings are animals designed for a specific purpose, the virtuous life, it follows that ‘every human being can be taught virtue without any great hardship;’ all that is required to tap into this natural inclination, ‘bursting with life’, is ‘the effort of a dedicated teacher’ (DPI, p. 310). This view leads Erasmus very close to the brink of denying the existence of original sin and postulating that wrongdoing has its roots in society rather than human nature. He does ultimately pull up short of this denial, acknowledging that human beings, even children, are ‘indisputably’ subject to original sin (DPI, p. 321). Indeed, he even uses this acknowledgement to provide another argument for early childhood education; a child’s early years, he tells us, require special care in moral education, since ‘at this stage their behaviour is guided by

74

John M. Parrish

instinct more than by reason, so that they are inclined equally to good and evil – more to the latter, perhaps – and it is always easier to forget good habits than to unlearn bad ones’ (DPI, p. 321; see also ECP, pp. 8–9). But the force of Erasmus’s argument points strongly in the other direction, toward identifying corrupt and irrational social institutions and practices as the key exacerbating conditions of whatever sinfulness may naturally be within the human heart. ‘It is a serious mistake’, Erasmus warns, ‘to think that the character we are born with is all-determining’ (DPI, p. 311). Instead, he argues, ‘the greater portion of this evil stems from corrupting relationships and a misguided education, especially as they affect our early and most impressionable years’ (DPI, p. 321). And since this is so, what is caused by a failure of moral education can be corrected by a proper application of the teacher’s art. The conventional wisdom ‘that children are inclined by nature to evil’ is unfair, Erasmus states; instead, ‘the evil is largely due to ourselves; for it is we who corrupt young minds with evil before we expose them to the good’ (DPI, pp. 312–313). So we should not be surprised that children ‘who have already been schooled in the ways of evil should exhibit so little promise for being trained in the ways of the good’, since ‘the unteaching of bad habits’ is far more difficult than teaching good ones (DPI, pp. 312–313). Thus, in the end Erasmus holds that much if not most of human sin is resistible by means of moral education, for while some part of the development of character and virtue does lie outside our influence, it is also ‘to some extent within our power to prevent degeneration in one who was born good and to improve by training someone born none too good’ (ECP, p. 6). As we will see in the next section, this identification of social evil with a failure of education is central not only to Erasmus’s own educational theory, but also to the most systematic (if also the most elusive) articulation of Erasmian humanism’s potential political applications: Thomas More’s Utopia.

Education in More’s Utopia Having outlined the views on education encountered generally in the Erasmian humanist movement and specifically in Erasmus’s own texts, I now want to turn to the literary product of the movement perhaps most widely known to contemporary readers, Thomas More’s Utopia.5 In doing so, I hope to show both how the institutions of Utopian life illustrate the ideals of the Erasmian approach to education, and also how Utopia reveals what larger social and political implications those ideals in fact carried (though always perceived through the complex ambiguity which characterises Utopia as a whole).6 In the first part of this section, I will briefly show how Utopia appears to accept and endorse the first two aspects of the Erasmian educational programme: early childhood education and the use of delightful and amusing as opposed to coercive methods of instruction. Having established these points, I will then turn to my major purpose in this section of the essay: to show that for More, as for the Erasmian movement more generally, the main importance of these first two points is precisely their contribution toward the third, the explicitly moralistic aims of education. For in

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

75

Utopia, the employment of alluring modes of learning from cradle to grave serves a single purpose: to fashion the virtuous persons and virtuous citizens without which it is impossible to have a flourishing society. (On this theme, see further Skinner, 1987.) The importance of education is a persistent theme throughout Utopia.7 In introducing Utopia, Hythloday stresses that the Utopians’ eagerness to learn is the principal feature that distinguishes them from their European counterparts (p. 39). Hythloday’s principal criticism of European councillors and kings (and by implication, of European readers as well) is their unwillingness to learn what is uncomfortable or unfamiliar (p. 14, and throughout). He illustrates the Utopians’ contrary tendency by noting that 1,200 years ago a shipwreck brought ancient Egyptians and Romans to their island; and due to the Utopians’ eagerness to learn, they soon acquired practically every useful aspect of ancient technology and culture (p. 39). ‘This readiness to learn’, Hythloday argues, is ‘the really important reason for their being better governed and living more happily than we do, though we are not inferior to them in brains or resources’ (p. 40). Education is a lifelong affair in Utopia. Before dawn, at mealtimes, in the evening’s leisure, the Utopians are constantly surrounded by public lectures, thoughtful homilies, table talk with wise elders, and the persistent invitation to learn more (p. 58). All citizens receive vocational training in both agriculture and at least one (and often two) necessary trades – including both men and women (pp. 48–49). More importantly, all citizens also receive a liberal education in the Erasmian model, notwithstanding the fact that only a very few are destined for full-time scholarly careers (pp. 63–64). In addition, much of the society’s plentiful leisure time is devoted to intellectual pursuits, including pre-dawn scholarly lectures that (somewhat implausibly) draw large crowds of eager listeners (p. 50). Love of learning and openness to new ideas runs through every dimension of Utopian life. Their moral philosophy revolves around pleasure, but this does not lead them to hedonism because they explicitly and systematically privilege the pleasures of the mind above any others (pp. 71, 73).8 Their religious practices, likewise, include the belief that God has created the intricacies of nature in order to be admired and studied and that God is pleased by humanity’s careful and curious exploration of nature (p. 76). Their religion also specifies that a Utopian worshipper must display a learner’s open-mindedness toward religious matters: he thanks God for such religious truths as he hopes he has attained, but also remains expressly open to the possibility of social and religious improvements he has not yet encountered (p. 103).9 Even in their military practices, the Utopians celebrate military victories achieved by the cunning of the mind over any other triumph: ‘they boast that they have really acted with manly and virile bravery when they have won a victory such as no animal except man could have achieved – a victory gained by strength of understanding’ (p. 86).10 Moreover, Hythloday tells us that in their educational practices the Utopians specifically employ the Erasmian approach of seeking to make the methods of learning as pleasing as possible. We can see this in the game-like qualities ascribed to their children’s agricultural field trips (p. 49) as well as in their private

76

John M. Parrish

amusements, in which they play two chess-like games in which ‘one number captures another’ or ‘in which the vices fight a battle against the virtues’ (p. 50). Indeed, the Utopians believe that Nature herself, like a good Erasmian humanist educator, teaches her truths to human beings by means of pleasure: she ‘coaxes her children with enticing delight to do what in any case they must do from necessity’ (pp. 73–74). The pervasiveness and allurement of learning in the commonwealth makes education in many respects a democratic activity in Utopia. Indeed, education is so central to their political purposes that according to Hythloday ‘the chief aim of their constitution is that, as far as public needs permit, all citizens should be free to withdraw as much time as possible from the service of the body and devote themselves to the freedom and culture of the mind’, in which they believe ‘lies the happiness of life’ (p. 53; see also p. 59). Yet education also remains an elite activity in the sense that some individuals are chosen for their intellectual promise to pursue full-time scholarship; these are the only Utopians who are exempted from a full day’s work at a trade. Membership in this scholarly class, moreover, is a prerequisite to all public and religious offices in Utopia, making Utopia truly a society in which philosophers rule (p. 52).11 Central to the Utopian vision of education, moreover, is the idea of education for virtue. This is true in part because they hold that the products of learning – or, put another way, the conclusions reached by natural reason – are themselves ultimately synonymous with the requirements of virtue.12 This does not mean of course that learning is thought to replace the conclusions of religion regarding virtue, but rather that learning properly pursued will fulfill them. Though they practise a kind of limited toleration of a wide range of theisms throughout their society, the Utopians do specifically hold that the fundamentals of religious belief are crucial to educating for virtue (p. 102), and it is in part for this reason that the priests supervise the Utopian education system (p. 99).13 Nevertheless, while they recognise the religious basis of virtue, they note that this too is ultimately grounded in natural reason. For since reason (as they believe) indicates the existence of a benevolent God, it follows that omitting this information from our moral reasoning must produce defective conclusions (p. 66).14 The Utopians’ central organising social principle is therefore to ensure that ‘virtue has its reward’ (p. 37). And this leads them to establish a society in which institutions themselves are in the first instance the citizens’ teachers in the ongoing project of moral education. By means of their system of communal ownership and their debasement of gold and jewels (which are used to make chamber pots and children’s toys, respectively), the Utopians systematically teach their citizens contempt for all the vicious preoccupations of European life, including sloth, luxury, and particularly greed (pp. 60–63). Utopian institutions constitute an immersive, even invasive educational environment. From birth onwards, the behaviour of Utopian young people is supervised at every stage by some form of familial or public authority, with the society’s total absence of privacy making for a disciplinary environment rather like Foucault’s panopticism (pp. 58, 101; Foucault, 1977).

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

77

The Utopians’ virtuous attitudes come partly from exposure to good institutions, but also explicitly from ‘instruction and good books’, Hythloday tells us (p. 63). The deliberate combination of learning with moral education is at the heart of the Utopian experiment. In Utopia, Hythloday explains, Instruction in morality and virtue is considered no less important than learning proper. They make every effort to instil in the pupils’ minds, while they are still tender and pliable, principles useful to the commonwealth. What is planted in the minds of children lives on in the minds of grown men and serves greatly to strengthen the commonwealth; its decline can always be traced to vices that arise from wrong attitudes. (p. 99) This is the defect of European educational practice. By not teaching these lessons early, as the Utopians do, Europeans systematically reinforce the sinful and irrational tendencies inherent in the culture. It is on these grounds that Hythloday in Book I criticises European practices of capital punishment for theft as educational failures, reminiscent of ‘bad schoolmasters, who would rather whip their pupils than teach them’ (pp. 15–16). Instead, Hythloday asserts, the source of Europe’s theft problem is its systematic education of people to be thieves. For, Hythloday asks, ‘if you allow young folk to be abominably brought up and their characters corrupted, little by little, from childhood; and if then you punish them as grown-ups for committing the crimes to which their training has consistently inclined them, what else is this, I ask, but first making them thieves and then punishing them for it?’ (p. 20). This is why the Utopians punish lawbreakers raised in Utopia more severely than foreigners, ‘feeling that they are worse and deserve stricter punishment because they had an excellent education and the best of moral training, yet still couldn’t be restrained from wrongdoing’ (p. 78). This is also why the Utopians have no lawyers and very few laws, ‘for their training is such that very few suffice’ (p. 82). Thus ‘More’ the narrator tells us that many of the Utopian practices should instead be seen as sources from which European nations ‘might take lessons in order to correct their errors’ (p. 12). That this combination of humanist learning with moral education expresses More’s own intention can be further seen in his contemporaneous letter to his children’s tutor, William Gonnell, in which he specifically describes his aims for the moral dimension of their educational programme. Throughout his letter, More stresses the close relationship between learning and virtue. Of the two goods, virtue is certainly the most important, More acknowledges; learning indeed is worthless in the absence of true virtue (Letter 20, pp. 103, 106). Fortunately, however, there is no conflict between them. On the contrary, More asserts that the virtues will always prove to be ‘the real and genuine fruits of learning’, and that those who pursue learning with the intent of improving their virtue will find success (Letter 20, p. 105). Furthermore, as More details his account of the moral dimension of the education he desires for his children, we find that it corresponds closely to the design of the

78

John M. Parrish

key institutions of Utopia. The tutor, More says, should continually warn his pupils: to avoid as it were the precipices of pride and haughtiness, and to walk in the pleasant meadows of modesty: not to be dazzled at the sight of gold; not to lament the lack of what they erroneously admire in others; not to think more of themselves for gaudy trappings, nor less for the want of them; not to deform the beauty that nature has given them by neglect, nor to try to heighten it by artifice; to put virtue in the first place among goods, learning in the second; and in their studies to esteem most whatever may teach them piety towards God, charity to all, and modesty and Christian humility in themselves (Letter 20, p. 105). Near the close of the letter, More repeats this theme in words that mirror almost exactly those of Hythloday’s peroration at the end of the discourse of Book II, in which Hythloday asserted that Pride was the only obstacle preventing both rational interest and Christian duty from leading to the creation of Utopian institutions elsewhere (p. 106). This Augustinian sentiment captures not only the central evil in More’s moral system – pride – but also the central intuition behind the Utopian plan to fight that evil – namely, the employment of moral education as the single indispensable point toward which all the other elements aim.15 This same policy is precisely what we find More counselling his own children’s tutor to pursue in carrying out the Erasmian humanist educational programme in the very house Erasmus himself had found to be exemplary of its ideals. But, dear Gonnell, the more do I see the difficulty of getting rid of this pest of pride, the more do I see the necessity of getting to work at it from childhood. For I find no other reason why this inescapable evil so clings to our hearts, than that almost as soon as we are born, it is sown in the tender minds of children by their nurses, it is cultivated by their teachers, it is nourished and brought to maturity by their parents; while no one teaches anything, even the good, without bidding them always to expect praise as the recompense and prize of virtue. Thus long accustomed to magnify praise, they strive to please the greater number (that is, the worse) and end by being ashamed to be good (p. 106). For More in reality, no less than for Hythloday in Utopia, the key to proper education lay in employing an early and comprehensively moral education to liberate the learner from vicious custom and open her horizons to the delights of true virtue.

The Erasmian legacy In some ways the most significant influence of Erasmian humanism on educational practice emerged within a few decades, as the Protestant Reformation

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

79

which drew so heavily on the ideas of Erasmian humanism came to transform the social world of early modern Europe, including, conspicuously, its educational practices. Though Erasmus and most of his humanist colleagues remained devout Catholics (some more devout than others), the leading lights of the Reformation, including specifically Martin Luther, Philipp Melancthon, Ulrich Zwingli, and John Calvin, drew heavily on key features of the Erasmian humanist movement, including several aspects of its attitude toward education. Like the Erasmian humanists, Reformation leaders emphasised a return to ancient sources, though these were mainly Biblical and Patristic rather than classical; and the elevation of the ministry of preaching in Protestant practice to a greater centrality than ever helped to cement much of the Erasmian humanists’ emphasis on rhetoric and composition as key educational skills (Spitz, 1990, p. 215). The Reformers’ simultaneous challenge to the twin pillars of medieval learning, monasticism and scholasticism, helped undermine their centrality to European thinking about the life of the mind. In their place, the Protestant Reformers helped to complete the Erasmian project of moving formal education to a central place in cultural life, leading to the institution of universal, compulsory education, frequently for both genders, as an increasingly probable option within Protestant society (Spitz, 1990, p. 215). Similarly, many aspects of the Catholic Counter-Reformation responded to these trends by increasing its own emphasis on (orthodox) education, perhaps most notably in the institution of the Jesuit order, with its educational philosophy so deeply grounded in the methods of Erasmian humanism (Olin, 1994, ch. 6). In a broader sense, however, the most lasting impact of Erasmus and his circle upon education may lie not with its immediate influence on the Reformation but rather with its exemplification and institutionalisation of the intellectual ideals of Renaissance humanism within Western culture generally and educational practice specifically. Within a century, Erasmus’s Colloquies had become a staple of European schoolrooms (McConica, 1991, p. 85), and thus their moral lessons and the humanist sensibility implicit within them filtered through to the larger culture. Erasmus’s own persistent concern with the importance of early childhood education and his encouragement of playful and pleasing modes of pedagogy – both driven, as we have seen, by key tenets of the Renaissance humanists’ intellectual agenda – have of course become two of the central premises of contemporary educational practice throughout the world. What has perhaps been lost to some degree is the Erasmian humanists’ insistence on the importance of explicit cultivation of virtue in the educational process. Yet this emphasis was derived from premises equally central to Renaissance humanism and, as we have seen, inseparably linked in Erasmus’s mind to his arguments for early education and alluring pedagogy. While modern thought has largely abandoned the robust conception of original sin which Erasmus criticised, it has not replaced it with what Erasmus thought was necessarily implied: an ethicallysaturated education designed to eliminate society’s pathologies from the ground up. In part this is because of factors such as a rapidly expanding pluralism of religious and moral beliefs, which Erasmus at the outset of the Reformation

80

John M. Parrish

could hardly have imagined, and which continues to pose serious and significant problems for any sort of programme of ‘education for virtue’. But since modern society also continues to cherish the Erasmian dream (pictured in More’s Utopia) of a society whose problems can be reformed through addressing their root causes, it might be well for us to consider again whether this is possible without an educational policy which seeks more aggressively to cultivate from earliest childhood the virtues necessary for citizenship and for individual flourishing within a good society.

Acknowledgements I am indebted to Christopher Brooke and Thomas I. White for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper; and to Kenneth Chatlos, not only for his thoughts regarding this paper, but also for first introducing me to Erasmus, More’s Utopia, and the study of the history of ideas.

Notes 1 Erasmus favours the sixteenth-century equivalent of ‘merit pay’ rather than equal compensation for teachers (see DRP, p. 376). 2 The centrality of moral education to Erasmus’s educational programme is presumably why he counted such morally-charged fictions as The praise of folly and The complaint of peace among his ‘educational works’. See Rummel, 2004, p. 14. 3 More also argues a similar point in Selected Letters, Letter 20 (to William Gonnell), p. 104. 4 On the importance of having a ‘blank slate’ to work with in moral education, see also ECP, p. 5, pp. 11–12. 5 Throughout this section I rely on the premise that More’s views in Utopia are representative of the general commitments of Erasmian humanism. For a careful argument of this point and a response to important counterarguments, see Hexter, 1973, pp. 57–82. 6 It is impossible to present a brief discussion of Utopia that does full justice to the complexity of its argumentative ambiguities and interpretive puzzles. Here I assume as a point of departure that generally (though not without complication) More intends Utopian institutions to be taken as at least a semi-serious model for the reform of European institutions. I offer an argument for what I merely assume here in Parrish, 2007, ch. 3. On the political ideals of the Erasmian humanists, see Tracy, 1978. 7 Throughout this section I am indebted to the detailed discussion of these themes in Surtz, 1957. 8 It is not accidental that the section on the Utopians’ moral philosophy is followed directly by Hythloday’s observation that ‘in intellectual pursuits they are tireless’, and by his account of their eager acquisition and immediate application of the ancient Greek literature Hythloday happens to carry with him (pp. 75–76). 9 On the significance of the Utopians’ religious practices for interpreting More’s intentions, see Fox, 1982. 10 Their good education also strengthens their effectiveness in battle, since, having ‘been trained from infancy in sound principles of conduct (which their education and the good institutions of their society both reinforce)’, they are more likely to exhibit true courage and sound judgment in battle (p. 90). 11 These ‘philosopher-kings’ are philosophers more in the ‘philosophy of Christ’ sense than in the more familiar medieval or scholastic sense, according to Hythloday; the

Education, Erasmian humanism, and More’s Utopia

12 13 14

15

81

Utopians apparently share the Erasmian humanists’ distaste for the logical quibbles of scholasticism (p. 64). On the Utopians’ moral philosophy, see further Logan, 1983. It is also in part because the priests are consistently among the best educated people in the society, as noted above. They do also acknowledge that natural reason can be misled and thus can be overridden by the truths of divine revelation, though conspicuously there is no such direct revelation visible in Utopia (p. 74). Erasmus reports that More gave public lectures on the political aspects of Augustine’s City of God, in Letter 1233.

References Augustijn, C. (1991) Erasmus: his life, works, and influence (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Augustine, St (1997) On Christian teaching (trans. & ed. R. P. H. Green) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Bietenholz, P. G. & Deutscher, T. B. (1985–87) Contemporaries of Erasmus: a biographical register of the Renaissance and Reformation (3 vols) (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Boyle, M. O. (1981) Christening pagan mysteries: Erasmus in pursuit of wisdom (Buffalo, University of Toronto Press). Cameron, J. (1990) Humanism in the Low Countries, in: A. Goodman & A. MacKay (eds) The impact of humanism on Western Europe (New York, Longman). Erasmus, D. (1974–) The collected works of Erasmus (Toronto, University of Toronto Press) (cited as CWE). Erasmus, D. (1997) The education of a Christian prince (trans. N. M. Cheshire & M. J. Heath; ed. L. Jardine) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press) (cited as ECP). Foucault, M. (1977) Discipline and punish: the birth of the prison (New York, Vintage). Fox, A. (1982) Thomas More: history and providence (New Haven, Yale University Press). Harbison, E. H. (1956) The Christian scholar in the age of the Reformation (New York, Scribner). Hexter, J. H. (1973) The vision of politics on the eve of the Reformation: More, Machiavelli, Seyssel (New York, Basic Books). Logan, G. M. (1983) The meaning of More’s Utopia (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Kristeller, P. O. (1961) Renaissance thought: the classic, scholastic, and humanistic strains (New York, Harper & Row). McConica, J. (1991) Erasmus (Oxford, Oxford University Press). More, T. (1967) St Thomas More: selected letters, revised edn. (ed. E. Rogers) (New Haven, Yale University Press). More, T. (2002) Utopia, revised edn. (eds G. M. Logan & R. M. Adams) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Olin, J. C. (1994) Erasmus, Utopia, and the Jesuits: essays on the outreach of humanism (New York, Fordham University Press). Parrish, J. M. (2007) Paradoxes of political ethics: from dirty hands to the invisible hand (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Phillips, M. M. (1949) Erasmus and the northern Renaissance (London, English Universities Presses). Rummel, E. (2004) Erasmus (New York, Continuum).

82

John M. Parrish

Skinner, Q. R. D. (1978) The foundations of modern political thought (2 vols) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Skinner, Q. R. D. (1987) Sir Thomas More’s Utopia and the language of Renaissance humanism, in: A. Pagden (ed.) The languages of political theory in early modern Europe (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Spitz, L. W. (1988) Humanism and the Protestant Reformation, in: A. Rabil, Jr. (ed.) Renaissance humanism: foundations, forms, and legacy (3 vols) (Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press). Spitz, L. W. (1990) Humanism in Germany, in: A. Goodman & A. MacKay (eds) The impact of humanism on Western Europe (New York, Longman). Surtz, E. (1957) The praise of pleasure: philosophy, education, and communism in More’s Utopia (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Tracy, J. D. (1978) The politics of Erasmus: a pacifist intellectual and his political milieu (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Valla, L. (1922) The treatise of Lorenzo Valla on the Donation of Constantine (trans. C. B. Coleman) (New Haven, Yale University Press).

6

Teaching the Leviathan Thomas Hobbes on education Teresa M. Bejan

I Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) is not primarily regarded as a philosopher of education; however, the only firm policy recommendation he made in his Leviathan (1651) was for the immediate reform of university teaching by the sovereign power.1 After initially coyly skirting the issue of who, in his view, might be competent to teach the universities – ‘any man that sees what I am doing may easily perceive what I think’ – he subsequently declared his hope that, at ‘one time or other this writing of mine may fall into the hands of a sovereign’ who will ensure ‘the public teaching of it’ (30:14, p. 226; 31:41, pp. 243–244). The sovereign monarch or assembly should also see to it that other doctrine be censored and their teaching suppressed, so that none but true – that is, Hobbesian – doctrines might be put before the people (18:9, p. 113). Once taken, Hobbes thought these steps might enable him to surpass even Plato by successfully ‘convert[ing] this truth of speculation into the utility of practice’ (31:41, p. 244). At least one of Hobbes’s contemporaries approved of his proposed curricular reform. In Academiarum examen, John Webster cited Hobbes favourably in his own case for reform and echoed the suggestion that the works of Aristotle (especially the Politics) might profitably be replaced, as ‘our own Countreyman master Hobbs hath pieces of more exquisiteness, and profundity in that subject, than ever the Graecian was able to reach unto’ (1654, p. 88). (Webster was a radical supporter of Cromwell, and an advocate of ‘natural magic’, so Hobbes would have agreed with him on little else (Jesseph, 1999, pp. 63–68).) Others, however, alternated between horror and incredulity. John Wallis (Savilian Professor of Geometry), Seth Ward (Savilian Professor of Astronomy) and John Wilkins (Warden of Wadham College, Oxford) took obvious pleasure in mocking Hobbes publicly for what they saw as his supreme arrogance. ‘He doth not spare to professe, upon all occasions’, sneered Wallis, ‘how incomparably he thinks Himself to have surpassed All, Ancient, Modern, Schools, Academies, Persons, [and] Societies … and What Hopes he hath, That, by the soveraign command of some Absolute Prince … his new Dictates should be peremptorily imposed, to be alone taught’ (Wallis, 1662, p. 3). Of the so-called ‘Hobbe-goblin’, Ward and Wilkins

84

Teresa M. Bejan

declared it ‘manifest, that the only thing which paines him is the desire that Aristotelity may be changed into Hobbeity, insteed of the Stagyrite, the world may adore the great Malmesburian Phylosopher’ (Ward & Wilkins, 1654, pp. 54, 58). (For background, Jesseph, 1999; Malcolm, 2002, pp. 317–335; Skinner, 2002, pp. 328–331.) Hobbes did not quail in the face of such criticisms. In his response to the ‘egregious professors’, he argued that his proposed reforms followed necessarily from an analysis of England’s late civil wars. In particular, ‘the cause of my writing [Leviathan]’, he explained, ‘was the consideration of what the ministers … by their preaching and writing did contribute thereunto’ – namely, the dissemination by them and other gentlemen of false and seditious doctrines, received first from their studies in the universities and spread thereafter to the whole English people. Convinced, as he was, that such teaching had caused the war and, furthermore, that he had at last demonstrated true civil doctrine in Leviathan, how could he fail to recommend it? Thus, ‘to me … that never did write anything in philosophy to show my wit, but, as I thought at least, to benefit some part or other of mankind, it was very necessary to commend my doctrine to such men as should have the power and right to regulate the Universities’ (Six lessons, 335). Though the ensuing controversy focused on Leviathan, Hobbes had been arguing along similar lines since the very earliest version of his political philosophy, The elements of law, circulated privately in 1640. There, he confidently declared that ‘if the true doctrine … were perspicuously set down, and taught in the Universities’, young men ‘would more easily receive the same, and afterward teach it to the people, both in books and otherwise, than now they do the contrary’ (29:8, pp. 176–177). Two years later, in De cive, he again insisted that ‘it is a duty of sovereigns to have … the true Elements of civil doctrine written and to order that it be taught in all the Universities in the commonwealth’ (13:9, p. 147). Neither regicide nor Restoration changed his mind; in Behemoth, finished in 1668, he described how ‘the people were corrupted generally’ by erroneous opinions spread by the preachers and ‘democratical gentlemen’ educated in the universities – notwithstanding the fact that the ‘rules of just and unjust sufficiently demonstrated, and from principles evident to the meanest capacity, [had] not been wanting’ (pp. 2, 26, 39–40). Consequently, the common people were ignorant of their true civic duty, which consisted simply in obedience to their rightful sovereign, and were thereafter easily manipulated by their teachers into rebellion against him (p. 39). The universities, in educating the educators of the people, had thus been ‘to this nation, as the wooden horse was to the Trojans’ (p. 40). Throughout, Hobbes maintained that although the educational situation was dire, the means to its amelioration remained straightforward. The disease itself suggested the cure: For seeing the Universities are the fountains of civil and moral doctrine, from whence the preachers and the gentry, drawing such water as they find,

Teaching the Leviathan

85

use to sprinkle the same … upon the people, there ought certainly to be great care taken to have it pure … and by that means, the most men, knowing their duties, will be the less subject to serve the ambition of a few discontented persons … . (Leviathan, ‘Review & conclusion’, p. 496) The universities’ very success in sowing rebellion offered hope for a peaceful future. Just as they had facilitated and exploited the people’s ignorance, he argued, they could be made to serve the opposite end. University reform for Hobbes did not concern higher education alone but rather the civic education of the entire commonwealth, and hence it was a matter of supreme political importance. As the recent civil wars had demonstrated, ‘where the people are not well instructed in their duty’, the peace of the commonwealth will be perpetually disturbed (Leviathan, 19:9, p. 122). In order to maintain peace, force was not enough; subjects must also be taught (Behemoth, p. 59). Sovereigns who failed to exercise their rights in overseeing the people’s education were not only shortsighted, they were guilty of neglecting the very end for which sovereignty was instituted. ‘The actions of men proceed from their opinions’, Hobbes explained, and ‘in the well-governing of opinions consisteth the well-governing of men’s actions, in order to their peace and concord’ (Leviathan, 18:9, p. 113). Hence education of the people in true civic doctrine was, he insisted, an essential duty of the sovereign power (30:6, p. 222). The conclusion that popular education was of paramount political importance derived for Hobbes from his conviction that the sovereign’s authority rested ultimately on the public opinion of his power and hence was ‘grounded on the consent of the people and their promise to obey him’ (Leviathan, 40:6, p. 319). Far from being merely a curious digression or megalomaniacal outburst, Hobbes’s proposed reform of the universities in Leviathan was instead a central and urgent conclusion of his civil science, and despite the prominence of the universities in his discussion, his educational aspirations extended well beyond hopes for a trickle-down enlightenment. His writings reveal instead a programme for truly universal civic education, effected through a variety of channels. This comprehensive instruction of the commonwealth would require Hobbes’s civil doctrine to be taught to people at all levels of society and at every stage of life. Not only the universities, but also the pulpit and the family must be made to serve the educational aims of the commonwealth, and these must furthermore be supplemented with sovereign assiduity in suppressing dissent. Hobbes hoped that the sovereign might thereby educate a true ‘public’, characterised not only by consensus, but by ‘a real unity of them all’ (Leviathan, 17:13, p. 109).

II Hobbes owed his own prominence to his education. Born into obscurity in Westport (near Malmesbury in Wiltshire) in 1588, his proficiency with classical languages saw him through to Oxford at the age of fourteen. He learned his

86

Teresa M. Bejan

languages under the tutelage of Robert Latimer, a graduate of Oxford who ran a small school in Westport. After graduation, Hobbes went to work as a tutor to the Cavendish family. Such service in noble households was a common path for young men of talent and education but little means. Over the next thirty years, Hobbes was a tutor three times over, while also serving as a companion and personal secretary. In light of his aspirations in Leviathan to be a teacher of sovereigns in true civil doctrine, it is notable that he served as a tutor (if only in geometry) to the Prince of Wales and other members of the nobility in exile while in France during the 1640s (Skinner, 1996, pp. 19–26, 217–221). At the time of the first civil war, England had reached the zenith of a remarkable educational expansion at all levels, from the ubiquitous petty schools responsible for teaching basic literacy, through the grammar schools, to the universities (Stone, 1964, pp. 42–44). It is likely that over half of the male population of London was literate, and in the 1630s enrollment at Oxford and Cambridge was at an historic high (Stone, 1964, pp. 68–69, 78). By 1642 the leaders in Parliament were an especially well-educated group, a fact that was not lost on Hobbes and undoubtedly contributed to his assessment of the universities as the very ‘core of rebellion’. After all, ‘it is a hard matter for men, who do all think highly of their own wits, when they have acquired the learning of the university, to be persuaded that they want any ability requisite for the government of a commonwealth’ (Behemoth, p. 23). Hobbes was not alone in blaming England’s system of education for the problems of the day, and cries for educational reform were to be heard from many quarters. In 1644, John Milton called ‘the reforming of Education … one of the greatest and noblest designs that can be thought on, and for the want whereof this nation perishes’ (1953, p. 363). Yet reform entailed very different things for different people. Milton favoured an elite education in (overtly republican) civic virtue (1953, pp. 413–414). For others, such as James Howell, the high level of education seemed itself to be the problem, leading to the conclusion that ‘so many Free-Schools do rather hurt than good’. Bacon himself had written in 1611: ‘Concerning the advancement of learning … for grammar schools there are already too many, and therefore no providence to add where there is excess … there being more scholars bred than the state can prefer and employ … which fills the realm full of indigent, idle and wanton people which are but materia rerum novarum’ (both quoted in Cressy, 1975, pp. 24–25, 27). Still others agreed with Hobbes that the problem was not an educated populace per se, but rather that their miseducation had left the people lacking in virtue; what was needed, then, was closer attention by the government to the further expansion of education and its scrupulous regulation. Samuel Hartlib described the magistrate’s ‘Duty towards the Young ones’ to ‘Order the Meanes of their Education aright, to which effect he should see Schools opened, provided with teachers, endued with Maintenance, regulated with Constitutions, and hee should have Inspectors and Overseers to looke to the observance of good Orders in this businesse’ (Considerations tending towards England’s Reformation, 1647). Hartlib and his associates, including John Dury and Jan Comenius, argued for

Teaching the Leviathan

87

public provision of education with the intention of improving the people in (mostly Christian) virtue (Turnbull, 1947; Webster, 1970). Nor was Hobbes alone in turning special attention to the universities. Figures as different politically as he and the republican Milton could agree with a radical Leveller like Gerrard Winstanley that the universities were, by and large, ‘standing ponds of stinking water’ (quoted in Solt, 1956, p. 310). In the Grand Remonstrance of 1641, the Long Parliament itself (in language echoed by Hobbes) declared the need ‘to reform and purge the fountains of learning, the two Universities, that the streams flowing from thence may be clear and pure, and an honour and comfort to the whole land’ (Gardiner, 1906, p. 230). Despite these good intentions, the state of education suffered because of the war, with many schools closing and university enrollment falling sharply. Yet even as the situation worsened and Parliament was forced to turn its attention elsewhere, educational reform movements in England flourished (Stone, 1964, p. 51; Cressy, 1975, pp. 10–11). Although he had graduated from Oxford more than forty years before the publication of Leviathan, Hobbes claimed to be well qualified to criticise the university curriculum. Ward and Wilkins complained that his criticisms could hardly claim to be current given his advanced age, and despite its mean-spiritedness there was something to this assessment (pp. 58–59). It seems clear that at the time Aristotle and scholasticism were hardly the monolithic presences Hobbes described in Leviathan – Wilkins himself had openly attacked the authority of Aristotle from within the university in the 1630s (Curtis, 1959, pp. 241; Malcolm, 2002, pp. 4–5). Still, Hobbes was joined by many of his younger contemporaries in deriding what they perceived as the lasting influence of scholasticism on university teaching. The virulent dislike of anything hinting of Roman ‘Anti-Christianity’ amounted to a kind of ecumenical anti-Catholicism, leading to a remarkable convergence between figures as different in politics and religion as Hobbes, Milton, Webster, and the Comenians on this issue. Throughout Leviathan, Hobbes criticised the ‘Schools’ and the ‘Schoolmen’ and accused them of trafficking in ‘vain philosophy’ characterised by absurdities and ‘insignificant speech’ (‘Review & conclusion’, pp. 457–458; 1:5, p. 7). Instead of devoting themselves to preaching sound morals and civil obedience, the university-trained divines bewildered the people with concepts like ‘freedom of will, incorporeal substance, everlasting nows, ubiquities, [and] hypostases’, all of which were unable to raise clear, corresponding concepts in the mind and so were, strictly speaking, nonsensical (Behemoth, p. 58). Hobbes suggested that this ‘philosophy’ was a kind of learned madness and likened its purveyors to ‘beggars, when they say their paternoster, putting together such words and in such a manner, as in their education they have learned from their nurses … [yet] having no images or conceptions in their mind’ (Elements, 10:9-10, p. 63; 5:14, p. 39). Such rote learning could not constitute knowledge for the same reason a parrot could not be considered to know the truth, though it recite true sentences perfectly (6:3, p. 41). Such an education, Hobbes insisted, served only to stupefy and dull the wits of students. It was little wonder, then, that philosophy no longer resembled the

88

Teresa M. Bejan

scientific pursuit of truth but rather the parroting of certain authoritative authors. Chief among these, of course, was Aristotle – so much so that philosophy in the universities was, according to Hobbes, no more than ‘Aristotelity’ (Leviathan, 46:13, p. 458). Hobbes held the Stagyrite to be doubly guilty for England’s educational woes: he blamed Aristotle not only for inspiring much scholastic absurdity, but also for the current vogue for Greek and Roman thought more generally, on account of which young men now subjugated their understandings to ‘Aristotle, Cicero, Seneca, and others of like authority’, accepting their definitions of ‘right and wrong, [and] good and bad’ unquestioningly (Elements of law, 27:13, pp. 170–171). Ward and Wilkins took these criticisms to mean that Hobbes thought the universities too hostile to free inquiry and expression, and so responded that those familiar with the universities ‘do know that there is not to be wished a more generall liberty in point of judgment and debate, then what is here allowed’ (1654, p. 2). Hobbes’s objection, however, was not that the universities allowed insufficient freedom of expression. On the contrary, when it came to the expression of beliefs he thought that students were simply subjecting their understandings to the wrong authorities – i.e. not the sovereign. For Hobbes, the uncritical embrace of anti-monarchical and ‘democratical’ notions by English republicans had plainly contributed to the recent revolution. ‘In these western parts of the world’, he complained, ‘we are made to receive our opinions concerning the institution and rights of commonwealth from … Greeks and Romans’, whose own judgments in favour of democracies or republics came from the security and honours that they had happened to enjoy within them. Those living under other regimes, however, mistook this preference for superiority in principle, and ‘by [the] reading of these Greek and Latin authors … from their childhood have gotten a habit (under a false show of liberty) of favoring tumults and licentious controlling of the actions of their sovereigns’ (Leviathan, 21:9, pp. 140–141). Such political notions gratified the ambitions of certain men, who ‘out of their readings of Tully, Seneca, or other anti-monarchics’ came to ‘think themselves sufficient politics, and show their discontent when they are not called to the management of the state’ (Behemoth, pp. 155–156). For Hobbes, the self-interested embrace by ‘democratical gentlemen’ of republican ideals in politics and religion (such, he thought, was the appeal of Presbyterian church-government) directly caused ‘the effusion of so much blood as I think I may truly say: there was never anything so dearly bought, as these western parts have bought the learning of the Greek and Latin tongues’ (Leviathan, 21:9, p. 141). England’s late misfortunes thus stemmed from the dual influences of scholasticism and the ancients on the universities – and unfortunately their negative effects had not been limited to those there educated. Dazzled by the ‘subtile doctrines’ preached by the university-educated clergy, the common people were led to turn against their lawful sovereign (Behemoth, p. 43). Hobbes argued that a number of specific seditious doctrines could be traced directly to scholastic or classical sources, including: (1) that sovereignty could be divided or limited;

Teaching the Leviathan

89

(2) that every private man could rightly judge good and evil for himself; (3) that to act against one’s conscience is a sin; (4) that private men have an absolute right in their property; and (5) that citizens in a democracy or republic enjoy liberty, while subjects in a monarchy are slaves (Leviathan, 29:6-14, pp. 212–215). The people called for reform on the basis of these and other errors and so, ‘like the foolish daughters of Peleus (in the fable) which, desiring to renew the youth of their decrepit father, did by the counsel of Medea cut him in pieces’, they brought about the commonwealth’s destruction (30:7, p. 222). Hobbes was not alone in believing the teaching of classical authors to have vicious effects upon the populace. Comenius, for example, held that ‘such a reformation of Schooles as is according to the rules of true Christianity’ required such ‘profane and heathen Authors … [be] quite rejected’ (quoted in Milton, 1953, p. 192). Hobbes was more moderate and argued that the sovereign must not allow ‘such books to be publicly read without present applying such correctives of discreet masters as are fit to take away their venom’ (Leviathan, 29:14, p. 215).2 Nor were his proposed reforms unusually extreme. Milton (one of the ‘democratical’ gentlemen in question) advocated that the universities be abolished altogether, a measure proposed in earnest in the Barebones Parliament of 1653 (Milton, 1953, p. 364; Malcolm, 2002, p. 326). Hobbes’s argument was by contrast relatively mild. Despite their shortcomings the universities were ‘not to be cast away, but to be better disciplined: that is to say, that the politics there taught be made to be (as true politics should be) such as are fit to make men know, that it is their duty to obey’ (Behemoth, p. 58).3 These ‘true politics’ were, of course, to be found in his Leviathan, and so Hobbes seemed to suggest that by tweaking the curriculum, the universities might easily be made to undo the harm they had done and be turned instead to the maintenance of peace and order.

III In his response to the ‘egregious professors’, Hobbes explained that his recommendation that Leviathan be taught in the universities did not mean necessarily the book itself, but rather its ‘doctrine’ – ‘for wiser men may so digest the same as to fit it better for public teaching’ (pp. 335–336). This doctrine was no more than the existence of a ‘mutual relation between protection and obedience’, which required an ‘inviolable observation’ (Leviathan, ‘Review & conclusion’, p. 497). Hobbes claimed that his conclusions were truly universal. The requirements for peace in all commonwealths, regardless of regime, were first, the absolute right of sovereigns to command, and second, the absolute duty of the people to obey. The obligation of subjects to the sovereign is understood to last as long and no longer ‘than the power lasteth by which he is able to protect them … the end of obedience is protection’ (Leviathan, 21:21, p. 144). Hobbes is clear that a subject can never alienate his right to resistance should the sovereign directly threaten his life. A sovereign, of course, could treat his subjects so terribly that they had no choice but to rebel. However, until the point where he

90

Teresa M. Bejan

was no longer ensuring their protection, such action by subjects could be neither righteous nor just. Civic virtue, then, consisted simply of obedience to the commands of the sovereign and the civil laws. This proposed unity of virtue was a firm rejection of the idea that civic virtue was relative to regime – and that the most virtuous citizens belonged to the best (republican) commonwealths. For Hobbes, the best regime was always the present one, that is, the one currently ensuring the security of citizens.4 Hobbes drew these conclusions from the (as he thought it) universally acceptable premise ‘that peace is good’ (De cive, 3:31, p. 55). According to his civil science – and confirmed, as he thought, by experience – mankind is naturally inclined to disagreement and discord because individuals left to their private judgment will judge according to their different personal perspectives and interests. Under such conditions it is no wonder that men can scarcely agree as to the meanings of words, let alone in their evaluations of right or wrong or just and unjust. In the absence of laws and of a sovereign power to enforce them, this diversity of opinion would lead necessarily to a war of all against all, wherein individuals would live in a state of ‘continual fear and danger of violent death’ and in which ‘the life of man, [is] solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short’ (Leviathan, 13:9, p. 76). Peace requires consensus and concord; thus, individuals must agree to foreswear their ‘private reason’ and submit to the unitary ‘public reason’ of the commonwealth – that is, the judgment of the sovereign alone (37:13, p. 300). Hobbes did not think that a perfect consensus (in the sense of genuine agreement) on controversial matters was possible, but rather that by submitting to the sovereign’s judgment in matters of the expression of disagreement, the outward appearance of consensus might be achieved. ‘There is virtually no dogma either in religion or the human sciences, from which disagreements may not arise and from them conflicts … one cannot prevent such disagreements from occurring. However, by the use of sovereign power they can be kept from interfering with the public peace’ (De cive, 6.11n, p. 81). This outward consensus, maintained through energetic regulation of education and public expression by the sovereign, would be sufficient for peace, though thought itself would necessarily remain free.5 Once this natural diversity in judgment is reduced to the unity of the sovereign’s public reason, the civil laws will become the rule of all men’s actions and the final authority in controversial matters, such as ‘whether they be right or wrong, profitable or unprofitable, virtuous or vicious’ or (especially) just or unjust. This sovereign right of authoritative determination, Hobbes insisted, would extend even unto the definitions of words, insofar as they tended to controversy. The definition of the term ‘human being’, for instance, cannot be decided ultimately by private men or philosophers, but only by the laws (Elements, 29:8, pp. 180–181).6 The subjection of individuals’ judgment to the sovereign’s was especially necessary in matters of religion. Individual claims of conscience were merely attempts by subjects to make themselves judges in matters that were properly the province of the sovereign. ‘The law is the public conscience’, he argued, ‘by which [the citizen] hath already undertaken to be

Teaching the Leviathan

91

guided’ (Leviathan, 29:7, p. 212). Not only is the sovereign the supreme definer of words and judge in temporal matters, he must also be acknowledged as the sole interpreter of Scripture and of God’s will on earth. Although Hobbes conceded that the sovereign could err and sin against the law of nature (which dictates peace), individuals could never claim the right to judge the matter for themselves.7 The doctrine of Leviathan emphasised above all the tenuousness of the peace secured by the commonwealth and the great risks attendant on any act of disobedience. Throughout his writings, Hobbes cast education in true civil doctrine as a necessary supplement to the ‘coercive power to compel men to the performance of their covenants’ exercised by the sovereign (Leviathan, 15:3, p. 89). In order to govern men’s opinions, one must first recognise that ‘opinions are sown in men’s minds not by commanding but by teaching, not by threat of penalties but by perspicuity of reasons’ (De cive, 13:9, p. 146).8 This is in keeping with Hobbes’s assertion in Leviathan that the sovereign has a duty to teach the people ‘the grounds and reasons’ of the rights of sovereignty ‘diligently and truly … because they cannot be maintained by any civil law or terror of legal punishment’ (30: 4, p. 220). Some contemporary readers have cited these statements alongside his appeals to ‘public reason’ as evidence against the traditional view that Hobbes relied entirely on self-interest and the fear of violent death in ordering social life, in favour of a more liberal (even Rawlsian) interpretation. Such statements, they argue, reveal Hobbes’s concern with justifying rule to the ruled and providing political stability for the ‘right reasons’, rather than on the sole basis of ‘coercion and fear’ (Button, 2008, p. 38; also Waldron, 1998, pp. 141–142; Lloyd, 1992, p. 2). This view, however, mistakes the kind of ‘reasons’ Hobbes’s civil doctrine can be understood to offer. The problem with punishments is not that they encourage obedience for the ‘wrong’ reasons, but rather that they cannot be relied upon consistently to provide the kind of constant, overwhelming inducement to obedience (namely fear) requisite to peace. Sovereigns are neither omniscient nor omnipotent, and self-interested subjects will seek out opportunities to break the law ‘whensoever the hope of impunity appears’ if they can hope to profit thereby (Leviathan, 27:18, p. 195). Teaching acts as a supplement to the ‘terror’ of punishments for Hobbes by constantly keeping men in mind of the terrible consequences (namely, the state of nature) that must result from the neglect of their duty of obedience (6:57, p. 34).9 The recognition, therefore, that punishments alone may not always suffice as incentives to obedience should not be taken as a revision of his basic contention that a person’s ‘will to do or not to do depends on the opinion [he] has formed of the good or evil, reward or penalty to follow’ (De cive, 6:11, p. 80). Science for Hobbes is precisely ‘the knowledge of consequences, and dependence of one fact upon another’ which can help men, who often struggle to reckon the consequences of their actions correctly, to foresee them and plan accordingly (Leviathan, 5:17, p. 25; 6:57, p. 34). Indeed, the civil wars alone would have ‘instructed’ men sufficiently as to the nature of their civic rights and duties, except for the fact that human memories are short

92

Teresa M. Bejan

and ‘miseries’ quickly forgotten (18:16, p. 116). It is precisely because every man’s actions are governed by his opinion of the likely consequences to follow that his instruction in ‘true’ civic doctrine is so crucial. The true civil science of just and unjust having been deduced, it was necessary still to bring it to the universities to be taught. Once this was done, however, ‘there is no doubt … that young men, who come thither void of prejudice, and whose minds are yet as white paper, capable of any instruction, would … receive the same, and afterward teach it to the people’ (Elements, 29:8, pp. 176–177). ‘Teaching’ here meant ‘begetting in another the same conceptions that we have in ourselves’, which might be done by leading the learner step-by-step through the same demonstration by which the teacher had reached his own conclusions (13:2, p. 73). If Hobbes had (as he thought) reasoned correctly, with conclusions confirmed by experience, then his proof should be easily taught and readily accepted by others, the sure sign of which would be consensus (13:2-2, pp. 73–74). Yet if – as the contemporary reception of Leviathan soon revealed – the expected consensus was not forthcoming, how might Hobbes account for it? Namely, by the fact that men’s minds were not ‘as white paper’, but rather hopelessly ‘scribbled over’ with prejudice, bad habits of reasoning, and false opinions. Hobbes referred to this problem as indocibility, or ‘difficulty of being taught’. Once ‘men have … acquiesced in untrue opinions, and registered them as authentical records in their minds; it is no less impossible to speak intelligibly … than to write legibly upon a paper already scribbled over’ (Elements, 10:8, pp. 62–63). Such indocibility might be compounded further by a student’s outright rejection of the definitions proffered by his master, which amounted to a simple refusal to be taught. In such cases, any subsequent demonstration (no matter how sound) would be entirely beside the point (De corpore, 6:15, p. 84). Although Hobbes was under no delusions as to the seriousness of the problem of indocibility, he seemed to have considered it no great impediment to the ready teaching of his doctrine in the universities.10 In order to understand why this is so, it is important to remember a particular feature of sovereignty on his account – namely, the right of the sovereign to define all words subject to controversy. For Hobbes, the ultimate master in the universities should be the sovereign, who would exercise total discretion in what is to be taught, who may teach it, and what doctrines must be suppressed. What distinguishes the sovereign from other schoolmasters is his right to punish those teachers and pupils who refuse to accept his definitions as the basis of their lessons, as well as those who insist on publicising unacceptable conclusions.11 Although he thought that the sovereign’s commands and punishments would be inadequate to give rise directly to genuine belief in any dissident intellect, by being able to mandate conformity in all external speech and action Hobbes bypassed entirely the problem of internal dissent in public teaching.12 Regardless of what teachers and students in the university might actually think, they could teach others only in accordance with the doctrines and definitions approved by the sovereignteacher.13 If the sovereign were assiduous in the regulation of doctrine, the

Teaching the Leviathan

93

punishment of (scandalous) heterodoxy, and the licensing of teachers so that ‘solid reason backed with authority’ reigned, Hobbes was certain that indocibility would present no insuperable obstacle to the teaching of true civil doctrine in the universities (Behemoth, p. 56). Hobbes thought heterodoxy would be a problem only for geniuses (like himself), who would be clever enough to think and express themselves safely within the confines of whatever limits the sovereign put in place. He was, however, a poor judge of such matters in practice, and was forced to flee from England to France and back again to avoid the threat of persecution for his views. He proved altogether too clever by half when he became the target of proposed anti-heresy legislation in 1666. Leviathan was burned publicly in the Bodleian quadrangle long before it was ‘publicly taught’ in the universities (Ryan, 1983, p. 205).

IV Given the considerable attention Hobbes devoted to university teaching in Leviathan and elsewhere, it is little wonder that scholars have taken that discussion to be representative of his views on education more generally. Yet he was careful throughout his writings to distinguish between the different forms of teaching appropriate to different sections of the population. These differences extended sometimes even to the content of the lessons to be learned (Hoekstra, 2006, p. 59). The vast majority of citizens would not attend university, but like many of his contemporaries Hobbes thought the safety and well-being of the commonwealth required universal civic education. Merely teaching elites aright and expecting their knowledge to trickle down would not be sufficient. Once he considered the instruction of the ‘vulgar’, Hobbes abandoned his technical definition of teaching as evident demonstration productive of knowledge – and, thus, distinguished from persuasion, which produced only ‘bare opinion’ (Elements, 13:2, p. 73). Rather, teaching appeared in Leviathan most often in conjunction with ‘preaching’ and was directed explicitly towards cultivating opinion as such (e.g. Leviathan, 18:9, p. 113; 27:36, p. 201; 30:6, p. 221). After all, ‘the power of the mighty has no foundation but in the opinion and belief of the people’ (Behemoth, 16). Although the Leviathan itself might be suitable for teaching in the universities, it would hardly be suitable for popular instruction.14 Hobbes acknowledged that the majority of men lacked the time, interest, or even sometimes the capacity to comprehend the whole; pithy summaries were therefore required. His favourite summary – that of all natural and moral laws into a negative version of the Golden Rule – was hardly the only one to be found in his writings (Leviathan, 15:35, p. 99). Indeed, the most suggestive précis of his civil doctrine appeared in his discussion of what, precisely, sovereigns were to have their subjects taught, wherein he presented the central political conclusions of Leviathan as analogues to the Ten Commandments (30:7-13, pp. 222–225). Bishop Bramhall accused Hobbes of writing in Leviathan a ‘Rebells catechism’ (1658, p. 515), and although Hobbes strongly rejected that characterisation of

94

Teresa M. Bejan

its conclusions, a civil catechism is exactly what Leviathan demanded for the instruction of the people. (Fittingly, Hobbes’s father, a disgraced clergyman, had been censured among other things for failing to catechise the young (Malcolm, 2002, p. 3).) The venue in which the bulk of popular instruction was to take place was the pulpit, and this civic education was modelled more or less explicitly on religious instruction. In order that the people be taught their duty and remember it, ‘it is necessary that some such times be determined wherein they may assemble together … hear those their duties told them … and be put in mind of the authority that maketh’ the civil laws (Leviathan, 30:10, p. 223). In this way, Hobbes hoped that the regular observance of the Sabbath might be turned to the end of peace and become a kind of civic Sunday school. Thus, the form of popular instruction proposed by Hobbes depended not on his method for achieving scientific knowledge, which ‘proceeds by cutting a proposition into small pieces, then chews it over and digests it slowly’ by way of definitions and evident demonstration, but rather on that which he describes as the way to religious belief (De cive, 18:5, pp. 238–239). ‘For it is with the mysteries of our religion as with wholesome pills for the sick, which, swallowed whole, have the virtue to cure, but chewed, are for the most part cast up again without effect’ (Leviathan, 32:3, p. 246). The discussion of popular education is further illuminated by Hobbes’s comment in a letter in 1636 that he ‘long[ed] infinitely to see those Bookes of the Sabbaoth; & am of your Mind, they will put such thoughts into the Heads of vulgar People, as will conferre little to their good Life. For, when they see one of the Ten Commandments to be jus humanum merely (as it must be, if the Church can alter it) they will hope also that the other nine may be so too. For every man hitherto did believe that the ten Commandments were the Morall, that is, Eternal law’ (Hobbes to Glen of 6/16 April 1636 in Correspondence, p. 30). The Ten Commandments were to serve as a mnemonic device to aid the vulgar in remembering their duty. Likewise, the memorable metaphoric images of the ‘Mortal God’, Leviathan, and the secular hell of the state of nature, sure to figure prominently in sermons based on Leviathan’s civil doctrine, would capture the popular imagination. Hobbes often analogised education to a process of ‘imprinting’. This metaphor recurs throughout his work, often in the context of the impressions made by religion and the arts upon the mind. He suggests that Numa, like other founders, took care to ‘imprint in [the people’s] minds a belief that those precepts which they gave concerning religion might not be thought to proceed from their own device’ (e.g. Leviathan, 12:20, p. 69; also 8:25, p. 43). In remarking upon an epic poem written by a friend, Hobbes claimed that the virtues represented therein were thus ‘so deeply imprinted, as to stay for ever [in my fancy], and govern all the rest of my thoughts and affections’ (The answer of Mr. Hobbes to Sir William D’Avenant’s preface before Gondibert, pp. 457–458).15 Hobbes treated the education of the people as a kind of sacrament of remembrance. The fountain metaphor used to describe the universities in Leviathan deliberately recalled a Baptismal font from whence ‘the preachers and the gentry, drawing such water as they find, use to sprinkle … upon the people’ (‘Review &

Teaching the Leviathan

95

conclusion’, p. 496). The end result of this kind of popular education would not be – as it was in the universities – simply the consequentialist embrace of civil society as always the lesser of two evils, but also a positive ‘love of obedience’ (Behemoth, p. 59). A well-educated populace, according to Hobbes, would think of themselves as ‘monks and friars, that are bound by vow to … simple obedience’ (Leviathan, 46:32, p. 464). This praise of unreflective obedience weighs against those who find in Hobbesian education primarily a ‘respect for individuals as reasoning beings … determine[d] to analyze politics and get to the bottom of human affairs’ (Waldron, 1998, p. 143). Such a reading becomes still more implausible when one considers the final site of education to which the sovereign must attend – namely, the family. Hobbes raised no children of his own, but he was well aware of the importance of the ‘first instruction of children’ by their parents for their later development, and hence for the commonwealth as a whole (Leviathan, 30:11, p. 223).16 An individual’s opinions and beliefs were not, for the most part, the result of considered reflection or evident teaching, but of this early instruction. This was most evident, again, in the case of religious belief, wherein ‘the ordinary cause of believing … [is] the hearing of those that … teach us, as our parents in their houses, and our pastors in the churches’ (43:8, p. 401). Parents, moreover, were responsible for the work of discipline through which children might first be habituated to obedience. Indeed, ‘it is by the rod that boys’ dispositions toward all things are shaped as parents and teachers wish’ (De homine, 16:4, p. 65). In De cive, Hobbes claimed that ‘all men (since all men are born infants) are born unfit for society and very many (perhaps the majority) remain so throughout their lives, because of mental illness or lack of discipline’. ‘Man is made fit for Society not by nature, but by discipline [disciplina]’, and this correction of children by their parents through the application of educative punishments was thus the cause of their sociability and a necessary precondition for the peaceful reproduction of society over generations (1:2n.1, pp. 24–25).17 As for what, specifically, Hobbes would have the sovereign teach young children, he suggested that they ‘be taught that originally the father of every man was also his sovereign lord, with power over him of life and death, and that the fathers of families, when … instituting a commonwealth … resigned that absolute power’ (Leviathan, 30:11, pp. 223–224). By calling on children to analogise their fathers to the civil sovereign in this way (and vice versa), Hobbes made the family the first school of the commonwealth, wherein the relationship of rule between father and child served to model the later relationship of simple obedience to the sovereign. While he habituates his children to obedience, the father acts as a placeholder for the sovereign until their majority, whereupon their obedience is transferred to its primary object. The family is ‘Leviathan writ small’ (Chapman, 1975). Hobbes even went so far as to argue that parental power over children, as an example of sovereignty by acquisition, is derived not naturally by ‘generation’, ‘but from the child’s consent, either express or by other sufficient arguments declared’ (Leviathan, 20:4, p. 126). Because every individual ‘ought to obey him by whom [he] is preserved; because preservation of life [is] the end,

96

Teresa M. Bejan

for which one man becomes subject to another’, the child can be presumed to have exchanged his obedience for his protection, like any adult citizen of the commonwealth (20:5, p. 130). In this way, the family represents the Hobbesian commonwealth to children and thereby schools them implicitly in (rational) subjection from infancy. Although the child, like the adult, never consented explicitly to being ruled, both will be taught to understand themselves as having done so. (For Hobbes’s analogies between adults and children: De cive, 1:2n.1, p. 25; Leviathan, 11.2,1 p. 61.) On Hobbes’s account, parents serve – just like the state-licensed teachers and pastors – as representatives of the sovereign power, and hence as public ministers in the home, ‘allowed and appointed to teach’ by the sovereign (Leviathan, 43:8, p. 401). Although the sovereign will generally leave subjects at liberty otherwise to ‘institute their children as they themselves think fit’, they do so only at his discretion (21:6, p. 138). In Hobbes’s commonwealth, parents hold their children in trust until such time as the sovereign reclaims his right. This work of first instruction in the family prepares children for Hobbesian ‘citizenship’ and is meant to attach securely those ‘artificial chains, called the civil laws’, that run from the sovereign’s lips to the people’s ears (21:5, p. 138). Far from neglecting early education, Hobbes’s commonwealth stands or falls by it. In Leviathan, Hobbes suggests that ‘the common people’s minds, unless they be tainted by dependence on the potent, or scribbled over with the opinions of their doctors, are fit to receive whatsoever by public authority shall be imprinted in them’ (30:6, p. 221). Hobbesian education requires that the minds of all citizens, the vulgar as well as the wise, be prepared for such imprinting by their primary instruction in the family and the pulpit. But keeping the paper of the people’s minds clean and white requires not only that they be kept free from dependence on the powerful, but also that ‘the dependence of subjects on the sovereign power of their country’ be emphasised and reinforced at every turn (46:18, p. 460).18 Thus, indocibility should be no impediment to Hobbesian ‘imprinting’ for the sovereign sufficiently attentive to the junior members of the commonwealth.

V Hobbesian education is an education in civic virtue. By reformulating the doctrine of Leviathan for presentation to each of the different parts of the commonwealth it aims to produce obedient citizens capable of the kind of stable consensus requisite to peace. In his response to his Oxford critics, Hobbes claimed that Leviathan in its original form, even in the absence of ‘digestion’ by wiser men to better suit it for public teaching, ‘hath framed the minds of a thousand gentlemen to a conscientious obedience to present government’ (Six lessons, pp. 335–336). How much more might it accomplish if aptly summarised and systematically taught? As we have seen, Hobbes’s contention that public education was a duty of sovereignty was not unique at the time – nor, for that matter, was government

Teaching the Leviathan

97

regulation of education. Nevertheless, the educational programme developed in Leviathan has struck Hobbes’s readers, from his contemporaries down to the present day, as something unusual. Its distinctiveness is summed up nicely in the image of ‘imprinting’. Hobbesian education – whether conducted in the university, from the pulpit, or in the family – aims always at uniformity; the virtuous citizen it produces is the same across all nations and regimes, which are themselves uniform with respect to their common end, peace. Such an education does not seek to cultivate the student’s individual capacities, for judgment or for anything else.19 Imprinting is not the cultivation of personality, but rather conformity to true civil doctrine, designed and systematically imposed from without by the sovereign power upon the ‘clean paper’ of men’s minds. Students come thereby to understand themselves as equal and atomistic, each tethered individually and so unified through their mutual relationship to the sovereign. The end result of this education would, Hobbes hoped, be a secure consensus and, at last, peace. The scope and character of the necessary consensus was, like most things, to be left to the sovereign’s discretion. (Hobbes thought that a good sovereign would leave his subjects at liberty in many things, interfering with them only in those matters he deemed essential to peace.) Modern students of Hobbes’s educational thought have tended to focus on this argument – that is, that the comprehensive education of society (whether as ‘popular enlightenment’ or indoctrination) constitutes a necessary precondition to peace because it alone can fashion citizens capable of this kind of consensus. Whereas an earlier generation – much like those troublesome Oxford professors – recoiled from Hobbes’s educational project, emphasising what they saw as its totalitarian aspirations, scholars in recent years have taken a decidedly more favourable view. For these authors, his educational thought reveals instead a more ‘liberal’ Hobbes, one who believed that political stability could be secured only by respecting individuals as reasoning beings.20 I have sought to show that neither view is wholly sustainable.21 What is clear, however, is that Hobbes believed the only architect and agent capable of fashioning a consensus adequate to the preservation of peace would be an absolute sovereign – and this would require, in turn, a state that might be relatively minimal in practice, but must be utterly authoritarian in principle. Thus, the conscientious sovereign would vigilantly oversee the intellectual life of his subjects from the cradle to the universities, and from there to the grave.

Acknowledgements I have incurred many debts in writing this article. Meredith Edwards, Shawn Fraistat, Bryan Garsten, Samuel James, Quentin Skinner, and Megan Wachspress read earlier drafts, and I thank them for their comments and criticisms. Jonathan Bruno, Alin Fumurescu, Calvert Jones, and Steven Smith were generous with their insights in various contexts during its development. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewer for the Oxford Review of Education and the tireless and endlessly helpful guest editors. I am especially grateful to Quentin

98

Teresa M. Bejan

Skinner and Mark Goldie for their wonderful supervision of my earliest work on Milton and early modern education reform in the context of the English Civil War.

Notes 1 Hobbes’s life in print began with his English translation of Thucydides’ Peloponnesian War (1629) and ended with translations of the Iliad and the Odyssey in 1676; Behemoth, finished in 1668, was published posthumously. Over this long period, Hobbes’s interests, methods and conclusions underwent significant changes, most notably with his storied ‘discovery’ of Euclidean Geometry in 1629. However, I find his treatment of educational matters to be reasonably consistent across his political philosophical writings, beginning with The elements of law (1640). For the purposes of this discussion I draw from a wide selection of works. 2 Lloyd cites this as evidence that Hobbes would not stifle all dissent (1997, p. 48); Nelson in his introduction to Hobbes’s translations of Homer somewhat undercuts such optimism (pp. xxxiii–xl); see also Hoekstra, 2006, p. 45. 3 In Six lessons, Hobbes spoke favourably of the idea of a lay-university (pp. 345–346); this comment was intended as a provocation to Ward, not as a serious proposal, although Tuck (1998) argues that it should be taken as evidence of Hobbes’s support for free inquiry in the universities; see also Garsten, 2006, p. 39. 4 This claim allowed Hobbes’s critics to cast Leviathan as a work written expressly in defence of Cromwell’s title. See Skinner’s ‘Hobbes and the engagement controversy’ (2002, p. 307) for emphasis on the similarities between Hobbes and other de facto theories of the period. 5 On possible similarities to the ‘Rawlsian’ notion of public reason, see Garsten (2006, pp. 27, 116), Gauthier (1995), Lloyd (1992 and 1997), Button (2008). 6 This question of influence over meanings is a point of controversy in scholarly assessment of Hobbesian eduction; see Pettit, 2008, pp. 115–132; Hoekstra, 2006, esp. pp. 34–35. 7 Hobbes insisted that although the sovereign could be guilty of iniquity he could not, by definition, commit injustice (Leviathan, 18:6, p. 113). Whether Hobbes meant his claim that the sovereign could sin against the law of nature as a serious appeal to a power higher than the sovereign’s self-interest is controversial. Supporters of the ‘Taylor-Warrender’ thesis argue that a belief in God is necessary to ground Hobbesian moral obligation (e.g. Warrender, 1957; Hood, 1964), while others argue that Hobbes’s political theory is secular in form and secularising in purpose. Johnston (1986) and Strauss (1953), for example, have argued that Hobbes wanted to ‘disenchant the world’ through education. Lloyd (1992) and Vaughan (2002) emphasise the importance to Hobbesian education of shaping – but not necessarily eradicating – religious belief. 8 I substitute ‘perspicuity of reasons’ (from ‘Philosophical rudiments concerning government and society’ (Hobbes, 1991), the 1651 English translation of De cive) for Silverthorne’s ‘clarity of arguments’. Although the former was long thought to have been authorised and approved by Hobbes, this has since been disproved. See Tuck’s introduction to De cive (Hobbes, 1998, pp. xxxiv–xxxvii). Malcolm (2002) argues that the translator was Charles Cotton. The Latin version runs: ‘Quoniam autem opiniones non imperando, sed docendo; non terrore poenarum, sed perspicuitate rationum’. 9 Heaven and hell obviously complicate the picture; it is therefore especially important for the sovereign to regulate closely doctrines pertaining thereunto. Whereas in Elements and De cive, Hobbes seemed content to maintain more or less traditional versions of heaven and hell – so long as eternal punishments could be shown to be annexed (like all temporal ones) to violations of the civil law alone – in Leviathan he revised them so as to be consistent with his materialism and therefore denied the immortal soul (pp. 418–431).

Teaching the Leviathan

10

11

12

13

14 15 16 17

18

99

Johnston argues against those who read Hobbes as a sincere Christian that a belief in hell – or in the Christian God, for that matter – could not possibly withstand a Hobbesian education (Johnston, 1986, pp. 142–150). While Hobbes clearly intends to undermine hell for those taught the doctrine of Leviathan in the universities, it is less clear that he thought it desirable for this part of his doctrine to be publicized to the population as a whole via public preaching, although the full arguments would certainly be available to those who should inquire. For brief treatments of this puzzle, see Tarcov (1999, pp. 48–49) and Chapman (1975, pp. 87–88). See also the growing literature on the role of rhetoric in Hobbes’s thought, which considers directly the limits of reason to persuade (e.g. Kahn, 1985; Johnston, 1986; Skinner, 1996; Vaughan, 2002; Garsten, 2006). Failure to appreciate this distinction between the rights of the sovereign as teacher versus those of the Church has led some scholars to draw a sharp distinction between teaching and coercion, thus neglecting the expansive role for educative punishments in Hobbes’s thought (see Lloyd, 1997, pp. 51–52 and 1992, p. 140; and Waldron, 1998, p. 142). Button (2008) acknowledges that this distinction is overdrawn (p. 64), yet continues to employ it elsewhere in his discussion (pp. 38, 62–69). Hobbes is very clear that the distinction does not apply in the case of sovereign-teachers, or those who act as ministers of the sovereign power; the discussion of teaching as ‘fishing’ as opposed to ‘hunting’ is meant to delimit ecclesiastical power only, not civil (Leviathan, 42:8, p. 337). An earlier generation of scholars treated Hobbes as straightforwardly advocating a programme of indoctrination and mind control; more recently scholars have made the case for ‘a more tolerant’ Hobbes – see Ryan (1983 and 1988), Tuck (1990 and 1998); Burgess (1996). Tuck goes so far as to suggest that Hobbes desired the universities to be places of protected free inquiry (1998, p. 155) – an interpretation I find implausible. I favour Murphy’s characterisation (1997) of Hobbes’s position as ‘tolerant anti-toleration’. Hobbes says as much in his discussion of Galileo (Leviathan, 46:42, p. 468). There, he argues that ‘disobedience may lawfully be punished in them that against the laws teach even true philosophy’. This passage, along with his claim that truth is by definition consistent with peace and the sovereign’s judgment of the same (18:9, pp. 113–114), has been a source of much scholarly contention. Arendt cited it as evidence that the sovereign can teach his subjects falsehoods in order to preserve the commonwealth (pp. 297–298); Waldron and Lloyd find it far less sinister (Waldron, 1998, pp. 142, 146 n.12; Lloyd, 1997, pp. 43–45). I dissent from Johnston’s suggestion that Leviathan was meant to be read by the public at large and attempted ‘to shape public opinion directly’ (1986, p. 89). See also Malcolm’s discussion of the role of such images in education in the context of the frontispiece of Leviathan (2002, p. 228). Some of Hobbes’s early critics accused him of fathering an illegitimate daughter and this claim has been accepted by some scholars, most recently Martinich (2005, p. 8). Again, I depart from the Silverthorne translation which has ‘training’ in place of ‘discipline’. Because the original English version translated disciplina here as ‘education’, many have assumed that this was Hobbes’s preferred translation. The original translation appeals especially to those authors who want to maintain a hard distinction between education and coercion in Hobbes’s thought; however, given that Hobbes refers to ‘discipline’ frequently in his writings, while also taking care at points to distinguish it from ‘education’ (e.g. Leviathan, 29:8, p. 213, ‘Review & conclusion’, p. 489), I believe this is to misrepresent his meaning in this passage. Malcolm, following Johnston, describes Hobbesian education as the ‘liberation’ of the people’s minds from both superstitious falsehoods and ‘the power of those groups, elites and confederacies that manipulate falsehood for their own ends’ (2002, p. 544). However, in this passage Hobbes states explicitly that he aims to combat such doctrines

100

Teresa M. Bejan

and factions because they serve to lessen the dependence of individuals on the sovereign power. This is, at best, a peculiar sort of liberation. 19 Garsten (2006) argues that Hobbes’s attempt to devalue judgment and seriously restrict its role in politics was a deliberate departure from classical political thought, and from his neo-republican contemporaries. 20 Although their specific arguments differ, Johnston (1986), Lloyd (1992 and 1997), Waldron (1998), Tuck (1998), Malcolm (2002) and Button (2008) can be seen alike as representatives of this trend, and all endorse Hobbes’s educational project to a greater or lesser extent. These accounts depart significantly from that of Voegelin, who claimed in 1938 that Hobbes’s system would be the envy of ‘a modern minister of propaganda’ (p. 55; see also Arendt, p. 290-1n.3). Ryan, while making the case for a more tolerant Hobbes, suggests that although ‘Hobbes’s sovereign cannot condition children as the Director in Brave New World can … there is no evident reason of principle to stop him applying the techniques when they are discovered’ (1983, p. 217). Vaughan (2002) and Hoekstra (2006) are notable exceptions to the recent trend. 21 Both groups treat Hobbesian education as though it were concerned with what people would be like; however, it is clear that Hobbes did not entertain high hopes that human nature could be changed (it was evidently quite stubborn) and so did not much care what people were like on the inside, so long as they were simply obedient in externals. Furthermore, when it comes to Hobbes the dichotomy between enlightenment and indoctrination is altogether inadequate. After all, the doctrine to be imprinted is, strictly speaking, ‘true’ – though what this means for Hobbes is (fittingly) subject to controversy. For a recent discussion, see Hoekstra (2006).

References Primary sources Bramhall, J. (1658) The catching of Leviathan, or the Great Whale (London). Hartlib, S. (2002) Hartlib papers project, 2nd edn. (electronic resource) (Sheffield, Humanities Research Institute, University of Sheffield). Gardiner, S. (ed.) (1906) Constitutional documents of the Puritan Revolution: 1625–1660 (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Hobbes, T. (1839 [1656]) De corpore, or elements of philosophy, in: W. Molesworth (ed.) The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. 1 (London). Hobbes, T. (1840 [1650]) The answer of Mr. Hobbes to Sir William D’Avenant’s preface before Gondibert, in: W. Molesworth (ed.) The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. 4 (London). Hobbes, T. (1845 [1656]) Six lessons to the professors of mathematics, in: W. Molesworth (ed.) The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. 7 (London). Hobbes, T. (1990 [1681]) Behemoth or the Long Parliament (F. Tönnies ed.) (Chicago, University of Chicago). Hobbes, T. (1991 [1651]) Man and citizen (De homine and de cive) (B. Gert ed.) (Indianapolis, Hackett). Hobbes, T. (1994a) The correspondence (2 vols) (N. Malcolm ed.) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Hobbes, T. (1994b [1640]) The elements of law natural and politic: human nature and de corpore politico with three lives (J. Gaskin ed.) (New York, Oxford University Press). Hobbes, T. (1994c [1651]) Leviathan, with selected variants from the Latin edition of 1668 (E. Curley ed.) (Indianapolis, Hackett). Hobbes, T. (1998 [1642]) On the citizen (R. Tuck & M. Silverthorne eds) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

Teaching the Leviathan

101

Hobbes, T. (2008 [1629]) Translations of Homer, vol. 1 (E. Nelson ed.) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Milton, J. (1856 [1641]) The reason of Church government urged against prelaty in: R. Griswold (ed.) The prose works of John Milton, vol. 1 (Philadelphia, Moore), 45–87. Milton, J. (1953 [c. 1644]) Of education in: E. Sirluck (ed.) The complete prose works of John Milton, vol. 2 (New Haven, Yale University Press). Wallis, J. (1662) Hobbius Heauton-timorumenos (Oxford). Ward, S. & Wilkins, J. (1654) Vindiciae academiarum (Oxford). Webster, J. (1654) Academiarum examen (London).

Secondary sources Arendt, H. (2006) Truth and politics, in: Between past and future (New York, Penguin). Burgess, G. (1996) Thomas Hobbes: religious toleration or religious indifference? in: Difference and dissent: theories of toleration in Medieval and Early Modern Europe (London, Rowman & Littlefield), 139–160. Button, M. (2008) Contract, culture, and citizenship: transformative liberalism from Hobbes to Rawls (University Park, Pennsylvania State University Press). Chapman, R. (1975) Leviathan writ small: Thomas Hobbes on the family, The American Political Science Review, 69, 76–90. Cressy, D. (1975) Education in Tudor and Stuart England (London, Arnold). Curtis, M. (1959) Oxford and Cambridge in transition, 1558–1642 (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Garsten, B. (2006) Saving persuasion: a defense of rhetoric and judgment (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Gauthier, D. (1995) Public reason, Social Philosophy and Policy, 19–42. Hoekstra, K. (2006) The end of philosophy (The case of Hobbes), Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106(1), 25–62. Hood, F. (1964) The divine politics of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Jesseph, D. (1999) Squaring the circle: the war between Hobbes and Wallis (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Johnston, D. (1986) The rhetoric of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes and the politics of cultural transformation (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Kahn, V. (1985) Rhetoric, prudence, and skepticism in the renaissance (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). Lloyd, S. (1992) Ideals as interests in Hobbes’s Leviathan: the power of mind over matter (New York, Cambridge University Press). Lloyd, S. (1997) Coercion, ideology, and education in Hobbes’s Leviathan, in: A. Reath, B. Herman, & C. Korsgaard (eds) Reclaiming the history of ethics: essays for John Rawls (New York, Cambridge University Press), 32–65. Malcolm, N. (2002) Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Martinich, A. (2005) Hobbes (New York, Routledge). Murphy, A. (1997) Tolerance, toleration, and the liberal tradition, Polity, 29, 593–623. Pettit, P. (2008) Made with words: Hobbes on language, mind, and politics (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Ryan, A. (1983) Hobbes, toleration, and the inner life, in: D. Miller & L. Siedentop (eds) The nature of political theory (New York, Oxford University Press), 197–218. Ryan, A. (1988) A more tolerant Hobbes? in: S. Mendus (ed.) Justifying toleration: conceptual and historical perspectives (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 37–59.

102

Teresa M. Bejan

Skinner, Q. (1996) Reason and rhetoric in the philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Skinner, Q. (2002) Visions of politics, vol. 3, Hobbes and civil science (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Skinner, Q. (2008) Hobbes and republican liberty (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Solt, L. (1956) Anti-intellectualism and the Puritan Revolution, Church History, 25, 306–316. Stone, L. (1964) The educational revolution in England, Past and Present, 28, 41–80. Stone, L. (1969) Literacy and education in England, 1640–1900, Past and Present, 42, 69–139. Strauss, L. (1953) Natural right and history (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Tarcov, N. (1999) Locke’s education for liberty (New York, Lexington Books). Tuck, R. (1990) Hobbes and Locke on toleration, in: M. Dietz (ed.) Thomas Hobbes and political theory (Lawrence, University Press of Kansas), 153–171. Tuck, R. (1998) Hobbes on education, in: A. Oksenberg Rorty (ed.) Philosophers on education: historical perspectives (London, Routledge), 148–156. Turnbull, G. (1947) Hartlib, Duty and Comenius (Liverpool, University Press of Liverpool). Vaughan, G. (2002) Behemoth teaches Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on political education (Lanham, Lexington Books). Voegelin, E. (2000) The political religions, in: M. Henningsen (ed.) Modernity without restraint (Columbia, University of Missouri Press), 23–74. Waldron, J. (1998) Hobbes: truth, publicity, and civil doctrine, in: A. Oksenberg Rorty (ed.) Philosophers on education: historical perspectives (London, Routledge), 139–147. Warrender, H. (1957) The political philosophy of Hobbes (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Webster, C. (1970) Samuel Hartlib and the advancement of learning (London, Cambridge University Press).

7

Locke on education and the rights of parents Alex Tuckness

Introduction John Locke (1632–1704) is often taken as a canonical defender of the rights of parents in education, even as someone who carries the rights of parents too far in that sphere (Gutmann, 1987; Carrig, 2001). This is somewhat ironic given the fact that in his own day he was famous for limiting the rights of fathers as part of his rejection of the divine right of kings. In response to those who thought that Adam, by virtue of fatherhood, was monarch of the world and that his paternal sovereignty was passed on to his oldest heir, Locke argued that paternal power exists for a different purpose than political power and the power of parents over children is limited to the purpose of families, the proper care and raising of offspring (TT, 1.50-72, 2.52-76).1 Nonetheless, it is true that Locke argued in favour of education at home by parents or tutors selected by parents, and it is also true that Locke talked about the education of children primarily as a right and duty of parents rather than of the state. This is a topic of no small importance now given the substantial number of children educated at home by parents and the frequent conflicts between parents and schools over policies and curricula. This chapter challenges the traditional reading of Locke’s view of education. Locke’s reasons for believing parents should play the leading role in educating children can be divided into pedagogical reasons and political reasons. Each type of reason requires a different type of argument. Pedagogical reasons simply explain why one type of educational arrangement is likely to work better than another in terms of the goals of education itself. While Locke did favour education by parents rather than schools, when his reasons for doing so are set in terms of his larger theory of education it follows that many of his objections to schools apply with less force today than they would have in Locke’s day. Political reasons, for Locke, are a qualitatively different kind of reason. Locke believed that people had rights, including the right to make foolish choices while raising children (L, p. 34). The question is how far such rights extend. This article will first explain Locke’s pedagogical reasons for preferring education by parents and then focus on Locke’s distinctly political reasons that seem to imply

104

Alex Tuckness

a right of parents to control their children’s education even in cases where their choices do not seem to be in the educational interest of the child. Previous studies of Locke’s views on the rights of parents have failed to notice the implications of his larger theory of toleration for his views on the rights of parents. In Locke’s theory, different entities (a government, a family, a church, a business) exist for different reasons and may have exclusive rights to act in pursuit of the goals of that sphere. Locke also realised that two different entities pursuing two different goals may legitimately make claims to regulate the same activity. In such cases, Locke allowed the government to enforce its views in the face of opposition so long as it does so in pursuit of a legitimate governmental goal. This implies a sphere of legitimate state control over education.

Locke’s pedagogical argument for parental education Some argue that in the eighteenth century, Locke, well known today for his An essay concerning human understanding and Two treatises of government, may have had his most significant immediate influence through his theory of education (Wood, 1983). His Some thoughts concerning education is based on a series of letters to his friend Edward Clarke, who was about eight years younger than Locke (Woolhouse, 2007, p. 175). They were first published under that title in 1693, and he made corrections and revisions on three more editions before he died in 1704. The book was reprinted and translated at an astounding rate and was very influential (Axtell, 1968, p. 17). That Locke was considered an expert on parenting despite having been a lifelong bachelor is less surprising than one might think, since he was both a tutor for the children of English nobility and a doctor and was therefore often asked by friends for his advice on the rearing of children. Locke began his book by claiming in the first section that ‘of all the Men we meet with, Nine Parts of Ten are what they are, Good or Evil, useful or not, by their Education’ (STCE, 1). This claim is related to the philosophical claim for which Locke is perhaps most famous, his rejection in the Essay of innate ideas. It is actually in his writings on education that Locke makes the point most strongly. He states that he imagines the ‘Minds of Children as easily turned this or that way as Water itself’ (STCE, 2). In the very last paragraph of the book, Locke reiterates that his focus has been only on the sort of education proper for the son of a gentleman ‘who being then very little, I considered only as white Paper, or Wax, to be molded and fashioned as one pleases’ (STCE, 217). Just as Locke argued in his theory of property that 9/10 (or 99/100 or 999/1000) (TT, 2.40, 2.43) of the value of property comes from the human labour that is invested into it, so too he thought people come to be what they are by the sort of education they receive (SCTE, 1). The implications of this are that education is of monumental importance. It would be a mistake, however, to assume that Locke considered human beings completely malleable. Yolton (1989) makes the case that although children are born with no ideas Locke did not think all children were born with identical

Locke on education and the rights of parents

105

natures. Locke also writes at the end of his book that much more would need to be said, ‘especially if one should take in the various Tempers, different Inclinations, and particular Defaults, that are to be found in Children; and prescribe proper Remedies’ (STCE, 217). Education must, therefore, be tailored to the diverse personalities of children (STCE, 66, 101–2).2 It is legitimate to infer from these passages that Locke believed education could have a tremendously important role. Locke believed throughout his life that most people unthinkingly adopt the beliefs and practices of those around them rather than revising their beliefs and actions on the basis of reason. In Of the conduct of the understanding, Locke admonished people to think for themselves and to love truth more than tradition (C, 10–12), just as he concluded the last sentence of his book on education by hoping that his book would give some direction to those who are ‘so irregularly bold, that they dare venture to consult their own Reason, in the Education of their Children, rather than wholly to rely upon Old Custom’ (STCE, 217). While some have read this as an invitation to utopianism in that human nature can be remade through education, Locke’s tone is not at all utopian. It is, rather characteristically, sober. The phrase ‘irregularly bold’ indicates Locke’s belief that few people will actually choose the path he recommends. Locke’s writing on education begins with the child’s body rather than his mind. Locke was trained as a doctor and so it is unsurprising that this topic would be of interest to him. It is important because Locke sees both the education of the mind and the education of the body as resting on the same principle, namely that education consists in the learning of correct habits by engaging in the requisite actions. Locke recommends that children be exposed to heat and cold, for example, by giving them ‘Shoes so thin, that they might leak and let in Water’ (STCE, 7). Training the body to endure hardships turns out to be a crucial element in the larger goal of education. As the Strength of the Body lies chiefly in being able to endure Hardships, so also does that of the Mind. And the great Principle and Foundation of all Virtue and Worth, is placed in this, That a Man is able to deny himself his own Desires, cross his own Inclinations, and purely follow what Reason directs as best, though the appetite lean the other way. (STCE, 33) Education, for Locke, thus consists in helping people to overcome the temptations of shortsighted behaviour. This idea summarises much of the overall message of Locke’s book on education and connects it with his hedonistic theory of motivation. Locke argued in the Essay that pain and pleasure were the only motivators of human behaviour. He wrote that ‘Pleasure and Pain, and that which causes them, Good and Evil, are the hinges on which our Passions turn’ (E, 2.20.3). Human beings therefore naturally act in pursuit of their own pleasure. Locke proceeded to explain why it is that human beings so often act in ways that are not likely to bring them pleasure if human beings are always motivated to pursue the greatest

106

Alex Tuckness

pleasure. He thought that pleasure or pain will move us to act only if there is some ‘uneasiness’. He wrote: This Uneasiness we may call, as it is, Desire; which is an uneasiness of the Mind for want of some absent good. … But here all absent good does not, according to the greatness it has, or is acknowledged to have, cause pain equal to that greatness; as all pain causes desire equal to itself: Because the absence of good is not always a pain, as the presence of pain is. And therefore absent good may be looked on, and considered without desire’. (E, 2.21.31) Locke thought that human beings neither automatically perceive the pleasures and pains that will flow from particular actions nor automatically desire pleasures that are not immediately present. He then explained that ‘by a due consideration and examining any good proposed, it is in our power, to raise our desires, in due proportion to the value of that good’ (E, 2.21.46). While we do not have the power to act for something that we do not perceive to be for our good, we do have the power to suspend judgment so that we can think through the ramifications of our actions and choose the action that is truly in our best interests (E, 2.21.47). Locke used these ideas to explain how virtue is acquired in Some thoughts concerning education. He repeated the hedonistic assumptions of the Essay when he stated that ‘Good and Evil, Reward and Punishment, are the only Motives to a rational Creature; these are the Spur and Reins, whereby all Mankind are set on work, and guided, and therefore they are to be made use of to Children too’ (STCE, 54). The task of education is therefore to help children both perceive the consequences of actions and, even more importantly, to become ‘uneasy’ about the possibility of missing out on important pleasures in the future. Since a present pain may seem to overwhelm a future good, much of the task of education is helping children to acquire the habit of learning to endure a present pain for the sake of a greater future pleasure and to forgo present pleasure to avoid a greater future pain (STCE, 45). Locke employed several different educational strategies to achieve this goal. Parents should not give children things that they do not need or are not good for them simply because the children demand them (STCE, 35). The father should be more stern with the child when the child is young to establish an appropriate ‘Awe and Respect’ (STCE, 44) but this can be relaxed as the child grows older (STCE, 41). Interestingly, a child should not be offered material rewards for behaving well since this will only increase his tendency to govern his behaviour by the pursuit of immediate rewards. ‘To make a good, a wise, and a virtuous Man, ‘tis fit he should learn to cross his Appetite, and deny his Inclination to riches, finery or pleasing his Palate, etc. whenever his Reason advises the contrary, and his Duty requires it’. And thus parents who motivate a child by promising a treat or new clothes to get a child to do something ‘by misapplied Rewards and Punishments sacrifice their Virtue, invert

Locke on education and the rights of parents

107

the Order of their Education, and teach them Luxury, Pride, or Covetousness, etc.’ (STCE, 52). Locke’s alternative was to cultivate a different kind of motive which is more indirect, the desire for esteem and the desire to avoid disgrace which Locke says are ‘the most powerful incentives to the Mind, when once it is brought to relish them’ (STCE, 56). These words are essential to understanding Locke’s approach. He had argued in the Essay that to a great extent popular conceptions of virtue and vice ‘in a great measure everywhere correspond with the unchangeable Rule of Right and Wrong, which the Law of God hath established; there being nothing, that so directly, and visibly secures, and advances the general Good of Mankind in this World, as Obedience to the Laws he has set them’ (E, 2.28.11). He also stated that the fear of being punished by a loss of esteem from other people is a more powerful motivator for most people than the fear of divine or governmental punishment (E, 2.282.12). In his book on education he stated that although reputation is not ‘the true Principle and Measure of Virtue’ (which stems from knowledge of God’s rewards and punishments) it is nonetheless ‘that, which comes nearest to it’ (STCE, 61). Locke’s remark that esteem and disgrace are the mind’s most powerful motives ‘once it is brought to relish them’ is also extremely important. The pleasure of being esteemed, like any other pleasure, will move a person only once he or she is uneasy about losing it. Parents, therefore, must nurture this desire to be well thought of by praising the child’s good actions and letting him or her know their disappointment when he or she behaves wrongly. Children should also be taught that those who are esteemed for doing well ‘will necessarily be beloved and cherished by everybody, and have all other good Things as a Consequence of it’ (STCE, 58). Reputation thus becomes a way to habituate children to seek pleasures that are more likely to correspond with the actual principles of right and wrong. Parents who do this will be able to minimise the use of corporal punishment. ‘Frequent Beating or Chiding is therefore carefully to be avoided’ (STCE, 60). Children should be praised in front of others, but reprimanded in private (STCE, 62). Locke was particularly critical of parents who give children complicated rules to follow and then punish them when they fail to follow them. Instead, parents should keep things simple and teach children by getting them to practise the action in question until it becomes a habit (STCE, 64). The one instance where Locke thinks corporal punishment should be used is when children are insubordinate (STCE, 78), since this is necessary to establish the parent’s authority. It is against this background that we can understand Locke’s criticisms of the schools of his day and his reasons for recommending education under the supervision of parents. Schools, in Locke’s opinion, lacked the ability to provide adequate supervision for the children outside the periods of formal instruction. Moreover, teachers were not able to tailor education to the specific needs of each child. Locke thought it highly likely that the child would learn rudeness, dishonesty, and a host of other vices from the other children at the school. Locke asks

108

Alex Tuckness

whether a father will ‘hazard your Son’s Innocence and Virtue, for a little Greek and Latin’ (STCE, 70). Moreover, the schools tended to practise exactly the kind of pedagogy that Locke criticised (beating children for making mistakes in Latin, for example). Locke was convinced that children would learn far more if learning was part of play and was not forced upon them (STCE, 72–74). As much as possible, children should learn additional languages (French, then Latin) in the same way they learned English to the extent possible, ideally finding a tutor who would speak to the child only in that language (STCE, 165). In the home, by contrast to the school, the father can find a tutor who will instruct and model virtue and manners for his child. Locke’s list of praiseworthy virtues presents a helpful picture of the sort of adults he sought to produce. A child should be taught civility, humanity (abstaining from cruelty), generosity, gracefulness, honour, humility, industry, kindness, love of God, love of study, modesty, politeness, prudence, reverence, self control, self-denial, and selfrestraint (Yolton & Yolton, 1989, pp. 22–23). Locke’s discussion of generosity is instructive because Locke explained that a child’s rational faculties are not advanced enough for the child to understand property, and therefore justice. Instead, since humans incline naturally to selfishness, parents are to contrive things so that self-sacrifice actually ends up being beneficial for the child, so that the child will develop a habit of generosity and will more generally desire the esteem that goes along with being thought generous (STCE, 110). Locke favoured education by a tutor because, given his views on education, it seemed at the time the better option. Locke believed each child was different and that individualised education was therefore important. Locke thought esteem the most important motivator and was eager to capture the natural desire to be esteemed by parents that children have and harness it for the purposes of education. He was also writing in a historical context where the crucial choice would be whether to have the child educated at home or whether to send the child off to a school wherein his contact with the family would be limited to a few weeks each year. Because, as indicated above, Locke’s view of education was significantly intertwined with developing virtuous character, allowing children to be without adequate supervision so many hours per day was too risky. Ruderman and Godwin (2000, pp. 508–509), for example, assume that since Locke was critical of schools he would have obviously opposed a system of public schools. Tarcov (1984, p. 210) on the other hand points out that Locke admitted that both home and school education had inconveniences and that some of Locke’s opposition to schools may have stemmed from the fact that they were boarding schools. A public school system where children can conveniently attend school and still live at home under the supervision of their parents is a very different system from the one Locke criticised. Tarcov is right to see that we must be cautious in making claims about how Locke would apply his ideas in a radically different historical context. Locke’s statements were a judgment based on his assessments of the positives and negatives of the two forms of education in his day; they were not a statement of a timeless principle.

Locke on education and the rights of parents

109

Locke and the rights of parents Where Locke did claim to be offering a timeless principle is with his political statements about the natural rights of individuals. In his more political works, Locke made a number of statements that taken together have been thought to mark him as a strong supporter of the rights of parents in education relative to the rights of communities. Locke argued against the theory of the divine right of kings articulated by Robert Filmer (1588–1653) in which Adam was understood to have been created king of the earth by God and to have passed that right on to his eldest son and so on through the generations. Filmer argued that fathers have complete power over their children, including the power to put them to death. Political power and paternal power for Filmer differ only in scale, not in kind. Against this position, Locke argued in the First treatise that fathers have a much more limited power over their children. Locke argued persuasively from the Hebrew text of the Bible (or Torah) that God’s grant of authority to Adam was not to him in particular but to mankind in general (TT, 1.21-43). Locke argued in the Second treatise that the appropriate term is ‘Parental Power’ not ‘Paternal Power’ since God commanded children to honour both father and mother (TT, 2.52). Unlike Filmer who believed human beings were born obligated to a particular family and political regime, Locke believed that ‘we are born Free as we are born Rational; not that we have actually the Exercise of either: Age that brings one, brings with it the other too’ (TT, 2.61). Since children are not able to act rationally, they are to obey their parents until they are adults, at which point they owe their parents only honour, not obedience (TT, 2.67-69). It is the power and duty of the parent to educate the child (TT, 2.69). Locke’s strategy, therefore, was to distinguish sharply between parental power and political power. Locke says that they are ‘built upon so different Foundations, and given to so different Ends, that every Subject that is a Father, has as much a Paternal Power over his Children, as the Prince has over his’ (TT, 2.71). The power and duty of parents is to educate their children until the point at which they can care for themselves (TT, 2.58), while the purpose of the government is to use its coercive power to secure the lives, liberties, and properties of its citizens (TT, 2.123).3 Locke must grapple with the fact that parents’ views on the education of their children may conflict with the views of the government about what will best secure the lives, liberties and properties of citizens. It is true that Locke holds that the right, duty, and power of educating children are with parents. Some have seen this as an even more important ‘separation of powers’ than Locke’s distinction between legislative and executive power (Tarcov, 1984; Ruderman & Godwin, 2000). Locke states in the Second treatise that parents are ‘by the Law of Nature, under an obligation to preserve, nourish, and educate the Children, they had begotten, not as their own Workmanship, but as the Workmanship of their own Maker, the Almighty, to whom they were to be accountable for them’ (TT, 2.56). Locke made it clear that the power parents have over children stems from the duties they have to care for children (TT, 2.58). The question then arises

110

Alex Tuckness

whether any part of this power is transferred to the government when individuals leave the state of nature. Locke went so far as to say that ‘Parents in Societies, where they themselves are Subjects, retain a power over their Children, and they have as much right to their Subjection, as those who are in the state of Nature’ (TT, 2.71). When Locke described ‘Conjugal Society’ he described it as a ‘voluntary Compact between Man and Woman’ to unite for the propagation of offspring and the care of those offspring until the children are ‘able to provide for themselves’ (TT, 2.78). We have already seen that Locke regarded education as part of that care. What this reading of Locke ignores is the fact that more than one entity can have a legitimate claim over a given human activity and that it is not enough to show that someone has a legitimate power, one must also know what happens when legitimate powers conflict. In his writings on toleration, Locke introduced the idea that what he called ‘societies’ exist for limited purposes and act legitimately only when trying to attain those purposes. He rejected the position of his opponent, Jonas Proast (1640–1710), who argued that governments can in principle regulate any action to produce any type of good. Locke responded that either societies are limited in the ends they can pursue by the purposes the parties who entered into the society agreed upon, or any society may act for any beneficial end. In other words, a prospective beneficial outcome does not justify acting for an end that a society does not exist to promote. Failure to recognise this, Locke argued, means ‘there will be no difference between church and state; a commonwealth and an army; or between a family, and the East India Company; all of which have hitherto been thought to exist for different ends’ (W, 6:117). The idea that different societies (commonwealth, corporation, church, family) exist for different ends is very important in Locke’s thought. By understanding how church and state relate to one another, we can learn about how state and family interact. Locke’s argument is that the family is a society that comes together for a particular end: the propagation, care, and education of children. Religious societies come together to further the spiritual interests of their members. Civil societies come together to further the civil interests of citizens. When Locke describes reasons for and ends of civil society (government), he states that: the pravity of Mankind … obliges Men to enter into Society with one another; that by mutual Assistance, and joint Force, they may secure unto each other their Properties in the things that contribute to the Comfort and Happiness of this Life; … But forasmuch as Men thus entering into Societies, … may nevertheless be deprived of them [goods], either by the Rapine and Fraud of their Fellow-Citizens, or by the Hostile Violence of Foreigners; the remedy of this Evil consists in Arms, Riches, and Multitude of Citizens; the Remedy of the other in Laws …. (L, 47–48) What is important to notice here is that Locke believed that protecting civil interest required the government positively to pursue ‘Arms, Riches, and

Locke on education and the rights of parents

111

Multitude of Citizens’ so that the state could defend itself from foreign attack. This is central to Locke’s argument for religious toleration and has important implications for his views on education as well because in both cases different societies pursuing different ends may try to assert authority over the same actions. In the toleration case, governments do not exist to pursue religious ends and act illegitimately if they use their power for those ends, but they do act legitimately when pursuing the civil interests of citizens. Although one can argue about how broadly Locke would define civil interests, a point to which we will return, at a minimum it includes things like an economy that can support a well funded and highly educated military to guard from attack. Governments must pursue positive goals to have the resources to protect ‘negative’ rights to non-interference with life or property (Tuckness, 2008). The complication for Locke is that a given act, killing an animal for example, might be commanded by a church as part of a religious purpose and forbidden by a government trying to protect the national economy. Locke gave the example of a case where many animals have died from disease and the government bans the slaughtering of animals for a time so that the numbers can be replenished. Such a law would restrict the freedom of religious groups who want to practice animal sacrifice. Locke argued that such a law is legitimate, even though it restricts religious liberty, because the government is still acting for civic, not spiritual ends (L, 42). The implication is that in the case of parents and education, even if we grant that nurturing children is the purpose of parents, and promoting civil interests the purpose of government, the commonwealth might legitimately restrict parental rights in education so long as it can claim that it is doing so for the sake of legitimate civil purposes such as improving the strength of the nation to resist enemy attack. Requiring parents to teach children to read or to learn science might be important for having a viable military and economic system. Suppose that the government, in pursuing what it takes to be the civic interests of the nation, requires children to learn things to which the parents object. Again, Locke gives us a parallel case with his writings on toleration. If a person thinks that the government, pursuing civic interests in good faith, has nonetheless issued an order that would violate the person’s religious beliefs to obey, he has the option of disobeying the law and accepting the appropriate punishment. On the other hand, if he thinks the policy is one that in fact has ends other than the civil interests of the people (the policy was enacted to try to change people’s religious beliefs or practices), he can regard the government actions as illegitimate uses of government force and regard the government as illegitimate and resist it (L, 49). Let us now take this as a model for how Locke would handle conflicts between parents and the state regarding education issues. Since Locke gives parents, not governments, the primary duty and power of educating children, the presumption is generally in favour of parental control. Nonetheless, a system of public education and some restrictions on parental rights are permissible if they have, so to speak, a non-educational justification related to improving the safety and security of the state. This would imply that public education should not restrict

112

Alex Tuckness

parental rights on the grounds that it will make the child a better or more knowledgeable person alone. A political reason, the public good, is needed. Perhaps the strongest objection against this interpretation is that it actually underestimates the extent to which political society can aim at virtue simply for its own sake. In Locke’s earliest defence of toleration he claimed that governments had no power to enforce morality if the vice did not affect the preservation of human life (PE, p. 144). In his later writings, he states that magistrates should ‘impartially set themselves against vice, in whomsoever it is found, and leave men to their own consciences; in their articles of faith, and ways of worship’ (W, 6:65). Marshall argues that Locke expanded the range of moral concerns open to the magistrate so that it would include moral reformation in general even if this did not directly improve the public good (1994, pp. 379–383). These texts would need to be weighed against others where Locke rules out laws of this sort. The best harmonisation of the various texts is likely that Locke later realised that the virtues he was concerned about (recall the list earlier in the paper) are all virtues that do affect the civil interests of the society and that it only confused matters to imply that the government had no legitimate interest in regulating such matters. What we are left with is an account of Locke’s views on the rights of parents that gives the state more authority to intervene in the realm of education than previous interpretations have suggested. While Locke was adamant that different societies exist for different ends, he recognised that certain actions affect more than one end and that there will therefore be conflicts over whose will should prevail. Locke believed that government would be unworkable if the state had to suspend the pursuit of its basic goals every time it came into conflict with a claim from another sphere and so he permitted the state to act in ways that restrict the rights of religious believers, and by extension the rights of parents, so long as the policy could be justified as one necessary to keep the lives, liberties, and properties of the citizens safe.

Conclusion An overlooked contribution of Locke to modern educational theory rests in his theory of toleration and its account of societies. The state, and the public school systems it supports (and in some cases requires students to attend), is not a family, and states and families do not exist for the same purposes. There is a sense in which states can be improperly paternal, acting as if the reasons that might motivate parents to educate children in a certain way must also be reason enough for the state to do it. Yet Locke also realises that the state’s interest in promoting the civil interests of citizens, even if interpreted narrowly as the defence of rights, gives the state an interest in producing citizens who will be able to safeguard those rights in the future. Setting up a public school system and regulating home schooling to insure that both provide an education compatible with citizens who will protect rights is thus a perfectly legitimate goal for governments to pursue. But it is also one that may legitimately conflict with a parent’s sense of how best to raise a child.

Locke on education and the rights of parents

113

The parent, in seeking the best interest of the child, is also aiming at an end legitimate for familial society. Locke would say that each is justified in acting on its best judgment, and thus the state could be justified in pursuing a policy against the wishes of parents if it believed there was a legitimate civil interest at stake.

Notes 1 References to Locke’s primary works will be given as follows: E = Essay concerning human understanding (Locke, 1979) by book, chapter and section number; C = Of the conduct of the understanding (Locke, 1996) by section number; L = Letter concerning toleration (Locke, 1983) by page number; PE = Political essays (Locke, 1997) by page number; STCE = Some thoughts concerning education (Locke, 1989) by section number; TT = Two treatises of government (Locke, 1988) by treatise and section number; W = Works (Locke, 1963) by volume and page number. The original formatting, spacing and punctuation are retained in quotations unless otherwise noted, but spellings have been modernised. 2 While Passmore has tried to argue that Locke’s Some thoughts was ‘the great turning point’ (2000, p. 242) in the transition to an optimistic view of human nature that saw no limits to human perfectibility, Spellman points out that Locke’s rejection of the Calvinist understanding of original sin did not necessarily imply a utopian view of human nature and human possibilities (1988). Locke, for example, believed that children had a natural inclination towards power and dominion (STCE, 103). 3 This strategy has been criticised from various angles. Gutmann (1987) argues that Locke’s position fails to recognise the legitimate claims that the state has in producing citizens with the requisite skills and knowledge for democratic self-governance. Carrig (2001) goes even farther in claiming that Locke’s liberalism is really despotism by parents. If we are nine-tenths of what we are by education and if parents control education, their rule over children is far more extreme than that of a political tyrant. Similarly, Sumser (1994) sees in Locke’s substitution of internalised controls (like the need for esteem) for external force (corporal punishment) a system that leaves people no more free than they were before. Neill (1989) and Leites (1979) both claim that if autonomy is correctly understood it is compatible with parents raising children in the way Locke suggested. These suggestions do not, however, respond to Gutmann’s contention that the state should have more say in the shaping of its future citizens. This paper does not challenge Gutmann’s conclusion about the interest of the state in its future citizens, it instead challenges her reading of Locke.

References Axtell, J. L. (1968) The educational writings of John Locke (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Carrig, J. (2001) Liberal impediments to liberal education: the assent to Locke, The Review of Politics, 63, 41–76. Gutmann, A. (1987) Democratic education (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Leites, E. (1979) Locke’s liberal theory of parenthood, in: O. O’Neill & W. Ruddick (eds) Having children: philosophical and legal reflections on parenthood (Oxford, Oxford University Press), 306–318. Locke, J. (1963) [1823] Works. 10 Volumes (Germany, Scienta Verlag Aalen). Locke, J. (1979) [1690] An essay concerning human understanding (ed. P. Nidditch) (Oxford, Clarendon Press).

114

Alex Tuckness

Locke, J. (1983) [1689] A letter concerning toleration (ed. J. Tully) (Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company). Locke, J. (1988) [1689] Two treatises of government (ed. P. Laslett) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Locke, J. (1989) [1693] Some thoughts concerning education (ed. J. W. Yolton & J. S. Yolton) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Locke, J. (1996) Some thoughts concerning education and Of the conduct of the understanding (eds R. W. Grant & N. Tarcov) (Indianapolis, Hackett). Locke, J. (1997) Political essays (ed. M. Goldie) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Marshall, J. (1994) John Locke: resistance, religion and responsibility (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Neill, A. (1989) Locke on habituation, autonomy, and education, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 27, 225–245. Passmore, J. (2000) The perfectibility of man (3rd edn) (New York, Liberty Fund). Ruderman, R. S. & Godwin, R. K. (2000) Liberalism and parental control of education, The Review of Politics, 62, 503–529. Spellman, J. (1988) John Locke and the problem of human depravity (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Sumser, R. (1994) John Locke and the unbearable lightness of modern education, Educational Philosophy and Theory, 26, 1–15. Tarcov, N. (1984) Locke’s education for liberty (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Wood, G. S. (1983, 3 February) This land is our land, The New York Review of Books, 16–21. Tuckness, A. (2008) Punishment, property and the limits of altruism, American Political Science Review, 102, 467–479. Woolhouse, R. (2007) John Locke: a biography (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Yolton, J. W. & Yolton, J. S. (1989) Introduction, in: J. Locke Some thoughts concerning education (Oxford, Clarendon Press).

8

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education Patrick Riley

Introduction Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) is widely, and correctly, viewed as the greatest political philosopher of the French Enlightenment. He is also widely, and correctly, viewed as the most important philosopher of education in the eighteenth century. For Rousseau, politics and education are strongly connected: he gives education the task of transforming naturally self-loving egoists animated only by their own ‘private wills’ into polis-loving citizens with a civic ‘general will’ (CW 4.140-1/OC 3.363).1 In Book 2, Chapter 7 of the Social contract, Rousseau introduces the figure of the ‘Great Legislator’ who must, over time, be ‘capable of changing human nature, so to speak’, by turning self-lovers into lovers of the general good (CW 4.155/OC 3.381). This paper argues that we should see the ‘legislator’ as a ‘civic educator’.2 Rousseau gives absolute primacy to radically transformative education which makes people ‘what they ought to be’. Only Plato among earlier philosophers emphasised such transformation. But Rousseau also insists that education, however transformative, however ‘denaturing’, must finally produce autonomous adults who can say to their teachers (with Emile), ‘What course have I chosen! To remain what you have made me’ (CW 13.665/OC 4.855). How far Rousseau succeeds in finding a stable equilibrium between denaturing education, stability in a political society of citizens, and final adult autonomy is the central difficulty of his social thought, as the following pages will try to show. In this chapter Rousseau’s theory of the general will is compared with ‘Kantian’ universal morality. At times something like a conversation between Rousseau and Kant is broached. Of course, Rousseau’s relevant work was produced in the 1750s and 60s; Kant’s philosophical works appeared in the 1780s. But there is a significant sense in which Rousseau can intelligibly be read as doubting (in advance of Kant) that a Kantian kind of morality and moral subject was possible, although in many other ways he can be read as a precursor of Kantian ideas. Rousseau’s account of general morality involves an understanding of education which takes place in the biological and human time that frames individual subjects, and which takes place also in the ‘civic’ or ‘political’ time in which the institutions and practices of societies and states bring about changes in the public political culture, and

116

Patrick Riley

in the mentality and morality, of citizens and subjects. For Kant, by contrast, one is not made free or moral in time: one simply knows the moral imperatives, and takes oneself to be free and able to comply with their commands. Where Kant offers rational universal cosmopolitan morality valid for persons, Rousseau offers educator-shaped, general, legislated, political civility for citizens. However, there are also passages in Rousseau which suggest that Rousseau also has an idea of ‘the end of time’ – a point at which freedom is perfected and authority perfectly accepted. At such points Rousseau’s theory seems to be ‘out of time’. The next, extensive, section of this paper analyses how Rousseau understands the relationships between generalised (as opposed to individual, particular) will, individual autonomy, and educational authority and power. In setting out his philosophical understanding of these matters, Rousseau’s relationship to the intellectual currents of his time, and, in particular, his consideration of the rival ‘kantian’ (in advance of Kant) position is explored.

Freedom, the general will and education In order to make sense of some of the structural features of Rousseau’s political thought, we have to see that he was concerned centrally and above all with freedom. In particular, the notion of the general will could not otherwise have become the core idea of his political philosophy. The general will as a concept goes decidedly beyond the idea of generality or unity – the ‘many as one’ – as that is articulated by Plato (Republic, 462b) or Montesquieu (1949, pp. 1134–44). Instead, Rousseau speaks in the Considerations on the government of Poland (and elsewhere) of generalising the will as something central but as difficult as squaring the circle (CW 11.170/OC 3.955). It is difficult because one must ‘denature’ particularistic beings without destroying their (ultimate) autonomy. It is necessary because ‘taking away all his freedom of will is taking away all morality from his actions’ (CW 4.135/OC 3.356) and ‘civil association is the most voluntary act in the world’ (CW 4.200/OC 3.440). The Legislator has to achieve his civic results by strikingly tortured means – he has to ‘win over without violence and persuade without convincing’ (CW 4.156/OC 3.383). Plato did not worry about this kind of difficulty because the philosopher-king simply knew the eternal verities, such as ‘absolute goodness’ (Phaedo, 7d) which even the gods know and love (Euthyphro, 10d-e), and therefore he deserved to educate and rule (Republic, IV). For Rousseau in the Social contract, ‘the union of understanding and will’ is needed for perfect politics so that the Legislator’s civic knowledge is finally, at the end of civic time, absorbed into an (originally ignorant) popular general will which is ultimately as ‘enlightened’ as it was always ‘right’ (CW 4.154/OC 3.380). The general will before Rousseau Here the history of the general will before Rousseau is illuminating. (For a full treatment of the subject, see Riley, 1986.) In Rousseau, the general will is

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

117

non-natural: it is artificially produced (over time) through the ‘denaturing’, counter-egotistic educative ministrations of a Legislator – although at the end of education informed, independent choice must finally be possible. In the thought of the 17th-century inventors of the idea, however, the general will of God to ‘save all men’ after the Fall is naturally general: the will of a perfect being could not be ‘denatured’ or transformed, or made over time to become what he ‘naturally’ was not. Rousseau knew intimately the entire seventeenth-century controversy over ‘general will’ and knew too that a non-divinity must be (to revise a phrase) ‘forced to be general’. Indeed, the central problem of all Rousseau’s thought is to find a form of non-authoritarian educative authority which will make men ‘what one needs them to be’ (CW 3.148/OC 3.251), without (permanently) depriving them of the freedom without which, as he put it in the ‘Letter to Franquières’, ‘neither virtues, nor vices, neither merit, nor demerit, nor morality in human actions’ is conceivable (CW 8.269/OC 4.1145). Rousseau’s aim is to ‘generalise’ will over time without destroying freedom. This makes it crucial that he find a non-authoritarian authority that can ‘win over without violence’. Rousseau’s reasons for using ‘general will’ as his central political concept were essentially philosophical. This is no matter how ready-made for his purposes the seventeenth-century theological notion may seem to have been. Does not the Spartan mother have a ‘general’ will to ‘save’ the city, as God has a general will to save ‘all men’? Philosophically, though, the two terms, ‘will’ and ‘generality’, represent two main strands in Rousseau’s thought. ‘Generality’ stands, inter alia, for the rule of law, for civic education that draws us out of ourselves and toward the general (or common) good, and for the non-particularist citizen-virtues of Sparta and republican Rome (see especially the Considerations on the government of Poland, CW 11.167-240/OC 3.951-1041). ‘Will’ stands, again, for Rousseau’s conviction that civil association is ‘the most voluntary act in the world’, that ‘taking away all [one’s] freedom of will is taking away all morality from [one’s] actions’. And if one could ‘generalise’ the will, so that it ‘elects’ only law, citizenship and the common good, and avoids willful self-love, then one would have a general will in Rousseau’s particular sense. The (originally divine) volonté générale of Pascal, Malebranche, Fénelon and Leibniz corresponded closely to these moral aims; why not employ a term already rendered politically usable by Bayle in the Pensées diverses sur la comète (Bayle, 1704, pp. 452ff)? Kant and Hegel At this point a comparison with Kant and Hegel will be helpful. (For full discussion of Rousseau, Kant and Hegel on voluntarism, see Riley, 1982.) All three are voluntarists who make ‘will’ ethically weighty (in the shape of ‘general will’, ‘good will’ and [so-called] ‘real will’). All three are in search of a non-willful will; all are in full flight from capricious particular will. According to Kant one ‘ought’ to move on to a universal Kingdom of Ends or (failing that) at least to universal republicanism and eternal peace (Kant, 1922, pp. 161–162; see also Riley, 1983,

118

Patrick Riley

pp. 167ff). Hegel wants our ‘real’ will to be ‘recognition’ of the state as rational freedom concretely realised (Hegel, 1942, p. 105; see also Kelly, 1978, pp. 113–114; Oakeshott, 1975, p. 160). For Rousseau, by contrast, the flight from egoism and the invidious comparative self-love that he calls amour propre ends with the conduct of the ‘Spartan mother’ in Emile who does not want to know whether her sons are dead, but whether the state has won the battle (CW 13.164/OC 4.249). Kant, more easily than either Rousseau or Hegel, preserves freedom or autonomy – because what ‘generalises’ (or rather universalises) will is reason-ordained ‘objective ends’, not a Legislator nor self-formation in education. Rousseau doubted that there could be a reason-ordained universal morality. For him the crucial line should be drawn between the ‘general’ and the ‘universal’, the polis and the cosmopolis. Rousseau set himself the daunting task of generalising will without recourse to ‘objective ends’ – but with recourse to educative authority whose highest ambition is to wither away after injecting its (civic, ‘politan’) knowledge into beings who become free in the course of time. Kant and Kantianism That our reason has causality, or that we at least represent it to ourselves as having causality, is evident from the imperatives which in all matters of conduct we impose as rules upon our active powers. ‘“Ought” expresses a kind of necessity … which is found nowhere else in the whole of nature. The understanding can know in nature only what is, what has been, or what will be … When we have the course of nature alone in view, “ought” has no meaning whatsoever’ (Kant, 1998, A 547/B 575). Precisely here – and equally in The critique of practical reason’s insistence that the moral law is just there as a ‘fact of reason’, underivable from anything else (nature, custom, God) (Kant, 1996b, p. 164) – lies the gulf that separates Rousseau and Kant (anti-willful voluntarists though they both are). If, for Rousseau, reason had ‘causality’, we would not stand in need of the Legislator’s educative ‘causality’. The will would be generalised (or rather universalised) by a Kantian ‘objective end’ (respect for persons as members of a kingdom of ends) which is unproblematic for freedom because all rational beings simply ‘see’ that end (at the age of reason). The whole Kantian ‘universalising’ operation is completely impersonal: there is no person (Lycurgus) bending backwards to be impersonal, non-authoritarian, persuading-without-convincing. In Kant one is not made free (in time): one simply knows ‘ought’ and takes oneself to be free (able to perform ought’s commands) ab initio. Of course – and Rousseau would (reasonably) insist on this – Kantianism works only if there are universal, reasonordained ‘objective ends’ which we ‘ought to have’. Rousseau worried about every term in that sentence: whether we can know a universal morality which is ‘beyond’ the general, whether ‘reason’ ordains anything (morally), whether there are ‘ends’ that all rational beings ‘see’ (as facts of reason). Negatively, Kant and Rousseau are companions-in-flight from self-loving particular will. Positively, they offer contrasting possibilities once that flight is over. Kant offers rational,

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

119

universal, cosmopolitan morality valid for persons. Rousseau offers educatorshaped, general, political civility valid for a Citizen of Geneva, or of Sparta. Diderot Rousseau’s radical doubts about the real existence of any universal, reasonordained morality come out most plainly and brilliantly in the (unpublished) First version of the Social contract, the so-called Geneva manuscript, where he refutes Diderot’s article for the Encyclopedia on ‘Natural Right’. Diderot had argued that ‘if we take from the individual the right to decide the nature of the just and the unjust’ we must then ‘bring this great question … before the human race’, for the ‘good of all’ is the ‘only passion’ that this most-inclusive group has. Paralleling Rousseau (initially), Diderot goes on to say that ‘individual wills are suspect’, for they can be indifferently good or wicked, but that ‘the general will is always good’, since ‘it has never been mistaken’ and never will be. It is to this always-good, never-deceiving general will that ‘the individual should address himself’, Diderot insists, ‘in order to find out to what extent he should be man, citizen, subject, father, child, and when it is suitable for him to live and to die’ (Diderot, reprinted in Rousseau CW 3.137). So far, no great gap has opened up between Diderot and Rousseau. But when Diderot begins to indicate where the general will is deposited, he moves in the direction of a proto-Kantian universalism which is (usually) foreign to the citizen of Geneva. One can ‘consult’ the general will, he urges, ‘[i]n the written principles of Right of all civilized nations, in the social actions of savage and barbarian peoples, in the tacit conventions of the enemies of the human race amongst themselves; and even in indignation and resentment, the two passions that nature seems to have even given to animals to make up for the absence of social laws and public vengeance’ (CW 3.138). Diderot’s nominal generality is, in fact, a universal morality (to use his own term). It relates to all humans, and seems to extend even to honour among thieves. Rousseau’s general will – of Rome, of Sparta, of Geneva – is a great deal more particular. Indeed in the Considerations on the government of Poland Rousseau insists on the importance of national peculiarities and particularities that should not be submerged in a cosmopolitan universalism. For Diderot, then, the general will is to be found almost everywhere, whereas Rousseau doubts that it has ever been fully realised anywhere. In the next section of ‘Natural Right’, Diderot goes on to urge that ‘the general will is in each individual a pure act of the understanding which reasons in the silence of the passions on what a man can demand of his fellow and on what his fellow has the right to require of him’ (CW 3.138). At this point, Diderot begins to be separated from Rousseau. Rousseau would have stressed precisely ‘citizenship’ and ‘Geneva’, and would never have urged that general will is immediately dictated by understanding or reason (as distinguished from will-generalising civic education). Had Rousseau thought that, the passions being ‘silent’ (a phrase Diderot borrows from Malebranche), understanding and reason could alone dictate what is right, he would never have made his famous claim in

120

Patrick Riley

The social contract that the ‘general will is always right, but the judgment that guides it is not always enlightened’ (CW 5.154/OC 3.380). If reason alone dictated right (as in Kant it furnishes ‘ought’), Rousseauean men would have no need of a Legislator, nor of an Educator, to help effect ‘a union of understanding and will’. Book 1, chapter 2 of the Geneva manuscript is a refutation of Diderot’s rationalism and universalism; but it also provides more than a hint of what Rousseau would have said about Kant’s distinctive way of combining ‘ought’ and freedom. At one time, to be sure, Rousseau had himself stressed a roughly comparable universal morality; in an early, unpublished fragment from around 1737 called the Universal chronology he had appealed to Fénelon’s notion of a universal Christian republic: We are all brothers, our neighbor ought to be as dear to us as we ourselves; I love the human race more than my fatherland, said the illustrious M. de Fenelon, my fatherland more than my family, and my family more than myself. Sentiments so full of humanity ought to be common to all men … The Universe is a large family of which we are all members … however small the extent of a private individual’s power might be, he is always in a condition to make himself useful somewhere to the great body of which he makes up a part; if he can, he owes it indispensably. (CW 11.2/OC 5.488) Later, and most clearly of all in the Geneva manuscript, Rousseau would abandon the universal in favour of the general, and would exchange the ‘Christian republic’ for the more modest Sparta, Rome and Geneva. That Rousseau is not going to argue for a reason-ordained universal morality valid for the entire human race is evident in the opening sentence of the Geneva manuscript: ‘Let us begin by inquiring why the necessity for political institutions arises’ (CW 4.76/OC 3.281). If a passion-silencing reason spoke to and governed all men, no mere particular political institutions would arise at all (as Locke had already shown in section 128 of the Second treatise, saying that only a ‘corrupt’ rejection of reason keeps a unitary, unified mankind from being perfectly governed by natural law). Rousseau is struck by the beauty of Diderot’s universal morality: ‘Indeed, no one will deny that the general will in each individual is a pure act of the understanding, which reasons in the silence of the passions about what man can demand of his fellow man and what his fellow man has the right to demand of him’ (CW 4.80/OC 3.286). But, Rousseau immediately and characteristically asks, ‘where is the man who can be so objective about himself; and if concern for his selfpreservation is nature’s first precept, can he be forced to look in this manner at the species in general in order to impose on himself duties whose connection with his particular constitution is not evident to him’ (CW 4.80/OC 3.286)? If reason is not directly morally efficacious (as it cannot be, if great legislators are to have the important formative function that is assigned to them in the Social contract), and if ‘natural law’ is scarcely natural (as the Second discourse tries to prove), then the natural man who fails to find his particular good in the general

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

121

good will instead become the enemy of the human race, allying himself with the strong and the unjust to despoil the weak. ‘It is false’, Rousseau insists, ‘that in the state of independence, reason leads us to cooperate for the common good out of a perception of our own interest’ (CW 4.79/OC 3.284). So strongly does this current of thought sweep Rousseau along that he mounts a brief assault on generality that would be fatal not just to Diderot, but to his own political aims as well: If the general society [of the human race] did exist somewhere other than in the systems of Philosophers, it would be, as I have said, a moral Being with qualities separate and distinct from those of particular Beings constituting it, somewhat like chemical compounds which have properties that do not belong to any of the elements composing them. There would be a universal language which nature would teach all men and which would be their first means of mutual communication. There would be a kind of central nervous system which would connect all the parts. The public good or ill would not be merely the sum of private goods and ills as in a simple aggregation, but would lie in the liaison uniting them. It would be greater than this sum, and public felicity, far from being based on the happiness of private individuals [des particuliers], would itself be the source of this happiness. (CW 4.78-9/OC 3.284) Plainly this argument goes too far, since Rousseau himself wants to argue for a general good that is more than a mere sum or aggregation of private goods and ills; it is no wonder that he suppressed the Geneva manuscript. Nevertheless the dilemma remains that a general society cannot be produced by passion-silencing ‘reason’ alone. The only way out of the dilemma, according to Rousseau, is through denatured, non-natural ‘new associations’ (Sparta, Rome, Geneva) that take the place of well-meant but imaginary reason-governed general societies, and which, through rigorous civic education, draw natural beings out of their (equally natural) ego-centrism, bringing them to think of themselves (finally) as ‘parts of a greater whole’ – a whole less extensive, but more realisable, than a ‘Christian republic’ or a kingdom of ends. The particular social remedies designed to overcome particularity and self-preference at the end of the second chapter of the Geneva manuscript are rather abstractly, even vaguely characterised (‘new associations’, ‘new insights’, ‘perfected art’) (CW 4.82/OC 3.288); but one knows from other works such as the Discourse on political economy and the Considerations on the government of Poland how Rousseau proposes to produce, through an educative shaping which finally yields ‘enlightened’ free choice, a civic general will which is certainly no cosmopolitan ‘universal spirit’. Reason and freedom Rousseau shared with modern individualist thinkers (notably Hobbes and Locke) the conviction that all political life is conventional, that it can be made

122

Patrick Riley

obligatory only through voluntary, individual consent. Despite the fact that he sometimes treats moral ideas as if they simply ‘arise’ in a developmental process, in the course of socialisation (in, for example, the ‘Letter to Beaumont’, CW 9.35/OC 4.945), he often falls back on the view that the wills of free men are the ‘causes’ of duties and of legitimate authority. Thus, in an argument against slavery in the Social contract, Rousseau urges that ‘taking away all [one’s] freedom of will is taking away all morality from [one’s] actions’ (CW 4.135/OC 3.356), and that the reason one can derive no notion of right or morality from mere force is that ‘[y]ielding to force is an act of necessity, not of will’ (CW 4.133/OC 3.354). In the Second discourse, in a passage that almost prefigures Kant, he insists on the importance of free agency, arguing that while ‘Physics’ (natural science) might explain ‘the mechanism of the senses and the formation of ideas’, it could never make intelligible ‘the power of willing, or rather of choosing, and in the sentiment of this power are found only spiritual acts about which the Laws of Mechanics explain nothing’ (CW 3.26/OC 3.142). It is this power of freely willing, rather than reason, that distinguishes men from beasts. All of this is confirmed by what Rousseau says about will in Emile, where he argues (through a speech put into the mouth of the Savoyard Vicar) that the ‘principle of every action is in the will of a free being’, and that ‘[o]ne cannot go back beyond that’, for ‘[i]t is not the word freedom which means nothing; it is the word necessity’ (CW 13.442/OC 4.586). The will is ‘independent of my senses; I consent or I resist; I succumb or I conquer; and I sense perfectly within myself when I do what I wanted to do or when all I am doing is giving way to my passions’ (CW 13. 441/OC 4.585-6). ‘If man is active and free’, the Vicar concludes, ‘he acts on his own’ (CW 13.442/OC 4.587). Moreover, human free will does not derogate from Providence, but magnifies it, since God has ‘given him an excellent nature’ and has ‘put in man’s actions the morality which ennobles them’ (CW 13.442-3/OC 4.587). Rousseau cannot agree with those theologians (for example, Hobbes) who argue that human freedom would diminish God by robbing him of his omnipotence: [Providence] has made him free in order that by choice he do not evil but good… What more could divine power itself do for us? Could it make our nature contradictory and give the reward for having done well to him who did not have the power to do evil? What! To prevent man from being wicked, was it necessary to limit him to instinct and make him a beast? (CW 13.442-3/OC 4.587) To be sure, the pre-Kantian voluntarism of Emile and of the Second discourse is not the whole story. In the Moral letters of 1757, which were used as a source in writing Emile, the relation of free will to morality is complicated and problematical. (On the importance of the Letters see Shklar, 1969, pp. 229–230.) The opening of the fifth Letter – ‘The entire morality of human life is in man’s intention’ (CW 12.193/OC 4.1106) – seems at first to be a voluntarist claim,

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

123

almost prefiguring Kant’s notion in the Groundwork that a ‘good will’ is the only ‘unqualifiedly’ good thing on earth (Kant, 1996a, p. 49). But this intention refers not to the ‘will’ of Emile, but to ‘conscience’ – which is a ‘divine instinct’ and an ‘immortal and celestial voice’ (CW, 12.197/OC 4.1111). Rousseau, after a striking passage on moral feelings – ‘Does one see some act of violence and injustice in the street or on a path, instantly a movement of rage and indignation rises up in the depths of one’s heart’ (CW 12.194/ OC 4.1106) – goes on to speak of ‘the cry of remorse that punishes hidden crimes in secret’; and this ‘intrusive voice’ he calls an ‘involuntary feeling’ (sentiment involontaire) which ‘gives us so many torments’ (CW 12.194/ OC 4.1107). That the phrase sentiment involontaire is not a mere slip of the pen (or of the mind) is proven by Rousseau’s deliberate repetition of ‘involuntary’: There is then in the depths of all souls an innate principle of justice and moral truth anterior to all national prejudices, to all maxims of education. This principle is the involuntary rule [la règle involontaire] based on which we judge our actions and those of others as good or bad in spite of our own maxims, and it is to this principle that I give the name of conscience. (CW 12.195/OC 4.1108) Conscience, then, is an involuntary moral feeling – not surprisingly, given Rousseau’s view that ‘our sensitivity is incontestably prior to our reason itself’ (CW 12.196/OC 4.1109). And so, while the fifth of the Moral letters opens with an apparent anticipation of Emile’s voluntarism, this is only an appearance that proves that it is not straightforwardly right to find in Rousseau a predecessor of Kant. Rousseau’s morale sensitive (one strand of his thought) is not easy to reconcile with rational self-determination (another, equally authentic, strand) for Rousseau says both that to deprive the will of freedom is to deprive one’s actions of morality, as we have seen, and also that conscience is a sentiment which is involuntaire. The fact remains, however, that while Emile was published, the Moral letters were held back. And in Emile Rousseau insists on the moral centrality of free will. Hence he can understand ‘will’ as an independent moral causality with the power to produce moral effects. He definitely thought that he had derived political obligation and rightful political authority from this ‘power’ of willing: ‘For civil association is the most voluntary act in the world. Since every man is born free and master of himself no one, under any pretext whatever, can subject him without his consent’ (CW 4.200/OC 3.440). Indeed, the first four chapters of the Social contract are devoted to refutations of erroneous theories of obligation and right – paternal authority, the ‘right of the strongest’ and obligations derived from slavery. ‘Since no man has any natural authority over his fellow man’, Rousseau concludes, ‘and since force produces no right, there remain only conventions as the basis of all legitimate authority among men’ (CW 4.134/ OC 3.355).

124

Patrick Riley

Educational authority and time ‘Will’ is plainly a central moral, political and theological notion in Rousseau’s thought, and his constant aim, indeed, is to ‘generalise’ will (CW 4.96-7/OC 3.307) – either through civic education, as in the Social contract and the Considerations on the government of Poland, or through private education, as in Emile. In his view, ancient societies such as Sparta and Rome had been particularly adept at generalising human will. Through their simplicity, their morality of the common good, their civic religion, their moral use of fine and military arts, and their lack of extreme individualism and private interest, the city-states of antiquity had been political societies in the proper sense. In them man had been part of a greater whole from which he ‘receives, in a sense, his life and his being’ (CW 4.155/OC 3.381). On the other hand, modern ‘prejudices’, ‘base philosophy’ and ‘passions of petty self-interest’ (CW 11.171/OC 3.956) assure that ‘the moderns no longer find in themselves any of that vigor of soul that everything inspired in the ancients’ (CW 11.173/OC 3.959). And that ‘vigor of soul’ may be taken to mean the avoidance – through identity with a greater whole – of self-love, ‘this dangerous disposition from which all our vices arise’ (CW 3.155/OC 3.260). Political education in an extremely unified (‘generalised’) state will, Rousseau writes in the Discourse on political economy, ‘draw us out of ourselves’ and provide us with a general will before the human ego ‘has acquired that contemptible activity that absorbs all virtue and constitutes the life of petty souls’ (CW 3.155/OC 3.260). It follows that the best social institutions, he says at the start of Emile, ‘are those that best know how to denature man, to take his absolute existence from him in order to give him a relative one and transport the I into the common unity’ (CW 13.164/OC 4.249). Rousseau found difficulty in making free will and rational, educative authority coexist in his practical thought. How to retain the moral attributes of free will while doing away with will’s particularity and selfishness and ‘willfulness’; how to generalise this moral ‘cause’ without causing its destruction? Freedom of the will is as important to the morality of actions for Rousseau as for any voluntarist coming after Augustine’s insistence that a good will (bona voluntas) alone is good (Augustine, 1993, book 1, chapter 12). But Rousseau was suspicious of the very ‘faculty’ – the only faculty – that could moralise. Thus he urges in the Discourse on political economy that the ‘most absolute authority is that which penetrates to the inner man and is exerted no less on his will than on his actions’ (CW 3.148/OC 3.251). Can the will be both an autonomous ‘moral cause’ and subject to the rationalising, generalising effect of educative authority? This is Rousseau’s constant difficulty. Even Emile, the best educated of men, chooses to continue to accept the guidance of his teachers right at the end of the work: ‘Advise us and govern us. We shall be docile. As long as I live, I shall need you’ (CW 13.675/OC 4.868). How much more, then, do ordinary men need the guidance of a ‘great legislator’ – the Numa or Moses or Lycurgus of whom Rousseau speaks so often, for example, in the Considerations on the government of Poland (CW 11.171-4/OC 3.956-9) – when they embark on the setting up

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

125

of a system which will not only aid and defend but also moralise them. The general will is dependent on ‘the union of understanding and will in the social body’ (CW 4.154/OC 3.380); but that understanding, which is provided (at least initially) by educative authority – rather than by a Kantian ‘fact of reason’ giving (timeless) ‘objective ends’ – is difficult to make perfectly congruent with ‘will’ as an autonomous ‘moral cause’. This notion of the relation of educative authority to will appears both in Rousseau’s theories of public or civic education and also in his theory of private education. In educating a child, Rousseau advises the tutor in Emile, ‘Let him always believe he is the master, and let it always be who you are. There is no subjection so perfect as that which keeps the appearance of freedom. Thus the will itself is made captive’ (CW 13.257/OC 4.362). One can hardly help asking what has become of ‘will’ when it has been ‘made captive’, and whether it is enough to preserve the mere ‘appearance’ of freedom. It has been argued that Rousseau simply was not ‘worried by the gap which opens up between the appearance and the reality of freedom’ (Charvet, 1974, p. 58). Actually Rousseau appears to have been of two minds: the poor who ‘agree’ to a social contract that merely legitimises the holdings of the rich preserve the appearance of freedom, but Rousseau in the Second discourse dismisses this contract as a fraud (CW 3.53-4/OC 3.177). On the other hand, will is ‘made captive’ in Emile, and ‘penetrated’ by authority in the Discourse on political economy; and neither that captivity nor that penetration is criticised by Rousseau – despite his dictum about depriving one’s actions of ‘all morality’ if one takes away the freedom of the will. So one sees again why a general will would appeal to him: capricious willfulness would be ‘canceled’, will rationalised by authority, ‘preserved’ (Hegel, 1967, p. 234). If will in Rousseau is generalised primarily through an educative authority, so that volition as ‘moral cause’ is not quite as free as he would sometimes prefer, it is at least arguable that any tension between ‘will’ and the authority that ‘generalises’ it is only a provisional problem. Rousseau seems to have hoped that at the end of political time (so to speak) men would finally be citizens and would will only the common good in virtue of what they had learned over time; at the end of civic time, they might actually be free, and not just ‘forced to be free’ (CW 4.141/OC 3.364). At the end of its political education – no more ‘denaturing’ or transformative than any true education – political society would finally be in a position to say what Emile says at the end of his ‘domestic’ education, that he chooses to ‘remain what you have made me’ (CW 13.665/OC 4.855). At this point (of ‘decision’) there would be a ‘union of understanding and will’ in politics, but one in which ‘understanding’ is no longer the private possession of a legislator. At this point, too, ‘agreement’ and ‘contract’ would finally have real meanings: the ‘general will’, which is ‘always right’, would be enlightened as well, and contract would go beyond being a mere rich man’s confidence trick (legalising unequal property) that it is in the Second discourse. At the end of political time, the general will one has ‘as a citizen’ would have become a kind of second nature, approaching the true naturalness of volonté générale in the

126

Patrick Riley

seventeenth-century version of the divine modus operandi. ‘Approaching’, however, is the strongest term one can use, and the relation of will to the educative authority that generalises it remains a problem in Rousseau – the more so because he often denied (in his more Lockean moods) that there is any natural authority on earth (CW 4. 134/OC 3.355). We still might ask how one can reconcile Rousseau’s insistence on an allshaping educative authority with his equal insistence on free choice and personal autonomy. A possible answer is: through his theory of education, which is at the heart of his thought – the one thing that can make Rousseauianism ‘work’. At the end of civic time, when men have been denatured and transformed into citizens, they will finally have civic knowledge and general will – just as adults finally have the moral knowledge and the independence that they (necessarily) lacked as children. For Rousseau there are unavoidable stages in all education, whether private or public. The child, he says in Emile, must first learn necessity, then utility and finally morality, in that inescapable order. If one says ‘ought’ to an infant he simply reveals his own ignorance and folly. This notion of necessary educational time, of becoming what one was not, is revealed perfectly in Emile’s utterance, when he chooses ‘to remain what you have made me’. That is deliberately paradoxical – many of Rousseau’s central moral/political beliefs are cast in the form of paradoxes. However, it does show that the capacity to ‘decide’ is indeed ‘made’. It is education that ‘forces one to be free’ – by slowly ‘generalising’ the will. Similarly, Rousseau’s ‘nations’ are at first ignorant: ‘For nations as for men there is a time of youth, or maturity if you prefer, that must be awaited before subjecting them to laws’ (CW 4.158/OC 3.386). Waiting, however, requires time; autonomy arrives at the end of a process, and the general will is at last as enlightened as it was (always) right. On the most favourable reading, then, Rousseau does not, as some critics allege, vibrate incoherently between ‘Platonic’ education and ‘Lockean’ voluntariness; if his notion of becomingin-time works, then the généralité of antiquity and the volonté of modernity are truly fused by this ‘modern who has an ancient soul’.

Conclusion In the end, for Rousseau, no universal morality – not a Christian one based on universal charity, nor a Diderotian one grounded in passion-silencing reason, nor a Kantian one resting on reason-ordained ‘objective ends’ – can help in the transformation of natural men into denatured citizens. The générale must be (somewhat) particulière. This explains the weight which Rousseau gives to education. For him, men do not naturally think of themselves as parts of a greater whole – a genre humain or a Reich der Zwecke – and must therefore be brought to a non-natural civic belief. But at the end of civic time – if volonté is to be equal to généralité – they must finally see the force of Emile’s decision ‘to remain what you have made me’. Rousseau not only wanted to ‘secularise’ the general will – to turn it (mainly) away from theology (and God’s will to save ‘all men’); he wanted to endow

Rousseau’s philosophy of transformative, ‘denaturing’ education

127

human beings with a will, a really efficacious ‘power’ of choosing, which can then be subjected to the generalising influence of civic education – a republican education which Montesquieu eloquently described but took to have vanished from the modern (monarchical) world. First real will, then general will: that is what Rousseau would say to his great French predecessors. And if that will can be generalised by a non-authoritarian educative authority, the final product will be the realisation of Rousseau’s highest civic ideal: the volonté générale one has ‘as a citizen’.

Notes 1 For all references to Rousseau’s texts in this paper, CW refers to the University Press of New England’s Collected Writings of Rousseau edition and OC to the Bibliothèque de la Pléiade’s Oeuvres complètes, followed by the relevant volume and page numbers. 2 This paper is a revised and edited version of ‘Rousseau’s general will: freedom of a particular kind’, Political Studies, XXXIX, pp. 55–74, 1991; by permission of John Wiley and Sons.

References Augustine (1993) On free choice of the will (trans. T. Williams) (Indianapolis, Hackett). Bayle, P. (1704) Pensées diverses, Ecrites à un docteur de Sorbonne [Diverse thoughts, writings of a doctor of Sorbonne] (4th edn.) (Rotterdam, Reinier Leers). Charvet, J. (1974) The social problem in the philosophy of Rousseau (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Hegel, G. (1942) Philosophy of right (trans. T. M. Knox) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Hegel, G. (1967) Phenomenology of mind (ed. & trans. J. B. Baillie) (New York, Harper & Row). Kant, I. (1922) Rechtslehre [The doctrine of right], in: E. Cassirer (ed.) Immanuel Kants Werke (Volume 7) (Berlin, Bruno Cassirer Verlag), 3–180. Kant, I. (1996a) Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals, in: M. J. Gregor (ed.) (trans. A. W. Wood) Practical philosophy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 37–108. Kant, I. (1996b) Critique of practical reason, in: M. J. Gregor (ed.) (trans. A. W. Wood) Practical philosophy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 133–271. Kant, I. (1998) Critique of pure reason (ed. & trans. P. Guyer & A. W. Wood) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Kelly, G. A. (1978) Hegel’s retreat from Eleusis (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Malebranche, N. (1958) Traité de la nature et de la grace [Treatise on Nature and Grace], in: A. Robinet (ed.) Oeuvres complètes (Paris, Vrin), vol. 1. Montesquieu. (1949) Mes pensées [My thoughts], in: R. Caillois (ed.) Oeuvres completès (Paris, Pléiade), vol. 1, 1134–1144. Oakeshott, M. (1975) On human conduct (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Plato (1961) Plato: the collected dialogues (eds E. Hamilton & H. Cairns) (New York, Bollingen). Riley, P. (1982) Will and political legitimacy: a critical exposition of social contract theory in Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Kant and Hegel (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Riley, P. (1983) Kant’s political philosophy (Totowa, NJ, Rowman & Littlefield).

128

Patrick Riley

Riley, P. (1986) The general will before Rousseau (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Rousseau, J.-J. (1990–2010) Collected writings of Rousseau (eds R. D. Masters & C. Kelly) (Hanover, NH, University Press of New England), 13 vols. Rousseau, J.-J. (1959–1995) Oeuvres complètes (eds B. Gagnebin & M. Raymond) (Paris, Gallimard), 5 vols. Shklar, J. (1969) Men and citizens: a study of Rousseau’s social theory (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

9

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment Ryan Patrick Hanley

Introduction The Scottish Enlightenment is celebrated for its many contributions to the natural sciences, the social sciences, and the moral sciences; a wide range of modern academic disciplines – including economics, history, and sociology – can even trace their origins to it. But for all this attention, one aspect of the Scottish Enlightenment has been almost entirely neglected by popular commentators and specialists alike: its educational theory. In what follows, I aim to illuminate the relationship between the educational theory of the Scottish Enlightenment and the moral psychology and political theory of commerce, corruption, and the civilising process that have long been recognised as distinguishing features of Scottish thought in the eighteenth century. In so doing I aim to complement the many existing studies of eighteenthcentury Scottish educational institutions – from the parish and burgh schools to the universities – that have emphasised the relationship between such institutions and the improving spirit associated with the Scottish Enlightenment.1 This spirit was particularly evident in the universities of Glasgow and Aberdeen and Edinburgh, which have long been recognised as major centres of pedagogical innovation as well as theological liberalisation as they struggled to emerge from the domination of Calvinism in the first half of the eighteenth century,2 and become dynamic institutions of education in both public virtue and practical morality and the natural sciences and mathematics.3 All of this has been carefully and well studied. Yet what has not been a focus of study is the close relationship of eighteenth-century Scottish educational theory to the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment. To begin: what exactly was this ‘social vision’? Scholars have uncovered a remarkable number of diverse concerns under this general aegis, but it seems fair to say that at its heart lay a certain understanding of human flourishing and the social institutions and individual virtues that best promote its realisation. This conception of human flourishing was particularly rooted in an effort to reconcile the pursuit and achievement of material opulence on a collective level with the pursuit and achievement of moral excellence on an individual level – that is, to combine ‘wealth and virtue’ (Hont & Ignatieff, 1983). In this sense, Scottish

130

Ryan Patrick Hanley

concern with progress was hardly limited to material progress, but extended to a concern to promoting the moral development of both the individual and society. Of course, to some degree such concerns were common to the European Enlightenment taken as a whole, yet in Scotland the question of the challenges and benefits of commercial society had a decidedly central place. In particular, the effort to reconcile wealth and virtue contributed to the development of several of the Scottish Enlightenment’s most distinctive contributions to the social sciences, including the effort to define a ‘science of man’ dedicated to the empirical study of human phenomena, the development of historical narratives capable of explaining the progress of society from savagery to civilisation or ‘rudeness to refinement’, the emergence of a distinctive approach to political economy, and the articulation of an ethical system suited to a commercial age.4 The educational theory of the Scottish Enlightenment was conceived in this context and sought to contribute to this social vision. Among its principal aims was to explain how modern citizens might be best equipped to meet the new challenges of commercial modernity. This project compelled a creative rethinking of the aims of a liberal education (Rhyn, 1999, pp. 5, 12), and particularly a shift to the view that ‘the liberal arts were not to be indulged as ornamental accomplishments, but as a vital forming-process for the character of citizens in a modern Scottish res publica’ (Jones, 1983, p. 90). At the same time, the Scots were hardly civic republicans in any simple sense; as Roger Emerson has recently and convincingly argued, ‘the Scottish Enlightenment was not principally about politeness or civic humanism but something more basic, the remaking of a society so that it could produce men able to compete in every way in a rapidly changing world’ (Emerson, 2009, p. 19). This ambition particularly compelled a reorientation of liberal education towards ameliorating the specific challenges posed by commercial civilisation in a manner that complemented the reform of educational institutions happening simultaneously on practical level in response to this stimulus (Withrington, 1970, esp. pp. 169–170, 177–181). For all their ostensible contributions to ‘the invention of the modern world’ (Herman, 2001), the Scots knew that their invention came at a potential cost of its own – and nowhere is this so clear as in their writings on education, which, as I argue below, play a central role in the larger Scottish inquiry into how to maximise the benefits of commercial society while also controlling its costs. Taken as a whole, the educational theory of the Scottish Enlightenment focused on two main questions. First, what particular virtues are necessary in a commercial society and how can education properly conceived contribute to their cultivation? Second, what particular vices are endemic to a commercial society and how can education properly conceived contribute to their mitigation? These questions govern the brief remarks on education to be found in the works of the most prominent thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment, including David Hume, Adam Smith, and Adam Ferguson, as well as the extensive reflections found in the Scottish Enlightenment’s three main treatises on education: George Turnbull’s Observations upon liberal education (1742), David Fordyce’s Dialogues on education (1745–1748), and Henry Home, Lord Kames’ Loose

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 131 hints on education (1781). These works attest to the fact that eighteenth-century Scotland’s contributions to innovation in education go well beyond its justly celebrated institutions and extend to a reconsideration of the proper aims of a liberal education in commercial modernity – an understanding deserving the attention of intellectual historians and educational theorists alike.

George Turnbull (1698–1748) While recent editions of his works have helped to reinstate George Turnbull in the canon of the Scottish Enlightenment, he remains best known today for his service at Marischal College, Aberdeen, where he was tutor to Thomas Reid, the great Scottish philosopher. But in his own day, Turnbull was recognised as an authority on educational theory.5 Educational theory and educational reform are indeed a principal focus of all three of his major works: The principles of moral and Christian philosophy (1740), A treatise on ancient painting (1740), and Observations upon liberal education (1742). Taken collectively, these works offer the Scottish Enlightenment’s most comprehensive reflection on education’s role in ameliorating the ills of commercial society. The Principles is a broad and sprawling work treating subjects from theology to metaphysics to epistemology.6 But the departure point for this inquiry was a characteristically Scottish treatment of the foundations of civil society. These foundations are in part to be found in human moral psychology; following Shaftesbury and Hutcheson and many other challengers to the egocentric moralities of Hobbes and Mandeville, Turnbull insists that it is not egoism but sociability that is natural to man.7 Our fitness for society, he argues, is evident not simply in our natural sociability, but also in our very needs and wants – needs and wants that require the assistance of others for their satisfaction. The very origin of society indeed lies in ‘mutual wants’ that necessitate ‘mutual dependence’ and give rise in time to the ‘reciprocal interchange of friendly offices’ among men defined by ‘diversity’ and ‘inequality of talents’ (Principles 1.212–218; see also Observations 94, 119–120, 329, 358) – a vision of commercial society built on specialised interdependent labour that anticipates Adam Smith (Wealth of Nations 1.1–2). But Turnbull especially anticipates Smith in his clear-eyed assessment of the advantages and disadvantages of such a society. Turnbull knows well that some think we ‘would be happier in small bodies, without any arts, but such as are necessary to mere subsistence’. He clearly thinks this untenable and that man can only develop fully in society (see esp. Ahnert, 2007, p. 99), but at the same time is under no illusions with regard to what is at stake in our choice. To think that one can enjoy the benefits of opulence without also being subject to its characteristic vices ‘is as absurd as to eat our cake and cry for it’ (Principles 1.353–54). It thus belongs to us to choose whether we prefer a ‘simple state’ without arts or one dedicated to ‘opulence and greatness’, but our choice is to be made knowing that we ‘cannot have the goods of both at the same time’ (Principles 1.358–59). Turnbull’s own preference was clear. Yet in choosing commercial modernity, he insisted that it is also necessary to mitigate the particular ills endemic to it.

132

Ryan Patrick Hanley

What then are these ills, and in what exactly did he think ‘our present corruption’ consists (Principles 1.331)? Some direct light is shed in one of his short essays: In the age we live in, every thing conspires to insinuate early into young minds the desire of riches, as that which makes the chief joy and honour of life; and a dread and contempt of poverty, as that alone which makes miserable, or brings disgrace and shame. Avarice is now the universal passion: ambition is no more. But ’till the mind is fortified against this fatal error, none of the great virtues can grow up in it. (Prefatory discourse x; see also Observations 123) Here and elsewhere Turnbull’s main target is his society’s exacerbation of egocentrism, which expresses itself in a love of money that transforms men into ‘narrow souls, who live as if they were born for themselves only’ (Prefatory discourse xii). This position might seem to parallel a now-familiar language of classical republicanism that was a prominent feature of eighteenth-century critiques of luxury. Turnbull however pointedly rejects this ‘general, confused way of declaiming against luxury’ (Principles 1.360; Painting viii; Observations 385), and herein lies the interest in his argument. Unlike the republicans, Turnbull criticised commercial society from the inside rather than the outside. His concern was not simply that commercial avarice would lead to an effeminacy that would vitiate martial virtue (Principles 1.361; Observations 410), but rather that the excesses of the emergent commercial society in which he lived might vitiate its capacity to deliver the genuine goods of which it is capable.8 Put differently, opulence requires the stimulation of passions that promote the pursuit of external goods, yet successful attainment of such goods seems to sap the industry necessary to sustain such pursuits; in Turnbull’s words, ‘the temper and spirit necessary to acquire them’ is ‘lost by great indulgence in the enjoyment of them’ (Principles 1.355). The challenge of commercial civilisation is then to establish a balance that ‘would produce consumption necessary to the maintenance and encouragement of industry, without the decrease of the industrious spirit’ (Principles 1.357) – a challenge as much for educators as for statesmen. A primary aim of Turnbull’s Observations is thus to explain how such a balance is to be achieved in practice. And it is here that the book’s value lies. Much in the Observations, it should be said, is hardly novel; its recapitulations of previous teachings on such commonplace subjects as the relationship of active to contemplative life, the real value of the study of classical languages, and the import of encouraging children’s curiosity, can be tedious. Yet Turnbull breaks new and genuinely important ground in his treatment of education’s social role. Some of this is the result of grounding his conception of education in a new epistemological framework. In the Observations, the key problem concerns a mistake in the ‘association of ideas’.9 This epistemological focus enabled Turnbull to connect his theory of education to his political diagnosis. For in the Observations, the ‘principal art’ of a

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 133 well-regulated education was to establish in the mind of the child a just association of ideas – a task of crucial importance for both individual and social happiness as it is by the ‘association and repetition of ideas that desires or aversions are kindled into propensities or passions’ (Observations 195, 222). On these grounds, it seems right to say that ‘advice regarding the identification of unsuitable associations lies at the heart of Turnbull’s educational theory’ (Broadie, 1994, pp. 40–43, at 40; Stewart-Robertson, 1981, p. 515). What remains to be seen is the intimate connection between the educational uses of association and Turnbull’s conception of commercial civilisation and its challenges. Turnbull’s key claim on this front is that the present corruption of commercial civilisation is in fact the result of a false association of ideas. Chief among these is the too-common association of happiness with external goods, and especially with wealth – a false association that has given rise to restless anxiety and ‘splenetic fretting’ (Observations 338), as well as to a mistaken conflation of material ‘pomp and pageantry, ribbons, jewels, and other shining gew-gaws’ with ‘true beauty, real honour, and genuine unfading greatness’. And with this Turnbull explains the ‘great art of education’ in commercial society: to overcome this false association of happiness with external goods by accustoming ‘young minds early to the inward work of regulating fancy, and rectifying opinion, on which all depends’ (Observations 136–137). To some degree this could be accomplished by ‘weeding’ out those false associations (Stewart-Robertson, 1981, pp. 520–521), but better would be to nip them in the bud before they take root (see Observations 29, 67, 93, 206). Turnbull’s faith in our capacity to succeed in such an endeavour attests at once to his faith in the natural goodness of man and the essential artificiality of vice (e.g. Principles 1.320, 327–329, 364), as well as his optimistic insistence that happiness, far from the mere effect of our circumstance, is rather ‘in a great measure our own work and acquisition’ (e.g. Principles 1.318, 334–335, 339, 344–345). In a practical sense, this insistence culminates in the claim that it is ‘the great business of education’ to pre-empt the association of happiness with wealth and instead ‘form early in minds a just notion of glory; and to strengthen in them a passion for honour’ (Prefatory discourse xviii–xix; cf. Principles 1.193 and esp. Observations 80–81, 132, 138–139, 175, 268, 289). Turnbull’s hope was that by interrupting this association of happiness with signs of external opulence, a proper education would encourage its students to ‘look down with disdain upon wealth and outward grandeur’ and prefer instead the self-sufficiency of one unencumbered by dependence on external goods (Observations 333). In so doing, Turnbull sought to call the citizens of his incipient commercial republic to a reverence for ‘true magnanimity’ by preserving ‘our natural Love of Knowledge, our Sense of Beauty natural and moral, our publick and generous Affections, and our Love of Greatness; to improve and perfect which Dispositions is certainly the principal Scope of Education’ (Observations 362; Painting xxiii), and thereby provide ‘the means of inculcating the personal responsibility necessary for living in a free society’ (Moore, 2003, p. ix).

134

Ryan Patrick Hanley

David Fordyce (1711–1751) Like Turnbull, Fordyce’s principal aim as an educational theorist was to set forth a vision of the proper education for citizens of modern commercial republics. Fordyce further focused on remedying several more vicious psychological dispositions – dispositions which would, in time, occupy a central place in the critiques of commercial modernity developed by Rousseau, among others. Fordyce’s educational theory begins with a set of assumptions already familiar to readers of Turnbull. First, he assumes that the principal aim of education is to instruct its recipients in the nature and obligations of the best life – a concern reflected both in the quotation from Plato’s Republic that opens the Elements, as well as his definition of ethics at Elements 3.5.10 Second, Fordyce assumes that this best life is to be found in action rather than contemplation; indeed the denigration of the ‘mere bookworm’ and concomitant celebration of the virtues of ‘men of action and business’ – men whose virtue is cultivated in the bustle of the world rather than the quiet of the cloister or library – is among the most frequently repeated tropes across his two quite repetitive works (e.g. Elements 57, 71; Dialogues 1.27, 1.87, 1.156–157, 2.63–64, 2.302). This concern is itself evidence of Fordyce’s ‘Scottish’ perspective; indeed in claiming that man is ‘principally formed for Action’, Fordyce would proclaim his allegiance to one of the Scottish Enlightenment’s central articles of faith (Dialogues 2.223; cf. Hanley, 2008, 36–38). And this would play a prominent role in Fordyce’s educational theory, particularly in the Dialogues, dedicated chiefly to articulating a vision of ‘an ideal academy’ whose activities and ends are ‘civic rather than merely educational’ (Jones, 1983, p. 109, see also p. 116). Yet Fordyce’s most important connection to the social theory of the Scottish Enlightenment lies in his conception of the origins and nature of society. Fordyce’s social theory begins with the insistence that human beings are naturally sociable (Elements 102). On such a foundation, he built his theory of society – a theory which, echoing Turnbull and anticipating Smith, would seek to employ this natural sociability in a system of mutual interdependence or ‘mutual necessity’ which promotes the ‘connection’ that binds those of diverse station into a unified body capable of satisfying reciprocal needs (see e.g. Elements 88–89, 94–98). But Fordyce’s discussion of sociability also goes a step further – a step that takes his discussion beyond Turnbull and brings him closer to some of the more sophisticated social analyses of Smith and the later Scottish Enlightenment. This was to recognise that natural sociability is not only the impetus for the development of civil society but also a force that continues to shape social interaction in civil society via its manifestation in sympathy (Elements 26, 44, 90–91; cf. Dialogues 1.350, 2.157–158). Fordyce was neither the first nor the last Scottish thinker to attend to the role of sympathy. What makes his analysis unique was his explicit emphasis on its dual nature. On the one hand, sympathy – and especially the indignation it sometimes prompts – promotes justice (see Elements 45). On the other hand, sympathy – and especially its tendency to be seduced by appearances which subvert judgment – plays a key

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 135 role in corruption.11 Like Turnbull, Fordyce gives prominent emphasis to the mechanism of association in this process (see Wasserman, 1953, pp. 46–47; Wood, 1993, p. 54) and indeed traces corruption to seduction of wealth – itself an effect of an improper association of ideas in the disordered imagination (Elements 124–125; Dialogues 1.255–256). Thus Fordyce insists that a chief aim of education is to reorganise the mind by ‘disjoining Unnatural and forming just Associations’ and instead form a ‘correct Imagination’ (Dialogues 1.253–254; Virtue 2) which will serve to ‘connect our Ideas of moral Excellence and Good with their natural Images and Representatives’ and thereby dispel these misleading ‘Phantoms of Good’ (Dialogues 1.266–268). For all their similarities, Fordyce’s emphasis on the role of sympathy in this process takes him beyond Turnbull. Given the propensity of the imagination to be seduced by appearances, Fordyce recognises that the danger in such confused associations is not simply the harm that the individual is likely to do to himself but rather the harm that such an individual is likely to do to others; that is, it is not simply the restless pursuit of external goods that worries Fordyce but the duplicity and cruelty of those who regard the manipulation of appearances as a useful tool in the pursuit and acquisition of such goods (Dialogues 2.8, 2.12, 1.74; cf. 1.77). Ultimately it is these moral concerns that form the problem to which his proposed education aims to respond. This practical education is built on Fordyce’s understanding of human psychology. On this view, the proper task of education is to cultivate or develop our natural passions. This point is made in several places by both Fordyce and his fictional interlocutors (Elements 50, 126; Dialogues 1.168, 1.108). As has been noted (Tatton, 1988, p. 81), at times this takes the form of a critique of culture and celebration of nature reminiscent of Rousseau: ‘Nature gives us Talents, it is Education that applies them right or wrong. Nature bestows Propensions and Affections, which may be directed to Good, either public or private. ’Tis Culture that improves or perverts them’ (Dialogues 1.168). More often, however, the emphasis of Fordyce’s interlocutors is on the responsibility of education to ‘work up’ nature’s gifts by polishing the passions (Elements 126; Dialogues 1.108). As an educator, Fordyce’s strategy is to develop the natural passions by channelling them to optimal ends. His interlocutors thus routinely and optimistically speak of their conviction that every natural passion can be cultivated into a virtue (Dialogues 2.69–70). In so insisting, Fordyce and his interlocutors frequently champion the modern commercial virtues. Fordyce himself dedicated one section of the Elements to the explication of the ‘social duties of the commercial kind’, and here and elsewhere one finds a pronounced emphasis on redirecting the passions associated with self-love towards virtues and duties that best promote the wellbeing of all; indeed it is in this vein that Fordyce celebrates ‘Justice, Fair-dealing, Sincerity, Fidelity to Compacts, and the like’ – a celebration of modern commercial virtues (Elements 94, 97; cf. Dialogues 1.15). In sum, much of Fordyce’s educational theory was dedicated to explaining how we might redirect ‘that little wretched Thing we call – Selfishness’ to habits and principles that are in both the public and in our private interest (Dialogues

136

Ryan Patrick Hanley

1.304–307). At the same time, Fordyce shared the Scottish mixed feelings towards what has been called the ‘new-model man’ of commercial civilisation (Lerner, 1979), insisting on the limits of such a man’s horizons. This is particularly clear in his several accounts of the ways in which we might cultivate certain virtues beyond the modern commercial virtues, including a love of tranquillity and beauty (Dialogues 1.240). His interest explicitly extends to two higher classes of duties that lie beyond the social duties of a commercial kind: duties to political society and duties to God. And on the latter front, one of Fordyce’s central aims is the recovery of what he calls the ‘true Religion’ or ‘true Theism’ that constitutes the ‘Completion of Morality’ (Elements 112–116). Fordyce’s interest in such binds him to an important if underemphasised line of thinking within the Scottish Enlightenment on the nature of ‘true religion’. But here I only want to call attention to his emphasis on the idea that religion is needed to ‘complete’ morality, for it is in this vein that Fordyce insists that ‘the various and solemn Offices of public Religion, are Duties of indispensible moral Obligation, among the best Cements of Society, the firmest Prop of Government, and the fairest Ornament of both’ (Elements 118) – a line of argument reaching its striking conclusion in the claim that ‘to be thoroughly social then, one must be truly religious’ (Dialogues 1.310).

Henry Home, Lord Kames (1696–1782) In his introduction to the Observations, Turnbull lamented that the ancients ‘took care to educate the heart as well as the understanding: but who thinks of the strange task at present!’ (Observations 27). As his century progressed, several would rise to Turnbull’s challenge, with Rousseau being by far the most famous. But in Scotland, Turnbull’s challenge would be most directly taken up by the eminent jurist, Henry Home, Lord Kames. In 1781, Kames published the first edition of his Loose hints upon education, chiefly concerning the culture of the heart. The Loose hints has been almost wholly forgotten today, yet it remains of crucial import for the response it gives to Turnbull’s challenge as well as for the way in which it unifies its author’s wide-ranging intellectual project. One of the most important threads running throughout his work is his insistence on the superiority of the heart and the passions over reason and understanding (see Lehmann, 1971, p. 242). Loose hints addresses this question directly, arguing that the heart is ‘the seat of emotions and passions, and of moral perceptions, such as right and wrong, good and bad, praise and blame’, and that ‘the chief branch of education’ is nothing less than ‘the culture of the heart during childhood’ (Loose hints 1n, v; cf. Introduction ix–x; Elements 32). On Kames’ view, the primary aim of education is thus to cultivate our natural passions (Essays 62). At the same time, Kames recognises the challenges of such a project, given that ‘nature may be warped by circumstances’ (Loose hints 69). And that Kames believed that the natures and hearts of his countrymen had been so warped seems beyond doubt. As has been noted, in Loose hints Kames ‘picked up the theme of corruption of civilisation which he had introduced in Sketches of the history of man’ (Ross, 1972, p. 366);

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 137 indeed in Loose hints one finds its author lamenting ‘this degenerate age’ given over to vanity (vi), just as he had insisted in Sketches that ‘the epidemic distempers of luxury and selfishness are spreading wide in Britain’, leading to ‘gradual decay of manhood’ and reducing London and Westminster to scenes of ‘luxury’ and ‘love of show’ and ‘love of gain’ (Sketches 1.220, 2.426, 2.554). To be sure: Kames knew well the social and political benefits of commerce, and was on the whole a friend rather than a foe of commercial society, yet this conception of its effects on the heart and mind is remarkable (see e.g. Sketches 2.372; Elements 3–4) and led him to the striking conclusion that ‘[r]iches, selfishness, and luxury, are the diseases that weaken prosperous nations’, and ‘corrupt the heart, dethrone the moral sense, and make an anarchy in the soul’ (Sketches 3.761). Kames’ analysis of the moral effects of ‘a flourishing commerce’ forms the foundation of his vision of the proper role of modern education: not simply to cultivate the heart, but to cultivate those natural passions which have been obscured and rendered unrecognisable. In developing this claim, Kames necessarily sounds like Rousseau. And this is hardly an accident; Kames was clearly a careful reader of Rousseau, and at several points the Loose hints engages directly with Emile. But for all their shared convictions about the nature of the problem, Kames and Rousseau hardly agreed on the proper remedy, and thus for all their common ground on cultivation of natural sentiment, Kames ultimately concludes that while Emile may be ‘a work of great genius’, its author ‘has unhappily too much imagination’ and ‘builds castles in the air, and in vain endeavours to give them a foundation’ (Loose hints 27). Kames goes on to delineate these differences at length, noting in particular their differing conceptions of the utility of force and fear in the education of youth (e.g. Loose hints 53, 145), their differing conceptions of the naturalness of industry and property (e.g. Loose hints 81, 100–101), their differing conceptions of the appropriateness of religious education in early childhood (e.g. Loose hints 238, 243), and their differing conceptions of the place of intellectual instruction in early childhood (e.g. Loose hints 5, 276). But all these are relatively minor in light of their principal difference. Rousseau’s aim was of course to educate a single individual, and render such an individual capable of living as a natural man in the midst of society. Kames’ aims were much more comprehensive; far from wanting merely to educate one man to render himself impervious to the corrupting influences of society, Kames sought to create a new model for the modern citizen. Interestingly, this ambition arises most clearly in an aspect of Kames’ educational theory closely aligned with Rousseau’s: namely their mutual hostility to books. Like Rousseau, Kames would have his students avoid books for as long as possible: ‘as man is intended to be more an active than a contemplative being, the educating of a young man to behave properly in society, is of still greater importance than to make him even a Solomon for knowledge’ (Loose hints 15). But in Kames’ hands, this observation takes on a Scottish cast as it leads him to align himself not with Rousseau’s project to recover natural man in society but to the view that unlike animals and natural savages content with food and rest, ‘man is not so made,’ as ‘his constitution fits him for action’ (Loose hints 282).

138

Ryan Patrick Hanley

In practical terms, this leads Kames particularly to focus on two sorts of virtues: the restraining and the active. The aim of the ‘restraining virtues’ was specifically to mitigate the corruptions of commercial society. In this sense, Kames regarded early childhood as a period in which early intervention could preserve natural instincts towards moderation prior to their corruption by commerce; thus his belief that ‘you cannot begin too early, to check the desire that children have for toys and gewgaws’, as they are ‘perverted’ by such indulgence (Loose hints 98) and his insistence that ‘when any irregular appetite breaks out, endeavour immediately to repress it’ (Loose hints 111). Such early interventions, Kames believes, are needed to mitigate and circumvent the dangerous propensities that he diagnoses in his studies of luxury, including that ‘miserable restlessness, the fruit of intemperance in grovelling pleasures’, as well as that pride or ‘imagined superiority’ and ‘self-partiality’ that leads the egocentric to neglect their social and moral duties (Loose hints 284, 315–316). Again and again Kames thus attests to the import of restraint, avoidance of intemperance, and the willingness to accept cheerfully one’s lot. It is in this vein – and indeed in unmistakably Rousseauian terms – that he insists that we need to cultivate both a resistance to the lure of opinion as well as a desire for a happiness that comes from the heart and is resistant to the judgments of others (see e.g. Loose hints 85, 106, 152; Art of Thinking 53–54). Yet Kames also is hardly any simple advocate of what Rousseau called ‘negative education’ and which seeks to keep all temptations at arm’s length. Thus at the same time that he praises the restraining virtues of self-command, Kames also encourages the active virtues of beneficence; indeed ‘there is no branch of education more neglected than the training of young persons to be charitable’ (Loose hints 86). The Loose hints are indeed full of praises not only of the polite modern virtues of cheerfulness, industry, and cleanliness (e.g. Loose hints, 61, 71, 74), but also the higher virtues of gratitude, forgiveness, and the sentiment of righteous indignation at spectacles of unwarranted suffering that is the origin of justice (Loose hints 89, 130, 221). Ultimately, this side of education is every bit as important to Kames as the negative education in the virtues of restraint, as both are necessary for providing that training of the moral sense so susceptible to ‘great refinements by culture and education’, and when properly refined gives rise to an agent in which the ‘selfish passions are tamed and subdued, and social affections gain the ascendant’ (Essays 64).

Conclusion The three thinkers profiled above offer the most significant and extended educational theories of the Scottish Enlightenment. How then do their studies comport with the thoughts on education offered by the more prominent thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment? In fact the connection between commercial corruption and education that lies at the heart of the educational theories of Turnbull, Fordyce, and Kames forms the core of the briefer thoughts on education set forth by Ferguson and Smith. Of these two, Ferguson tends to be more readily associated with the critique of commercial corruption. Among his

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 139 principal worries was that the corruption endemic to commercialisation vitiates human excellence; ‘recommending employments in proportion as they are lucrative, and certain in their gains’ merely ‘drives ingenuity, and ambition itself, to the counter and the workshop’. In order to preserve within commercial society the natural human concern for perfection, a renewed emphasis on education is required. But not any sort of education; too often modern education itself, on his view, further encourages this mediocrity. In this vein the growth of libraries and university education, often viewed as a great advance, is in fact detrimental insofar as it leads us to ‘become students and admirers, instead of rivals; and substitute the knowledge of books, instead of the inquisitive or animated spirit in which they were written’ (Essay 206). Adam Smith would in time come to extend both Ferguson’s lament of the conditions of contemporary education, as well as his insistence that the best remedy for the challenges posed by commercial corruption was an education of a quite different sort. Indeed the tie that binds all of Smith’s reflections on education is this theme of corruption. Smith introduces this theme in his comments on the state of contemporary educational institutions. Too often, he laments, no real instruction is given there – a fact he famously blames on the absence of incentive structures for faculty pay (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.3–6). But this is only the tip of the iceberg, for in truth the modern European university system itself represents little more, on Smith’s view, than a set of ‘sanctuaries in which exploded systems and obsolete prejudices found shelter and protection’ (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.34). Founded originally for the training of clergymen, curricula failed to adapt to meet the needs of a new class of students, and far from teaching their students ‘the real business of the world’, colleges chose to focus on the ‘austerities and abasement of a monk’ rather than ‘the liberal, generous, and spirited conduct of a man’ (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.30–35). Smith’s emphasis on the uselessness of contemporary education to provide men of the new commercial age with what they need to know (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.46) parallels several criticisms set forth in the educational treatises examined above, as well as the justifications for several more practical attempts to reform eighteenth-century Scottish university curricula in a manner that would render them more fit for a commercial people (see Gerard, 1755; Thom, 1762; see also Stewart-Robertson, 1981, p. 510; Jones, 1983, pp. 113–114). But Smith hardly stops here. For all the corruptions of the contemporary institutions of education, Smith still insists that it is to education that we need to turn to discover a remedy for the most acute forms of commercial corruption itself. Here we find perhaps the clearest parallels between Smith and the Scottish educational theorists profiled above. Smith’s account of commercial corruption is in fact one of the most developed in the Scottish Enlightenment. He particularly notes that for all the benefits of the division of labour, its gains are often bought at a high human cost, as specialisation of labour often leads to repetition that leads a labourer to become ‘as stupid and ignorant as it is possible for a human creature to become’ (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.50). Smith’s worry was that in this state of ‘drowsy stupidity’ or ‘mental mutilation, deformity, and

140

Ryan Patrick Hanley

wretchedness’ that ‘all the nobler parts of the human character may be, in a great measure, obliterated and extinguished in the great body of the people’ (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.51, 60). Much of Smith’s later moral philosophy can be understood as an attempt to provide a normative solution to this problem (Hanley, 2009). But more immediately, Smith turned to educational institutions as a remedy for this particular form of corruption (e.g. West, 1996, p. 100; for further references, see Hanley, 2009, p. 60 n.12). It is Smith’s conviction that where the great majority of citizens are placed in circumstances disadvantageous to both their own and the civic wellbeing, ‘some attention of government is necessary, in order to prevent the almost entire corruption and degeneracy of the great body of the people’ (Wealth of Nations 5.1.f.49). His particular recommendation is that government should especially fund science education – and for specifically political reasons, as such a citizenry would be susceptible to ‘the delusions of enthusiasm and superstition, which, among ignorant nations, frequently occasion the most dreadful disorders’ (Wealth of Nations 5.i.f.61). On the grounds that ‘science is the great antidote to the poison of enthusiasm and superstition’, Smith’s hope was that a people trained in scientific analysis might be rendered more discriminating, if not impervious to manipulation by interested factions (Wealth of Nations 5.1.g.14). Thus Smith and Ferguson, like their contemporaries, insisted that the chief aim of proper education was to fit the citizens of a commercial society to respond to the challenges – at once intellectual, moral, and political – posed by commercialisation itself. In so doing, they testify to the broader consensus within the Scottish Enlightenment that the true aim of education is not merely the production or dissemination of knowledge but the preservation and perpetuation of the virtues required for life in liberal, commercial society. Perhaps nowhere does this conviction find such eloquent testimony as in the brief reflections on education set forth by two of the greatest luminaries of the Scottish Enlightenment, Francis Hutcheson and David Hume.12 Hutcheson is more typically understood as a defender of the view that virtue is education’s proper aim (Short introduction 1.3.4; Meditations 6.16). But it is Hume who particularly drives this point home. Hume is not typically regarded today as a theorist of character education.13 Yet even Hume claims that virtue never flourishes except in a state ‘where a good education becomes general’. In so saying he largely reaffirms the claims of his Scottish contemporaries, insisting that ‘general virtue and good morals in a state, which are so requisite to happiness, can never arise from the most refined precepts of philosophy, or even the severest injunctions of religion; but must proceed entirely from the virtuous education of youth’ (History of England 1:179; Essays 55).

Acknowledgements The author is grateful to Colin Heydt and Ingrid Gregg, as well as to the editors and reviewers for the Oxford Review of Education, for their many helpful suggestions.

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 141

Notes 1 See e.g. Cant, 1967 and 1982; Camic, 1983, pp. 64–71; Valdés Mirayes, 2005, pp. 102–103; cf. Anderson, 1995, pp. 1–23. 2 See e.g. Sloan, 1971, pp. 9–32; Berry, 1997, pp. 12–16; Emerson, 2003, pp. 18–20. This evolution itself paralleled contemporaneous struggles of evangelicals and moderates in the Kirk; see e.g. Cameron, 1982; Sher, 1985, esp. pp. 324–328. 3 For the former, see esp. Sher, 1990; for the latter, see esp. Wood, 2003. 4 For comprehensive treatments of these themes, see esp. Phillipson, 1981; Skinner, 1990; Berry, 1997. 5 See e.g. Benjamin Franklin’s prominent reliance on Turnbull’s work in his Proposals relating to the education of youth in Pennsylvania (1749). 6 The work is nowadays mainly read as an attempt to domesticate moral philosophy within the broader context of epistemology, and is often read in contrast to Hume’s more famous execution of the same project; see e.g. Broadie, 2003b, pp. xiv–xv. For further important comparisons, see esp. Norton, 1975, p. 705; Mackinnon, 1987, p. 109; Broadie, 1994, p. 39; Ahnert, 2007, p. 89. 7 For studies emphasising this ‘Shaftesburianism’, and the harmonisation of morality, religion and the moral and physical sciences, see esp. Wasserman, 1953, pp. 45–52; Norton, 1975, pp. 704–706, 712; Mackinnon, 1987, p. 105; Stewart, 1987, p. 99; Wood, 1993, pp. 46–55; Rivers, 2000, pp. 179–184. 8 Thus Ahnert’s helpful description of Turnbull’s recognition that ‘the natural, providential rewards for industry’ also ‘to some extent contained the seeds of its corruption’ (2007, p. 101). 9 Turnbull’s employment of this self-conscious ‘philosophical style’ (Observations 74) may have been the effect of his engagement with Hume’s treatment of associationism in the just-published Treatise; or, perhaps more likely, the influence of Locke and Hutcheson (see e.g. Broadie, 1994, pp. 35–43; Moore, 2003, pp. xii–xiii). 10 In this respect Fordyce is indeed representative of what has been called ‘the preference for the Socratic over the Lockean position in Scottish educational thinking’ (StewartRobertson, 1981, p. 522). 11 In lamenting the corruption of their age, Fordyce’s speakers (2.13, 2.18) echo Turnbull and also anticipate better-known arguments of Ferguson and Smith from several decades later. 12 Hutcheson and Hume are today often regarded as on different sides of this particular issue in light of their notorious epistolary interchange on the normative duties of the moral philosopher. Yet that debate focused on the more specialised question of the nature and aims of moral philosophy itself. With regard to education understood broadly, however, one finds greater agreement. 13 Thus Paul Russell has noted that Hume has ‘little or nothing to say in his major writings about how the virtues are actually acquired, developed and sustained’ (2006, p. 162; cf. Hanley, 2011, on Hume’s emphasis on the claim that the natural moral sentiment of humanity is a sufficient foundation for modern virtue).

References Ahnert, T. (2007) The ‘Science of Man’ in the moral and political philosophy of George Turnbull (1698–1748), Acta Philosophica Fennica, 83, 89–104. Anderson, R. D. (1995) Education and the Scottish people 1750–1918 (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Berry, C. J. (1997) The social theory of the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press).

142

Ryan Patrick Hanley

Broadie, A. (1994) The association of ideas: Thomas Reid’s context, Reid Studies, 5, 31–53. Broadie, A. (2003a) Introduction, in: A. Broadie (ed.) The Cambridge companion to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Broadie, A. (2003b) Introduction, in: G. Turnbull (ed.) The principles of moral and Christian philosophy. 2 vols (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Cameron, J. K. (1982) Theological controversy: a factor in the origins of the Scottish Enlightenment, in: R. H. Campbell & A. S. Skinner (eds) The origins and nature of the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh, John Donald). Camic, C. (1983) Experience and ideas: education for universalism in eighteenth-century Scotland, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 25, 50–82. Cant, R. G. (1967) The Scottish universities and Scottish society in the eighteenth century, Studies on Voltaire and the 18th Century, 58, 1953–1966. Cant, R. G. (1982) Origins of the Enlightenment in Scotland: the universities, in: R. H. Campbell & A. S. Skinner (eds) The origins and nature of the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh, John Donald). Emerson, R. (2003) The contexts of the Scottish Enlightenment, in: A. Broadie (ed.) The Cambridge companion to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Emerson, R. (2009) Essays on David Hume, medical men and the Scottish Enlightenment (Burlington, VT, Ashgate). Ferguson, A. [1767] (1995) An essay on the history of civil society, (ed. F. Oz-Salzberger) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Fordyce, D. [1745–1748] (1755) Dialogues concerning education, 2 vols. 4th edn. (Cork). Fordyce, D. [1754] (2003) The elements of moral philosophy (ed. T. D. Kennedy) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Fordyce, D. (1757) The temple of virtue, a dream (London). Gerard, A. (1755) Plan of education in the Marischal College and University of Aberdeen (Aberdeen). Hanley, R. P. (2008) Social science and human flourishing: the Scottish Enlightenment and today, Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 7, 29–46. Hanley, R. P. (2009) Adam Smith and the character of virtue (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Hanley, R. P. (2011) David Hume and the ‘Politics of Humanity’, Political Theory, 39, 205–233. Herman, A. (2001) The Scottish Enlightenment: the Scots’ invention of the modern world (London, Fourth Estate). Hont, I. & Ignatieff, M. (eds) (1983) Wealth and virtue: the shaping of political economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Hume, D. [1742–1777] (1985) Essays, moral, political, literary (ed. E. Miller) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Hume, D. [1754–1762] (1983) History of England (ed. W. B. Todd) 6 vols (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Hutcheson, F. [1747] (2007) A short introduction to moral philosophy (ed. L. Turco) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Hutcheson, F. & Moor, J. [1742] (2008) The meditations of the Emperor Marcus Aurelius Antoninus (ed. J. Moore & M. Silverthorne) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Jones, P. (1983) The Scottish professoriate and the polite academy 1720–46, in: I. Hont & M. Ignatieff (eds) Wealth and virtue: the shaping of political economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

Educational theory and the social vision of the Scottish Enlightenment 143 Kames, Henry Home, Lord [1751] (2005) Essays on the principles of natural religion (ed. M. C. Moran) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Kames, Henry Home, Lord [1761] (1764) Introduction to the art of thinking, 2nd edn. (Edinburgh). Kames, Henry Home, Lord [1762] (2005) Elements of criticism (ed. P. Jones) 2 vols (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund). Kames, Henry Home, Lord [1774] (2007) Sketches of the history of man (ed. J. A. Harris) 3 vols (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Kames, Henry Home, Lord [1781] (1782) Loose hints upon education, 2nd edn. (Edinburgh). Lehmann, W. C. (1971) Henry Home, Lord Kames, and the Scottish Enlightenment (The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff). Lerner, R. (1979) Commerce and character: the Anglo-American as new model man, William and Mary Quarterly, 36, 3–26. Mackinnon, K. A. B. (1987) George Turnbull’s common sense jurisprudence, in: J. J. Carter & J. H. Pittock (eds) Aberdeen and the Enlightenment (Aberdeen, Aberdeen University Press). Moore, T. O. Jr. (2003) Introduction, in: Observations on liberal education (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Norton, D. F. (1975) George Turnbull and the furniture of the mind, Journal of the History of Ideas, 36, 701–716. Phillipson, N. (1981) The Scottish Enlightenment, in: R. Porter & M. Teich (eds) The Enlightenment in national context (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Rhyn, H. (1999) The formation of liberal education in England and Scotland, Studies in Philosophy and Education, 18, 5–14. Rivers, I. (2000) Reason, grace, and sentiment: a study of the language of religion and ethics in England 1660–1780 (vol. 2) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Ross, I. S. (1972) Lord Kames and the Scotland of his day (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Russell, P. (2006) Moral sense and virtue in Hume’s ethics, in: T. Chappell (ed.) Values and virtues: Aristotelianism and contemporary ethics (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Sher, R. B. (1985) Church and university in the Scottish Enlightenment (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Sher, R. B. (1990) Professors of virtue: the social history of the Edinburgh moral philosophy chair in the 18th century, in: M. A. Stewart (ed.) Studies in the philosophy of the Scottish Enlightenment (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Skinner, A. S. (1990) The shaping of political economy in the Enlightenment, Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 37, 145–165. Sloan, D. (1971) The Scottish Enlightenment and the American college ideal (New York, Teachers College Press). Smith, A. [1776] (1981) An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations (eds R. H. Campbell & A. S. Skinner) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Stewart, M. A. (1987) George Turnbull and educational reform, in: J. J. Carter & J. H. Pittock (eds) Aberdeen and the Enlightenment (Aberdeen, Aberdeen University Press). Stewart-Robertson, J. C. (1981) The well-principled savage, or the child of the Scottish Enlightenment, Journal of the History of Ideas, 42, 503–525. Tatton, S. (1988) John Locke, David Fordyce, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau: On liberty, in: S. Tweyman & W. E. Creery (eds) Early modern philosophy II (New York, Caravan Books). Thom, W. (1762) The defects of a university education (London).

144

Ryan Patrick Hanley

Trevor-Roper, H. (1967) The Scottish Enlightenment, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century, 58, 1635–1658. Turnbull, G. [1740] (1971) A treatise on ancient painting (ed. V. M. Bevilacqua) (Munich, Wilhelm Fink Verlag). Turnbull, G. [1740] (2005) The principles of moral and Christian philosophy (ed. A. Broadie) 2 vols (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Turnbull, G. (1742) Prefatory discourse, in: Justin’s history of the world translated into English (London). Turnbull, G. [1742] (2003) Observations upon liberal education (ed. T. O. Moore, Jr) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund). Valdés Mirayes, J. R. (2005) The prejudices of education: educational aspects of the Scottish Enlightenment, Atlantis, 27, 101–118. Wasserman, E. (1953) Nature moralized: the divine analogy in the eighteenth century, English Literary History, 20, 39–76. West, E. G. (1996) Adam Smith on the cultural effects of specialization: splenetics versus economics, History of Political Economy, 28, 83–105. Withrington, D. J. (1970) Education and society in the eighteenth century, in: N. T. Phillipson & R. Mitchison (eds) Scotland in the age of improvement (Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press). Wood, P. (1993) The Aberdeen Enlightenment: the arts curriculum in the eighteenth century (Aberdeen, Aberdeen University Press). Wood, P. (2003) Science in the Scottish Enlightenment, in: A. Broadie (ed.) The Cambridge companion to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

10 Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education Elizabeth Frazer

Introduction In 1790 Mary Wollstonecraft was 31, a published author, editor and translator, with experience running a school, working as a ladies’ companion, and as a governess in an aristocratic household. She moved in dissenting circles, and in the radical circles of her publisher Joseph Johnson in central London.1 At the end of November 1790 Wollstonecraft published her Vindication of the rights of men, a riposte to Edmund Burke’s hostile attack on the French Revolution (Reflections on the revolution in France) which had been published on November 1, 1790.2 Catharine Macaulay was 59; and a famous woman in the sense that chinaware figurines of the ‘Female Patriot’ were manufactured by the Crown Derby porcelain factory in the 1770s.3 Her History of England (Macaulay, 1763–1783) rivalled and for a time outsold David Hume’s work of the same name (Hume, 1883/1754–1762). Macaulay was remarkably involved in daily political controversy as a partisan of the ‘old’, ‘true’, or ‘real’ Whig cause (Hume was associated with the ‘Tory’ position). She was the author of a number of pamphlets on philosophical and political matters including one on Thomas Hobbes (Macaulay, 1767) and one contesting Burke’s moderate Whig analysis of problems of parliament and administration (Macaulay, 1770; cf also Macaulay, 1775). She was celebrated in revolutionary north America, and in Paris, and was accordingly a figure of suspicion for the Hanoverian state. By the 1780s her reputation had suffered from the pitfalls of celebrity culture. As aspects of her family life were lampooned, her reputation and power as a Whig propogandist receded and the later volumes of her History were not the best sellers that the earlier ones were. Her intellectual efforts turned to religion and morality and in 1783 she published her Treatise on the immutability of moral truth. This then developed into her Letters on education published in 1790 (Part III of the Letters is more or less a reproduction of the Treatise). The December 1790 issue of the Analytical Review included warm reviews of both Wollstonecraft’s Vindication and Catharine Macaulay’s Observations on the Reflections of ... Edmund Burke on the revolution in France which was published in December 1790 (Anon, 1790a, 1790b; Hill, 1995 p. 182). The reviewer

146

Elizabeth Frazer

judged Wollstonecraft’s and Macaulay’s works very favourably as compared with Burke’s. In November 1790 the Analytical Review had published an admiring review by Wollstonecraft of Macaulay’s Letters on education (published November 1790). Wollstonecraft and Macaulay were in private communication at this time, although to Wollstonecraft’s lasting regret they were never to meet (Hill, 1995). Macaulay died in 1791, before Wollstonecraft turned to writing her Vindication of the rights of woman, in which she spent more words on Macaulay’s praise (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, p. 180). There is then a personal and an intellectual link between Macaulay and Wollstonecraft, and reason to attach weight to the similarities in their views on education. Macaulay and Wollstonecraft both participated in controversy (which continues to our own time) about whether ‘virtue’ can be taught, as opposed to being a natural capacity that everyone is simply given. In the eighteenth century, the whole question was bound up with theological matters, and also political ones. Given agreement that virtue can be taught, there is the question whether this involves teaching knowledge of propositions and principles, or whether, rather, ethical education is more like teaching skill. There are many diverse and subtly distinct positions within this schematic framework. Above all, Macaulay and Wollstonecraft both dissent from any model of education as manipulation, or the use of concealment or subterfuge. For both, the matter of truth that is at the heart of virtue, and hence should be at the heart of political and social life, must be enacted also in the process, as well as the outcome, of education (Wollstonecraft, 1974/1787, pp. 7–9; Macaulay, 1996/1790, pp. 85, 185). There are also politically significant contrasts between the two. In particular we can emphasise a difference in their respective theories of rights, which bears on the questions of feminism and of education. Macaulay attacks Hobbes’s abstract theory of rights; and she also resists Burke’s theory which makes rights a matter of tradition (Macaulay, 1767, pp. 8–10; 1790, pp. 13–14, 31). For her rights are historical, but they are also natural. She is concerned to establish the correct philosophical foundation for rights, and her historical and political writing emphasises a continuing struggle to recover lost and continually threatened rights (e.g. Macaulay, 1770, p. 31; Hill, 1992, pp. 31, 229; Pocock, 1998, pp. 248f). Wollstonecraft follows this theory of rights as natural (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1790, p. 12). She insists that they are properties of women as well as men (Zagarri, 2005, pp. 667–670). The most important thing is to secure them culturally and legally (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, intro. pp. 66–67, ch. 1, p. 79; Taylor, 2003, pp. 213–214). She is suspicious of inherited rights (1994/1790, p.10) and aware of the novelty of the rights she proposes – women’s enfranchisement, their right to paid occupation, transformed rights within marriage and the family. So history, whether near or distant, has a different significance for her than it has for Macaulay. In this paper I aim to put these respective theories of rights and education into the complicated context of eighteenth-century factional and intellectual debates and inheritances. I want to emphasise the striking accord between Wollstonecraft and Macaulay in matters of religion and morality in relation to education.

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 147 Here in particular it seems that Macaulay’s work has some direct influence on Wollstonecraft, although the ideas that infuse their thinking are very much part of the general heritage of progressive, oppositional eighteenth-century intellectual culture.4

Intellectual and political context Macaulay’s response to Hobbes on the one hand and Burke on the other is centred on considerations about civilisation, human sympathy, governmental and social responsibility, and the possibility of education.5 She puts these possibilities against views of human fear and failing, the need for absolute authority, and the claims of monarchs. She asserts a powerful version of a doctrine of popular sovereignty (e.g. Macaulay, 1767, pp. 3–1, 1770, pp. 7–13, 1790, pp. 13–14, 44–45, 75, 95). Theories like Macaulay’s face an obvious riposte: people cannot be relied upon to be good. The Hobbesian solution is that they must be ruled by the sword of an absolute power. An alternative response, associated with Hume, is that doubt about moral values, about the validity and objectivity of moral precepts, should lead to a focus instead on what cannot be doubted: the self-interest of human individuals is the surest foundation we have for morality and civilisation (Hume, 1975/1751). Alexander Pope popularised this kind of rationalism in his influential Essay on man which expounds the ‘deist’ view that our belief in God is rational, and does not depend on any organised religion, revelation, or dogma (Pope, 1950/1733–4). Macaulay argues against any idea that self-interest is the foundation for morality, belief in God, or our understanding of the law of nature, and against any hint of deism (Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt. 3 II p. 346, VIII p. 409). Her defence of Christian virtue centres on essential and eternal discriminations of good and evil, just and unjust, and the certainty of a regular, simple, and universal rule of action for all intelligent nature (Pt 3 II p. 347). Nothing in morality can depend on our enjoyment or our pain, on what is in our material interests or their negation. She also defends ‘stoicism’. Stoic themes were pervasive in intellectual and political culture at the time, and references to self-sacrifice, putting the state or commonwealth before personal interests or needs, were ubiquitous in popular culture (and recur in her historical writing). In the Treatise and in the Letters on education she responds to those who criticise stoic philosophy because it is ‘pagan’, and also to those who, like Hobbes and Hume, reject it because its philosophical anthropology is inconsistent with modern scientific understanding of passion and interest (Macaulay, 1783, pp. 289–325, 1996/1790, Pt. 3 X–XII pp. 428–453). Aspects of stoic doctrine are ‘consonant to the purity of Christian doctrine’ (1996/1790, Pt. 3 XII p. 448). First, the idea that the proper exertion of rationality in overcoming difficulty or weakness gives rise to a consciousness of merit which is, itself, a reward for virtue (1996/1790, Pt. 3 IX p. 424). Second, that knowledge of virtue is one of the most important means for the acquisition of virtue, and that knowledge of the mechanisms of human mind is ‘a necessary and useful auxiliary in the contest between wisdom and folly’ (Pt. 3 IX p. 426).

148

Elizabeth Frazer

Third, she quotes Epictetus: no great thing is to be brought to perfection suddenly (p. 427). That is to say, education, of body, of volitions, and of reason and understanding, is key in stoic ethics. Macaulay’s insistence on the ‘immutability of moral truth’ is her answer to the various errors of the Humeans, the Hobbesians, and the Deists as represented by her and thinkers like her. Against theorists of ‘free will’ Macaulay argues that their own views about the efficacy of education, and of institutions of punishment and blame, undermine any idea that our will can be indifferent to truth (Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt. 3 XIV p. 463). According to her compatibilist view, rational agency cannot be prevented from distinguishing differences in the nature of things (e.g. the difference between good and evil, vice and virtue), and actually the necessity of morality ‘constitutes the very essence of rational agency’ (XVIII p. 499). That is, necessity presupposes rationality and freedom. These philosophical considerations underpin Macaulay’s insistence that education of body, of understanding, and hence of will, involves an education in values (Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt. 1, e.g. IX pp. 84, XIII pp. 119–121). Equally, education is a necessary condition for morality itself. Confusion, and evil, will arise from confounding laws and customs of society with obligations which are founded on correct principles of equity and justice, or from assimilating right and wrong to pleasure and pain. One rule of right for all rational beings must prevail; so virtue must be taught on principles (Pt. 1 XXI p. 201). In her review of Macaulay’s Letters Wollstonecraft explicitly approves the centrality of these religious and moral themes. She approves Macaulay’s clear and succinct account of the doctrines of the Stoics, and her repudiation of misreadings of them (Wollstonecraft, 1790, p. 241). She also appreciates Macaulay’s treatment of the problem of good and evil, while dissenting from some of the detail of Macaulay’s treatment of God’s will (pp. 246, 250–253). As Wollstonecraft puts it: These acute observations on moral necessity, are a very judicious conclusion to a book on education, for the influence of motives on human conduct, and necessity of informing the understanding that it may regulate the will, is the ground spur to industry, in every attempt to promote domestic and national education. (p. 253) I shall return to this theme of the central relevance of religion and morality to Wollstonecraft’s educational and political theory. First, though, we must turn to an important source for both Macaulay and Wollstonecraft – the inheritance of the conflicting views of John Locke and JeanJacques Rousseau on education (Rousseau, 1979/1762, esp. Bk III pp. 89–90; Locke, 1989/1693).6 Lockean themes pervade both Macaulay’s and Wollstonecraft’s views of education: experience as the only efficiacious instructor, the superiority of reason over instinct, as well as detailed views about diet, dress, play, sleep, techniques and topics of instruction, and so forth. (Wollstonecraft, 1787, p. 11, 1994/1792, ch. IV p. 123, ch. XI p. 237; Macaulay, 1996/1790,

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 149 Pt.1 e.g. III p. 23, IV pp. 40–45). In particular, of course, they both endorse Locke’s views about educational equality between girls and boys (Locke, 1989/1693 passim; Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, intro. p. 71; Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt.1, IV pp. 46–50). Rousseau’s Emile, by contrast, with its romantic conceit of keeping a child from society and the world, sheltering him from understanding of truth and falsity in order to preserve innocence and guard against corruption, is rejected by both Macaulay and Wollstonecraft in favour of a sterner, more rationalist project of moral education and the learning of hard lessons backed up by precept and principle (Wollstonecraft, 1787, p. 11; 1994/1792, ch.1 p.79; Macaulay, 1996/1790, e.g. Pt1.VI p. 60, VII p. 66, IX p. 85, XIII p. 119). However, versions of the Emile project are ubiquitous in the educational works that Macaulay and Wollstonecraft are writing to and from, and they both produce versions of the uncorrupted educated individual as the product of a pedagogic social process. I shall go on to discuss how Wollstonecraft’s Original stories, in particular, explicitly echo a Rousseauian educational project. But by far the most significant aspect of the inheritance of Locke and Rousseau on education is Macaulay’s attack, echoed and theoretically elaborated by Wollstonecraft, on Rousseau’s depiction of the education of a girl, and his model of ideal womanhood in the person of Sophie (Rousseau, 1979/1762, bk. V). Macaulay’s and Wollstonecraft’s lines of attack on Rousseau are paralleled by some of the lines of their attack on Burke. By the 1760s Macaulay was divided from Burke by Whig factionalism (Macaulay, 1770; Hill, 1992, pp. 74–6, 122). The antagonisms between them widened as her History became more famous and hence more criticised, with Burke referring in correspondence to ‘the patriotick scolding of our republican Virago’ and calling her an ‘Amazon’ (Hill, 1992, p. 173). Of course in 1790 Burke’s attack on the French revolution intensified the bitterness of the controversy between him and the defenders of republicanism, equality, and rights. Both Macaulay and Wollstonecraft attack Burke for his treatment of sex. They also attack his written style as over-rhetorical and over-emotional. Wollstonecraft’s version of this line, while sharing a good deal with Macaulay’s, is theoretically and politically elaborated in a distinctive way.7

Macaulay and Wollstonecraft against Rousseau and Burke Macaulay identifies a central problem with both Burke and Rousseau – commitment to hierarchy. In Rousseau’s case this is squared with anti-hierarchical republicanism and the kind of popular sovereignty to which Macaulay herself is committed; in Burke’s case it is assimilated to hierarchical monarchical authoritarianism. In both cases, although in different ways, hierarchy turns on sexual difference.8 In Rousseau’s case ideal femininity is a necessary condition of ideal ethical masculinity; and the education of a girl must encourage hypocrisy and dependence, she must be corrupted and debilitated in mind and body (Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt. 1 XXII pp. 207, 211–212). Rousseau’s representation of Sophie lowers him (a genius) to the level of ‘licentious pedant’ (p. 206).

150

Elizabeth Frazer

His philosophical status is cut down by his inability to escape from his own masculine sexuality which must explain this otherwise unaccountable misunderstanding (XXIIII pp. 212–213). Wollstonecraft picks up this theme: Rousseau’s ‘voluptuous reveries’ are shot through with the fantasy of an apparently modest woman who is really coquettish (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. II pp. 90–91). Rousseau’s account of sex and gender, and his educational philosophy which centres on withholding the faculty of reason from girls, can only be understood if his expressed understanding of and normative strictures regarding femininity are put in the context of the mundane (and depressing) popular manners of the day. Everywhere Macaulay and Wollstonecraft look there is evidence of a sexual system which purportedly rewards women for the appearances of weakness, ignorance and timidity. In acting this way women are, at one level, conforming to standards of femininity that are all the stricter for being understood as natural. But praise of such femininity always also carries an admixture of censure. From Macaulay and Wollstonecraft’s perspectives the material rewards that can follow on a successful acting out of feminine helplessness (such as the security of a successful marriage) are always liable to be matched by material punishments (such as the reproach of hypocrisy, or the disadvantages stemming from the marriage contract). Even if this social fate is avoided, women have to live with themselves as cut off from the right standards of virtue (Macaulay, 1790, Pt. 1 XXII p. 207, XXIII pp. 211–212, XXIV p. 221; Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. IV pp. 122–126, 135–136; ch. VIII p. 215). Burke, in his celebrated Philosophical enquiry into our ideas of the sublime and the beautiful (1757), had pushed home exactly this sexual distinction (Hicks, 2002, p. 172). The sublime – powerful, terrible – is associated with the great virtues of fortitude, justice, and wisdom (Burke, 1990/1757, Pt. 2 §.I, Pt. 3 §.X). The association of the beautiful – delicate, small, smooth – with lesser virtues and with femininity is underlined by his remarks about beauty in women (Pt. 3 §§. X, XII–XVI). This is associated with weakness, delicacy, timidity, and the like – an association of which women are very sensible ‘for which reason, they learn to lisp, to totter in their walk, to counterfeit weakness, and even sickness. In all this, they are guided by nature’ (S.IX; cf. Wollstonecraft, 1994/1790, p. 45). Gendered distinctions such as Burke’s sublime versus the beautiful, the distinction between reason and emotion, or sense and sensibility, mind and body, are central to eighteenth-century systems of thinking. In particular, we should pick out Burke’s invocation of ‘nature’, as opposed to artifice or to culture. Strikingly, we should note, Burke associates ‘nature’ with ‘learning’ here – although some characteristic is natural it must nevertheless be learned. Macaulay and Wollstonecraft both tackle this set of dualisms. They do this in three ways. First, their arguments about the objectivity of moral precept and virtue, universally applicable, push home the themes that ‘mind has no sex’, there is one standard of virtue, and reason, which applies to all. Second, the associations made by Burke, Rousseau, and others between femininity and weakness, dissimulation, hypocrisy and vanity, emotion rather than reason are insulting and ridiculous. More to the point, they overlook the complicated social arrangements,

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 151 cultural conventions, and legal force that are required to secure them. If women are uneducated it is because education is denied them; if they are dependent it is because laws deny them property or autonomy; if they are dissimulating or hypocritical it is because the ‘reward’ of marriage and social approval will only be won by obsessive attention to appearances. The exaggerated sexual differences that associate women’s (but not men’s) virtue with a particular form of ‘chastity’ are taken on by Wollstonecraft in a chapter-length treatment of the theme, its history, its effects, and the alternative thesis that chastity is indeed a virtue that applies in a specific way to men and women alike (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. VII). Third, though, they take Rousseau and Burke to task for exhibiting the kind of vices and disvalued tendencies that are attributed to women. So, Rousseau associates women in general with voluptuousness, and his idealised picture of Sophie is of a creature who is really voluptuous while appearing to be chaste (but the appearance of chastity belies the voluptuousness). In writing these passages he reveals his own pornographic imagination (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. II p. 90; Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt. 1 XXII pp. 205–207). Burke is accused of being over-emotional, with his overwrought metaphors, his abusive angry language against the revolutionaries, and his protest that Marie-Antoinette’s person ought to be sacred (Macaulay, 1790, p. 53; Wollstonecraft, 1994/1790, p. 24, 1994/1792). Macaulay and Wollstonecraft deploy reason and the understanding of truth to discern and reveal the lacunae in Rousseau’s and Burke’s thinking. They impugn their reason by imputing emotion and rhetorical excess to their writing, and their thought. In the Vindication of the rights of man Wollstonecraft repeats this point about Burke’s emotional and rhetorical excess, to the point where she herself is unable to express her disgust any further and her text trails off into a series of ellipses (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1790, p. 60).9

Wollstonecraft on education Three of Wollstonecraft’s works are particularly salient for analysis of her theory of education – her first published work: Thoughts on the education of daughters (1787); her book about and for the education of children: Original stories from real life (1788); and the Vindication of the rights of woman (1792). Perhaps the most striking thing about these works is the pervasiveness of the themes of virtue, analysis of the corruption and possible improvement of society, and the relationship of these to religion. In the two Vindications the themes of state and law are added, so that the critique of society is supplemented by an explicit theory of public policy. Thoughts on the education of daughters was written in the midst of Wollstonecraft’s career in education – after shutting down the school she ran with her sisters in Newington Green, prior to embarking on a new job as a governess. In the preface she makes reference to several popular books on this topic that were extant, and the inheritance of Rousseau’s Emile and Locke’s Thoughts is also prominent (Wollstonecraft, 1974/1787, p. 11). Education

152

Elizabeth Frazer

includes care and socialisation from the earliest days of infancy. She is concerned to repudiate harshness, and to affirm values such as respect and affection, and early in the book she adverts to the theme of truth: ‘Children are taught revenge and lies in their very cradles’ (Wollstonecraft, 1974/1787, p. 10). This emphasis on truth and truthfulness is underpinned by an account of truth similar to the one that is so central to Macaulay’s Letters on education and to her Treatise. This is that ‘principles of truth are innate’ – our assent to many truths is without ‘reasoning’ (Wollstonecraft, 1974/1787, p. 13). Our understanding and apprehension of truth is not based on inference (from our senses, or from evidence). It is rather that ‘we feel their force’ (1787, p. 13). In turn, like Macaulay, Wollstonecraft links this philosophy of truth and reason to her opposition to ‘deism’. For both Macaulay and Wollstonecraft our belief in God is based on revealed truth. Reason and rationality are certainly to be brought to bear in human affairs. But the prospects for educating virtuous persons are threatened if the truth of moral principles is in doubt. In Original stories Wollstonecraft crafts a book out of the pedagogical technique of story-telling. The book itself is a story, about two young girls whose misfortune it is to have been deprived of adequate education and socialisation and accordingly are ignorant and badly behaved. These girls come under the tutelage of Mrs Mason who in order to eradicate these prejudice and substitute good habits instead of those they had carelessly contracted ... never suffered them to be out of her sight. They were allowed to ask questions on all occasions, a method she would not have adopted, had she educated them from the first. (1788, p. vii) We can only read this as a rejoinder to Emile. Emile’s tutor is able to educate him from a very early age, bringing him up to embody the ideal of natural, uncorrupted understanding and virtue. Wollstonecraft’s teacher has to be more in the remedial line. Mrs Mason’s method of education is largely based on story-telling, often with the stories illustrated by the real life of the neighbourhood and countryside in which the girls live. The Original stories are of interest for present purposes mainly for the substantive set of virtues that Wollstonecraft’s teacher is concerned to instil in her pupils: kindness and the repudiation of cruelty; honour, integrity, truthfulness; generosity and charity; industriousness; fortitude and courage. In the Vindication of the rights of woman the theme of virtue is central. Virtues are potentially realisable characteristics of the human condition in civilisation. Virtuous conduct is predictable and stable. The courageous or benevolent person is reliable, not just in the sense that they can be relied upon to be benevolent or courageous, but in the double sense that we know what benevolence and courage are, how they manifest themselves (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch I pp. 76–77, ch III pp. 113–115). By contrast, vice is all over the place – the vicious parent can be randomly kind to her children, which only shows up not only the lack, but the very corruption of, benevolence (ch. X pp. 232–234). It is this random,

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 153 unpredictable, out of control quality of the vices – extravagance, intemperance, cruelty, mendacity – that make them so significant and so evil. Critically Wollstonecraft ties virtues and vices to the political circumstances of the society. Laws, public institutions, and cultural norms are all critical in determining whether a person acquires the virtues, and in determining the distribution of virtuous and vicious conduct in the society (ch. II p. 82, ch. IX pp. 228f). Above all, education is pervasive in, and central to, this work of ethics, political theory, philosophical anthropology, and social theory. The first edition’s dedication includes a specific reference to ‘National Education’ (Todd, 1994, p. 382n). The book begins by adverting to education: I have turned over various books written on the subject of education, and patiently observed the conduct of parents and the management of schools; but what has been the result? – a profound conviction that the neglected education of my fellow-creatures is the grand source of the misery I deplore. (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, p. 71) In many ways the Vindication is continuous with Wollstonecraft’s earlier educational works. First, in the broad conception of education as encompassing early socialisation, formal learning of knowledge and skills, and also the acquisition of conduct and patterns of behaviour that are incentivised, as we might put it, by the costs and benefit structure of social and cultural rules and norms. Second, for Wollstonecraft, education is virtue-centred. Third, I want to return to the questions of religious philosophy that are intimately intertwined with Wollstonecraft’s thinking about virtue. Fourth, there is the clear continuity with the Vindication of the rights of man and a programmatic view that rights – to education, to work, to equal standing in marriage and in parenthood – must be institutionalised if virtue, private or public, is to be realised. However, there are also discontinuities, attributable to Wollstonecrafts’s developing political position. In the Vindication of the rights of woman she launches a powerful argument for schools (as opposed to private education at home), for day schools (as opposed to boarding schools), and for nationally funded and regulated schools (as opposed to schools which are private businesses). At the beginning of chapter one, Wollstonecraft sets out in summary form her convictions about philosophical anthropology, centred on reason, virtue, passion, experience, and wisdom. Many philosophers disagree with this basic picture, including Rousseau who, despairing of the viciousness of society and state, becomes enamoured of solitude (p. 78); he has a wrong idea of what is ‘natural’ for man (p. 79n) – and his exaltation of nature altogether overlooks our social capacities, our duties to care for others (p. 79). She also reads Rousseau as rejecting passion in favour of an entirely reason-dominated life (pp. 78–79). Wollstonecraft argues that passion cannot be treated as a curse – why should God lead us from love of ourselves to the sublime emotions which the discovery of his wisdom and goodness excites, if these feelings were not set in motion

154

Elizabeth Frazer to improve our nature, of which they make a part? (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, p. 79)

Here enter Wollstonecraft’s rehearsals of anti-deist arguments. Rousseau argues that evil is introduced into the world by man (p. 78); but he also wants to argue that while God has made all things right, men, like him, must reject civilisation and return to ‘nature’. This cannot be correct. Wollstonecraft’s argument is that God has indeed made human beings with the capacity for good and evil; that he has endowed us with passions and reasons and that these two are connected; that he has given us the capacities for civilisation. But mainly she, like Macaulay, needs to argue that all these reasonings about the nature of God’s creation are likely to undermine truth, and, pace the purposes of the present paper, that is likely to undermine education. Wollstonecraft’s arguments that mind, reason, and virtue cannot be sexed centre on a sceptical point. Do the men who argue for sex-specific virtue, that there are different standards of conduct for men and women, really mean to say that women do not have souls (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. II p. 84; ch. III p. 110; ch. IV p. 133)? Positively, Wollstonecraft’s arguments that the same standards of rationality, virtue, and knowledge apply to men and to women encompass a range of consequentialist considerations – children will be brought up to be reliable and responsible, women will no longer be dependent on the whims of others and hence will have no need to dissimulate, cruelty and other vices will be marginalised in society. At the heart of these possibilities lie a number of questions about how education is to be delivered. In her earlier work Wollstonecraft had argued that schools, at least the ones with which she was familiar, were not good for children, who were at the mercy of illtreatment at worst, and bizarre educational ideas at best (Wollstonecraft, 1974/1787, pp. 57–60). This is in part a Lockean theme.10 His model of education features the trusted and skilled tutor, whether that be a parent or a wise and thoughtful man like himself. Macaulay concurs that education should be domestic (Macaulay, 1996/1790, Pt 1 II pp. 16–20). And Wollstonecraft in Original stories, as we have seen, continues the conceit of the teacher in an essentially domestic setting. By the time of the Vindication Wollstonecraft had changed her mind: The good effects resulting from attention to private education will ever be very confined, and the parent who really puts his own hand to the plow will always, in some degree, be disappointed, till education becomes a grand national concern. A man cannot retire into the desert with his child. (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. XII p. 241, also II p. 86) Wollstonecraft’s hostility to the anti-social aspects of Rousseau’s thought has, by 1792, evolved into a commitment to the political provision of social institutions. To be sure, ‘till society be differently constituted, much cannot be expected from education’ (Wollstonecraft, 1994/1792, ch. II p. 86), and she still considers

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 155 schools as they mostly are now to be ‘hot-beds of vice and folly’ (ch XII p. 242). In particular, boarding schools put children of one sex together in a hothouse atmosphere that might be deliberately designed to generate bullying, obsessions with fashion, sentimentality, and worse (ch.VII p. 205, XII p. 242).11 Even at their very best, Wollstonecraft is averse to boarding schools because they produce an ‘unsettled state of mind’ at the constant prospect of the vacations; and vacations at home are not conducive to any proper acquisition of domestic virtues (p. 246). Children should be educated at home, where the ‘domestic affections’ can be instilled in them while spending a ‘great part of their time, on terms of equality, with other children’ (p. 243). This latter aspect of schools is absolutely key to Wollstonecraft’s political vision: (of) the social affections that are to constitute the happiness of life as it advances ... equality is the basis, and an intercourse of sentiments unclogged by that observant seriousness which prevents disputation, though it may not inforce submission. (p. 241) Wollstonecraft’s ideal standard for relationships between marital partners, and between parents and children, as for all social and political relationships, is friendship (Abbey, 1999; Frazer, 2008) and she elaborates this model in her later work, in particular in her book on the French revolution. In particular, the only defensible political relationship is citizenship (compare it with subjection to a monarch). Citizens together can govern themselves, and can maintain friendly relationships in society, in the home, and between those with office and authority, and the mass of political participants. Here her egalitarianism, as far as children are concerned, is radical – it is crucial for children to be socialised and educated in relationships of equality. These can be corrupted, to be sure, in situations where emotions and domination lead to bullying and manipulation, as can happen in certain school settings. True friendship cannot be attained except in situations where equality prevails. And all education, at school and at home, must be education to citizenship.

Conclusion Bridget Hill remarks that Macaulay’s Letters contain a ‘bewildering variety of ideas’ and that large parts of it do not seem to be about education at all (Hill, 1992, pp. 160f). This raises the critical question of genre – are ‘educational treatises’ actually about education? The matter is critical in reception and interpretation of Wollstonecraft. Thoughts on the education of daughters is written very much in the tradition of didactic advice books to parents and tutors (V. Jones, 2002). Although wider theses about reason and subjectivity, and philosophical anthropology, are undoubtedly present there can be no doubt that this is a book ‘about education’. But the Vindication of the rights of woman is also a book that is centred in the late eighteenth-century tradition of republicanism, and rights theory, is steeped in theology, is a seminal contribution to feminist philosophy

156

Elizabeth Frazer

and ethics, contains an outline of prescriptive political theory, and, we must add, makes a distinctive and lastingly significant contribution to social theory. In focusing on the educational aspects of the Letters and the Vindication this paper produces, accordingly, a partial reading. In doing so, though, I have wished to resist the idea that we can ignore theology, ethics, cultural critique, or political and social theory, when we analyse Macaulay and Wollstonecraft on education. Stoic ethics and concerns about theological and philosophical truth are present in Wollstonecraft’s work from the outset, but Catharine Macaulay’s extended discussion in the Treatise and the Letters undoubtedly influenced Wollstonecraft in her writing of her second Vindication and later works, and reinforce our sense that the two are united in a theoretical and political effort. This effort is directed against currents of philosophy and politics that argue that ‘self-interest’ and ‘commercial’ impulses not only have to be accommodated, but can further be made central to our ethics and promoted in our polity. For both, any evident tendencies to individualism and the predominance of relations of exchange and profit are to be understood both as corruptions of ethical life, and also as explicable by reference to social and political conditions. Far from being impressed by rationality as self-interest, we should see it as a matter of laws and customs which can, of course, with political will, be reconstructed. For both, this political reconstruction must involve the institutionalisation of rights, including for women. But the discernment of right rights, and the political construction of a virtuous polity, demands education. Macaulay was engaged in direct demands on government: demands for a constitution centred on human dignity and self-government, an administration that reflects republican values, and policies and laws that reward virtue and punish vice. For Wollstonecraft, a new distribution of rights is indissolubly linked to a thoroughgoing transformation in culture and in conduct. One reason why Wollstonecraft is such a significant figure in the history of political theory is that her project is that of an uncompromising politicisation of social and cultural relationships.12 The values, virtues, and rights that her and Macaulay’s visions seek to realise in government, and in political society, must also be realised in social and cultural settings. Among these rights are those of women to work, and their rights to the prerogatives, and the duties, of citizenship. Women’s citizenship is a condition of the decent socialisation and education of children. But more, education is the only way to morality and to effective citizenship, because morality requires discernment, of truth and of virtue, and the rejection of what passes for truth in a world of unequal power, and corruption.

Notes 1 For biography of Mary Wollstonecraft and accounts of intellectual and political context see Todd, 2000; C. Jones, 2002; Taylor, 2003; Gordon, 2005. 2 For further detail on the writing of the Vindication see Bromwich, 1995. 3 For biography of Catharine Macaulay and intellectual context see Hill, 1992; Hicks, 2002; Davies, 2005; O’Brien, 2009.

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 157 4 In the case of both Wollstonecraft and Macaulay there is considerable controversy about how to classify them in political theory terms – as republican, liberal, etc., and how exactly they relate to subsequent feminisms – and about their exact position vis-à-vis the complex range of religious and partisan positions of their time and inheritance; see Barker-Benfield, 1989; Hill, 1992; Pocock, 1998; Taylor, 2002, 2003; Davies, 2005; O’Brien, 2009. Wollstonecraft in particular has been taken to be a key figure in the ‘feminist canon’, although her understanding of sexuality and embodiment (and the question of her ‘puritanism’) was a matter of controversy for late twentieth-century feminist thinkers as also were her assumptions about domestic labour and class, and hence the identification of feminism as a middle-class concern: see Gatens, 1991; Coole, 1993. 5 For commentary and discussion of Macaulay’s work on education see Gardner, 1998; Gunther-Canada, 2003. 6 The opposition between Rousseau as a ‘natural’ educator and Locke as ‘rationalist’ is an interpretation that structures presentation of the two to now – see e.g. Curren (ed.) 2007; it is possible, of course, to read them in ways that bring them closer than this emphasising e.g. Locke’s consistent emphasis on ‘age appropriateness’ and interpreting Rousseau’s criticism of ‘reasoning with a child’ as criticism of arguing with a child. 7 For more detailed discussion of these engagements with Burke than is possible here see Sapiro, 1992; Bromwich, 1995; Hicks, 2002. 8 For a more detailed account of rank and gender in 18th-century thought see O’Brien, 2009, esp. ch. 5. 9 It is difficult to locate the irony here, as Wollstonecraft’s own emotion overcomes her in her criticism of Burke’s emotion; see Sapiro, 1992, pp. 204–206. 10 For more on this point, Cohen, 2005, esp. pp. 226ff. 11 For an account of Wollstonecraft’s educational theory that puts it in the context of contemporary concerns about sex, see V. Jones, 2005, and 2002. 12 According to this interpretation, Wollstonecraft makes more congenial reading for theorists who deconstruct models of political power, and resist the identification of politics with public and state matters, than she does for either liberals or republicans of later times.

References Abbey, R. (1999) Back to the future: marriage as friendship in the thought of Mary Wollstonecraft, Hypatia, 14, 78–95. Anon (1790a) Art IX (review of) A vindication of the rights of men, in a Letter to the Right Hon. Edmund Burke; occasioned by his Reflections on the revolution in France. By Mary Wollstonecraft. 2nd edn. 159 pp, price 2s.6d. Johnson, J. (1790) in The Analytical Review, VIII, September to December inclusive (London, J. Johnson), 416–419. Anon (1790b) Art X (review of) Observations on the reflections of the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, on the revolution in France. In a letter to the Earl of Stanhope. 8vo. 95pa. Price 2s.6d. Dilly (1790) in The Analytical Review, VIII, September to December inclusive (London, J. Johnson), 419–421. Barker-Benfield, G. J. (1989) Mary Wollstonecraft: eighteenth-century Commonwealth woman, Journal of the History of Ideas, 50, 95–115. Bromwich, D. (1995) Wollstonecraft as a critic of Burke, Political Theory, 23, 617–634. Burke, E. (1990 fp 1757) A philosophical enquiry into the origin of our ideas of the sublime and beautiful (ed. with intro. & notes by Adam Phillips) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Burke, E. (1993 fp 1790) Reflections on the revolution in France (ed. with intro. by L. G. Mitchell) (Oxford, Oxford University Press).

158

Elizabeth Frazer

Cohen, M. (2005) ‘To think, to compare, to combine, to methodise’: girls’ education in Enlightenment Britain, in: S. Knott & B. Taylor (eds) Women, gender and enlightenment (London, Palgrave Macmillan). Coole, D. (1993) Women in political theory: from ancient misogyny to contemporary feminism (London, Harvester Wheatsheaf). Curren, R. (2007) Philosophy of education: an anthology (Malden, MA, Blackwell). Davies, K. (2005) Catharine Macaulay and Mercy Otis Warren: the revolutionary Atlantic and the politics of gender (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Frazer, E. (2008) Mary Wollstonecraft on politics and friendship, Political Studies, 56, 237–256. Gardner, C. (1998) Catharine Macaulay’s letters on education: odd but equal, Hypatia, 13(1), 118–137. Gatens, M. (1991) The oppressed state of my sex: Wollstonecraft on reason, feeling and equality, in: M. L. Shanley & C. Pateman (eds) Feminist interpretations and political theory (Cambridge, Polity Press), 112–128. Gordon, L. (2005) Mary Wollstonecraft: a new genus (London, Little, Brown). Gunther-Canada, W. (1998) The politics of sense and sensibility: Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay Graham on Edmund Burke’s Reflections on the revolution in France, in: H. L. Smith (ed.) Women writers and the early modern British political tradition (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 126–147. Gunther-Canada, W. (2003) Cultivating virtue: Catharine Macaulay and Mary Wollstonecraft on civic education, Women and Politics, 25(3), 47–70. Hicks, P. (2002) Catharine Macaulay’s civil war: gender, history and republicanism in Georgian Britain, Journal of British Studies, 41, 170–198. Hill, B. (1992) The Republican Virago: the life and times of Catharine Macaulay, historian (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Hill, B. (1995) The links between Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay: new evidence, Women’s History Review, 4(2), 177–192. Hume, D. (1883 fp 1754–1762) A history of England from the earliest times to the Revolution in 1688 (London, John Murray). Hume, D. (1975 fp 1751) Enquiry concerning the principles of morals, in: L. A. SelbyBigge (ed.) David Hume enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Jones, C. (2002) Mary Wollstonecraft’s vindications and their political tradition, in: C. L. Johnson (ed.) The Cambridge companion to Mary Wollstonecraft (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Jones, V. (2002) Mary Wollstonecraft and the literature of advice and instruction, in: C. L. Johnson (ed.) The Cambridge companion to Mary Wollstonecraft (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Jones, V. (2005) Advice and enlightenment: Mary Wollstonecraft and sex education, in: S. Knott & B. Taylor (eds) Women gender and enlightenment (London, Palgrave Macmillan). Locke, J. (1989 fp 1693) Some thoughts concerning education (ed. intro., notes, & critical apparatus by John W. Yolton & Jean. S. Yolton) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Macaulay, C. (1763–1783) The history of England from the accession of James I to that of the Brunswick line (8 vols) (London). Macaulay, C. (1767) Loose remarks on certain positions to be found in Mr Hobbes’s Philosophical rudiments of government and society; with a short sketch of a democratical form of government, in a letter to Signor Paoli (London, Printed for T. Davies, Robinson & Roberts, and T. Cadell).

Mary Wollstonecraft and Catharine Macaulay on education 159 Macaulay, C. (1770) Observations on a pamphlet, entitled ‘Thoughts on the cause of the present discontents’ (3rd edn., corrected) (London, Edward & Charles Dilly). Macaulay, C. (1775) An address to the people of England, Scotland and Ireland on the present important crisis of affairs (2nd edn.) (London, Edward and Charles Dilly). Macaulay, C. (1783) A Treatise on the immutability of moral truth (London, Printed by A. Hamilton, sold by C. Dilly, G. Robinson, T. Cadell, T. Lewis, J. Walter & R. Faulder). Macaulay, C. (1790) Observations on the reflections of ... Edmund Burke, on the revolution in France, in a letter to the earl of Stanhope (by C.M. Grahm) (London). Macaulay, C. (1996 fp 1790) Letters on education. Vol III of J. Todd (ed.) Female education in the age of enlightenment edn. (London, Pickering & Chatto). O’Brien, K. (2009) Women and enlightenment in eighteenth century Britain (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Pocock, J. G. A. (1998) Catharine Macaulay: patriot historian, in: H. L. Smith (ed.) Women writers and the early modern British political tradition (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 243–258. Pope, A. (1950 fp 1733–34) An essay on man (London, Methuen & Co). Rousseau, J. -J. (1979 fp 1762) Emile, or on education (trans. A. Bloom) (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Sapiro, V. (1992) A vindication of political virtue: the political theory of Mary Wollstonecraft (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). Taylor, B. (2002) The religious foundations of Mary Wollstonecraft’s feminism, in: C. L. Johnson (ed.) The Cambridge companion to Mary Wollstonecraft (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 99–118. Taylor, B. (2003) Mary Wollstonecraft and the feminist imagination (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Todd, J. (ed.) (1994) Mary Wollstonecraft: political writings (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Todd, J. (2000) Mary Wollstonecraft: a revolutionary life (London, Phoenix Press). Wardle, R.M. (1947) Mary Wollstonecraft: analytical reviewer, Proceedings of the Modern Language Association, 62, 1000–1009. Wollstonecraft, M. (1790) Art I. (Review of) Letters on education: with observations on religious and metaphysical subjects. By Catharine Macaulay Graham. 8vo. 507 pages. Price 6s. in boards. Dilly. The Analytical Review, VIII (III), 241–254. Wollstonecraft, M. (1974 fp 1787) Thoughts on the education of daughters (Intro G. Luria) (New York, Garland Publishing). Wollstonecraft, M. (1975 fp 1795) An historical and moral view of the origin and progress of the French Revolution and the effect it has produced in Europe (Introduction J. Todd edn.) (Delmar, NY, Scholars’ Facsimiles and Reprints). Wollstonecraft, M. (1994 fp 1790) A vindication of the rights of men, in: J. Todd (ed.) Mary Wollstonecraft political writings (Oxford, OUP World’s Classics), 3–62. Wollstonecraft, M. (1994 fp 1792) A vindication of the rights of woman, in: J. Todd (ed.) Mary Wollstonecraft political writings (Oxford, OUP World’s Classics), 63–284. Wollstonecraft, M. (2001 fp 1791, 1st edn. 1788) Original stories from real life (2nd edn. 1791 illust. William Blake; 2001 intro Jonathan Wordsworth edn.) (Otley UK, Woodstock Books). Zagarri, R. (2005) American women’s rights before Seneca Falls, in: S. Knott & B. Taylor (eds) Women, gender and enlightenment (London, Palgrave Macmillan).

11 Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability between mankind and the nation Fichte and Schleiermacher on higher education Alexander Schmidt Introduction In the decades around 1800 the German public witnessed a substantial and controversial debate about the reform of higher education with contributions by nearly every thinker of note. This debate was informed by a deep concern with individual self-cultivation (Bildung) in a society marked by an increasing division of labour and by the questions about the status and unity of (scientific) knowledge that were posed by Kantian epistemology.1 Historically, this discussion responded both to the institutional crisis of the university as an ancien régime corporation and to French expansionism with its ensuing destruction of the political structures of the German empire. This confrontation with Revolutionary and later Napoleonic France intensified an ongoing German (and European) controversy about the final purpose of education: should all education eventually be ‘cosmopolitan’, as Kant contended (Kant, 1923, p. 448); or should it rather be concerned with the political and cultural unity of the nation? And if higher education had to form, in Wilhelm von Humboldt’s words, the ‘pinnacle of all that is undertaken for the cultivation of the nation’ (Müller, 1990, p. 273) should the university not be abandoned in favour of the seemingly more efficient French model of polytechnics? The somehow surprising reassertion of the university against the centralised post-Revolutionary French system of special écoles, particularly by Prussian thinkers (Schubring, 1991), is usually considered as the starting point of what was much later labelled as the ‘Humboldtian’ model of the modern university, combining teaching with research in ‘solitude and freedom’ (Müller, 1990, p. 274). As a common narrative goes, this model, epitomised by the newly-founded university of Berlin (1809/10), had a considerable influence on nineteenth- and twentieth-century educational policies and university reforms across Europe, including Britain, and North America (Turner, 1987; Rüegg, 2004; Schalenberg, 2002). In recent years, however, both this model and its heroic narrative have been eroded and questioned in various ways. Historians of the university have stressed that, within the plurality of German states, Berlin did not present the only type of academic reform and that the characteristic combination

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 161 of research and teaching was achieved in various ways (Rüegg, 1997; cf. Eichler, 2012). This historicising of the ‘Humboldtian university’ allows us to take a fresh look at the plurality of competing visions for the future university around 1800. This article concentrates on three pivotal contributions to the debate: Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s Some lectures on the vocation of the scholar (1794) and his later Deduced plan of a higher institute of education to be erected in Berlin (1807, fp. 1817), and the Occasional thoughts about universities in a German spirit (1808) by Daniel Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768–1834). The two latter texts were interventions in the discussion about the foundation of a new university in Berlin, of which both thinkers were later to preside as rectors. My analysis focusses on two interrelated issues of the debate: first, the relation between individual self-cultivation (Bildung), human society and the state and, second, the role of the university in the acquisition, organisation, and economy of knowledge. According to these thinkers, should priority be given to ‘universal’ knowledge or to particular knowledge, preparing students for their future professions? To understand the solutions Fichte and Schleiermacher offered to these questions it is important to identify their historical context. It is no accident that the debate about higher education was particularly differentiated in Germany, which boasted 35 universities in 1789. In the absence of major urban centres like Paris, provincial places such as Göttingen, Königsberg, or Jena were focal points of intellectual life. In an essay that was published in the Monthly Register in 1803, Friedrich Carl von Savigny (1779–1861) succinctly depicted this national significance of the university to a British audience. Written in the year of the Reichsdeputationshauptschluss, the last phase of the dissolution of the Holy Roman Empire, he conceded that Germany lacked nearly every element usually considered essential for a flourishing intellectual culture: economic wealth, a capital city, a constitution, political power and civic spirit. But that which in Germany supplies the want of almost all these advantages, and in which it is unparalleled in any other country, is its Universities. To them, more than to any thing else, Germany is indebted for its vast progress in the arts and sciences. By means of them, Germany is that which it in all other respects is, in so slight a degree, a nation. It may even be asserted, that Germany is contained in its Universities. (Wellek, 1931, p. 534) Savigny pointed in particular at the moral and social effects of university training and student life in the socialisation of every educated individual. Students from poor backgrounds would, for the first time, experience independence and their real moral worth, while students from wealthy and privileged families were forced to accept equality – an aspect he later reasserted in his review of Schleiermacher’s Occasional thoughts in 1808. Creative intellectual pursuit, he wrote against Schleiermacher, was probably not the most formidable result that should be highlighted in defence of academic freedom. Rather it was this

162

Alexander Schmidt

experience of mutual moral and intellectual exchange between students that would ‘humble excessive sense of status’ and thus form a moral counterweight to the often arbitrary differentiation of society old and new (Savigny, 1808/1990, p. 265). With a slightly different emphasis, modern social historians stress a similar aspect of higher education around 1800. Despite declining student numbers, university training was decisive in the gradual transformation of the old society of estates (ständische Gesellschaft) into a modern bourgeois society (bürgerliche Gesellschaft) based on functional differentiation, property, and individual skills which predated the Industrial Revolution in Germany. As will be shown below, university education was central in a social vision of a nonviolent evolution of society. Preceding the Bildungsrevolution of the nineteenth century, recipients of higher education increasingly believed that they formed a new meritocracy, representing the common concern of mankind and the nation. Against an eroding society of privileges based on birth, they claimed a prime access to key positions of public life such as state and church service as well as literary and scientific authority (cf. Müller, 1990, pp. 39–42). These claims were rooted in the Enlightenment concern with, to borrow John Robertson’s coinage, the ‘betterment in this world, without regard for the existence or non-existence of the next’ (Robertson, 2005, p. 8). An increasing part of the enlightened public, however, was sceptical as to whether the majority of current universities or even the institution itself would be up to the task. Many, particularly the smaller universities, were underfunded, with outdated curricula, declining student numbers, academic inbreeding and favouritism, and a general inability to reform. A special problem was posed by student discipline, resulting from the privileged corporate status of German universities with their own jurisdictions on the one hand and a mercantile competition for students on the other. Many university cities were filled with unruly and often armed adolescents. There was an endemic problem of riots, abuse, duels, and alcohol. Student fraternities could exert enormous pressure on university officials and fellow students, often leading to rather mild punishments of transgressions. Concerned with the problem of how to provide a wider population with practical and morally useful knowledge, a number of German enlightened thinkers such as Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803), Joachim Heinrich Campe (1746–1818), and the members of the famous Wednesday Society in Berlin thus agreed in a scathing criticism that the university was a moribund medieval institution (Stölzel 1889, cf. König, 1935, pp. 22–29). These vocal critics wanted profound reform of many universities, if not their complete abolition, in order to promote enlightenment and meet the demands of the state, social utility, and a greater adaptation to future professions. Echoing a Rousseauian scepticism about the wider use of theoretical knowledge, Herder and the Popularaufklärer put their main emphasis on school reform, leaving the future of intellectual debate to the select few scientific and literary academies. They harangued against young men allegedly flocking in their thousands to universities to gain the useless knowledge of a scholarly type, although student numbers were in fact declining.

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 163 To achieve reform of learning, Herder and others demanded, governments had to rein in academic autonomy through review committees and to exert greater control of student numbers, particularly those from poorer backgrounds (Schmidt, 2012).

Fichte’s reassertion of university education To counter this criticism of university education and to redefine the social role of the academic, potent arguments were needed. They were provided by the vocal reassertion of the worth of academic philosophical studies in meeting the demands of moral progress emerging from Kantian and post-Kantian idealist thought (Kant, 1798a/1917). Despite some important differences between thinkers like Fichte, Schelling, and Humboldt, they all basically agreed that the university was the paramount institution within which individuals could achieve self-directed autonomy through the active appropriation of knowledge. ‘Universities are thus schools of self-cultivation (Selbstbildung) ... where it is granted to all spirits to pursue their own direction’, wrote the Norwegianborn philosopher and professor at Halle, Henrik Steffens in 1808 (Anrich, 1956, pp. 352–353). Nowhere was the central historical and social importance of university education guided by philosophical principles formulated more powerfully than in Fichte’s Some lectures on the vocation/determination (Bestimmung) of the scholar held at the university of Jena in 1794 and published in the same year (La Vopa, 2001, pp. 214–230). To be sure, Fichte was equally critical of the traditional university and later took enormous personal risks in challenging the dominance of the student orders and the practice of duelling at Jena. Yet, as will be shown below, he was strongly opposed to a higher education that would dissolve into the purchase of professional skills based on empirical knowledge. Some lectures was part of Fichte’s characteristically unhumble, yet serious intellectual struggle to identify the right levers with which to solve such central political questions of his time as social inequality, moral corruption, and war (cf. La Vopa, 2001; James, 2011; Nakhimovsky, 2011). On the one hand, Some lectures can be read as Fichte’s attempt to reformulate Kant’s notion of the rational public as a force for social reform developed in his essay, What is Enlightenment? (Kant 1784/1991). On the other hand, Some lectures was the upshot of a highly original engagement with Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s disquieting analysis of the anthropological origins of modern commercial society. Fichte tried both taking seriously Rousseau’s demand for a society of free equals, and correcting him at the same time. Fichte indeed dedicated his entire fifth (and final) lecture to an ‘examination of Rousseau’s claims about the influence of the arts and sciences on the well being of mankind’. (Fichte, 1966, pp. 59–68) In general terms, Fichte’s appraisal of Rousseau came to a rather perplexing result. For his assertion of learning as essential to human nature and improvement seemed to propagate something that Rousseau had identified as deeply implicated in the ills of modern society (Rousseau, 1997; cf. Schmidt, 2012).

164

Alexander Schmidt

Fichte began his lectures not, as might be expected, with a positive definition of what it means to be gelehrt (academically educated). Instead he stressed that the Bestimmung (denoting both determination and calling) of the academically educated can only be understood negatively through its relational, i.e. social character, by distinction ‘from other men who are not scholars’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 146; Fichte, 1966, p. 27). The determination of the scholar thus involved answering two questions first: ‘What is the vocation of man within society? ... What is the vocation of man as such?’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 146; Fichte, 1966, p. 27). Both questions echoed a wider Enlightenment concern with the ‘science of man’ as a foundation to understand morality, the mechanisms of human society, and history. Particularly the second question almost literally repeated the title of Johann Joachim Spalding’s (1714–1804) influential Reflection on the calling of man (Betrachtung über die Bestimmung des Menschen) of 1748 which triggered the discourse about anthropology in Germany (Adler, 1994). Bringing together human anatomy, epistemology, moral philosophy, and natural theology, its participants tried to determine such diverse problems as the relation between the body and the mind, the origins of language, the immortality of the soul, or God’s providence with respect to human happiness. Sidelining such issues, however, Fichte set out to answer this question in the very different terminology of his (post-)Kantian attempt to reconstruct the relation between freedom and action in a way that gives primacy to practical reason in the Wissenschaftslehre (Ameriks, 2000, pp. 187–202). By opposing our absolute self (I or Ich) to a not-I, through which we can understand the I but from which it is not derived, Fichte formulated a Kantian notion of man as a rational, i.e. self-determined being which is his own end and thus not heteronomously determined in any way (Fichte, 1988, p. 148; Fichte, 1966, p. 29). Yet while our will is free within its sphere, our empirical features, such as our feelings, are influenced by external causes. In order to preserve ‘the complete harmony of a rational being with himself’ man has to acquire the ‘skill to modify and alter external things in accordance with our concepts’ – a process that Fichte described as ‘culture’ (Fichte, 1988, pp. 150–151; Fichte, 1966, pp. 31–32). This goal, Fichte conceded, can never be fully achieved by man as a finite creature but only approximated. It is here that the second question about man’s calling in society ties in. For this approximation can only be made possible through social cooperation in human history. Fichte thereby linked the question of the purpose of higher education to two interrelated debates in Enlightenment moral and political thought. The first was concerned with man’s natural fitness or unfitness for society (Hont, 2005, pp. 37–51 and 159–184), or, to put it differently, whether civil society was an extension of human propensities or an artifice. The second revolved around the division of labour in human history and its relation to social inequality (La Vopa, 2001, p. 215). A prominent and late contribution to the first debate had been made by Fichte’s academic teacher Kant. In his Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim he argued that it was particularly men’s selfish or unsociable

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 165 qualities like pride and greed that made them overcome sloth, develop their intellectual and physical faculties, and found states – consequentially driving the process of civilization (Kant, 1784/1912, pp. 15–31; cf. Rorty and Schmidt, 2009). Fichte agreed with Kant that it was man’s moral duty to live in society and ‘to cultivate, civilise, and moralise himself through the arts and sciences’ (Kant, 1798b/1917b, p. 324). But he did not share Kant’s emphasis on the antagonistic mechanism of unsocial sociability. In his claim that the ‘social drive is one of man’s fundamental drives’ and that ‘it is man’s destiny to live in society’, Fichte rather sided with the proponents of a concept of the natural sociability of man (Fichte, 1988, p. 156; Fichte, 1966, p. 37) such as Francis Hutcheson (1694– 1746), Isaak Iselin (1728–1782), or Herder. For them, sociability was an immediate propensity which manifests itself, for example, in benevolence or in the pleasure we take in communication and exchange with our fellow human beings. By contrast, given his different epistemological point of departure, Fichte made some important qualifications to their argument. These qualifications foreshadowed his later, more elaborated concept of recognition, but are also central to his concept of education. According to Fichte, our sociable drive resulted not from empirical causes but was an extension of our drive to identity and harmony with ourselves. In order to reach this, we need to assume the existence and gain the recognition of other morally-autonomous selves. But we cannot have certainty about their existence from their mere representation in our finite consciousness. Hence we had to enter into a ‘free interaction’ (Wechselwirkung durch Freiheit) with other rational beings (Fichte, 1988, p. 157; Fichte, 1966, p. 37). ‘The social drive’, Fichte contended, ‘aims at interaction, reciprocal influence, mutual give and take, mutual passivity and activity’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 158; Fichte, 1966, p. 39). Fichte envisioned this domination-free interaction as a spiritual and moral struggle between different selves leading not only to an advancement of the succumbing opponent but also to ‘the improvement of the species’ in general. His concept of Gesellschaftlichkeit as a reciprocal mechanism by which we are morally cultivated and natural inequalities mended can hence be related to a process of education propelling mankind towards greater perfection and a cosmopolitan unity grounded in the unity of reason. As he pointed out, the ‘social drive offers man a new, special type of education (Bildung); that is education for society, as well as an extraordinary facility for education as such’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 170; Fichte, 1966, p. 51). Fichte’s account, in his third and fourth lectures, of the division of social ranks and of the particular role of the scholar was a mere extension of his concept of sociability. At first glance, the division of classes sat rather uneasily with the goal of a free society of equals. Again Rousseau’s account of social inequality was an unavoidable point of reference. And Fichte was well aware that, in contrast to physical inequality, ‘the inequality of classes appears to be a moral inequality’ – the very distinction Rousseau used in the Exordium of the Second discourse (Fichte, 1988, p. 161; Fichte, 1966, p. 42; cf. Rousseau, 1997, p. 131). The division of labour, however, Fichte contended, would allow us to meet our needs better, to overcome nature, and thus to facilitate the progress of

166

Alexander Schmidt

mankind towards greater freedom from necessity. In many ways, this was a fairly conventional defence of the benefits of the division of labour. But Fichte deviated from this well-trodden path of natural law and political economy when he focussed on the moral goal of a collective education of mankind. If we accept ‘self-harmony or absolute identity’ as the ‘highest law of mankind’ ‘then the demand that every person ought to cultivate all of his talents equally contains at the same time the demand that all of the various rational beings ought to be cultivated equally’ (Fichte, 1988, pp. 162–163; Fichte, 1966, pp. 43–44). Paradoxically, this equality can be achieved through specialisation, i.e. by freely choosing a certain station within society in which we can develop our talents best. The sociable drive of exchange (Mitteilungstrieb), later redefined as a moral duty, here is immensely important for it warrants that our fellow human beings, including future generations, will profit from our achievements (Fichte, 1988, pp. 164, 168; Fichte, 1966, pp. 44, 49). On the surface this redefinition of the division of labour in terms of free communication and public discourse looks like a rather naïve riposte to Rousseau’s detailed account of the social bonds of spiralling needs and desires generated in society by our imagination and amour-propre. But as his fifth lecture demonstrates, Fichte was highly aware of the problem of needs with respect to human progress (Nakhimovsky, 2011, pp. 151–154). And it is with respect to the management of needs that the scholar takes a prominent role as ‘the educator of mankind’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 175; Fichte, 1966, p. 57). For it is his calling to enlighten society about its real needs and how they can be met under various circumstances both in the present and in the future. The scholar should detect the ills of society, such as illegitimate inequalities slowing down its progress, and thus provide a remedy to them. The scholar thereby presents the moral pinnacle of a concept of society in which the social drive is transformed into an exercise of rational discourse aiming at mutual cultivation (Bildung). The scholar is especially destined for society. More than any other class, his class, insofar exists only through and for society. Accordingly, it is his particular duty to cultivate to the highest degree within himself the social talents of receptivity and the art of communication. (Fichte, 1988, p. 173; Fichte, 1966, p. 55) It is no surprise that such passages have been repeatedly quoted to emphasize the well-established interpretation of Some lectures as a battle-cry against an ivory tower notion of academe. However, the idea that scholarship and university education had to serve society was hardly new or contested. What was strikingly different was that Fichte assigned to the scholar the central managerial role with respect to mankind’s moral advancement, replacing the Christian narrative of salvation with a vision of permanent progress – a vision that in many ways came surprisingly close to Condorcet’s yet unpublished Esquisse d’un tableau historique des progrès de l’esprit humain of 1793 (first published 1795). The ‘true vocation of the scholarly class’, Fichte emphatically declared to his audience, ‘is the

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 167 supreme supervision of the actual progress of the human race in general and the unceasing promotion of its progress’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 172; Fichte, 1966, p. 54). This supreme responsibility could only be matched by an equal moral integrity. Thus, ‘the scholar ought to be the ethically best man of his time’ (Fichte, 1988, p. 176; Fichte, 1966, p. 58). According to Anthony La Vopa, Fichte identified the scholarly community with a modern clerisy of the spiritually elect (La Vopa, 2001, pp. 229–230). Yet Fichte equally stressed that the university was not a place of contemplative virtue but a school of character which prepared for free, i.e. non-dependent, action (Fichte, 1971, p. 366). Fichte’s immodest attempt to inspire his addressees to take up a career that would contribute to a cosmopolitan aim was part of a wider debate about transforming society while avoiding the potential setbacks of a violent revolution (Schmidt, 2009; Schmidt, 2013). In all these alternative accounts, such as On the aesthetic education of man in a series of letters by Fichte’s Jena colleague, Friedrich Schiller (1759–1805), education and free public discourse were of crucial essence in developing human autonomy. In Fichte’s version of this idea, progress ‘would radiate from the universities to regenerate the entire society’ (La Vopa, 2001, p. 226). Fichte believed that this cosmopolitan advance would be the result of man’s natural capacity for free reciprocity enhanced through a class exclusively committed to furthering mankind’s cultivation. This had rather radical political implications which were only adumbrated in Fichte’s lectures. Those ancien régime institutions and corporations which either restrained the natural freedom to exchange, tried to fix human capacities, or separated society in a detrimental way – like the church, the nobility, or the student orders – had to be removed. Even the state, as Fichte made clear, had only a transient role to play in his vision of history. Its aim was to become superfluous and make way for the cosmopolitan community of free rational beings. Because of its tendency to implicate society in the pathologies of power politics, the (absolutist) state rather had to keep out of education, which it would merely exploit in order to train the future cogs and wheels of its machine. As he noted with satisfaction in an unpublished lecture of the Some lectures series, ‘wisdom, science and talent have ceased to be of value exclusively under the seal of the state, to be only useful as a tool of its drive to oppression’ (Fichte, 1971, p. 358).

Fichte’s 1807 plan for a university in Berlin When Fichte drafted his Deduzierter Plan einer zu Berlin zu errichtenden höhern Lehranstalt (Deduced plan of a higher institute of education to be erected in Berlin) in 1807 he had significantly altered his view of the state and its relation to education.2 In line with the redirection of his thinking about the relation between morality and right in his Foundations of natural right (1796), Fichte had redefined the state as a Zwangs-Anstalt (compulsory institution) exerting legitimate force on its citizens (Fichte, 1991, p. 307). The aim was not just internal peace and the state’s self-preservation but the promotion of culture and the education of its citizens to serve the progress of mankind. While the highest

168

Alexander Schmidt

degrees of human culture, religion, science, and virtue could not become purposes of the state, it nevertheless had the responsibility to facilitate them through education, even if their progress would lead to the state’s alienation from an ever more specialised science (Fichte, 1991, pp. 310–311 and 325–326). Fichte’s plan was written in response to a request by Karl Friedrich Beyme (1765–1838), the Prussian chef du cabinet (Lenz, 1910, pp. 71–132), who sought the expertise of scholars concerning the government’s plan to found a new university in Berlin after Prussia’s crushing defeat at the hands of Napoleonic France at Jena in October 1806, and the resulting loss of half of its territory including Halle, its finest university. The fiscal and moral crisis of the Prussian state after the Peace of Tilsit in 1807 led the administration to implement a comprehensive reform programme working on all levels of society (Nolte, 1990). Its aim was to enable Prussia to recover from its losses and prepare for a future confrontation with France. Founding a new university might seem to be a surprising move, for it was expensive and Prussia still had two. But it must be seen in the light of this policy. In 1807, in response to the first proposal for a transfer of the university at Halle to Berlin, King Frederick William III allegedly said that Prussia now had to compensate in the field of intellect what it had lost in terms of political power (Lenz, 1910, p. 78). Reformers like Freiherr vom Stein believed that Prussia had to become the cultural and intellectual powerhouse of the German nation in order to marshal its resources and gain wider support in a future struggle with Napoleon. Saxon-born Fichte, who like Stein viewed Prussia as a mere instrument for the recovery of the German nation and Europe from the military imperialism of Napoleon, was sympathetic to such plans. In 1805/6 he had already proposed to the Prussian government that the recently acquired university at Erlangen could be turned into a new intellectual and moral focal point for German youth in the spirit of ancient Athens (Fichte, 1993). In his Deduced plan, drawn up immediately before the famous Addresses to the German nation, Fichte pursued a less obviously patriotic agenda. Characteristically, he could not resist proposing a radical overhaul of the current university. His point of departure was the problem of the type of competence to be procured at university. Should the university be the final stage of school education, inculcating the student with the specialist knowledge immediately relevant to a civil occupation? Fichte clearly rejected any such notion. The attempt to fix erratic knowledge through exams, in particular, was eventually illusory. Instead, the ultimate purpose of the university should be the acquisition of the art of using knowledge. Students should cultivate their facility for self-directed learning, enabling them creatively to appropriate and transform knowledge in infinite ways. The proper title of such an institution would thus be ‘a school of the art of the scientific use of reason’ (Fichte, 1998, §5, p. 87). Fichte specified three conditions which were integral in achieving this purpose. First, students had to receive a proper education at school level; second, they had to entirely dedicate themselves to their studies; third, they had to be freed from any kind of concerns regarding their livelihood (§10, pp. 91–96).

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 169 As in Fichte’s 1794 Jena lectures, his assertion of a philosophically-guided learning was connected to a certain social vision. The students should be separated from the ordinary bourgeois life and its ‘dull joys’. The ‘regular’ students should live in the autarky of a shared household like one family. They were to receive only little pocket money for most of their needs (food, books, etc.) were procured in kind by the university thus minimising their commercial exchange with the rest of society. These regular students should also be distinguished from civil persons by a uniform as their dress of honour (§ 33, p. 122). These passages have frequently led scholars to deem Fichte’s proposal authoritarian and to compare his university unfavourably with a monastery or a military barracks (Crouter, 2005; Schelsky, 1971, p. 83). Fichte was eager to stress, however, that he had drawn his practical inspiration from similar regulations at Cambridge, Oxford, Tübingen, and the Saxon princely Gymnasia (Fürstenschulen) like Schulpforta, of which he himself was a pupil (§ 57, pp. 152–153).3 What has been overlooked in recent scholarship is that Fichte’s proposal was also a sequel to his Closed commercial state of 1800. Here he had sought to address the problem of how to regulate human needs through state intervention in order, to put it broadly, to end international rivalry and minimise social conflict – an issue that was already essential to his Some lectures (Nakhimovsky, 2011, pp. 151–154). Following Rousseau, Fichte’s students were to become Émiles, carefully prevented from being exposed prematurely to commercial society until they were prepared to enter it. In a corollary of his Deduced plan, the parallels between the Closed commercial state and Fichte’s vision of academe became even more obvious. The Fichtean university was to become the kernel of a renewal of human society both in the state and the international level (Fichte, 1998, § 67, pp. 169–170). Future statesmen would, through their university socialisation, learn to appreciate the organic order of an institution based on the republican principles of equality, freedom, and a fraternal commitment to the common good.4 The universities, whose relations Fichte wanted to organise through a network of envoys, would foreshadow the peaceable and lawful order of republics working free from mean jealousy towards one common rational goal. The careful purging of student life from any trace of the utilitarian preoccupations of bourgeois life also reflected a moral concern that united Fichte with the mainstream in German thought around 1800. Analogous to a Kantian concept of morality and aesthetics, scholarly pursuit should not be motivated by heteronomous motives. Even Schleiermacher stressed in his rather different Occasional thoughts about universities in a German spirit that the students need seclusion from society and ‘should not be drawn into the emptiness of the usual mundane sociable intercourse’ (Schleiermacher, 1998, p. 76). As Fichte pointed out in the Addresses to the German nation (1808), any proper (national) education must make sure that the pupil would pursue something out of love for the good and the joy he takes in self-directed action (Selbsttätigkeit) instead of stimulating him with recourse to his selfish wellbeing (Fichte, 2005, pp. 119–122). The strictures on student life were not least intended to ensure absolute equality between the students. Here Fichte, the son of a humble weaver from

170

Alexander Schmidt

Saxony who had fought his way through the education system, again addressed the relation between academe and social inequality. He wanted the university to offer places according to intellectual merit only. The regular students had to be kept in total ignorance of whether their fellow-students’ fees were paid by their parents or whether they received free education. Only thus did he hope to form a new meritocracy out of the corps of regular students (Regularien) who would take the first places in the state (Fichte, 1998, § 51, pp. 145–148). The harsh separation of the university from the whims of society was not matched by an equally authoritarian ‘deductive’ climate within the university. On the contrary, following the Jena lectures, the relation between student and teacher was characterised by a constant and equal exchange. Examinations should thus not be an interrogation but rather an ‘expressive Socratic dialogue’ which was only part of a permanent ‘invisible dialogue which characterises academic life as a whole’ (§ 9, p. 90).5 Students also had to produce their own self-directed written work. They were thus not only at the receiving end of education but would, through intellectual exchange, also contribute to the further advancement of the teacher.

Schleiermacher’s Occasional thoughts of 1808 It has become a standard interpretation that Schleiermacher’s public intervention in the debate about the new university in Berlin ‘was meant to oppose the views of Fichte’ (Crouter, 2005, p. 146). Indeed the deliberately relaxed title (for a relatively lengthy tract), Occasional thoughts about universities in a German spirit, sounds remarkably anti-Fichtean. Yet there is no direct evidence that Schleiermacher, whose tract decisively influenced Humboldt’s foundation in 1809, had any knowledge of Fichte’s manuscript before its publication in 1817. During the French occupation of large parts of Prussia (including Berlin), Schleiermacher, Reformed pastor, classicist, philosopher, and professor of theology at Halle, was moved by a rather different concern from merely refuting the despised thought of Fichte. From early on, he was an outspoken opponent of Napoleon’s military imperialism. As is clear from his extensive private correspondence, Schleiermacher feared that the Empereur would seek to solidify his military occupation of Northern Germany by crushing both Protestantism and Kantian speculative philosophy, the alleged spiritual and intellectual residues of German cultural autonomy (Wolfes, 2004, pp. 151–167). The temporary closure of the university at Halle, one of main centres for the training of Protestant pastors, by personal order of Napoleon on 20 October 1806, seemed to confirm those very fears. As Schleiermacher made clear in a letter to his friend, the Swedish diplomat Karl Gustav von Brinckmann on 1 March 1808, the intention of Occasional thoughts was to defend the ‘German university’ tradition and to reject the adoption of the French technocratic model of special écoles (Müller, 1990, p. 257). Their misguided German advocates, Schleiermacher wrote in Occasional thoughts, were ‘infected by a pernicious un-German spirit’ (Schleiermacher,

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 171 1998, p. 46). In contrast to the cosmopolitan-patriotic vision of Fichte’s Deduced plan, Schleiermacher’s tract was thus nationalist and in favour of a characteristically Prussian ‘anti-modern modernisation’ (Schubring, 1991, p. 303) of the university as a kernel of a regeneration of the German nation. And Schleiermacher was not alone in his efforts to save the ‘German’ university. His work was paralleled by an essay from the French Kantian and Germanophile emigré Charles de Villers (1765–1815), who as part of an attempt to prevent the closing down of such places as Göttingen and Halle in the recently-created Napoleonic kingdom of Westphalia, pointed out the significance of the Protestant university for German cultural progress (Villers, 1808). Crucially with respect to the political fragmentation of Germany, Schleiermacher’s point of departure was the relation between the (particular) state and the university as a natural creation of the nation. He established his concept of scholarly and scientific pursuit on the basis of man’s sociable drive to communicate with others and to share knowledge (Schleiermacher, 1998, p. 22). Taking up the Herderian and Romantic focus on national language, Schleiermacher linked learning as a sociable activity to a national language, participating in and enlivening it. In a rather cavalier treatment of the history of universities, he claimed that scientific and scholarly communities had first developed independently from the state. The state had only integrated and promoted them at a later stage in order to profit from the knowledge they produced (Schleiermacher, 1998, pp. 22–24). As in his various lectures on ethics, first delivered in 1804/05 at Halle and later continued at Berlin, Schleiermacher distinguished between the different spheres of society: family, state, church/religion, free sociability, and learning/ university. These spheres would follow their own respective rationalities with respect to moral agency, and were characterised by antagonisms of various duties and moral goods both on the internal level and with other spheres of social life (Schleiermacher, 2002; cf. Pleger, 1988, pp. 53–57). To lessen these antagonisms it would be vital to introduce certain intermediary elements, such as political representation between the ruler and the ruled, as well as to respect the autonomy of each area as an equally valuable sphere of moral agency. Schleiermacher’s ethics of goods not only sought to solve some of the problems he observed in Kantian deontology with its conflicting duties, it also offered a federal (nationalist) solution to the complexities of a politically and religiously fragmented German nation. Following Kant’s Quarrel of the faculties, Schleiermacher’s Occasional thoughts observed a conflict between reason of state and the sociable origins of the university, which ought to promote the pursuit of knowledge within a nation for its own sake only (Schleiermacher, 1998, pp. 23–30 and 66–67; cf. Kant, 1798a/1917a, pp. 21–23). He warned of the effects that state competition and protectionist policies would have on universities and the search for truth. For the states would perceive academic institutions, first of all, as a mere accumulation of skills and applicable knowledge – with the French special schools as the quintessential incarnation of this rationale. The politically fragmented German

172

Alexander Schmidt

nation, whose cultural unity depended on the supra-regional character of the universities, was most affected by these restrictions on intellectual freedom by this jealousy of state. Against this, Schleiermacher contended, the ‘state should leave the sciences to themselves’. Instead of exerting censorship on ideas, the state should only care for the economic administration and the external discipline of the universities (Schleiermacher, 1998, pp. 40–41; cf. Schleiermacher, 2002, p. 75, § 112). Prussia would become a national model of free intellectual exchange by giving up any attempts to protect the monopoly of its universities through bans on the free movement of its native students. Thus every German should have equal access to education offered by universities in free competition. Schleiermacher had witnessed the French expulsion of Halle’s students in October 1806 because a student drinking party had shouted pereat (he shall perish) outside Napoleon’s window during his stay in the town. And it was with respect to the regulation of student life that his Occasional thoughts made the most striking claims. Against the consensus of the vast majority of authors writing about universities, Schleiermacher rejected any strong notions of either restricting the number of university candidates or of regulating students’ life. Instead, intellectual qualities should be allowed to develop and differentiate at university level, before the able and less able were precipitately separated in life after education (Schleiermacher, 1998, pp. 44–45). Furthermore, he claimed, the essence of academic liberty consisted in students’ freedom to try out various ways of life free from the conventions of society. To live on the streets like the Ancients, to fill them with music and singing like people from the Mediterranean, to feast like the rich, as long as money lasts, and then to despise all comforts of life like ancient Cynics, completely to neglect one’s clothing or to dress up fashionably ... that is academic Freedom. (Schleiermacher, 1998, p. 73) Only by this anarchic disregard of conventions would students become truly able to choose their proper position in society. For Schleiermacher, the university was not just a place of intellectual education but in an equally important sense a laboratory of morals (Sitten) for the whole nation, even if this implied the (tacit) acceptance of duels – a practice acutely abhorred by Fichte (see Sweet, 1993). Morals had to be kept mouldable (bildsam), Schleiermacher believed, and Germany was particularly fortunate that its moral education was not shaped according to the model of the upper classes but in the free sphere of academic life (Schleiermacher, 1998, p. 75). Only through this freedom could the German nation hope to achieve an ethical life which was ‘the liberal expression of particularity in a common form’ (Schleiermacher, 1998, p. 76). In a corollary to this urban vision of higher education, Schleiermacher decisively opted for Berlin and thus a great city as the future seat of the new university, rejecting other plans to situate the university in the frugal and allegedly sober environment of a small town (Schleiermacher, 1998, pp. 86–100; also Haase, 2005).

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 173

Conclusion In many details, there could not be greater disagreement about the reform of higher education than between Fichte’s and Schleiermacher’s proposals (cf. Crouter, 2005). And yet there is a striking accord between them and, one might add, Wilhelm von Humboldt, in their emphasis on education as a selfdirected pursuit in a constant exchange within a community of equals. Only through this, they believed, the student could develop the capability to embrace and to judge knowledge. Higher education had to defy a utilitarian notion of knowledge that was mainly concerned with practical application. Combined with emancipation from the constraints of class and the concerns of commercial society, this would allow students to form a moral character. With a different emphasis, Fichte’s and Schleiermacher’s notion of individual self-formation was thereby informed by a reformulated concept of natural sociability. According to this notion, both our selves and society as a whole are the product of an interplay between man’s receptive and communicative dispositions. In Fichte’s and Schleiermacher’s respective visions of the linkage between individual and collective education, the university was to become the principal laboratory of the education of mankind (Fichte) and the nation (Fichte and Schleiermacher). Their claim that the state had to accept the autonomy of higher education was thereby defended with a paradox: only by defying the state’s narrow utilitarian and moral (religious) demands could the university, in the end, serve the requirements and the true purpose of the state better, promoting the (moral) education of its citizens and the progress of mankind. Today there might be thought to be good reasons to dismiss these ideas of the reform of higher education as outdated, illusory, and ill-suited to the challenges of a global knowledge society. Given the intellectual poverty of current reform programmes, such as the Bologna process, however, we might nevertheless take some courage from the grandeur and daring of Fichte’s and Schleiermacher’s visions of academia.

Acknowledgements The first version of this chapter was written during a fellowship at the Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences and Humanities (Cambridge) in spring 2012. The author is grateful to David James, Isaac Nakhimovsky, Chris Newfield and James Vigus, as well as to the editors of this volume, for their many helpful suggestions.

Notes 1 Among the vast literature on the debate about Bildung around 1800, see Bollenbeck, 1994; Geuss, 1996; Reitz, 2003. 2 See König, 1935; Turnbull, 1937; Hahn, 1969; Reiß, 2006, pp. 84–102. 3 Johannes von Müller, Prussian court historiographer and later to be the secretary for education in the kingdom of Westphalia, leaked to his friend Böttiger in Dresden in

174

Alexander Schmidt

October 1807 that, according to Fichte’s plan, the future university in Berlin would resemble a college of the Oxford or other English type (Fuchs, 1987, p. 60). 4 It is important to note here against a reading of Fichte as a theorist of an authoritarian national state, which is associated with Isaiah Berlin, that the role of the state is not defined as compelling virtue but as controlling the social interference that prevents the internal capacity for culture and morality from operating. See Berlin, 2000, pp. 191 and 195–197. 5 For a differing interpretation see Crouter, 2005, p. 149.

References Adler, H. (1994) Die Bestimmung des Menschen. Johann Joachim Spaldings Schrift als Ausgangspunkt einer offenen Anthropologie, Das achtzehnte Jahrhundert, 18.2, 125–137. Ameriks, K. (2000) Kant and the fate of autonomy: problems in the appropriation of the critical philosophy (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Anrich, E. (ed.) (1956) Die Idee der deutschen Universität. Die fünf Grundschriften aus der Zeit ihrer Neubegründung durch klassischen Idealismus und romantischen Realismus (Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft). Berlin, Isaiah (2002) Two concepts of liberty, in I. Berlin, Liberty, (ed. Henry Hardy) (Oxford, Oxford University Press), 166–217. Bollenbeck, G. (1994) Bildung und Kultur: Glanz und Elend eines deutschen Deutungsmusters (Frankfurt/Main, Suhrkamp). Bruch, R. v. (2001) Zur Gründung der Berliner Universität im Kontext der deutschen Universitätslandschaft um 1800, in: G. Müller & K. Ries (eds) Die Universität Jena: Tradition und Innovation um 1800 (Stuttgart, Steiner). Crouter, R. (2005) Friedrich Schleiermacher: Between Enlightenment and Romanticism. (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Eichler, M. (2012) Die Wahrheit des Mythos Humboldt, Historische Zeitschrift, 294, 59–78. Fichte, J. G. [1794–95] (1966) Einige Vorlesungen über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten, in Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. I. 3 (eds R. Lauth & H. Jacob) (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 23–68. Fichte, J. G. [1794] (1971) Schlusswort der Vorlesungen ueber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten. Bruchstück, in Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. II. 3 (eds R. Lauth & H. Jacob) (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 343–367. Fichte, J. G. (1988) Early philosophical writings (trans. & ed. D. Breazeale) (Ithaca and London, Cornell University Press). Fichte, J. G. [1806] (1991) ‘Die Grundzüge der gegenwärtigen Zeitalters’, in: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. I, 8 (eds. R. Lauth and H. Gliwitzky) (Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 141–396. Fichte, J. G. [1805–06] (1993) ‘Ideen für die innere Organisation der Universität Erlangen’, in: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. II. 9 (eds R. Lauth & H. Gliwitzky) (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 359–380. Fichte, J. G. [1807] (1998), Deduzierter Plan einer zu Berlin zu errichtenden höhern Lehranstalt, in: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. II, 11 (eds. R. Lauth, H. Gliwitzky, E. Fuchs & P. K. Schneider) (Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 65–170.

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 175 Fichte, J. G. [1808] (2005) Reden an die deutsche Nation, in Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften vol. I, 10 (eds. R. Lauth, E. Fuchs, P. K. Schneider, H. G. von Manz, I. Radrizzani, M. Siegel & G. Zöller) (Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt, Frommann-Holzboog), 1–298. Fuchs, E. (ed.) (1987) J. G. Fichte im Gespräch: Berichte der Zeitgenossen vol. 4 (1806–1812) (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Frommann-Holzboog). Geuss, R. (1996) Kultur, Bildung, Geist, History and Theory, 35, 151–164. Haase, S. (2005) Metropolitane Gelehrsamkeit statt “Einsamkeit und Freiheit” – Die Diskussion um den Universitätsstandort Berlin um 1800, in I.-M. D’Aprile (ed.) Tableau de Berlin. Beiträge zur ‘Berliner Klassik’ (1786–1815) (Hannover-Laatzen, Wehrhahn), pp. 113–128. Hahn, K. (1969) Staat, Erziehung und Wissenschaft bei J. G. Fichte (Munich, Beck). Hont, I. (2005), Jealousy of trade: international competition and the nation-state in historical perspective (Cambridge, MA, The Belknap Press). James, D. (2011) Fichte’s social and political philosophy: property and virtue (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Kant, I. [1784] (1912) Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht, in: Gesammelte Schriften vol. I.8 (Akademie-Ausgabe) (Berlin, Reimer), 15–32. Kant, I. [1798a] (1917a) Der Streit der Fakultäten, in: Gesammelte Schriften vol. I.7 (Akademie-Ausgabe) (Berlin, Reimer), 1–116. Kant, I. [1798b] (1917b) Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht, in Gesammelte Schriften vol. I.7 (Akademie-Ausgabe) (Berlin, Reimer), 117–334. Kant, I. [1803] (1923) Über Pädagogik, in Gesammelte Schriften vol. I.9 (AkademieAusgabe) (Berlin, de Gruyter), 437–500. Kant, I. [1784] (1991) What is Enlightenment? in: Political writings (ed. H. Reiss) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 54–60. König, R. (1935) Vom Wesen der deutschen Universität (Berlin, Verlag die Runde). La Vopa, A. J. (2001) Fichte. the self and the calling of philosophy (1762–1799) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Lenz, M. (1910) Geschichte der Königlichen Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität zu Berlin vol. 1: Gründung und Ausbau (Halle, Verlag der Buchhandlung des Waisenhauses). Menze, C. (1991) Wilhelm von Humboldt und die deutsche Universität, Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Pädagogik 67, 471–484. Müller, E. (ed.) (1990) Gelegentliche Gedanken über Universitäten von J. J. Engel, J. B. Erhard, F. A. Wolf, J. G. Fichte, F. D. E. Schleiermacher, W. v. Humboldt, G. F. W. Hegel (Leipzig, Reclam-Verlag). Nakhimovsky, I. (2011) The closed commercial state: perpetual peace and commercial society from Rousseau to Fichte (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Nolte, P. (1990) Staatsbildung als Gesellschaftsreform. Politische Reformen in Preußen und den süddeutschen Staaten 1800–1820 (Frankfurt, Campus). Pleger, W. H. (1988) Schleiermachers Philosophie (Berlin & New York, de Gruyter). Reiß, S. (2006) Fichtes “Reden an die deuthsche Nation” oder: Vom Ich zum Wir (Berlin, Akademie Verlag). Reitz, T. (2003) Bürgerlichkeit als Haltung: Zur Politik des privaten Weltverhältnisses (Munich, Fink). Rorty A. O. and J. Schmidt (eds) (2009) Kant’s Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim: A Critical Guide (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Robertson, J. (2005) The case for the Enlightenment. Scotland and Naples 1680–1760 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

176

Alexander Schmidt

Rose, M. (2012) Schleiermachers Staatslehre (Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck). Rousseau, J. J. (1997) The discourses and other early political writings (ed. V. Gourevitch) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Rüegg, W. (1997) Der Mythos der Humboldtschen Universität, in M. Krieg and M. Rose (eds) Universitas in theologia – theologia in universitate. Festschrift für Hans Heinrich Schmidt zum 60. Geburtstag (Zürich, Theologischer Verlag). Savigny, F. C. v. [1808] (1990) Rezension von F. Schleiermachers ‚Gelegentliche Gedanken über Universitäten in deutschem Sinn’, in Müller, E. (ed.) Gelegentliche Gedanken über Universitäten von J. J. Engel, J. B. Erhard, F. A. Wolf, J. G. Fichte, F. D. E. Schleiermacher, W. v. Humboldt, G. F. W. Hegel (Leipzig, Reclam-Verlag). Schalenberg, M. (2002) Humboldt auf Reisen? Die Rezeption des‚ deutschen Universitätsmodells’ in den französischen und britischen Reformdiskursen (1810–1870) (Basel, Schwabe & Co). Schelsky, H. (1971) Einsamkeit und Freiheit: Idee und Gestalt der deutschen Universität und ihrer Reformen, (2nd edn) (Düsseldorf, Bertelsmann Universitätsverlag). Schleiermacher, F. (1998) Gelegentliche Gedanken über Universitäten in deutschem Sinn. Nebst einem Anhang über eine neu zu errichtende, in Kritische Gesamtausgabe I.6 (ed. D. Schmidt) (Berlin, de Gruyter), 18–100. Schleiermacher, F. (2002) Lectures on philosophical ethics (ed. & trans. by R. B. Louden) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Schmidt, A. (2009) The liberty of the ancients? Friedrich Schiller and aesthetic republicanism, History of Political Thought, 30, 286–314. Schmidt, A. (2012) Scholarship, morals and government: Jean-Henri-Samuel Formey’s and Johann Gottfried Herder’s responses to Rousseau’s First discourse, Modern Intellectual History, 9.2, 249–274. Schmidt, A. (2013) Freedom and state action in German late Enlightenment thought, in: Q. Skinner and M. v. Gelderen (eds) Freedom and the construction of Europe vol. 2 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 208–226. Schubring, G. (1991) Spezialschulmodell versus Universitätsmodell: Die Institutionalisierung von Forschung, in: G. Schubring (ed.) 'Einsamkeit und Freiheit' neu besichtigt: Universitätsreformen und Disziplinenbildung in Preußen als Modell für Wissenschaftspolitik im Europa des 19. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart, Franz Steiner Verlag). Stölzel, A. (1889) Die Berliner Mittwochsgesellschaft über Aufhebung oder Reform der Universitäten (1795), Forschungen zur Brandenburgischen und Preußischen Geschichte 2, 201–222. Sweet, P. R. (1993) Fichte and the Jews: A case of tension between civil rights and human rights, German Studies Review, 16, 37–68. Tenorth, H. -E. (2010) Wilhelm von Humboldts (1767–1835) Universitätskonzept und die Reform in Berlin: eine Tradition jenseits des Mythos, Zeitschrift für Germanistik, 20, 15–28. Turnbull, G. H. (1937) The changes in Fichte’s attitude toward state intervention in education, International Journal of Ethics, 47, 234–243. Turner, S. R. (1972) University reformers and professorial scholarship in Germany (1760– 1806), in L. Stone (ed.) The University in society, vol. 2 (Princeton, Princeton University Press), 491–531. Turner, S. R. (1987) Universitäten, in: K.-E. Jeismann & P. Lundgreen (eds) Handbuch der deutschen Bildungsgeschichte, vol. III: 1800–1870: Von der Neuordnung Deutschlands bis zur Gründung des Deutschen Reiches (Munich, Beck), 221–249.

Self-cultivation (Bildung) and sociability 177 Villers, C. (1808) Coup d'œil sur les universités et le mode d'instruction publique de l’Allemagne protestante, en particulier du royaume de Westphalie (Kassel, Imprimérie Royale). Wellek, R. (1931) Ein unbekannter Artikel Savignys über die deutschen Universitäten, Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte, Germ. Abt. 51, 529–537. Winkler, M. (2008) Schleiermachers Beitrag zur preußischen Erziehungsreform, in: A. Arndt, U. Barth and W. Grab (eds) Christentum – Staat – Kultur. Akten des Kongresses der Internationalen Schleiermacher-Gesellschaft in Berlin März 2006 (Berlin & New York, de Gruyter), 497–516. Wolfes, M. (2004) Öffentlichkeit und Bürgergesellschaft. Friedrich Schleiermachers politische Wirksamkeit, vol. 1 (Berlin & New York, de Gruyter).

12 Education and utopia Robert Owen and Charles Fourier David Leopold

Introduction The aims of education, and the appropriate means of realising those aims, have been a persistent, if not universal, concern of utopian authors (Massõ, 1927; Fisher, 1963; Ozmon, 1969). Thomas More (1478–1535) might be thought to bear much of the responsibility here, since education plays an indispensable role in the commonwealth of ‘Utopia’ (whose citizens are said to be so well educated that they need few laws). However, whilst More named he did not invent the utopian tradition, and this preoccupation with education certainly predates him. Plato (429–347 BCE) would be an obvious example; the central role of education is made clear in Book Four of the Republic, a work plausibly considered the first great political utopia. (I use the term ‘utopia’ here to refer to a detailed description of an ideal society, whether or not that description takes the narrative form typical of what we might call a literary utopia proper – in which a traveller from the world of the author visits a superior society in a chronologically or geographically distant location.) It is tempting to contrast this longstanding and characteristic preoccupation with educational questions on the part of utopian authors with a lack of equivalent interest in utopia on the part of educationalists. That contrast looks real enough, but should not be overdrawn. Not least, the relation is a shifting one. In the nineteenth century, for instance, when educationalists were perhaps more engaged with wider issues of social reform, their links with certain kinds of utopia were stronger. Moreover, the lack of utopian enthusiasms on the part of modern educationalists is not universal. There are recent signs, for example, of a minority interest in what are sometimes (predictably) labelled ‘Edutopias’ (Halpern, 2003; Peters & Freeman-Moir, 2006). My ambition here, however, is not to unpack the many and complex connections between education and utopia, but to give a taste of what two nineteenthcentury utopian writers thought about education. Robert Owen (1771–1858) and Charles Fourier (1772–1837) are usually characterised as ‘utopian socialists’ (a somewhat problematic label popularised by Karl Marx (1818–1883)). Both authors placed human nature at the centre of their educational views, and they both saw their educational views as forming an important and integral part of

Education and utopia

179

their wider project of radically transforming the social and political world. However, they developed their educational and other views independently of one another, and they conceptualised the fundamental importance of human nature in very different ways. (Their direct engagement was largely limited to a brief and unproductive correspondence, and a few passing and unsympathetic comments on the myriad errors of the other.)

Robert Owen Born in Newtown in central Wales, Robert Owen left home at the age of ten. He worked first as a draper’s assistant, before moving – with considerable entrepreneurial success – into the expanding cotton industry in Manchester. As manager and part-owner of the New Lanark Mill in Scotland, he sought to implement his already-formed views about human character and the environment: improving working (and living) conditions, moderating child labour, and providing infant education. Those views and that social experiment were promoted in A new view of society (1813–1814). Owen subsequently sought a larger public role, initially as an authoritative voice on factory legislation, and then as a radical critic of contemporary society. In increasingly millenarian language, he prophesied the imminent collapse of the old order and the emergence of a new moral world. He now recommended small communitarian settlements, initially as an alternative to poor relief, and then as an alternative form of society. Owen lost most of his personal fortune on a communal experiment at New Harmony, in Indiana (1825–1827), but subsequently pursued another settlement at Harmony, in Hampshire (1839–1845). Between these two transatlantic communal experiments came the brief period when (parts of) the growing Owenite movement coalesced with two mass working-class movements: the first wave of the cooperative movement (when Owenite ‘labour exchanges’ issued labour notes as currency); and a period of dramatic growth in trade unionism (culminating in the short-lived Grand National Consolidated Trades Union). The Owenite movement subsequently retreated into its so-called ‘sectarian’ phase, with Owen promoting his ‘new religion’ through The book of the new moral world (1842–1844) and lectures to the Rational Society. His last years were marked by a conversion to Spiritualism, to the embarrassment of some of his subsequent admirers. (Happily, following a spiritual communication from the former Duke of Kent, Owen was able to confirm the absence of titles in the afterlife.) Owen’s central claim about human nature (repeated endlessly in his writings) has two (equally contestable) component parts. First, he insists that individuals do not form their own character, rather their character is wholly formed for them by circumstances. Second, he insists that individuals are consequently not accountable for their own sentiments and habits; to imagine that they merit rewards for some actions and punishments for others is a fundamental mistake. Owen maintains that with the application of the right means any ‘general character’ from the ‘best’ to the ‘worst’ can be created in a community. In A new

180

David Leopold

view of society, the contrast here is broadly between a ‘good’ character that is intelligent, rational, and happy, and a ‘bad’ character that is ignorant, irrational, and miserable. (An elaborated version has ‘manly’, ‘just’, ‘generous’, ‘temperate’, ‘active’, ‘kind’, and ‘benevolent’ traits, being contrasted with ‘effeminate’, ‘deceitful’, ‘ignorantly selfish’, ‘intemperate’, ‘revengeful’, and even ‘murderous’ ones (Owen, 1993a, p. 62).) It is not that human nature provides no constraints whatsoever on what can be created, but rather that human nature is sufficiently plastic that, with the appropriate means, it can be formed into either the best or the worst of characters. The appropriate means of forming human nature consist of education in what we might call broad and narrow senses. In a broad sense, education is synonymous with the social environment in which all individuals are circumstanced. In a narrow sense, education is concerned with the training of the young, typically in specialised institutions. The right direction of these means requires their being controlled by a minority with an understanding of, and authority in, human affairs. (Even in his most radical moments, Owen subscribed to a variety of socialism ‘from above’, a socialism that viewed ‘self-emancipation’ and democratic control with mistrust.) Initially, Owen wrote as a ‘manufacturer for pecuniary profit’, advising his peers to take as much care of their ‘vital machines’ as they did of their ‘inanimate machines’, ensuring that both were kept neat, clean, kindly treated, and wellsupplied (Owen, 1993a, p. 28). The workers of New Lanark before his own arrival are portrayed (perhaps exaggeratedly) as sunk in vice: they lived ‘in idleness, in poverty, in almost every kind of crime; consequently, in debt, out of health, and in misery’, all this overlain, in Scotland, by religious sectarianism (Owen, 1993a, p. 45). However, with a few judicious changes Owen claimed to have transformed their sorry condition. Circumstances were instituted which quickly and effectively formed habits of order, regularity, health, temperance, industry, and faithfulness to employers. Some changes were of general application. For example, housing conditions were improved, roads were maintained, and a company shop providing necessities at low prices was established. Other changes were more closely linked to specific kinds of behaviour. For example, to reduce alcohol abuse, public houses were closed, alternative recreation was provided (gardening and walking are identified as economical and innocent pleasures which individuals can be trained to enjoy), and the health benefits of temperance were explained to workers (when they were most receptive – whilst suffering from hangovers). Owen was keen to appeal to New Lanark as experimental proof of the veracity of his claims about the formation of character. He presented himself as a successful practical man (not yet another speculative theorist), whose thorough study of human nature was reflected in a combination of self-evident propositions and empirically proven recommendations. Having succeeded locally, Owen sought to work on a national scale to form character and ameliorate the ‘lower classes’. He initially urged the British government to institute a series of measures – said to follow from abandoning

Education and utopia

181

the absurd and damaging notion that individuals form their own characters – including: restricting the sale and consumption of alcohol; ending the state lottery; removing religious tests; reforming the poor law (providing a modest system of public works); and introducing a system of education along the lines established at New Lanark (see below). Owen insisted that these changes could be made without social upheaval and injury to any part of society. Existing social arrangements are said to be held together, not by class interests, but by an ignorance that the light of (Owenite) truth was already beginning to dispel. Class struggle is ‘irrational’ because it presupposes what is – on the Owenite account – false, namely that the ‘higher classes’ are responsible for the misery of the ‘lower classes’. And it is ‘useless’ because it encourages (misplaced but nonetheless real) resistance to change on the part of the ‘higher classes’. Rich and poor, Owen avers, have but one interest, and the latter ought to view the former not as class enemies but as potential friends and active collaborators. Owen always retained both this foundational assumption about the formation of character, and this innocence about the nature of political power. What changes is that he subsequently adopted more radical views about the problems besetting modern society and the measures required to solve them. Contemporaries were outraged by Owen’s increasingly critical pronouncements on contemporary religion and marriage. He attacked all of the religions of the world (as currently taught) for their sectarian and superstitious attitudes, and for being based on ideas (about character formation) destructive of human well-being and happiness. And he attacked existing marriage arrangements for compelling men and women who did not love each other to live together (thereby generating selfishness, cunning, deception, prostitution, and crime). However, it was his evolving economic and communitarian ideas which were ultimately a more influential part of his growing radicalism. Owen criticised the contemporary economic system – which was based on competition and the idea of buying cheap and selling dear – on various grounds: for being inefficient and wasteful; for creating unhealthy and unpleasant employment; for overproducing commodities with little or no intrinsic utility or worth; and for encouraging injurious inequalities. Its central failing, however, was predictably its effect on character, since competition encourages the ‘most inferior feelings, the meanest faculties, the worse passions, and the most injurious vices’ (Owen, 1991, p. 358). Owen increasingly identified small communal settlements as both the means to, and the final institutional form of, the rational and humane future. The triumph of communitarian socialism would take a gradualist and nonconfrontational form; spreading by example from community to community, country to continent, until the whole world is organised according to cooperative principles. He enthused about the many advantages of communal life, including the avoidance of domestic duplication; for example, better food would be prepared at a fraction of the effort and cost of individual family arrangements. He found it much harder to imagine any potential disadvantages of communal

182

David Leopold

living. Indeed, the only practical worry he raises concerns the dangers of people living under the old order rushing precipitately into the new settlements. A consistent picture of the ideal Owenite community emerges despite some variation in the detail. Communities should be small, not falling below 500 or rising above 2,500 persons. Agriculture (adopting a specific kind of spade cultivation) should predominate over manufacture; machinery could be used – for example, to reduce harmful and laborious tasks – but must always be subordinated to human interests. Each settlement should be built in a closed ‘parallelogram’, with living quarters on each side, and school, church, and dining hall in the middle. Property arrangements are a little less certain. Owen’s conviction that labour was the source of all wealth, and that competition bred an undesirable kind of character, encouraged him to endorse common rather than private property. However, his views on this issue are not always clear or consistent, and he remained cautious about the speed with which divisions between rich and poor might be overcome. The place of politics and government in these communities is also uncertain. Owen’s resistance to democratic control was constant, and he always personally sought paternalistic authority over both communal experiments and the wider Owenite movement. In later formulations of his communal plan, he settled on a kind of gerontocracy as the ideal arrangement. In one version, he divides the population of each settlement into eight age cohorts, the seventh and eighth of which would control ‘domestic affairs’ (preserving communal harmony and affection) and ‘foreign affairs’ (managing communications between communities), respectively. It seems that the artificial and irrational distinctions of class and status are gradually to be replaced by natural and rational divisions based on age and experience. Turning from the broad to the narrow sense of education, Owen maintains that the right kind of schooling is both crucial – the best-governed state is the one with the best system of education – and seemingly relatively easy to accomplish. At least, forming the character of children is said to be much less difficult than reforming the character of adults. Adults resist the need to unlearn and abandon long acquired (bad) habits, whereas children are without exception ‘passive and wonderfully contrived compounds’. A rightly directed environment, of which a rational system of schooling is a crucial part, might easily mould this ‘plastic’ into an appropriate bundle of rational wishes and desires (Owen, 1993a, p. 41). Discussion of Owen’s educational views typically focus on the schooling in New Lanark and in the New Harmony settlement (Harrison, 1968). However, it was William Maclure (1763–1840) rather than Owen who was the predominant influence on the latter project. It was Maclure who brought in European teachers – part of the famous ‘boatload of knowledge’ – who had trained with the Swiss reformer Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi (1746–1827), who initiated the School of Industry providing ‘useful’ rather than ‘ornamental’ education, and who subsequently established the school as a separate entity under his direct control (see Bestor, 1950, pp. 133–159, 190–201). Consequently, I concentrate

Education and utopia

183

here on New Lanark as the most extended and successful practical educational experiment in which Owen was the predominant influence. Whilst the social context of education alters radically in his later writings – schooling is now organised within a global network of cooperative communities rather than the towns and villages of a competition-ridden nation state – Owen’s narrowly educational views are relatively unchanged. New Lanark appears to give us as accurate a picture of the narrowly educational content of the future as we are likely to get this side of the Millennium (Owen, 1993d, p. 166). The ‘Institution for the Formation of Character’ at New Lanark (which opened in 1816) admitted children from eighteen months (when they could walk unaided) until ten when they could work in the factory (or occasionally, as Owen would have preferred, until twelve). It occupied a two-storey building with a playground. The upper storey was divided into two, and consisted of a classroom for the older children – with the furniture arranged after the monitorial system associated with Andrew Bell (1753–1832) and Joseph Lancaster (1778–1838), with desks against the walls and a free space in the centre of the room – and a lecture room, complete with history time-lines, globes, models, and specimens (Silver, 1996, pp. 49–52). The lower storey was divided into three rooms for the younger children. The older children were taught for some five hours daily, the infants for half of that (with supervised play for the rest of the day). Younger children were taught in mixed-sex classes, whilst older children were taught separately (although mixed for lectures). There was a school uniform (improbably combining the shape of a Roman tunic with tartan material). Parents were charged a small amount for the schooling of the older children, much less than the full cost but thereby avoiding the stigma of a pauper school. (Educational subsidies are easily justified, Owen maintains, by the wider benefits to the community.) Owen did not neglect education before and after these ages. The earliest periods of a child’s life were particularly important on his account, since a great deal of good or evil could be taught in the first twelve months. He sought to influence this period before school indirectly, for example, by providing lectures on parenting to workers, with a focus on forming children into valuable members of the community. There were also evening classes for young persons (between ten and twenty years old) who wanted to continue their education outside of work. (Universities are not mentioned in A new view of society, but are later portrayed as irrational and distorting ‘moulds’ for forming character that will disappear with the triumph of communitarian socialism.) The content of the Owenite curriculum might look broadly familiar, but contains some innovations. The core curriculum consisted of reading (using books which are practical and relevant to the young), writing (encouraging a legible business hand useful in later life), and arithmetic (latterly adopting the ‘tables’ of Pestalozzi). The older children were also taught natural history, geography, and history. Perhaps more striking, in terms of content, was the attempt to balance physical and mental instruction. Owen viewed singing and dancing as powerful means to forming a rational and happy character (appearance, bearing,

184

David Leopold

and health were all thereby improved), and they constituted a regular part of the curriculum (charming many visitors but provoking the disapproval of his Quaker business partners). Both sexes were to have equal opportunities to acquire useful knowledge, although Owen presumes that the useful knowledge in question would vary according to sex. Girls were taught to sew and make useful garments, to prepare appetising food economically, and to keep a neat and ordered house. Boys were instructed in the art of war – there were drill exercises in the playground, training in the use of firearms, and some introduction to military tactics. Owen enthuses about the individual and collective advantages of such training: it encourages ‘attention, celerity, and order’, and provides for the selfdefence that would be necessary as long as irrational beings still remained in the world (Owen, 1993a, p. 72). The place of religious instruction at New Lanark was always controversial, and the issue contributed to Owen’s eventual resignation from the school management. Owen was a deist – believing in the existence of natural moral laws and a supreme being – and he would have preferred to teach (only) the foundational part of ‘pure and undefiled’ religion (the lesson that one should seek to promote the interests of others). However, since neither his co-owners nor the parents concerned shared these views, Owen was compelled to ensure that Christian scriptures were read and the catechism taught. Perhaps more remarkable than the curriculum are the teaching methods and aims that Owen advocated. The means of instruction were designed to make learning a pleasure and delight to children. Reflecting Owen’s controversial views on responsibility, there was to be no scolding or punishment (or rewards) of children; teachers were required rather to show affection and ‘unceasing kindness’ to all their charges (Owen, 1993d, p. 287). Children were not to be irritated or bored by books, and every effort was made to use ‘sensible signs’ in lessons and lectures (that is, models, diagrams, and specimens of the things themselves). Conversation with teachers was to be the norm, and children were encouraged to ask questions and seek clarification. Lessons might be held indoors or outdoors, and there were occasional trips (to learn about agriculture and natural history). The aim of Owenite instruction was to develop both character and reasoning. The ‘New Institution’ was fundamentally a place of safety where children would acquire the best habits. From their first admission, they were instructed that they must never injure one of their ‘playfellows’, but must rather strive to make them happy. This central precept was repeatedly emphasised until it became ‘easy and familiar’ (and therefore ‘natural’) to them (Owen, 1993a, p. 57). Having internalised this lesson in their behaviour, they were then taught the Owenite theory of character formation that lay behind it. For example, they might learn that if they had grown up in such and such a country, then they would have been ‘cannibals or Hindoos’ themselves (Owen, 1969, p. 158). Such a discovery would: first, encourage interest in, and sympathy with, a wide sphere of humanity; and second, demonstrate the central Owenite claim that our characters are formed for us, and that ‘consequently’ notions of individual praise and blame are

Education and utopia

185

misguided. As well as being formed with the best of characters, children would be taught to reason for themselves. For example, when learning to read, the content of books was to be discussed (not learnt by rote). If children could be taught to think and reason correctly, Owen insists, they would discover how to distinguish truth from falsehood for themselves. This focus on character and reasoning was central to Owen’s criticism of contemporary educational theory and practice. He did not doubt that the Bell and Lancaster schemes, for example, constituted an improvement on what went before, and contained much of pedagogic value at the level of detail. However, both approaches, he noted, could produce individuals who – whilst undoubtedly able to ‘read, write, account, and sew’ – had the worst of habits and characters. Similarly, he maintains that so-called ‘national’ schools encouraged rote learning at the expense of understanding. A visitor to these institutions, he recounts, would be shown pupils able to reproduce the most precise answers to the most insoluble theological questions, without those children having understood a word of what they had memorised (Owen, 1993a, p. 87). Owen thought that the results of his proposed transformation in the aims and methods of education were liable to be underestimated (since contemporaries were usually familiar only with the results of poor and erroneous instruction). With the right direction, and the appropriate communitarian changes to the wider society in place, he confidently predicted that children would soon outstrip the learned of previous generations. In due course, the second of his eight age cohorts (at least by the age of ten) would emerge as well-trained, rational beings, whilst those of the fourth group (aged fifteen to twenty) would effectively be men and women of ‘a new race’ – physically, intellectually and morally far superior to any who have previously lived upon the earth (Owen, 1991, p. 349).

Charles Fourier Fourier was born in Besançon, in the French province of Franche-Comté. His childhood was dominated by the commercial background and religiosity of his family, against which he subsequently rebelled. In adulthood, Fourier earned a modest living from a variety of commercial jobs (mainly in the silk and textile industry of Lyon), but increasingly devoted his energies to producing a torrent of idiosyncratic brochures, multi-volume treatises, letters, and polemics. Educational themes took up a large part of his Traité de I’association domestiqueagricole (1822), and early references to Fourier often describe him as a theorist of education. His lesser publications also include a strange pamphlet (the Mnémonique géographique), which sought to function as both a coded introduction to his own system and a critique of contemporary geography teaching (Beecher, 1986, pp. 378–380). Despite a deserved reputation for being a difficult and suspicious person, Fourier gradually accumulated a small school of followers, complete with its own journals (Le Phalanstère and La Phalange). He lived in Paris for the last fifteen years of his life, obsessed with the threat of plagiarism and the need to find a patron (to fund a trial community).

186

David Leopold

Fourier’s systematic and often extraordinary worldview includes: an account of the origin and development of the universe; a philosophy of history (including a 32-stage narrative of infancy, ascent, descent, and decrepitude); a critique of ‘Civilisation’ (a term used with ironical intent to refer to contemporary society); and a vision of an ideal future (which, simplifying somewhat, we can identify with the historical stage called ‘Harmony’). I will focus here on the social and educational arrangements of Harmony, but begin with Fourier’s views on Providence and human nature. Fourier shared Owen’s concern with human nature, but with a crucial difference: he saw character as God-given and liable to discovery, rather than plastic and open to creation. Given His own nature, it was impossible that God had not provided for the terrestrial happiness of humankind. The role of the social theorist was consequently to discover the key which would make that earthly paradise achievable. Fourier acknowledges that he appears an unlikely prophet, but maintains that God had once before chosen the most obscure man to deliver the most important message to the world. The key in question involves a divinely underwritten model of human nature, according to which individuals are born with different innate dispositions and propensities. The problem with all hitherto existing societies was that they had (unintentionally) constrained and misdirected that nature. What was needed instead were social arrangements that would facilitate the free development and deployment of these basic human characteristics. These opening assumptions about Providence and the liberation of a God-given human nature may not seem so remarkable. The same cannot be said of the ways in which Fourier elaborates these foundational ideas. Fourier’s complex account of human nature identifies twelve basic drives or ‘passions’: five ‘luxurious’ passions corresponding to the senses (taste, smell, hearing, sight, and touch); four ‘affective’ passions corresponding to the need for other people (friendship, love, ambition, and ‘familism’); and three ‘distributive’ passions which govern the gratification of the others (the ‘Cabalist’ passion for intrigue; the ‘Butterfly’ passion for variety; and the ‘Composite’ passion requiring both spiritual and physical gratification). These twelve ‘passions’ were combined in various ways to generate a ‘scale’ of some 810 basic personality types (Fourier, 1972, p. 220). (Fourier often uses musical and mathematical language to elaborate his ideas.) Fourier illustrates this account with confident identifications of the character types of various historical figures, and brief descriptions of the ways in which social arrangements failed to discern and liberate the drives and propensities in question. The Emperor Nero (37 BCE–68 CE) can provide both a representative example and an introduction to Fourier’s educational views (Fourier, 1972, pp. 303–307). Nero is identified as a relatively unusual character type; a ‘tetratone’ dominated by four passions (cabalist, composite, ambition, and love). He had been born with blood-thirsty inclinations, which his teacher Seneca (3 BCE–65 CE) – mistakenly believing his nature to be corrupt – had foolishly sought to deny and constrain. The result was that Nero’s natural dispositions

Education and utopia

187

subsequently reappeared in distorted and dangerous form, as he gave vent to the inclinations repressed in childhood. For Fourier, it was not Nero who was corrupt, but rather the society which had failed to utilise his natural inclinations constructively. In a rational and humane world, Nero’s blood-thirsty penchants would have drawn him at an early age to one of the work groups involved with the preparation of meat for consumption, and by the age of twenty he would have been an accomplished butcher happily serving the community. Harmony is based on this account of liberating natural drives. All its basic institutions are designed to facilitate rather than restrict human nature, and can be seen as contributing to education in the broad sense. However, education in the narrow sense is radically transformed, since there are no specialised institutions for the training of the young (see below). Perhaps the most obvious feature of Harmonian society is its communal organisation. The ideal society would be organised into Phalanxes – intentional communities of roughly two thousand individuals. (The ideal Phalanx would have 1620 members, twice the complete ‘scale’ of basic personality types.) There are few details of communal life that Fourier can resist describing, but its architecture is a particular obsession. He was especially enthusiastic about the covered walkways (cooled in summer and heated in winter) encircling the Phalanstery – the grand central building of the community, combining public and private spaces – and connecting it to surrounding buildings. The most striking social feature of the community is that it has class divisions but no class antagonisms. There would be classes in that disparities of income would coalesce to form three groups with slightly distinct lifestyles (the rich would include wealthy shareholders helping to finance the community, and drawing an income from their investment). There would be no class antagonisms, however, because their primary cause – poverty – would be absent. Fourier insists that it is not inequality per se that causes class antagonisms; disparities in wealth only provoke conflict in the absence of provision for our essential needs. And Harmony would eradicate poverty by instituting what would now be called a universal basic income; that is, an income paid to individuals, irrespective of their income from other sources, and without requiring the performance of any work. In Harmony, this income would be set at a subsistence level (covering basic needs). Class antagonisms would also be removed by Harmony’s property arrangements (in which labour, talent, and capital all share an annual dividend), by rich and poor working together in small groups, and by a unified system of education (establishing a commonality of language and manners). The political arrangements of the Phalanx are less clear. Initially, it appears that the coercive and coordinating tasks undertaken by states in Civilisation would either be unnecessary, or occur in a decentralised or informal manner. Closer inspection, however, reveals a rather shadowy central body – the ‘Areopagus’ (made up of elders, large shareholders, and representatives from various work groups) – that issues infrequent advice not backed by coercion (for example, recommending the day on which to start the harvest). In addition, there is some

188

David Leopold

similarly shadowy use of something like punishment. At least, Fourier recognises that circumstances might arise in which an individual would be excluded by their peers from a workgroup, or even – although this seems almost unimaginable to him – banished from a community as a whole (Beecher, 1986, p. 256). It will already be apparent that productive activity plays a central role in Harmonian life. Fourier rejects the familiar view of work as a necessary evil, as something both unpleasant and which we are compelled to undertake. He sees work rather as potentially creative and fulfilling, and identifies self-realisation in work as a central part of the good life. The adoption of a universal basic income (set at a substantive level) together with the absence of coercion, raises the question of whether, and why, Harmonians would engage in productive activity. Fourier’s answer is ‘attractive work’; individuals would freely engage in productive activity as one of the central ways in which to self-realise, to develop and deploy their essential human characteristics. To facilitate this self-realisation, work in Harmony is organised ‘serially’. That is, productive tasks are carried out by small groups (typically some fifteen people) which are voluntary, hierarchical, socially diverse, and united by a passion for the activity in question. A typical work session might last only an hour, but there could be as many as ten sessions in a day (Fourier, 2001a, p. 193). Education, in both senses, plays an important role in Fourier’s vision (Zeldin 1969). All social arrangements in Harmony are broadly educative, aimed at liberating human nature and enabling individuals to discover and deploy their own particular combination of human characteristics. Education in the narrow sense plays this role at a vital early stage, revealing the various (plural) vocations of each individual. Fourier criticises the educational arrangements of contemporary Civilisation as unnatural and incoherent. They are ‘unnatural’ in seeking to constrain the passions, and in treating children as unproductive. They are ‘incoherent’ in that what children are taught in schools not only varies according to sex and class, but also conflicts with, and is undermined by, what they are taught by their peers and family. Fourier had some limited knowledge of contemporary educationalist ideas – he had certainly read about Pestalozzi and the ‘Lancastrians’ (Andrew Bell and Joseph Lancaster) – although he was characteristically dismissive of the opinions of others. The most striking institutional feature of Harmonian education is that it takes place without schools and without teachers. First, education occurs not in schools, nor in the family, but in the wider community. It is the Phalanx that collectively raises and educates Harmonian children. Fourier is usually said to ‘abolish’ the family, but that description is surely misleading. The modern family certainly disappears, and there are communal arrangements for child rearing. However, mothers breastfeed their children, biological parents often have close relationships with their offspring, and the familial passion is identified as one requiring expression. Second, there is no longer a class of professional educators. Harmony would, of course, contain people who teach others, but they would do so as one of many different activities as they go about their daily lives.

Education and utopia

189

Up to the age of four and a half, although they might be visited by their biological parents, children would be brought up by adults working serially as nurses (the latter drawn from the minority of adults attracted by nature to child care). These nurses would introduce their charges to the world of work, but thereafter (from the age of four or so) children would become free and independent members of the Phalanx, contributing to production from the start. Work is central to life in Harmony, and voluntary engagement in productive activity is the context in which education usually occurs. Fourier loved detailed typologies, although – to the frustration of commentators – these often vary without explanation between texts. One account has children progressing through a series of eight ‘choirs’, corresponding approximately to age ranges. Progression through these choirs is governed by a satisfactory performance in various practical tests. (Fourier does not worry quite as much as we might like about the fate of those unable to progress; there is some unclear talk of ‘half-character’ choirs, and of ‘late developers’ being able to catch up.) For example, an ‘urchin’ of four and a half, hoping to enter the choir of ‘cherubs’, might have to perform the following tasks: participating in the choir and corps de ballet at the opera; washing 120 plates in half an hour; peeling a quantity of apples within a given time; and lighting (and extinguishing) a fire promptly. Their success at these tasks would be judged by slightly older children, who would prove much more reliable critics than the parents of Civilisation (all too quick to praise the mistakes of their own offspring). Those various tasks illustrate a number of features of Fourier’s views on education, including the developmental importance of voluntary participation in cooking and opera. He saw children as nascent gourmands, drawn instinctively to the kitchen by smell and taste. Harmony would encourage participation in the culinary arts, thereby developing the child’s manual dexterity and control, introducing them to the world of work, and engendering a practical interest in the sciences of agronomy, biology, and chemistry. Similarly, opera would attract children through sight and sounds, and develop their physicality. (Harmonian opera is a superior art form unifying music, song, poetry, dance, gymnastics, design, and gesture.) Every Phalanx would have an opera house in which ordinary Harmonians combined to produce performances superior to those of the largest cities in Civilisation. One of the interesting formal features of Fourier’s writings is his use of narrative and quasi-narrative, episodes alongside more conventional theoretical passages. The following two examples – involving the shelling of peas and the cleaning of sewers – illustrate both the importance of work and the changing focus of education depending on the age of the child. Until the age of nine, education focuses on physical faculties and senses; after nine, it focuses on moral and emotional development. These episodes also convey Fourier’s love of ceremony, and his interest in the ways in which decorations and ranks might motivate a contribution to production. In Harmony, the shelling and grading of green peas will be done by children as young as two to four years old. We are asked to imagine a group of such

190

David Leopold

children sitting at a sloping table, with a number of slots in it, ranked from the oldest at the top to the youngest at the bottom. Those at the top would shell and handle the smallest of peas, those in the middle would collect the medium peas, and the youngest would simply gather up the remaining large peas in a basket and return the occasionally rogue medium pea up the table to the older children. A new volunteer for the series – a candidate member of the green pea shellers – would perform the latter role. Their task was the simplest, but they would, if successful, feel that they had contributed as much as anyone, and be rewarded with a decoration for their hat or collar. (A succession of such decorations would, in due course, mark their ascent through the work group.) In this way, social arrangements which encourage natural proclivities are used to initiate children into the world of work. Fourier identifies the five dominant tastes of children as: a desire to ‘ape’ or imitate; an eagerness to follow (slightly) older children; a fondness for small things; the enjoyment of rummaging about; and the love of making noise. The tableau of the little peas shows the first two of these instincts, in particular, being used to constructive ends within the Phalanx (Fourier, 1972, pp. 307–310). Notoriously, Fourier also offers a solution to the problem of certain (literally) ‘dirty jobs’ in Harmony (cleaning the sewers, tending the communal dungheap, and washing out slaughterhouses are all mentioned). He estimates that twothirds of boys, and one-third of girls, aged between nine and fifteen, enjoy getting dirty (and, more generally, being fearless and creating havoc). Whereas Civilisation sought to repress these proclivities, Harmony would encourage and utilise them. These children would choose to enrol in the work group known as ‘the Little Hordes’, who dauntlessly perform certain tasks that ordinary workers would find debasing. Marx would later charge Fourier with confusing work and play, mistakenly imagining that sewer cleaning could become a game played by children. Closer examination, however, shows that the Little Hordes are not simply having fun, but are rather motivated by a concern for the community at large, and for the honour of their own corporation. This is an age when selfless devotion is at its strongest, and corporate pride is here directed towards the common good. These moral motivations are accompanied, and reinforced, by a bewildering range of ceremonial ranks and titles, which are highly sought after by members who yield to no one in loyalty to their own intermediate association (Fourier, 1972, pp. 317–318). Two surprising absences in Fourier’s account of education (narrowly understood) might be noted. First, despite Fourier’s deserved reputation as holding extravagant and (to some) shocking views on love and sexuality, there is no place for sex education. Adolescence arrives late in Harmony, and up until the age of fifteen children have no interest in, or exposure to, sexual activity. Second, there does not appear to be much room for ‘book learning’ narrowly understood. This is surprising because elsewhere we are told that Harmony will have a huge number of brilliant scholars and great authors (all well-remunerated and appropriately honoured). It seems that any engagement in narrowly intellectual pursuits will have been largely self-motivated, and come later in life.

Education and utopia

191

Some concluding remarks It might be helpful to rehearse some of the more specifically educational threads in the work of these two utopian authors. Owen sees education, first, as properly aimed at creating character (moulding children into valuable members of the community) and developing the faculty of reason (teaching children to understand). Second, he stresses the importance and efficacy of early schooling, and acknowledges the correspondingly greater difficulty in (re)forming characters once they have been established. Third, his views about the delivery of education emphasise the importance of kindness on the part of teachers, and the use of ‘sensible signs’ in the classroom. Fourth, he maintains that the sexes should have equal opportunities to acquire useful knowledge, albeit that utility here might reflect a somewhat traditional sexual division of labour. Fifth, although his views about institutional arrangements and curriculum are broadly progressive, they look rather less radical than his developing ideas about the social context within which education takes place. Sixth, he sees education as having an extraordinary constructive potential; the rationally moulded inhabitants of the new moral world will effectively be a ‘new race’, far superior to the products of poor and erroneous instruction with which we are familiar. Fourier sees education, first, as properly aimed at liberating character, developing and deploying (not repressing and misdirecting) our God-given essential passions. Second, education for Fourier is always closely connected with the world of work, engaging in productive activity is the main way in which we discover and express who we are. Third, he endorses a striking institutional integration of education into the community; there are no schools and no teachers, only a variety of social spaces in which we might learn, and lots of different people who might teach us something. Fourth, he maintains that education should start early and initially focus on physical development and dexterity (only later turning to concentrate on moral and emotional development). Fifth, freedom is at the heart of Harmonian education; children seemingly profit from instruction only when, and insofar as, they have themselves solicited it. Sixth, his enthusiasm for social differences and competition between work groups does not stop him endorsing educational arrangements that are broadly egalitarian, in that all classes, and both sexes, would enjoy the same opportunities. Picking out these (narrow) educational threads in this way risks treating the work of Owen and Fourier in a fashion that they would have resisted. They both emphasised the systematic character of their theories, and portrayed the meaning and value of their educational views as dependent on the broader social and political transformation to which their writings were a contribution. And yet their practical impact on the world typically took what we might call a ‘cannibalised’ form. Particular policies were isolated from the systematic radical vision, modified, and then adopted in contexts very different to those intended by their authors. The appearance of certain Fourierist themes – including the focus on production, and the use of ceremony and decorations – in the pedagogic

192

David Leopold

experiments of Anton Makarenko (1888–1939) in the Soviet Union might serve as a particularly stark example. It might surprise some readers to learn that Owen and (perhaps especially) Fourier left any mark on the wider world (given the wilder shores of some of their work). In that context, I close with two observations. First, although their practical impact fell short of their own ambitions (namely, the radical transformation of the existing social and political world), their educational views did have some (albeit limited and often indirect) influence. In the nineteenth century, that influence was carried by two conduits, in particular: communitarian socialism, and the movement for popular education. Communitarian experiments flourished in the first half of the century, especially in the United States (one recent study identifies some 22 Owenite and 31 Fourierist examples) (Pitzer, 1997, pp. 481–482). Historians once dismissed these often short-lived settlements as failures (heroic or otherwise), but increasingly recognise not only that ‘success’ might be more complex than longevity but also that these communities had some influence upon the larger societies of which they formed a part. Education looks to be an important part of that complicated and still-emerging story. (Examples might include the involvement of ex-Owenites in the ‘state guardianship’ plan proposed in New York elections in 1829, and the Fourierist adoption of ‘industrial education’ in 1840s Wisconsin.) In addition, these utopian ideas formed one of the intellectual sources of the, somewhat better documented, movement for popular education, especially in Britain and France. (For example, the influence of Owen was felt by Samuel Wilderspin (1792–1866) of the Infant School Society, amongst others; whilst Jean Macé (1815–1894) and the founders of the école maternelle both owed some debt to the educational views of Fourier.) Second, and finally, it is important not to think of utopias as only having a ‘constructive’ function; as if their sole purpose, and the only possible benchmark by which they might be assessed, is their practical and reforming impact. Detailed descriptions of an ideal society, of the kind that Owen and Fourier provide, can have a number of additional functions. These utopian designs can, for instance, play a critical role, providing a vantage point from which to evaluate less than ideal societies. They can also reflect their historical context, telling us something about the world in which they were written. They can also help to clarify particular (conceptual and normative) issues, acting as thought experiments which help us understand something better. They can also console, acting as a diversion from the harsh realities of the existing world. And they can also, of course, cheer, entertain, and otherwise amuse their readers. I do not mean to suggest that all of these potential functions – the list is not intended to be exhaustive – will necessarily be of interest to educationalists (qua educationalists). However, the existence of these other functions does show that the constructive weakness (real or imagined) of these ideal commonwealths is not enough to make them worthless to that audience. The interest of utopian writings can sometimes lie elsewhere.

Education and utopia

193

References Beecher, J. (1986) Charles Fourier: the visionary and his world (Berkeley, University of California Press). Bestor, A. E. (1950) Backwoods utopias. The sectarian and Owenite phases of communitarian socialism in America 1663–1829 (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Fisher, R. T. (1963) Classical utopian theories of education (New Haven, College & University Press). Fourier, C. (1972) The utopian vision of Charles Fourier (eds J. Beecher & R. Bienvenu) (London, Jonathan Cape). Fourier, C. (2001a, 1st edn. 1822) Théorie de l’unité universelle, vol. 1 (Paris, Presses du réel). Fourier, C. (2001b, 1st edn. 1822) Théorie de l’unité universelle, vol. 2 (Paris, Presses du réel). Fourier, C. (1996, 1st edn. 1808) Theory of the four movements (eds G. Stedman Jones & I. Patterson) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Halpern, D. (2003) Hope and education. The role of the utopian imagination (London, Routledge). Harrison, J. F. C. (1968) Utopianism and education. Robert Owen and the Owenites (New York, Teachers College Press). Massó, G. (1927) Education in utopias (New Haven, College & University Press). Owen, R. (1969) Robert Owen on education (ed. H. Silver) (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Owen, R. (1991) A new view of society and other writings (ed. G. Claeys) (London, Penguin). Owen, R. (1993a, 1st edn. 1813–1844) vol. 1 of G. Claeys (ed.) The selected works of Robert Owen (London, Pickering & Chatto). Owen, R. (1993b, 1st edn. 1803–1822) The development of socialism, vol. 2 of G. Claeys (ed.) The selected works of Robert Owen (London, Pickering & Chatto). Owen, R. (1993c, 1st edn. 1825–1848) The heyday of Owenism, vol. 3 of G. Claeys (ed.) The selected works of Robert Owen (London, Pickering & Chatto). Owen, R. (1993d, 1st edn. 1857) The autobiography of Robert Owen, vol. 4 of G. Claeys (ed.) The selected works of Robert Owen (London, Pickering & Chatto). Ozmon, H. (1969) Utopias and education (Minneapolis, Burgess). Peters, M. A. & Freeman-Moir, J. (2006) Edutopias. New Utopian thinking in education (Rotterdam, Sense). Pitzer, D. E. (ed.) (1997) America’s communal utopias (Chapel Hill, University of North Carolina Press). Silver, H. (1966) The concept of popular education: a study of ideas and social movements in the early 19th century (London, Routledge). Zeldin, D. (1969) The educational ideas of Charles Fourier (London, Routledge).

13 Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education Ruth Watts

Introduction Harriet Martineau is a very apposite figure to choose for a collection which examines the interrelationships of education, political and personal life, and power. Throughout her life (1802–1877)1 she concerned herself with a wide variety of political, economic, social, and cultural issues but both her voluminous writings and her actions were underpinned by a fervent desire to educate the public, unfailingly optimistic that if everyone was correctly educated necessary social change would take place. Eager to publish the knowledge she gained through extensive reading, travel, and active engagement in many intellectual and social debates, her constant questioning of cherished assumptions and desire for scientific answers, even in religion, made her both a celebrated and a controversial figure. Her concerns and approach, especially her belief in certain educational principles, owed much to her Unitarian upbringing.

The Unitarian ‘tradition’ in education Modern Unitarianism emerged from eighteenth-century ‘Rational Dissent’. Denying both the Trinity and original sin, Rational Dissenters fervently upheld the right of all individuals to free enquiry in religion, the application of reason to all things and a search for moral order and perfection. Naturally comprising a range of thinking, by the 1790s Unitarianism was becoming their most dominant form. Chiefly attractive to men and women of the middle and artisan ranks in urban, commercial, and industrial areas, some of their chapels became citadels of ‘enlightened’ liberal thought, although Unitarians were never large in number. Generally, they held an optimistic belief in the goodness and potential possibilities of humanity while their hope of unravelling the laws of nature by reason, experience, and experiment led them to an eager search for scientific explanation and methods in all matters including education (Watts, 2010, pp. 13–14). Rational Dissent and then Unitarianism emerged, indeed, largely from the dissenting academies – those institutions established to educate Dissenting Protestant males denied Oxbridge degrees because they would not subscribe to the 39 Articles of the Church of England. The most radical – Warrington

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 195 (1757–1786), followed by Hackney (1786–1793) and Manchester (1786– 1803)2 – not only educated both future ministers and male laity in the modern curriculum emerging from Dissenting education, but also in a fervent love of liberty and civil reform (Watts, 1991). A particularly dynamic tutor at Warrington from 1761 to 1767 was Joseph Priestley (1733–1804), fast becoming a renowned scientist, an explosive, radical political and religious activist, and an innovative educationalist. Priestley’s educational philosophy was deeply influenced by the full associationist psychology of David Hartley (1705–1757). He reissued Hartley’s Observations on man (1749) in a condensed edition. This omitted Hartley’s hypothesis that body and soul were bound together, although Priestley’s acceptance that all capacities were reducible to external impressions led him to believe that everything was part of a chain of cause and effect traceable to a first cause or God, a philosophy termed necessarianism. Not all Unitarians accepted necessarianism, but Hartley’s philosophy much influenced both them and other progressive educationalists (Priestley, 1782a, pp. 221–249; 1782b, pp. 454–535; Watts, 1995, pp. 344–345). It taught that environment and circumstance rather than innate character or divine intervention formed children, and promised that with the right, carefully interrelated intellectual, physical, and moral education from birth, people would find the way to unbounded knowledge, happiness, love of God, and perfect virtue. Thus everyone needed such, both for their own moral development and to educate others. The crucial significance of associationist psychology meant that neither women nor anyone else could be assumed to be inferior in mental capacity, although Dissenters’ fear of state control of education limited demands for national education before the nineteenth century (Priestley, 1771, pp. 40–54; 1780, pp. 137–138; 1790). Freedom of inquiry, thinking for oneself, learning from experiment and experience – all underpinned by Hartleian psychology – were at the heart of the education for liberal, humane, active, ‘enlightened’ citizens which Priestley promoted. So were modern subjects – Priestley pioneered modern history, taught from the sources themselves, and promoted science as a liberalising, humanising part of education, stimulating improvements in everything. In all subjects, including English, he offered innovative, active, experiential scientific methods of learning and teaching. Such an education was to help both males and females to understand better the times and society in which they lived, the importance of freedom of speech, the advantages of democracy, the miseries caused by superstition and slavery, and the improvements accruing from science and trade (Priestley, 1761 & 1798; 1762; 1767, pp. 341–345; 1780; 1803). Other Rational Dissenters contributed to the main ethos in different ways. Richard Price (1723–1791), especially, depicted a benevolent God who gave all human beings the chance to achieve true wisdom and reform of society through use of their reason (Fitzpatrick, 1985, pp. 87–88). Despite bitter hostility from most orthodox Christians, including other Dissenters, to their religious views, such educational ideas were developed in practice and in print. Importantly, this helped generally to educate women far above the norm. Priestley was not alone

196

Ruth Watts

in believing that any culture or country could be judged truly civilised quite simply by ‘the treatment of women among them’ (Priestley, 1803, p. 346). Certainly, female Unitarians were part of an enterprising, energetic community, at its best brimming with intellectual vitality. This did not change their expected roles in life or employment opportunities much, but some took advantage of their better education (Watts, 2010). One such woman was Priestley’s younger friend Anna Barbauld (1743–1825). Firstly renowned as a poet, she subsequently became a celebrated essayist and educationalist. She and her brother, Dr John Aikin, wrote educational books for children which interwove the principles of association with poetry, literature, science, technology, and their lifelong engagement with liberal and humane ideals. Stimulating observation and experiment, they stressed humanity’s dependence on the useful and practical arts of life. Their joint venture Evenings at home encouraged whole families to enjoy learning together (Aikin & Barbauld, 1793). This much-published work influenced generations of children in Britain and America including the young Harriet Martineau (Martineau, 1983b, I, pp. 302–303). Equally influential was Barbauld’s pioneering of reputable and suitable writing for infants, particularly through her very innovative Lessons for children (Barbauld, 1844). At the same time, Barbauld, whose own home was always a cultural and educative centre, became famous or infamous for treatises on religious freedom and civil liberties which gave her a political platform in the vanguard of Rational Dissent (Watts, 2010, pp. 16, 17, 19, 21–24, 26). Unitarian educational philosophy, indeed, was closely bound to what they perceived as the interests and civil rights of the rising industrial and commercial middle class – the ‘true sources of wealth, power and happiness in a nation’ (Priestley, 1780, pp. 185–187, 193–196) – to which most of them belonged. Priestley, for example, warned that the ‘gunpowder’ that Dissenters were ‘assiduously laying grain by grain under the old building of error and superstition’ was not of chemicals but ‘of arguments’ which could only be met by proper debate. He likened the universities to ‘pools of stagnant water, secured by dams and mounds, and offensive to the neighbourhood’, unlike Dissenting academies which, giving a ‘truly liberal education’, ‘like rivers ... taking their natural course, fertilize a whole country (Priestley, 1787, p. 128). Thus civic and religious ideas and education were tightly bound. Priestley, Richard Price (1723–1791), and other Rational Dissenters fought against the Test and Corporation Acts, argued for constitutional reform, and vociferously supported the American and French Revolutions (Watts, 1991, 1998). Their educational ideas also inspired arguments for women’s rights. Both Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–1797) and Mary Hays (1759–1843), in particular, built upon Price’s philosophy to argue that women must have liberty, civil, and political rights and knowledge in order to exercise their conscience and acquire virtue (Wollstonecraft, 1975; Watts, 2010, pp. 15–16, 26–27). But Price’s famous sermon ‘A discourse on the love of our country’ delivered to the Society for Commemorating the Revolution in Great Britain in November 1789,3 glorying in the French Revolution, provoked Edmund Burke’s Reflections on the revolution in France. The subsequent

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 197 reaction against both apparent political extremism and the growth of Unitarianism resulted in Rational Dissenters suffering persecution, loss of property, imprisonment, or exile. The demise of Hackney Academy, for instance, seen as the epitome of religious, political, and educational unorthodoxy, was likened to the fall of Babylon by the Gentleman’s Magazine (Watts, 1991). Nevertheless, Unitarian educational ethos and philosophy continued into the nineteenth century, despite Unitarianism itself undergoing changes, though mostly without changing Unitarians’ commitment to moral evolution within an open-ended religion (Watts, 1998, pp. 101–103; 2000, p. 40). Their educational activities were unceasing, mostly desiring education on Hartleian principles including experiment and questioning, healthy physical education, no corporal punishment and, if possible, the same education for females as males (see, for example, Beard, 1859). This led them to play a part out of proportion to their numbers in progressive schooling, university reform, mechanics institutes, working-class education, all levels of education for girls, as well as in political and social reform, local government, urban culture, science, and publication. They were influenced by others such as Johann Pestalozzi (1746–1827) and Friedrich Froebel (1782–1852) and worked with others such as the Utilitarians with whose ideas on political economy many Unitarians agreed. This was to the detriment of their reputation with the working-class, who perceived they were teaching the economic selfishness of one class as scientific law (Watts, 1998). At the same time their commitment to liberal reforms led some of them like William Johnson Fox (1786–1864) into more radical politics (Gleadle, 1995). One Unitarian educationalist particularly influential on Harriet Martineau was Lant Carpenter (1780–1840), a leading exponent of Priestley’s ideas as evidenced in his Principles of education (1820) especially. His own school in Bristol, which Martineau knew well, exemplified the best in Unitarian education with a curriculum including classics, mathematics, physical sciences, natural history, geography, English literature, French and Italian, ethics, and mental philosophy, especially the work of Hartley. Carpenter involved his pupils in science and the social and political issues of his day which interested him so deeply. From his and other Unitarian schools, and homes, came a disproportionate number of public figures and reformers, industrialists, scientists, professional and business men, and those at the forefront of educational reform and the fight for national education. This included women, not least those striving for better education and rights for women. Carpenter’s daughter Mary (1807–1877), indeed, became a better-known educationalist than he was (Watts, 1998, pp. 42, 134–135, passim; 2000).

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education Born in 1802, Martineau was the sixth of eight children in a liberal Unitarian family in Norwich. Apart from two happy years from the age of eleven in a mixed school4 and another 15 months, 1818–1819, at school in Bristol, she was

198

Ruth Watts

educated at home to the best of her parents’ means, although in her late teens she added to her prodigious learning as inconspicuously as possible since, even in her highly articulate household, this ‘was not thought proper for young ladies ... especially with pen in hand’ (Martineau, 1983b, I, p. 100). Deeply influenced by the educational and philosophical ideas of Priestley and Carpenter, she retained a deep admiration of Priestley, although later she thought Carpenter ‘narrow in his conceptions’. Becoming ‘a sort of walking Concordance of Milton and Shakespere [sic]’, she also became ‘a political economist without knowing it’ through reading the Globe (1969, I, pp. 175–198; 1983b, I, pp. 70–72, passim). She remained an omnivorous reader, learning also from much travel, including lengthy visits to the USA, Egypt, and the Near East (1983b, I & II). Unitarianism powerfully influenced Martineau. She enjoyed its questioning approach and rational morality (1983b, I, pp. 35–41). From Dr Carpenter she learnt to love Priestley’s edition of Hartley, a ‘philosophically ... elevating’ book which, despite some faults, became ‘perhaps the most important book in the world to me, except the Bible’, stimulating ‘self-discipline, and devotion to duty’ and emphasising ‘fact and ... action’ rather than the ‘dreaming’ ‘spiritual philosophy’ beginning to influence some American and English Unitarians (1983b, I, pp. 104–105). She studied other philosophers but found lifelong happiness and peace of mind in accepting the doctrine of Necessity with its certainty that ‘every department of the universe’ was governed by ‘eternal and irreversible laws’ which could not be broken. From this and her surety that a good environment, ‘good influences and good habits’, rather than constant spiritual anxiety, engendered moral advancement, she drew her vigour, courage and a ‘steady growth’ in ‘integrity and disinterestedness’ (1983b, I, pp. 108–116), even though, by the 1850s, she was less certain that everything was accounted for by people’s capacity for pain and pleasure and the principle of association (Roberts, 2002, pp. 174–176). Believing in the interrelationship of mind and body, however, helped her later appreciate the physiognomical system of Gall and Spurzheim, albeit she and Henry Atkinson critiqued George Combe’s popular version of phrenology, advancing a more egalitarian interpretation affected by environmentalism (Martineau, 1870, pp. 265–271; Roberts, 2002, pp. 107–186, 193–196). The powerful effect of her own education was reflected in Martineau’s thoughtful assessment of the aims and processes of education in Household education (1849). Seeing that education was responsible for most of the differences between people, yet many cultures excluded from education large numbers – ‘women, the poor, the infirm’ – without knowing exactly what each individual was capable of, she argued that the only ‘absolutely safe and wise’ course was ‘to bring out and strengthen and exercise all the powers given to every human being’ (Martineau, 1849, pp. 11–20). Although good schools were best for thorough ‘book-learning’, she stressed that, as things were, home was the place where the majority of people received their real education, preferably as a family cooperating together in lifelong and useful learning. Her over-riding aim always moral, she carefully and engagingly delineated how parents could help their children and themselves grow intellectually, physically, and morally in

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 199 a loving, sympathetic atmosphere where each had space and assistance to follow their own path and learn naturally by being given and taught the materials and skills appropriate for their age and ability (1849, passim).5 Having learned to think for herself and then educate others, provided she had evidence for her arguments, Martineau often turned her own experiences – not only her travels but also her serious illness and seeming cure through mesmerism in the 1840s and her growing loss of faith – into educative treatises. Despite this later rejection of Unitarianism, her writings testify to her lifelong commitment to freedom of individual, reasoned inquiry and questioning, and her optimism about human progress, especially if all people were educated aright. Her earliest publications demonstrated that she had imbibed well Unitarian teachings on contextual biblical criticism, the crucial significance of circumstances on individual development, and the way to strip contemporary assumptions of absurdities and accretions (Martineau, 1831, 1832a, 1983b, I, pp. 150–159). In the 1820s and 1830s she wrote many articles for The Monthly Repository, a Unitarian journal. Here, for example, she argued for women to have equal education (MR, 1823, XVIII, 77–101) and made clear her indebtedness to Hartley, by teaching those who had never studied, nor were likely to study, the works of great thinkers how to learn habits of accurate thought, a development she thought could end half the evils which affect humanity. She traced the process of forming habits of accurate thought and observation through understanding how to classify, arrange, and relate facts and perceive the multiple causes of ideas and then to develop ideas further, ultimately deducing and applying general principles from observed facts. Such an ‘enlightened intellect’, she said, could invigorate the moral sense, although learning itself was ‘not wisdom’ (MR, 1829, 29, pp. 521–526, 599–606, 707–712, 745–757, 817–821). Martineau learnt much herself through working with the editor of the Monthly Repository, the radical Unitarian minister William Johnson Fox – ‘unquestionably ... in great measure the cause, of the greatest intellectual progress I ever made before the age of thirty’ (Martineau, 1983b, 1, pp. 140, 147). From 1829, her family having lost their money, Martineau was able to become an independent, professional writer, her comments always clear, pointed and peppered with telling anecdotes. Her first series of books, Illustrations of political economy, 25 novelettes published monthly between 1832 and 1834, was born of her determined conviction that she must reveal the ‘truths’ (as she then saw them) of political economy to all readers, since few understood much about them yet nothing touched everyone more than ‘the way in which the necessaries and comforts of life may be best procured and enjoyed by all’. Seeing it as a moral ‘science’, she deliberately developed Jane Marcet’s example of using fictional methods to make political economy accessible, in her case demonstrating its principles as they naturally worked in social life, working up from domestic economy and summarising, at the end of each story, the economic principles illustrated (Martineau, 1832b, pp. iii–xiii; 1983b, I, pp. 138–139; II, pp. 244–245).6 Her enormous success, at home and abroad, brought her immediate fame with politicians, civil servants, and society people queuing up to seek

200

Ruth Watts

her advice and support on political, economic and social matters (Martineau, 1983b, I, pp. 178–268; Logan, 2004, I, p. xxv), thus truly emulating Priestley’s vision of liberal education as part of active, civil life. Financially secure, she moved to London. Martineau was praised for her depictions of poverty and working-class life, although her decided views against such things as strike action and fencing machinery, plus her support of the New Poor Law, militated against winning working-class favour. She aimed to teach people how to live together in cooperative communities where all could attain a fair living and an education which could develop their whole being. For instance, in Briery Creek, she portrayed a settlement in America where the humane Dr Sneyd (modelled on Priestley) and his family provided facilities which could be used for employment, education, and leisure at different times, in particular using the schoolhouse as a museum, library, and place for both women and men of the community to share warmth and light in the evening and enjoy various activities including music and dancing, thus dispelling vice, loneliness, and misery with properly organised ‘social mirth’ (Martineau, 1834a). Similarly, in The scholars of Arneside in the ensuing Tales of taxation, Martineau demonstrated the iniquities of indirect taxation, especially the Stamp Act, by showing how the illiterate people of Arneside were deprived of useful, liberal, rational knowledge, a situation which prevented the illiterate and rich alike from progressing in moral and intellectual development and led them to make bad, even evil choices in life. Martineau particularly fulminated against the privileged who wanted to keep knowledge to themselves: God ‘did not make his beautiful world that one might walk abroad on it, while a thousand are shut into a dark dungeon ... Does the sun shine more brightly when a man thinks he has it all to himself?’ She thought that Mechanics Institutes, with all their deficiencies, did more for most people than the Universities of Oxford and Cambridge (Martineau, 1834b, pp. 110–113, 129, passim). A well governed, happy state needed everyone to have access to knowledge provided it was the ‘right’ type of knowledge. Reviews varied: some lauded her for making ‘abstruse’ political economy a popular ‘entertaining and instructive’ subject – albeit expressing dismay at her restricting charity ‘to the enlightenment of the mind’ (Empson, 1833, pp. 1–9; Quarterly Journal, 1833, pp. 142, 150–153), but others thought she trivialised a serious study, or, although administering ‘rank poison’ [sic] agreeably, was heretical and unfeminine (Christian Rembrancer, 1841, pp. 178–184). Daring to articulate her own views on ‘masculine’ topics, her Malthusian over-population themes particularly scandalised some, especially the Quarterly Review, but Martineau was undaunted by their ribaldry (1983b, I, pp. 199–211). Martineau’s story Demerara, which cleverly opposed slavery as economically wasteful and unproductive, corrupting both slaves and their owners alike, also upset some middle-class readers (Martineau, 1833). In her long American tour she risked attack for her abolitionist views and her subsequent books judged the USA by how far social reality matched the Declaration of Independence and

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 201 found it wanting with regard both to slavery and to the treatment of women (Martineau, 1837, 1969). Her later historical novel on Toussaint L’Ouverture, the slave who expelled colonial rule from Haiti, portrayed a black man as hero, able to become an enlightened ruler because he had the fortune to be allowed to read, learning from classical works to admire the liberty he had never encountered and from others how to conduct troops and battles (Martineau, 1841, pp. 68, 90, 120–121, 123). The plot might be didactic and overdrawn, although Martineau backed it with much evidence (1841, III, pp. 247–304), but her point was that black people, even slaves, could overcome their brutal upbringing and show themselves naturally as intelligent, virtuous, humane, and loving as Europeans could be, if given the right education and opportunities. Equally, Europeans could be corrupted by living in an unjust, brutal society as a slave state necessarily was. Martineau was not alone, of course, in either her anti-slavery or in her assumptions of ‘superior’ western culture, although her writings on empire demonstrated understanding of different cultures and the double standards of the colonials and she pioneered how to observe and study a society (Martineau, 1837; Hoecker-Drysdale, 1992, pp. 50–52; Logan, 2004; Goodlad, 2010, pp. 197–213). Catherine Hall has linked her History of the peace, where she insisted on including literary, biographical, industrial, scientific, and educational developments, to this (Martineau, 1864; Logan, 2005, I, pp. xv–xxv), saying ‘she was the nation’s governess and she would teach her readers their history, the history of the present ... Her readers should learn from her not only the distinctively modern character of their own nation, patterned by class, gender and ethnicity, but also of the weighty responsibilities this leading nation carried for less “civilized sites across its Empire” ’ (Hall, 2010, p. 238). Martineau was equally sure of the social progress for all to be derived from technological invention and scientific discoveries and enthusiastically promoted a wide conception of science. Her novel Deerbrook depicted the struggles the growing number of professional medical practitioners faced from an ill-informed populace and the need for scientific knowledge and public hygiene to prevent epidemics. She became, indeed, Florence Nightingale’s chosen populariser of sanitary reform and nursing. Promoting drainage in Tynemouth and good housing for workers in Ambleside, she educated by personal practice, but she also advanced these and other reforms through her regular contributions to leading journals and as a leaders writer for the Daily News for fourteen years7 (Martineau, 1983a, 1983b, I, pp. 356–358, 371; II, pp. 306–308; Sanders, 1990, pp. 166–167, 182–183; Logan, 2005, VI, pp. vii–xv, 125, 161–202, 241–242, 258–305, 418; II, pp. 180–181, 451–454, 693–694). After her move to Ambleside, despite initial local distrust of her religious views, she began what became annual lectures on sanitary matters, intemperance, history, and other subjects to the local workmen and their families, a task which afforded her ‘more vivid and unmixed pleasure than any, except authorship, that I ever undertook’ (Martineau, 1983b, II, pp. 301–310). She educated her own servants, regularly spending time with them and giving them a library in the kitchen (Logan, 2004, I, p. xix).

202

Ruth Watts

A tireless supporter of education for all, Martineau consistently argued for national education, fulminating alike against early nineteenth-century governments who preferred an ‘ignorant, dependent, and wretched’ to an ‘enlightened’ populace and the ‘miserable pretence of learning’ monitorial schools and others offered. She despaired of the rivalry between Dissenters and the Church which prevented the growth of a proper fully-fledged system of national education for everyone, welcomed Robert Lowe’s Revised Code of 1861 which tied grants to examination results, and desired manual training, education in physiology for health, and education for democracy. Admiring Cobbett, whose books enabled labourers to read and debate parliamentary reform, she berated the Society for the Diffusion of Useful Knowledge for failing to do the same, albeit acknowledging its help in providing affordable and suitable books (Logan, 2005, I, pp. 358–359, II, pp. 58, 89–92, 252–254, III, pp. 171–173, 183, 193, 284–285, 386–387, IV, pp. 58–62, V, pp. 61, 100–102, 127–178). In her mind these should include matter which would convince working people of the rightness of political economy beliefs, particularly the need for ‘free’ labour. Martineau’s long-held stridency against trade unionism as tyrannically preventing individuals negotiating their own terms of employment (for example, see Logan, 2005, I passim), was shown again in 1859 when the activities of new trade unionism and demands for extension of the franchise to include sections of the working class combined. Martineau favoured the extension of the suffrage, but not for those she believed were self-interested men who, seducing the more ignorant workers by false economic arguments, forced the most ‘intelligent’ and ‘independent’ working men whom she was certain opposed strikes, into union action. Amassing masses of evidence, including from her relatives in Birmingham, she published ‘Secret organisation of Trade Unions’ in the Edinburgh Review of October 1859 in which, in exposing the extent of trade unionism and their powers over individual members, she hoped to set ‘free’ the most intelligent workers whom she wanted enfranchised. Her article did gain her a brief authoritative standing on labour matters of the kind she had enjoyed in the 1830s, with politicians and many contributors to the question using her arguments and evidence as their point of reference. The reaction of others, however, especially the unionist Thomas Dunning and the National Association for the Promotion of Social Science (NAPSS), an organisation she approved of, undermined her arguments and indeed helped persuade many, including Gladstone, to realise that the trade unionists were sufficiently intelligent, moderate, respectable, and independent thinking to be worthy of the franchise. Martineau was thus very rapidly displaced as an authority on the labour question (Curthoys, 2010, 140–150; MSS 3/i HM on strikes 1859 HM 1321–1337). Martineau did want all the population to have access to educative resources which would open their minds, however. She welcomed John Pyke Hullah’s (1812–1884) stimulus to good music as a popular pursuit; she argued that foreign immigration improved popular taste; she celebrated the ‘virtual education’ of museums, art galleries and exhibitions in large towns, greater humanity in education, and Mechanics Institutes. Martineau also advocated

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 203 professional training for both elementary school-teachers and governesses – the latter particularly being in need of ‘honour and independence’ (Sanders, 1990, pp. 75–76, 80, 148, 200, 227, 243, 255, 259; Logan, 2005, I, pp. 316–318). It had to be worthwhile education, however, which is why Martineau (like many Unitarians) praised the ideas on natural and timely development of children’s faculties stimulated by Pestalozzi, provided his system was not abused; and accordingly she disliked corporal punishment and rote learning. She believed ardently that education had to be interesting and enjoyable, demanding, after her visit to the Hanwell Lunatic Asylum in 1834, proper public institutions for all lunatics so that they could enjoy liberty, fresh air, sunshine, and amusement (1834b; Logan, 2005, III, pp. 191–192). Martineau particularly wanted women of all classes to receive the best education conceived, castigating the ‘nonsense’ talked about restricting female education. She ridiculed the fact that females were forbidden classical languages because they would not enter those professions which required them, while it was chiefly reasoned that boys needed these subjects ‘to improve the quality of their minds’. Similarly, she cited good evidence to prove that females were capable of abstract thought. Always glad her early education saved her ‘from being a literary lady who could not sew’ (Martineau, 1983b, 1, p. 27), she argued convincingly that men did not attend the less [to their daily work] for having their minds enlarged and enriched and their faculties strengthened by sound and various knowledge; ... the most ignorant women I have known have been the worst housekeepers; ... the most learned women ... have been among the best (provided they had) been early taught and trained to household business (as?) every woman ought to be. (Martineau, 1849, pp. 221–222) Her example for this was Mary Somerville (1780–1872) whom she knew and admired for her scientific prowess, her ‘womanly’ bearing and the ‘order and beauty’ of her home (Martineau, 1983b, I, pp. 356–358, 1849, pp. 223–224).8 The argument that well-educated women were the best housekeepers, wives, mothers, and teachers of the young, was significant. Although Martineau recognised the father’s responsibilities in family education, she put mothers at the centre of domestic economy – the basis of political economy (Martineau, 1849). Aware that many women had now to support themselves, she welcomed developments that enabled them to leave ‘overstocked’ female industries and gain access to wider, more skilled employment (Martineau, 1849, pp. 224–226, 283–287). Always deeply conscious of the importance of hygiene and of education in it, she enthusiastically promoted Nightingale’s nursing reforms and the scientific, practical, and moral education and training girls and women needed to become professional nurses rather than ‘floating saints and virgins’ or ‘grovelling mercenaries’. Equally she campaigned for women doctors and their education (Logan, 2005, VI, pp. 161–202, 241–242, 258–291, 301–305 ff.; III, pp. 162–163; V, pp. 105–106).

204

Ruth Watts

Supporting the early campaign for higher education for women, Martineau ironically dismissed those who thought the whole purpose of such was merely to fit women to be ‘companions to men’ and ‘mothers of heroes’. She had little room for ‘female pedants’, preferring scholars who were useful to society such as the Unitarian educational philanthropist Lady Byron (Martineau, 1870, pp. 316–325, 386–392; Yates, 1985, pp. 74–78, 101–102). Above all women, she praised Anna Barbauld, whom she knew as a child, for her ‘exquisite writings’, moral character, and ‘womanly grace’ – a prime illustration of how a well-educated, intellectual, rational woman could still be a virtuous and moral role model, unlike the Mary Wollstonecrafts of this world (Yates, 1985, p. 103).9 A lifelong feminist, Martineau’s support of women’s rights permeated her writings and actions. She signed the women’s petition for the vote in 1866, championed ground-breaking Acts of Parliament which slowly gave more rights to women, and was an ardent campaigner against the Contagious Diseases Acts of the 1860s. She welcomed the Women’s Movement of the 1850s and ’60s and their use of the National Association for the Promotion of Social Science to promote their struggles for reform of women’s education, legal rights, and other causes. This was the type of educative association that she liked, diffusing greater knowledge about social issues and thus stimulating important legislation (Yates, 1985, pp. 51–83, 216–224, 239–267, passim; Hoecker-Drysdale, 1992, pp. 135–137).

Conclusion Harriet Martineau became an influential, well-known woman, speaking to generations on political, economic, social and educational questions of the day. A lifelong public educator who published over seventy volumes, dozens of articles and nearly 2,000 newspaper leaders and letters (Hoecker-Drysdale, 1992, p. 2), she was committed to social change and to representative democracy and both campaigned for such and sought to educate potential new participants as liberal, humane, and active citizens so that they could create a better world. She clarified what she saw as muddled thinking and saw herself as a national educator, taking significant ideas of the day to as many people as possible, often forging new methods to do this. She was not afraid to challenge assumptions such as women being fulfilled in patriarchal systems (Roberts, 2002, pp. 96–104, passim). She tried to educate people in new ideas which had caught her interest; for example, she was a significant figure in social science and the translator and purveyor of Comte’s ideas to Britain and then back to France (Daily News, 1875). Martineau was controversial but also successful and influential in her time, a role model for younger women. On political economy, the abolition of slavery, and women’s rights, for instance, her support was constantly requested. Her subsequent neglect by historians has much to do with the not uncommon difficulty before the late twentieth century of women being properly recognised for their achievements. This has been complicated by factors such as her involvement in and writing on so many issues. She also became unfashionable in the

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 205 twentieth century for her economic liberalism. She was a pioneer on many issues such as women’s rights, but her fame has been eclipsed by the struggles and achievements of the generations who followed her. In the very issues she became interested in, the way she sought to publish on them and educate others, Martineau indicated her Unitarian heritage as she did in thinking for herself, speaking freely, and, above all, upholding an environmentalist form of education as underpinning all reform and progress. This has been recognised both now (e.g. James, 2010) and in the nineteenth century. For example, her old enemy the Quarterly Review traced her ‘uniformly condemned’ philosophy to Hartley and Priestley (Heywood, 1877, pp. 484–503). Often helped by her Unitarian networks, she was an active educationalist who surmounted both gender and religious animosity to fulfil that which she termed her duty. Studying her writings and role as public educator gives us greater understanding of the struggles for education in the nineteenth century and the part women could play in them.

Notes 1 Principal biographies are by R. K. Webb and Deborah Logan; Ella Dzelzainis and Cora Kaplan’s edited book on Harriet Martineau has much useful recent analysis of her life. 2 It reopened in York 1803–1840, moved back to Manchester until 1853 when it moved to London affiliated to University College, finally moving to Oxford in 1889. It is now Harris Manchester College, Oxford. 3 The Revolution commemorated by this Society is the ‘Glorious Revolution’ of 1688. 4 The school of Rev Isaac Perry who lost his pulpit and most of his boys’ school when he changed from orthodox dissent to Unitarianism. Martineau thoroughly enjoyed the rigorous teaching of Latin and French, writing composition, and doing arithmetic. 5 Martineau was writing this at a time when there was no national system of education and the government involvement which did exist, although increasing, was only in elementary education for the working classes. Martineau wished the latter to increase until education was provided for all children but this was long before it was considered that middle-class education would be part of a national system. 6 Jane Marcet’s Conversations on political economy of 1816 became an immensely popular and successful book as did other of her works on political economy and science. 7 The Daily News was established in 1846 as a Liberal counterpoise to The Times. It became successful from the 1850s (Webb, 1960, pp. 314–315 and ff., to 358). 8 Mary Somerville gained European fame for her insightful and wider ranging scientific works from 1831. She also became part of the Unitarian networks in which Martineau still moved. 9 After Wollstonecraft’s death, shortly after the birth of her daughter Mary, her husband William Godwin published a memoir of his wife (Godwin, 1798) in which he told the story of her life including her sexual relationships. In the atmosphere of conservative political reaction against the French Revolution in the early 19th century, which was accompanied by more general social conservatism, Wollstonecraft’s name was maligned and she became a by-word for immorality.

References Aikin, J. & Barbauld, A. L. (1995) Evenings at home (London, Joseph Johnson). Barbauld, A. (c. 1844, 1st edn. 1778–1779) Lessons for children (London, William Darton & Sons).

206

Ruth Watts

Beard, J. R. (No date but 3rd edn., 1st edn. 1859) Self-culture (Manchester & London, Abel Heywood & Son). Carpenter, L. (1820) Principles of education (London, Longman, Hurst, Rees, Orme & Brown). Curthoys, M. (2010) ‘Secret organisation of trades’: Harriet Martineau and ‘free labour’, in: E. Dzelzainis & C. Kaplan (eds) Harriet Martineau: authorship, society and empire (Manchester, Manchester University Press), 138–150. Daily News (1875) Cutting in Cadbury Research Library, University of Birmingham (see microfiche 11 of Harriet Martineau papers). Dalley, L. L. (2010) Domesticating political economy: language, gender and economics in the Illustrations of Political Economy, in: E. Dzelzainis & C. Kaplan (eds) Harriet Martineau: authorship, society and empire (Manchester, Manchester University Press), 104–117. Fitzpatrick, M. (1985) Radical dissent and the enlightenment, Faith and Freedom, 38, 2(13), 83–101. Gleadle, K. (1995) The early feminists: radical Unitarians and the emergence of the women’s rights movement, 1831–51 (Basingstoke, Macmillan). Godwin, W. (1987) [1798] Memoirs of the author of ‘The Rights of Woman’ (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Goodlad, L. M. E. (2010) Imperial woman: Harriet Martineau, geopolitics and the romance of improvement, in: E. Dzelzainis & C. Kaplan (eds) Harriet Martineau: authorship, society and empire (Manchester, Manchester University Press), 197–213. Hall, C. (2010) Writing a history, writing a nation: Harriet Martineau’s History of the peace, in: E. Dzelzainis & C. Kaplan (eds) Harriet Martineau: authorship, society and empire (Manchester, Manchester University Press), 231–253. Hoecker-Drysdale, S. (1992) Harriet Martineau: first woman sociologist (Oxford/ New York, Berg). James, F. (2010) ‘Socinian and political-economy formulas’: Martineau the Unitarian, in: E. Dzelzainis & C. Kaplan (eds) Harriet Martineau: authorship, society and empire (Manchester, Manchester University Press), 74–87. Logan, D. A. (2002) The hour and the woman: Harriet Martineau’s ‘somewhat remarkable’ life (DeKalb, IL, Northern Illinois Press). Logan, D. A. (ed.) (2004) Harriet Martineau’s writing on the British Empire (London, Pickering & Chatto). Logan, D. A. (ed.) (2005) Harriet Martineau’s writing on British history and military reform vols I &VI (London, Pickering & Chatto). Martineau, H. (1831) The essential faith of the Universal Church deduced from the sacred records (London, Printed for the Unitarian Association). Martineau, H. (1832a, 1st edn. 1823) Devotional exercises and A guide to the study of scriptures. Martineau, H. (1832–4) Illustrations of political economy (London, Charles Fox). No. 1 Life in the wilds (1832b). Available online at: http://books.google. co.uk/books? id=QRI1AAAAMAAJ. No. 4 Demerara (1833) In D. Logan (ed.) (2004) Harriet Martineau’s writing on the British Empire (London, Pickering & Chatto), I. Available online at: http://books. google.co.uk/books?id=QRI1AAAAMAAJ. No. 22 Briery Creek (1834a). Available online at: http://books.google.co. uk/books? id=AUPQAAAAMAAJ.

Harriet Martineau and the Unitarian tradition in education 207 Martineau, H. (1834b) The scholars of Arneside. Illustrations of taxation no. 5 (London, Charles Fox). Martineau, H. (1834c, June) The Hanwell Lunatic Asylum, Tait’s Edinburgh Magazine. Available online at: http://www.mdx.ac.uk/www/study/xmad1834.htm. Martineau, H. (1837) Society in America 3 vols (London, Saunders & Otley). Martineau, H. (1841) The hour and the man: a historical romance (London, Edward Moxon). Martineau, H. (1849) Household education (London, Edward Moxon). Available online at: http:// essays.quotidiana.org/Martineau/household_education/. Martineau, H. (1859) Cadbury Research Library, University of Birmingham, Harriet Martineau papers, MSS 3/i HM on strikes 1859 HM 1319–1417. Martineau, H. (1864, 1st edn. 1849) History of the peace: being a history of England from 1816–1854 with an introduction from 1800–1815, in: D. A. Logan (ed.) (2005) Harriet Martineau’s writing on British history and military reform. Martineau, H. (1870, 1st edn. 1868) Biographical sketches 1852–1868 (London, Macmillan). Martineau, H. (1969, 1st edn. 1838) Retrospect of western travel 3 vols (New York, Greenwood Press). Martineau, H. (1983a, 1st edn. 1839) Deerbrook (London, Virago). Martineau, H. (1983b, with an introduction by Gaby Weiner; 1st edn. 1877) Autobiography 3 vols (London, Virago from the 3rd edn. 1877 London, Smith, Elder & Co with Memorials by Maria Weston Chapman). Priestley, J. (1817–1831) (ed. J. T. Rutt) The theological and miscellaneous works of Joseph Priestley 25 vols, printed by private subscription): (1761 & 1798). The rudiments of English grammar, XXIII. (1762) A course of lectures on the theory of language and universal grammar, XXIII. (1767) The history and present state of electricity, with original experiments, XXV. (1771) An essay on the first principles of government, XXII. (1780) An essay on a course of liberal education for civil and active life; a syllabus of a course of lectures on the study of history; the plan of the course of lectures on the history of England (published with Miscellaneous observations relating to education, 1780, 1st edn. 1765), XXV. (1782, 1st edn. 1777) Disquisitions relating to matter and spirit; the doctrine of philosophical necessity illustrated, III. (1787, 28 March) A letter to the Rt. Hon William Pitt ... on the subjects of toleration and church establishments occasioned by his speech against the repeal of the Test and Corporation Acts, XIX, 111–134. (1790) Introductory essays to Hartley’s Theory of the human mind, III. (1803, Philadelphia, 1st edn. 1788) Lectures on history and general policy, XXIV. Priestley, J. (ed. J. Lindsay) (1970) Autobiography ... (Bath, Adams & Dart). Roberts, C. (2002) The woman and the hour. Harriet Martineau and Victorian ideologies (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Sanders, V. (ed.) (1990) Harriet Martineau selected letters (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Watts, R. (1991) Revolution and reaction: ‘Unitarian’ academies, 1780–1800, History of Education, 20(4), 307–323. Watts, R. (1995) Joseph Priestley (1733–1804), Prospects: the Quarterly Review of Comparative Education (Paris, UNESCO: International Bureau of Education), 34(1/2), 343–353.

208

Ruth Watts

Watts, R. (1998) Gender, power and the Unitarians in England, 1760–1860 (London, Longman). Watts, R. (2000) Mary Carpenter: educator of the children of the ‘perishing and dangerous classes’, in: M. Hilton & P. Hirsch (eds) Practical visionaries: women, education and social progress 1790–1930 (Harlow, Longman). Watts, R. (2010) Rational Dissenting women and the travel of ideas, Enlightenment and Dissent, 26, 1–27. Webb, R. K. (1960) Harriet Martineau: a radical Victorian (London, Heinemann). Wollstonecraft, M. (1975, 1st edn. 1792) A vindication of the rights of women (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Yates, G. G. (ed.) (1985) Harriet Martineau on women (New Brunswick, NJ, Rutgers University Press).

Reviews Empson, W. (1833) Review of John Hopkins Notions of Political Economy and Illustrations of Political Economy, Edinburgh Review, 63(115), 1–39. Heywood, A. (1847) Harriet Martineau’s autobiography, Quarterly Review, 143(286), 484–527. Heywood, A. (1833) Illustrations of Political Economy, Quarterly Journal of Education, 5(9), 142–160. Heywood, A. (1841) Miss Martineau’s Tales, The Christian Remembrancer, 2, 178–184. For a full bibliography of Martineau’s writings and writings on her see Oxford Bibliographies Online at http://www.oxfordbibliographiesonline.com.

14 J. S. Mill on education Alan Ryan

The omnipresence of education in Mill’s work To write about Mill is to write about education. In the opening paragraph of his Autobiography Mill explains: I have thought that in an age in which education, and its improvement, are the subject of more, if not of profounder study than at any former period of English history, it may be useful that there should be some record of an education which was unusual and remarkable, and which, whatever else it may have done, has proved how much more than is commonly supposed may be taught, and well taught, in those early years which, in the common modes of what is called instruction, are little better than wasted. (Mill, 1874a, p. 25) In middle age Mill himself became an educational institution. Disraeli sneered ‘here comes the finishing governess’ when Mill entered Parliament in 1865. But, not only were Mill’s major works such as A system of logic and Principles of political economy taught in the universities and colleges of Victorian and Edwardian England, Mill and his publisher forewent their profits to sell them in popular editions at low prices for working-class readers.1 Mill’s discussions of education display many of his characteristic rhetorical and argumentative tropes. As in the passage quoted, his taste for antithesis is given free rein. On the one hand, there is almost nothing that education cannot achieve, whether full social and political equality for women, the intellectual and moral elevation of the working class, or fitting India for independence. On the other, contemporary education is ‘wretched’, endowments are squandered, and almost everyone underestimates how much students of all ages might learn, given ambition and energy. John Dewey was asked whether he was an optimist or a pessimist, and replied that he was a tremendous optimist about things in general, but a terrible pessimist about everything in particular. There is a good deal of that in Mill: optimism about what mankind could achieve set against an unsparing assessment of how far short we fall.

210

Alan Ryan

Mill wrote little about education in the ‘classroom’ sense – about schools, universities, funding, staffing, or curricula. The volume of the Collected works devoted to Law, equality, and education reprints only three essays on education. One dates from 1834 and is notionally a review of a report on the Prussian education system, though it largely consists of extracts from George Edward Biber’s savaging of the National Schools.2 The second (1866) is Mill’s evidence to the Taunton Commission on ‘middle-class’ schools. The third dates from 1867. This is Mill’s ‘Inaugural Address’ as Rector of the University of St Andrews. It is, in effect, Mill’s version of The idea of a university.3 Had the editors of the Collected works included Mill’s 1833 essay ‘Corporation and Church Property’, and the 1869 essay on ‘Endowments’, the sum total would not be much greater. The Collected works, though, produce a misleading effect. By education Mill meant whatever helps to make the human being what he is or what he is not (Mill, 1867, p. 217).4 Mill was everywhere and always alert to, obsessed by, the impact of a society’s educational level on the functioning of its social, economic, and political institutions, and equally obsessed by the educational impact of those institutions on the people who lived under them. To take one obvious instance, the doctrine that underlies Mill’s defence of representative government is that the goodness of a form of government is to be assessed by the degree to which it makes the most of the existing moral and intellectual capacities of the citizenry, and promotes their further development (Mill, 1861, p. 392). This is not quite a pedagogical view of the political process, but not far from it. It is matched by his discussions of the justification of the avowedly ‘despotic’ rule of Britain over her colonies. His argument was that ‘Despotism is a legitimate mode of government in dealing with barbarians, provided the end be their improvement, and the means justified by actually effecting that end’ (Mill, 1859, p. 16). This is the teacher’s defence of autocracy in the classroom. Among Mill’s proposals for the improvement of the political process in Victorian Britain, second only to his advocacy of votes for women in startling his readers, was his argument for giving extra votes to the better educated. The case for plural voting was in part based on the widely perceived need to offset the dangers from the introduction of universal suffrage. That would give the vote to an uneducated working class which would numerically swamp every other. The means advocated by Mill to offset the simple weight of numbers were intended to bring home to everyone the value of education. He agreed that suffrage should be restricted to the literate, but his further idea that educational attainment should be acknowledged by conferring additional votes on the better educated was more surprising (Mill, 1861, pp. 470, 473–476). He did not have in mind the kind of privilege that gave the holders of Oxford and Cambridge masters’ or doctoral degrees a vote for their own, extra, Member of Parliament.5 Mill wanted to encourage intellectual attainment in all social classes: ‘I consider it an absolutely necessary part of the plurality scheme, that it be open to the poorest individual in the community to claim its privileges, if he can prove that in spite of all difficulties and obstacles, he is in point of intelligence, entitled to them’ (Mill, 1861, p. 476).

J. S. Mill on education 211 The same thought animated Mill’s submission to the Northcote-Trevelyan Committee’s deliberations on the reform of the Home Civil Service.6 A typically Millian note is struck at the end of his submission where he concedes that ‘It would be absurd to subject a tide-waiter, a letter-carrier, or a simple copyist to the same test as the confidential adviser to a Secretary of State’, but immediately goes on to say that the tests for applicants for even humble occupations ought not to be too narrow (Mill, 1855, p. 211). The greater part of his submission was concerned with senior administrative positions. The reforming tide was running against patronage appointments, and it was a common complaint that government offices were misused as a system of outdoor relief for impecunious but well-connected young men. Mill was strongly opposed to the continuation of a system where aristocratic connections counted for more than competence.7 In his submission to the Northcote-Trevelyan Committee, Mill also deplores the suggestion that members of the clergy should provide certificates of good character for candidates for the civil service. In the Inaugural address and Liberty he denies that religious instruction should play any role in the curriculum: the study of the facts about religious belief and practice was unexceptionable; the inculcation of the belief that one or other creed was uniquely right was the business of the several churches, not of educational institutions.

Meritocracy and clerisy Many years earlier, Mill had imbibed Coleridge’s concern for the existence of a ‘clerisy’ – a class of the spiritually, intellectually, and politically enlightened, who might give coherence to an incoherent culture, and enlighten a public opinion that was destined to become increasingly powerful in the new democratising era. Mill concluded in the 1820s, and believed ever after, that public opinion would rule the new mass society, no matter what the political institutions were through which it ruled. If public opinion was destined to rule, the task of the liberal intellectual was to do what he could to ensure that it was liberal and enlightened, rather than reactionary and oppressive, or even merely dull and unambitious. The old landed aristocracy should give way to an aristocracy of merit (Mill, 1831).8 What merit consisted of was not wholly stable; but this reflected the utopian reach of Mill’s hopes for the new class rather than incoherence in the ambition itself. Changes of emphasis also reflected changes in his perception of what dangers needed to be addressed. In the 1820s and 1830s he thought the public was morally lost, not knowing quite what to think and whom to believe, whereas by the time he wrote Liberty, that danger was less salient than the danger of dead-weight uniformity. Minimally merit was understood as task-oriented competence. Mill unhesitatingly defended the concours system of selection against the existing system of patronage (Ryan, 1972, pp. 60–62). He went further, however, by distinguishing the higher policy-making level of the civil service from the executive level, where competence in following orders and implementing policies was the primary requirement. The heads of the administrative grade of the civil service

212

Alan Ryan

should possess an authority that rested on their concern for the public interest and their unimpeachable probity, as well as their intelligence and knowledge. His respect for expertise appeared again when he insisted that it was not the job of parliament to draft legislation; that required a dispassionate expertise that ‘political men’ did not possess (Mill, 1861, pp. 428–432). Elsewhere, especially when younger, he displayed a hankering after the leadership of those possessed of a poetic sensibility; poets were to be no longer the unacknowledged legislators of mankind, but the articulate leaders of public sentiment and thought. He never quite lost the concern with le pouvoir spirituel that he acquired from the Saint-Simonian missionaries9 and from Comte.10 But the concern that educated intelligence should be given the stamp of social approval by being a prerequisite for the exercise of administrative power in the Victorian state was straightforward.

Ethology Mill’s Autobiography – the record of an unusual education – displays some internal tension. It is both a piece of scientific analysis, in which the author adopts a third-person stance towards the boy and young man whose upbringing he analyses, and a Goethean Bildungsroman, where the ‘crisis in my mental history’ is the central episode. Mill’s account of his transition from being the pupil of ‘men of the eighteenth century’ to becoming his own man mirrors the political drama of the epoch of the French Revolution: collapse of the ancien régime, followed by a period of upheaval, followed by a new stability. On any reading, however, an interesting question about education is at the heart of the story. Both teachers and pupils have been known to wonder how far a student’s attainments are her or his own; ‘is everything I achieve really owed to those who taught me?’ is a not unfamiliar question. For Mill it was particularly acute, both because of the intensity of the education he had received from James Mill, and because his mental crisis coincided with his friendship with disciples of Robert Owen, who held a rigidly determinist theory of character.11 Knowing that he was widely regarded as a ‘manufactured man’ who had been ‘made’ by his father and Bentham, Mill was haunted by the fear that he was trapped in the character they had fashioned for him. He described this as the spectre of Owenite necessitarianism, the idea that the educator is omnipotent, and individuals are entirely and unchangeably what they have been reared to be. Not only in the Autobiography but in the Logic, it is the ‘Owenite’ threat to the freedom of the will that he discusses (Mill, 1843, VI, ii, 3, pp. 839–842; 1874a, pp. 134–135). In both works, he provides an answer that he thinks consistent with universality of causation. In the Autobiography, he also suggests that his anxiety was short-lived. Readers who expect Mill’s education to conclude with his rejection of his father and Bentham, the ‘men of the eighteenth century’, and a declaration of spiritual independence might find it surprising that he emanicipated himself from James Mill only to find a new teacher in Harriet Taylor. That one of the main

J. S. Mill on education 213 purposes of the Autobiography is to explain just this emerges on the first page. Having noted that ‘in an age of transition of opinions’, his intellectual development may be of some interest, he emphasises his desire to make acknowledgment of the debts which my intellectual and moral development owes to other persons; some of them of recognized eminence, others less known than they deserve to be, and the one to whom most of all is due, one whom the world had no opportunity of knowing. (Mill, 1874a, pp. 25–26) Mill never says that he was dependent on Mrs Taylor in the same way as he unavoidably was on his father, and he plainly was not. There was a good deal of difference between the teacher–pupil relationship of James and J. S. Mill, and the marriage of two minds represented by the way he and she learned from each other. Mill drew a distinction between education in the widest sense of all the influences that make us who and what we are, and education in the narrower sense of the instruction we receive in schools and universities, and in his case from his father. The wider sense is his main concern, and it is all of a piece with his concern for the formation of character. Mill’s response to Owen’s insistence that a man’s character was made ‘for him and not by him’ was that we can be agents in our own remaking. Only a person who wants to refashion his character will actually do so, and Mill acknowledges like any rational person that we need resources with which to achieve the remaking. Encouraging and intelligent, but not uncritical, interlocutors are very effective resources. How valuable a teacher and critic Harriet Taylor really was is hard to decide. Her influence was enhanced by the fact that she kept the world very much at bay. Mill’s oldest and closest friends were among those who thought his praise of his wife was hyperbolic (Mineka and Lindley, 1972, pp. xxiii–xxxiv). Even if life is a continuous process of education and re-education, some readers will wonder whether there is meant to be a time when we have finished our education. Mill himself invites the question with his rousing peroration at the end of The subjection of women (Mill, 1869, p. 39). There he insists that nobody wants to have their affairs managed even by the most benevolent tutor or parent. They want adult independence. This, of course, is the question at least indirectly answered by the distinction, drawn by Mill himself at the beginning of his Inaugural address between the broad, all-inclusive and the narrower senses of education. Mill’s education in the narrower sense was more or less complete when he was fourteen. One might hope that the education of any of us in the broader sense would be a matter of lifelong learning. The broader sense of ‘education’ is coterminous with the subject matter of the discipline that the Logic baptised as ‘ethology or the science of the formation of character’ (Mill, 1842, p. 869). Whatever influences the intellectual, emotional, political, or moral development of the individual is in this broad sense ‘educational’. Taylor’s impact on Mill was, if the expression is permissible, ethological rather than instructional.

214

Alan Ryan

We should therefore attend to Mill’s concern with, and hopes for, the social science of ‘ethology’. Mill hoped that ethology would provide a theoretical grasp of the mechanisms of socialisation, enabling us to control the process more effectively than by unaided intuition. It would thereby facilitate, first, one aspect of ordinary political socialisation. In the Logic Mill quoted his earlier essay on Coleridge in extenso about the necessary conditions of effective government – one element is that the citizens should possess a common sense of national identity (Mill, 1843, pp. 921–924). The issue is the need to reconcile a strong sense of national identity with the diversity of outlook to which liberals were committed. Mill took from Alexis de Tocqueville’s description of democratic America the suggestion that under favourable conditions these two desiderata could be jointly achieved. Tocqueville had linked the fundamental drives of human nature as he and Mill understood them to the historical and social conditions in which that human nature displayed itself in America. In Democracy Tocqueville gestured towards the thought that this wholly new society needed a new social science to analyse it; Mill gave the new science a name – ethology – and a description in the Logic. A related aspect of the role of ethology is that it may illuminate the cultural conditions of economic and social progress. Mill’s concerns are wide-ranging: how might Ireland be set on the path to rational self-government and prosperity? How might the Indian sub-continent achieve the same thing? Might an already highly developed society such as contemporary Great Britain embrace the stationary state so dreaded by most classical economists, and treat it as an opportunity to measure well-being, not by tons of steel and coal produced and consumed, but by intangibles such as the spread of industrial self-government, the minimisation of environmental destruction, and the emancipation of women from the burdens of excessive child-bearing (Mill, 1848, pp. 752–757)? The choices we might make, within the constraints of physics and political economy could change dramatically if we educated ourselves to value the right sort of well-being. Mill regretted that he had been unable to make a greater contribution to the development of ethology as a social science (Capaldi, 1972). It is difficult to know what he had hoped for, and what hopes had been dashed. The ‘science of the formation of character’ covers a lot of territory, and seems to embrace both the formation of individual character, and therefore child-rearing and education in all its aspects – moral, cultural, and intellectual, and the formation of ‘national character’, a better understanding of which might provide a key to the sorts of progress with which Mill was so concerned. It is harder to know what Mill hoped ethology might achieve and what he had failed to do, in light of his attraction to the historical speculations of the SaintSimonians and Comte. He dismissed Comte’s developed system as something that could ‘only have been invented by a man who had never laughed’ (Mill, 1865, p. 343). Comte sets out a theory of the three stages of intellectual development, and this, according to Mill, let in a flood of light on the study of history. But as a good empiricist Mill could not think that history was governed by laws sui generis that did not in the last resort rest on individual psychology.

J. S. Mill on education 215 For Mill any such holistic theory of the way in which social, economic, political, and intellectual formations give way to their successors demands decomposition. It must rest on an understanding of individual human nature and how that first nature is transformed into a second nature by upbringing. That introduces the third and most obvious aspect of the importance of ethology as a science of socialisation. Utilitarians must be concerned with education for two reasons. First, if the ultimate end of action is the happiness of those affected by the action in question, simple effectiveness requires an accurate understanding of the consequences of our actions, and that can only be acquired by some sort of educative process. Simple trial and error will teach children a lot, just as it does all animals. Nonetheless, this is a slow and expensive method of learning, and formal education is a way to reduce the cost of acquiring the knowledge necessary for prudent behaviour. The second is moral education. Education is not only about inculcating in children a proper appreciation of the causal environment in which they are to pursue the goals they already have, but inducing them to pursue goals that will ensure both their own happiness and that of everyone with whom they interact. This is the point at which ethology intersects with utilitarian ethics, and with Mill’s ambivalence about the utilitarianism in which he had been reared. Utilitarianism presupposes that moral training can ensure that children come to associate the pursuit of other people’s interests with their own happiness and to associate failure to pursue other people’s interests with their own unhappiness. This is the process of giving children a conscience by contriving that they internalise the approval and disapproval of other people. Mill takes it for granted that dependence on adults enables the child to acquire the idea that morality depends on an acceptance that everyone’s interests should be counted equally, with the perhaps unintended implication that if we were born with a baby’s utter selfishness but the physical strength of an adult, life might be poor, solitary, nasty, brutish, and short for all of us. Moral philosophy, as opposed to moral socialisation, has an educative role of a different kind. It can affect our conduct much later in the day, when we reflect on the nature of morality, reconsider which of the convictions we absorbed as infants we should continue to take seriously, and from which we should try to free ourselves. Its role should not be underestimated, since Mill relied on the possibility of a clearer understanding of the nature of morality both to assist us in making moral progress, and to help us to draw the essential distinction between ‘mere likings and dislikings’ and the moral judgments strictly speaking on which the argument of Liberty depends.

Education in the narrow sense Mill drew the distinction between a wider and a narrower sense of ‘education’ on which we have been relying in his Inaugural address. Almost uniquely in his works the Address is a discussion of the curriculum of an educational institution. Before examining his ideas about university, we should explore Mill’s views on the education of children. We are faced with a poverty of material on what

216

Alan Ryan

children should learn, but many obiter dicta on why and how they should learn it. In the first place, however terrifying to many readers his account of what he learned, and at what a pace he learned it, Mill is insistent in the Autobiography that ‘it was not an education of cram’ (Mill, 1874a, p. 45). It was in essence tutorial instruction adapted to a child who began his learning at three, and for practical purposes stopped at fourteen (Mill, 1874a, p. 44). Since Mill insisted that he was not especially talented, it is likely that he thought that many children could have benefited from a similar education. It was not unusual in emphasising classical languages and literature, mathematics, and a great deal of history. What was more out of the way was the attention paid from Mill’s twelfth year to subjects such as logic and political economy that would ordinarily be part of a university education, if part of an education at all. It is important that it was not an education of cram, since the background to Mill’s education might lead us to fear that it was. Bentham, James Mill, and Francis Place were very taken with the possibilities of mass public education that seemed to be opened up by the so-called Bell-Lancaster monitorial system of instruction. Andrew Bell devised the system in the late 1780s when he was employed by the East India Company in Madras.12 It was very much a case of necessity being the mother of invention; competent teachers were impossible to find, and he hit on the idea that the brighter of his pupils could teach their colleagues. Bentham took a technical interest in the monitorial system. His Chrestomathia spells out how to construct a school where one trained teacher could instruct as many as 1,000 pupils in one vast hall, aided by monitors or teaching assistants drawn from the pupils, who would themselves be encouraged in their efforts by a system of payment by results (Bentham, 1817). The monitorial system was advocated ‘for the instruction of the poor’, but Bentham and his allies were inclined to think that it could provide members of any social class with a superior education to any that they were likely to receive in the chaotic conditions of turn of the century public schools (Leach, 1899, pp. 418–423). For its first inventors the monitorial system promised cheapness by minimising the number of trained teachers required, but also promised effectiveness, since the monitors were themselves monitored by their superiors and their effectiveness as instructors was tested by the performance of those they were instructing. Advocates of reform in British and American school systems who emphasise varieties of payment by results today sound very like their predecessors of two centuries ago. The system seems to have fallen out of favour in the 1830s for reasons not very closely connected with the monitorial system narrowly understood. At least some schools established by the rival societies seem to have settled for getting the children to memorise answers to simple questions and to have paid no attention to whether the children understood what they had learned. Nothing could have been further from what Bentham hoped for and James Mill practised.13 In the Mill household, one feature of the Bell-Lancaster system was all too visible. The young Mill was made responsible for the education of his younger siblings. It was in its way a good device for ensuring that he understood what he

J. S. Mill on education 217 had learned from his father, but since the test of whether he had done an adequate instructional job was the ability of his sister Wilhelmina to answer James Mill’s questions, it also meant that if she failed to give a proper account of what she had learned, it was her brother who went to bed without his supper. In that domestic context, it had another drawback that James Mill recognised when he wrote to Francis Place that John could have got on a good deal faster if he had not been held back by Willie. Although Mill complains in one of the rejected leaves of the draft Autobiography that he ‘grew up in the absence of love and the presence of fear’, he does not complain about the content of what he learned as a boy, nor about his father’s methods (Mill, 1874b, p. 612). Not his instructional methods, but his unreasonably high expectations, and his ‘asperity of temper’, were at fault. James Mill was a deeply passionate man with a very short fuse, but the impression he gave his son was that he thought strong emotions were a sort of madness. When Mill subsequently reflected on his ‘mental crisis’ he decided that his education had failed to cultivate the passive sensibilities that he now saw as an essential complement to the analytical skills that he never rejected. It is unclear just what James Mill might have been able to do to provide the emotional education that his son felt he had been deprived of. The catalogue of books that occupies so much of the early pages of the Autobiography includes a great deal of poetry, history, and drama. Mill observes that he was too young to get very much out of a good many of the books he read, but it was not that he was fed a restricted diet. There are some clues to what was missing, in Mill’s account of his own attempts at dramatic and poetic composition in his early teens. His father encouraged him, both because some things were better expressed in verse than in prose, and because most people over-estimated the value of verse and being able to compose poetry would impress them. Let us turn, then, to Mill’s thoughts on education ‘narrowly conceived’. That everyone should get an education he took for granted. In Liberty he explains in a bare couple of sentences that parents who bring children into the world incur as a minimum the duty to ensure that those children do not become a burden on others, and therefore to see that they are adequately educated to be economically self-supporting. Anyone who neglects the education of their children violates the rights of both the children and the rest of society. This doctrine is enunciated in the Principles of political economy, too (Mill, 1859, pp. 118–119; 1848, pp. 947–950). Where the parents cannot pay, the state should subsidise the cost; where the parents can, they should, as he more than once insists when discussing the broad-gauge subsidies provided by educational endowments. The state must not monopolise the provision of education, however; that would threaten the variety and innovation that Mill was so anxious to protect. Some continental countries forbade private citizens to set up schools; Mill was emphatic that this was liberticide. The state’s role was to make parents do their duty, and to exercise a supervisory role to ensure that schools and teachers are of an adequate quality. In line with the general principle adumbrated in the Principles of political economy that the state may do things that private individuals

218

Alan Ryan

may do, where its role is not coercive but educative, the state certainly may and probably should establish model schools that others may emulate. The state may also play a useful role in setting national examinations, but these must be tests of factual knowledge. The principle for the management of public education is familiar from everything Mill writes. There should be a centralisation of information and ultimate authority, but as much decentralisation as is consistent with probity and efficiency in provision. The insistence on variety rather than uniformity was always at war with the belief that there is, or should be, one best solution; one of Mill’s virtues was awareness of the fact. The ‘centralising’ Mill is at his most uninhibited in his essay on Cousin’s report to the French government on the Prussian system (Mill, 1834). He emphasises the efficiency of the Prussian government, contrasting its ambition with the feebleness of the British, which only ever reacted to external pressures. The gulf between the effectiveness of public education in Prussia and the uselessness of what is provided in England is emphasised in an extract from his essay on ‘Corporation and Church Property’ (1833). Mill proposes, uncontroversially enough, that the wishes of those who endow schools and ecclesiastical establishments should be respected for a decent period, but that the state has every right to intervene if the institutions affected depart from their original purpose. Oxford and Cambridge feared that a view like Mill’s might animate the Royal Commission of 1854 that remodelled the ancient universities. In Mill’s 1834 essay, however, the passage he quotes is an ad hominem jibe at the public schools of the day. The second interesting part of the essay is a long extract from Biber’s lectures on Christian education. The ‘Christian’ aspect is entirely absent from the passages Mill quotes, although we may assume that Mill’s readers – Biber’s essay appeared in the Monthly Repository, a Unitarian journal – knew very well what arguments had gone on about religious instruction in the Bell and Lancasterian schools. The extracts from Biber’s lectures defy summary; they consist of horror stories that almost two centuries later still leave a reader torn between laughter and rage. The children whose attainments are discussed parrot strings of mathematical calculations, without having the least idea what they are about; they display a facility in spelling long words, about whose meaning they have no idea whatever. They can engage in complicated turn-taking, but what looks like the cooperative solution of a mathematical problem is really the recitation of nonsense syllables as far as the children are concerned. Mill’s enthusiasm for Prussian solutions waned over the next three decades, but when he gave evidence to the Taunton Commission in 1866, the concerns so prominent in Liberty were almost invisible. Most endowed schools provided a poor education; part of the reason was that schoolmasters were paid a fixed stipend out of the endowment, and therefore had no interest in either increasing the numbers of their pupils or teaching them better. Payment by results was the only way to ensure good teaching. Mill acknowledged that there was a shortage of available instruction in how as well as what to teach, but his emphasis throughout is on the need for efficiency, for finding ways of putting educational endowments to more effective use by amalgamating trusts,

J. S. Mill on education 219 establishing large schools, and assembling groups of schools to provide instruction for all ages.14 Three years later, the essay on ‘Endowments’ strikes a very different note. It is an example of another of Mill’s antithetical themes, in this case, the importance of not reforming variety out of existence. Against the suggestion that endowments should be made unlawful, Mill argues both for the need to protect variety and novelty, and that the state must keep an eye on the application of endowments to their proper purposes. He observes that parents generally had no real understanding of what education their children needed, and brushes off the common view that parents had a natural right to determine the content of their children’s teaching. The uncultivated cannot be judges of cultivation; this is a variation on the argument about education in the Principles of political economy (Mill, 1869, 1848). His closing thought was that everything said about the need to educate boys applied to girls.15 Mill does not make a big issue of this theme, either here, or in Liberty or in the Inaugural address. The subjection of women, on the other hand, is in large part a treatise on the role of a bad and misguided education in both the wider and its narrower senses in persuading the enemies of female emancipation to believe that women are intellectually inferior to men, ‘naturally’ acquiescent in their dependent status, ‘naturally’ uninterested in politics, and unfitted to economic independence. The remedy is an education of both the wider and the narrower sort that does not rest on a conflation of customary or ‘second’ nature with women’s true nature. His major target in Subjection was in practical terms the exclusion of women from higher and professional education, but he ends his essays on ‘Endowments’ with the broader principle as applicable to education at all levels. The founders of Newnham College, Cambridge were as close to being disciples of Mill as his fastidiousness and their own independence of mind would allow them to be.16 Only in his Inaugural address as Rector of the University of St Andrew’s did Mill spell out what he thought university students should study. Alexander Bain, ordinarily devoted to Mill and subsequently his biographer, complained that the address was far too long, and also that Mill’s programme for liberal education was absurdly over-demanding. Two decades would hardly be long enough to get a degree in Mill’s ideal university.17 Mill’s unrealism was to some extent a reflection of his father’s success sixty years earlier in persuading his son that his abilities were, if anything, below the average. It may also have reflected a simple lack of acquaintance with students in their late teens and early twenties. Among the things he did was to explain why students should read his System of logic: students needed to understand not only and perhaps not primarily the factual results of the natural and social sciences but above all the methodological principles underlying all scientific inquiry. On the more narrowly pedagogical front, Mill insisted on keeping the classics in the centre of a liberal education. This went along with the view that teaching modern foreign languages was not a task a university should engage in. Whether Mill really considered that the poetry of Pushkin was no part of a liberal education or thought that any schoolboy could teach himself Russian it is impossible to guess.

220

Alan Ryan

Many years before, he had complained that the treatment of Plato in the ancient universities was excessively literary and insufficiently philosophical. When he reprinted his earlier essays he acknowledged that much that he had said was no longer true. Oxford and Cambridge had been reformed as they needed to be by the Royal Commission of 1854.18 In particular, they took ancient philosophy and political theory seriously. Mill, however, was looking at the future, and arguing that it would be a mistake to give up the classics in an attempt to found higher education on the natural sciences rather than the humanities. Mill tried to preempt the argument between T. H. Huxley (for the sciences) and Matthew Arnold (a defence of literature) with the question ‘why not both?’ No doubt the response prompts Bain’s complaint that Mill’s curriculum needed two decades, not four years. There is more to it than that, though. Mill’s argument for the classics had a slightly shaky foundation, but a clear purpose. The shakiness of the foundation was that Mill wanted to argue both that the classics offer us a chance to see ourselves in a different context and that they confront us with the real otherness of our predecessors. In the background was Mill’s passion for Athenian democracy. He was unusual in much preferring Athens to Rome, and in lining up the argument as the politics of autonomous self-governing citizens versus the carefully managed, legalistic oligarchy of the Romans (Urbinati, 2002). Mill’s fear that his own education had been lacking in the cultivation of the passive sensibilities is perhaps heard in his insistence that in addition to the sciences and the humanities, space must be found for the fine arts. It is not an area in which Mill showed to advantage on a public platform – his problem, perhaps, is an excess of earnestness. Instead of doing as either Arnold or Newman would have done and offering a few persuasive examples of fiction, drama, poetry, or painting for lack of an encounter with which a student’s life would be thinner or duller, he falls back on the obvious but not very relevant fact that many songs have had an impact on politics and history. Those who have never had to address a Scottish university in the role of Rector should perhaps say nothing about the choice of ‘Scots wha hae’ as a telling example. Mill, of course, knew very well what he could have said, but it may be that the man who could not read Shelley aloud, because of the emotions aroused, thought himself obliged to rein in his deeper feelings about the importance of an aesthetic education. The same is perhaps true of his unexceptionable but predictable views on moral education; the familiar insistence that no sect could use the university to instil an orthodoxy does not lead on to any suggestions about the positive moral training a university might do. One must not complain; the upsurge of the desire to cross class barriers and do something directly for the disadvantaged which led to such ventures as the University Settlements in the East End of London was a dozen years in the future. Wrenching Mill’s Address out of its historical context is not fruitful. The twenty-first-century reader may be amused by the certainty with which Mill insists that it is no part of a university’s task to provide professional education. But the nineteenth-century notion of what constituted a member of a profession,

J. S. Mill on education 221 and what doctors, lawyers and clergy needed to know then, is dramatically far from the understanding of such a reader. Take the example of Harvard: what Mill would have recognised as a university is the College of Arts and Sciences which enrols about 6,000 undergraduates and half as many graduates. But beyond that, graduate programmes in public health, medicine, nursing, education, divinity, law, and business bring the total to around 20,000 enrolled students; beyond them there are students in continuing education. The University Mill addressed had around 150 students, all undergraduates, and a dozen professors. If this essay has occasionally seemed to complain that Mill said too little about ‘narrow education’, that is to say what and how students are to be taught in schools and universities, it seems right to redress the balance in a last sentence. Mill was a great philosopher and political theorist, a liberal, a feminist, and a reformer; not only did he write a great deal about education in its broader sense, reading him today is as important an educational experience as a century and a half ago (Skorupski, 2008).

Notes 1 Mill’s Principles were taught in Oxford until 1919, when Alfred Marshall’s Principles of economics became the basis of economics teaching in most universities; System of logic was in use in the University of London and elsewhere into the 1930s; although Mill’s broader philosophical views were attacked by Idealists of all stripes during his lifetime and afterwards it was a sign of his centrality to intellectual life that he could not be ignored. 2 Review of Sarah Austin’s translation of Victor Cousin’s report on Prussian education. George Edward Biber (1801–1874) wrote prolifically on educational theory, Christian education and the history of the Church of England. 3 Compare with John Henry Newman (1801–1890) central in the Oxford Movement of the 1840s, converted to Catholicism, created Cardinal in 1879, beatified in 2010; The idea of a university (1852 and 1858) consists of lectures delivered as Rector of the newly established Catholic University of Ireland; it remains the most often-quoted discussion of the principles of a liberal education. 4 Collini, 1984, p. xlviii re the editing of Mill on education in the Complete works. 5 Two members of the House of Commons for each of the ancient universities dated to a Royal Charter of 1603; all holders of the MA or Doctorate could vote; after 1918, elections were conducted by the Single Transferable Vote system; abolished by the Representation of the People Act of 1948, effected with the General Election of 1950; London University returned one member from 1868 to 1950. 6 Set up in 1855; see Hart, 1972, pp. 63–81. 7 Mill set economics exams for Haileybury College, established 1806, the training college for the East India Company whose administrators Mill considered to be meritorious and well trained. 8 Mill first articulated these ideas in The spirit of the age written in instalments for The examiner spring and summer of 1831; left unfinished as the public agenda moved to parliamentary reform. 9 Mill made friends with Gustave d’Eichthal (1804–1886) in 1829, though he was more sceptical by 1831 when Saint-Simonians arrived in England. 10 Auguste Comte (1798–1857), founder of ‘Positivism’, coined the word ‘sociology’; although he was influenced by Comte and sympathetic, Mill’s Auguste Comte and positivism (1865) is unsparingly critical.

222

Alan Ryan

11 Robert Owen (1771–1858), Utopian Socialist, held that actions flow from character which is made for not by us. In the 1820s, Mill debated with Owenites. 12 Andrew Bell (1757–1832), Anglican clergyman, spent ten years in Madras where he devised the monitorial system (hence, ‘Madras schools’); Joseph Lancaster (1778– 1838) independently invented the monitorial system in South London; schools based on the system were established in the United States and Canada; under the label ‘peer supported learning’ it still has a place in American higher education; Coleridge was an enthusiastic supporter although no friend to utilitarianism. 13 F. R. Leavis’s association of James Mill’s education of his son with Dickens’ Gradgrind in Hard Times is a misidentification attributable to Leavis’s loathing for ‘Benthamism’; it is unlikely that Dickens had read Bentham, who was anyway opposed to rote learning (Fielding, 1956). 14 Mill was advised by Edwin Chadwick (1800–1890), Benthamite, responsible with Nassau Senior (1790–1864), for the report on poverty that led to the Poor Law of 1834. 15 Mill mentions Christ’s Hospital established 1552 to co-educate, which in 1869 had 1129 boys and 28 girls. (The present author was Almoner of Christ’s Hospital in the late 1990s when concerted effort was made to achieve equal numbers.) Mill may have seized on Christ’s Hospital because he was a friend of Henry Cole (1808–1882), former pupil there. 16 Henry Sidgwick and Millicent Garret Fawcett (1847–1929), sister of Elizabeth Garret, campaigner for the right of women to practise medicine, supporter of women’s rights; her husband Henry Fawcett (1833–1884), MP and economist, was an ally of Mill’s in the campaign for female suffrage. In contrast to the USA where Oberlin was founded as co-educational in 1833, even progressive, non-sectarian University College London admitted women students only in 1878. 17 Alexander Bain (1818–1903) Professor of Philosophy, University of Aberdeen, first biographer of both James Mill and J. S. Mill. Mill’s delivery must have been deliberate – the address is hardly longer than Isaiah Berlin’s inaugural, Two concepts of liberty. 18 The ancient universities were still governed by the Test Acts, repealed 1872; Mill deplored the remaining Anglican monopoly (although when Henry Sidgwick asked whether Mill thought he should resign his fellowship at Trinity College, Cambridge because he no longer believed the Thirty-Nine Articles, Mill did not encourage him to throw away his livelihood for a principle; in fact, Trinity behaved decently, and kept Sidgwick as a lecturer until repeal allowed the college to elect him to a fellowship once more).

References Bentham, J. (1817) [1984] Chrestomathia (ed. M. J. Smith & W. H. Burston) (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Burston, W. H. (ed.) (1969) James Mill on education (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Capaldi, N. (1972) Mill’s forgotten science of ethology, Social Theory and Practice, 409–420. Collini, S. (1984) Introduction, Collected works, vol. XXI, Essays on equality, law, and education (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Fielding, K. J. (1956) Mill and Gradgrind, Nineteenth century fiction, 148–151. Hart, J. (1972) The genesis of the Northcote-Trevelyan Report, in: G. Sutherland (ed.) Studies in the growth of nineteenth-century government (London, Routledge). Leach, A. F. (1899) A history of Winchester College (New York, Scribner’s Sons).

J. S. Mill on education 223 Mill, J. S. (1831) [1986] The spirit of the age, in: Collected works, vol. XXII, Newspaper writings (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 227–234, 238–245, 252–258, 278–282, 289–295, 304–307, 312–316. Mill, J. S. (1833) [1967] Corporation and church property, in: Collected works, vol. IV, Essays on economics and society (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 193–222. Mill, J. S. (1834) [1984] Reform in education, in: Collected works, vol. XXI, Essays on equality, law, and education (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 61–74. Mill, J. S. (1843) [1974] A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive, in: Collected works, vols VII–VIII (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Mill, J. S. (1848) [1965] Principles of political economy, in: Collected works, vols II–III (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Mill, J. S. (1855) [1977] Reform of the Civil Service, in: Collected works, vol. XVIII, Essays on politics and society (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 205–211. Mill, J. S. (1859) [2006] On liberty and the subjection of women (ed. A. Ryan) (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Mill, J. S. (1861) [1977] Considerations on representative government, in: Collected works, vol. XIX, Essays on politics and society (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 371–577. Mill, J. S. (1865) [1969] Auguste Comte and positivism, in: Collected works, vol. X, Essays on ethics, religion and society (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 261–368. Mill, J. S. (1866) Educational endowments, in: Collected works, vol. XXI (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 207–214. Mill, J. S. (1867) [1984] Inaugural address delivered to the University of St Andrews, in: Collected works, vol. XXI, Essays on equality, law, and education (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 215–257. Mill, J. S. (1869) [1967] Endowments, in: Collected works, vol. V, Essays on economics and society (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 613–629. Mill, J. S. (1874a) [1989] Autobiography (ed. J.M. Robson) (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Mill, J. S. (1874b) [1981] Autobiography, in Collected works, vol. I, Autobiography and literary essays (Toronto, University of Toronto Press), 1–290. Mineka, F. & Lindley, D. (1972) [1981] Introduction to Collected works, vol. I, Autobiography and literary essays (Toronto, University of Toronto Press). Ryan, A. (1972) Utilitarianism and bureaucracy: the views of J. S. Mill, in: G. Sutherland (ed.) Studies in the growth of nineteenth-century government (London, Routledge). Skorupski, J. (2008) Why read Mill today? (London, Routledge). Urbinati, N. (2002) Mill on democracy (Chicago, University of Chicago Press).

15 Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England Laura Schwartz

Introduction: Feminism and the movement for women’s education: an uneasy relationship? Definitions of ‘Victorian feminism’ continue to be the subject of historical debate. The nineteenth-century movement for women’s emancipation was so diverse and continually developing that historians have urged caution with regards to overly unitary terminology (Offen, 1988, p. 131). Women who declined to see themselves as women’s rights advocates often worked to further the interests of their sex alongside others who proudly laid claim to such a political identity; while individuals not necessarily motivated by specifically feminist aims may still have contributed or been important to a feminist tradition (Caine, 1997, p. 3). Feminist ideas did not derive from any one key text or thinker, nor did the English women’s movement as a whole acknowledge an official leader or produce official propaganda. It is not possible, therefore, to ‘measure’ its development solely according to criteria or patterns of growth arising from studies of predominantly male social movements or political organisations (Levine, 1987, p. 20; Caine, 1997, p. 6). Such problems of definition are particularly pertinent to analyses of the campaign for women’s education. Education was a central concern for those struggling against female oppression well before the formation of an organised women’s movement in the second half of the nineteenth century (Wright, 1831, p. 38; Sharples, 1832, p. 17; Wollstonecraft, 1989, ch. 4). Post-1850 activists such as Elizabeth Wolstenholme (1833–1918) and Josephine Butler (1828– 1906) drew on an older feminist tradition that directly equated freedom with the acquisition of knowledge. Wolstenholme campaigned on a wide range of women’s rights issues, including sex education and the suffrage, and was also a member of the North of England Council for the Higher Education of Women. Echoing earlier feminist writings, her tract on girls’ schooling ended with a cry to slay the ‘cruel tyrant’ of enforced ignorance, calling on her sisters to ‘Set free the women who sigh in the dark prison-houses, the captives of ignorance and folly’ (Wolstenholme, 1869, p. 328). Butler, a fellow member of NECHEW who went on to lead a national campaign against the exploitation and legal oppression of prostitutes, similarly declared that, for women, ‘[w]orse than bodily privations

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

225

or pains ... are these aches and pangs of ignorance’ (Butler, 1868, p. 7). Education became a central campaigning issue for the English Woman’s Journal (1858–1864), one of the first periodicals to campaign on a cross section of women’s rights including suffrage and the legal position of married women. Calls to improve standards in girls’ schools and to set up women’s higher education establishments thus came to be closely bound up with broader feminist concerns. Because, as Butler put it, ‘The desire for education which is widely felt by English women ... springs ... from the conviction that for many women to get knowledge is the only way to get bread’, calls for education led on especially to the wider question of women’s right to work (Butler, 1868, pp. 7–8). Yet the relationship between feminism and women’s education was by no means straightforward. The foundation of girls’ schools and women’s colleges also involved men and women who did not necessarily identify with a broader set of feminist politics. After the Taunton Commission of 1870 revealed the inadequacy of existing provision, it was the government, rather than feminist campaigners, who went on to establish the majority of girls’ secondary schools (Fletcher, 1980). The drive for improved standards in schools and the foundation of women’s colleges must also be seen as part of broader educational reform, led by a liberal elite keen both to secure their socio-economic ascendancy and promote more professional and competitive values within education as a whole (Pederson, 1987; Sutherland, 1987). Historians have also questioned the extent to which the new schools and colleges for women really did challenge traditional gender roles, pointing to strict disciplinary codes which formally endorsed conservative models of femininity (Dyhouse, 1981; Delamont, 1989). The pioneers of women’s higher education were renowned for the cautious manner in which they pursued their aims – ‘Degrees by Degrees’ according to one activist (Rogers, 1938). By the beginning of the twentieth century, this approach was often at odds with the increasingly militant tone of large sections of the women’s movement, especially those fighting for the vote. Even Emily Davies (1830–1921), founder of the first residential women’s college and editor of the English Woman’s Journal, was careful not to identify too closely the cause of women’s education with the less respectable issue of suffrage, let alone the campaigns around prostitution to which many Victorian feminists devoted themselves. Many Oxford-based educationalists, including Elizabeth Wordsworth (Principal of Lady Margaret Hall and founder of St Hugh’s College), Lucy Soulsby (Headmistress of Oxford High School for Girls, 1879–1889), and Mary Ward (one of the founders of Somerville) not only sought to disassociate themselves from the more militant elements of the women’s rights movement, but also opposed female enfranchisement (Bush, 2005).1 However, to ask whether campaigns for women’s education were or were not ‘feminist’ is to pose the question in a manner which implies too rigid a conceptual framework, for neither one of these movements possessed a fixed or homogenous identity. A more fruitful approach traces a current of feminist thought and practice running through the various educational initiatives of the period, to which some individual reformers adhered more than others, and which

226

Laura Schwartz

intersected with particular projects at particular historical junctures. The term ‘feminism’ did not come into use in the English language until the 1890s, and even then its meaning was contested (Offen, 1988, p. 129; Caine, 1997, p. 8; Delap, 2005, p. 382). Yet those historians who argue for a more thoughtful and precise application of the term have nevertheless sought working definitions ‘not tied down to a specific historical time’ with which to indicate women’s recognition of their collective oppression and ‘positive identification with each other in a context of political struggle’ (Cott, 1987, pp. 4–5; Levine, 1987, p. 14). Such a definition is flexible enough to encompass those who remained committed to the value of sexual difference and a special role for women distinct from that of men (Offen, 1988, p. 141). Even as we recognise the ambiguous relationship that many female educational reformers had with the women’s movement, it is worth remembering that all were fighting in the face of entrenched and widespread opposition to educating women outside the home (Howarth & Curthoys, 1987, pp. 214–215). Their schools and colleges were undoubtedly established as part of a more general reform of education, but the very fact of their being for women rather than men radically shifted the grounds upon which they sought legitimacy. Not only did the pioneers of women’s education face far greater obstacles than reformers of the boys’ public schools and ancient universities; for women to promote public and professional values within their institutions represented a far greater challenge to dominant ideas of acceptable female conduct (Levine, 1990, p. 147). The newly professionalised schools, often run by women with connections to women’s rights networks, formed an important part of the improvement of girls’ secondary education (Glenday & Price, 1974; Levine, 1990, pp. 128, 136–137). Examples include Frances Buss’s North London Collegiate School (est. 1850), Dorothea Beale’s Cheltenham Ladies’ College (est. 1854), and the Girls’ Public Day School Company established by Emily and Maria Sheriff in 1871. Women’s rights advocates were also active in the Ladies’ Educational Associations set up in most large towns throughout the 1860s and 70s, which pushed for girls to be allowed to sit for Local Examinations and lobbied universities for access and facilities (Dyhouse, 1995, p. 14). Queen’s College in London, the first higher education establishment for women, was founded by Christian Socialists F. D. Maurice and Charles Kingsley in 1848, followed by the Unitarian Elizabeth Jesser Reid’s Bedford College in 1849 (Tuke, 1939; Sutherland, 1990). In 1878, London became the first university to admit women to its degrees (excluding medicine), and by 1897 the university at Manchester also permitted women to read for degrees in all subjects bar engineering and medicine. Resistance to women’s higher education was especially strong at Oxford and Cambridge, where women were not admitted to read for degrees until 1920 and 1947, respectively. The ancient universities thus became the arena for some of the most iconic battles in the struggle against male privilege, and will be focused on in this chapter as places in which competing theories of women’s education were particularly clearly articulated. Three overlapping networks of educational reformers are identified – supporters of Girton College, Cambridge; Newnham

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

227

College, Cambridge; and the Oxford Anglican women’s colleges. This article will examine the ways in which they addressed a number of key themes with regards to education and women’s emancipation. The next section will discuss how feminist arguments intersected with other social, political, and economic factors leading to the emergence of the movement for women’s education. The following section looks in more detail at the different ways in which women’s right to education was justified in the face of strong opposition. The contested nature of sexual difference was key to these debates, with all sides asking if men and women had different intellectual capacities and whether educating women stripped them of their femininity. Religious arguments were employed by almost all feminists entering this debate, though varying conclusions were reached. The final section looks at the more practical discussions and disagreements within the Oxbridge women’s colleges over the kind of education best suited to women.

Education: for what and for whom? First and foremost, feminists maintained that women needed to be educated in order to improve society. This was an argument common to discussions of women’s emancipation generally, whereby it was insisted that women needed to be freed from the home and allowed into the public sphere so that they could ‘do God’s work in the world’. ‘We hear cries that the world is going wrong for want of women, that moral progress cannot be made without their help’, complained Barbara Leigh Smith Bodichon (1827–1891), founder of the English Woman’s Journal, and yet women were denied access to education and professions that would enable them to carry out their saving mission (Bodichon, 1857, p. 6). The notion of ‘woman’s mission’ had been appropriated by feminists in the Utopian Socialist Owenite movement earlier in the century but also had a strong religious dimension, deriving from the evangelical emphasis on women as the bearers of moral and social transformation (Taylor, 1983, pp. 123–128). Feminists also echoed evangelical sentiments when, discussing the lack of activities and professions open to middle-class women, they declared idleness to be the greatest sin of all (Howarth, 1988, pp. ix–xvi). ‘Every human being should work’, wrote Bodichon, ‘no one should owe bread to any but his or her parents ... it lowers the dignity of women’ (Bodichon, 1857, p. 11). Such arguments were also imbued with a language of productivity and efficiency. Elizabeth Wolstenholme lamented the thousands of girls currently abandoned to ignorance and idleness, and suggested that ‘it is worth considering how enormous a power for good all this energy might become if economised and trained’ (Wolstenholme, 1869, p. 298) Nor were feminists averse to invoking the ‘economic gain to the community’ that a better educated female workforce could provide (Wolstenholme, 1869, p. 319). Though feminist arguments utilised dominant nineteenth-century capitalist discourses of hard work and moral improvement, they nevertheless presented a serious challenge to the idealisation of the bourgeois family. Not only did feminists condemn the enforced idleness of the middle-class wife, engaged neither in household labour (which was now performed by servants) nor

228

Laura Schwartz

professional occupations (Cobbe, 1862, pp. 4–5; Davies, 1988, pp. 38, 44); they also exposed the myth that all middle-class women could rely upon a male relative for financial support. Elizabeth Wolstenholme protested that ‘It is to the last degree indecent that women should be dependent upon marriage for a professional maintenance’ (Wolstenholme, 1869, p. 318). This was not merely a question of principle, but, for many women, a painful reality. Josephine Butler pointed out in 1861 that at least two-fifths of women were unmarried, and perhaps one-quarter of married women were compelled to perform some labour to support themselves and their families (Butler, 1868, p. 4; Davies, 1988, pp. 75–76). Without adequate training or employment, middle-class women were forced into low-paid positions of ‘drudgery’ – most commonly as teachers or governesses (Bodichon, 1857, p. 18). The lack of adequate training for governesses was widely perceived to be an ‘evil’, not simply for the women themselves but also for the children they were so ill-equipped to teach (Butler, 1869). Queen’s College was initially set up to help such women acquire qualifications, and was supported by the London Governesses’ Benevolent Institute. As well as better training for female teachers, feminists proposed that women be educated to enter a variety of professions. Emily Davies was perhaps the most ambitious in insisting that women could work as doctors, managers of hospitals, workhouses, prisons, and charitable institutions, and also go into farming or business (Davies, 1988, pp. 71, 76–78). As this list of professions suggests, feminist thinking on education was unquestioningly geared towards the interests of middle-class women. Education in the nineteenth century was stratified not in terms of age, but of class, so that ‘elementary education’ meant working-class schooling including provision for adults, such as the mechanics institutes. Feminists seldom concerned themselves with elementary education and it was mainly at the secondary and especially the tertiary level that their ideas were put into practice (Sutherland, 1987, p. 94; Levine, 1990, p. 127).2

Women’s intellect and sexual difference Cultural resistance to the idea of educating women remained strong throughout the nineteenth century (Howarth & Curthoys, 1987, pp. 214–215), setting the terms of the debate so that feminists were compelled to spend much energy countering the arguments of their opponents. Opposition to women’s education was based upon a strong assertion of sexual difference. In its most extreme manifestations, women’s intellects were seen as insightful and sensitive without the ability to make rational evidence-based judgements; physiologically, they were not equipped to deal with the rigours of university education which would threaten their capacity to bear children; and because women’s vocation in life was supposedly different from that of men, it was believed to be pointless and cruel to educate her beyond her sphere as wife and mother. These supposedly inherent obstacles to women acquiring an education meant that any woman who had successfully done so was abhorred as an aberration – an unwomanly woman

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

229

for whom the acquisition of reason had destroyed her natural femininity (Burstyn, 1980). Supporters of female education varied in their willingness to challenge such thinking on women’s intellectual capacities. Emily Davies insisted that ‘there is between the sexes a deep and broad basis of likeness’ and she felt that only good could come of enabling women to take a greater part in the intellectual and public life of men. She preferred a method of training that sought to cultivate the ‘common human element’, rather than one which began by ‘dividing mankind into two great sections and forcing each into a mould’ (Davies, 1988, pp. 163–165, 116–117). Although Davies claimed not to question the existence of ‘distinctive man-hood and womanhood’, she asserted that while women continued to be denied the opportunity to develop their intellectual powers, it was not possible to say what was ‘naturally’ feminine and what was merely the result of ‘convention’. She thus maintained that ‘until artificial appliances are removed we cannot know anything about the native distinctions. As to the future, who can say?’ (Davies, 1988, pp. 159–161). Elizabeth Wolstenholme also insisted that all ‘artificial’ causes of differences between the sexes ought to be eradicated, and that the ‘monopoly of sex’ in education and the professions should be rejected in favour of a free market in which any ‘natural’ differences would be free to assert themselves. She therefore reassured her readers that ‘men need not for one moment fear that in any work in which they have special natural advantages they will ever be driven out of the field by woman’ (Wolstenholme, 1869, p. 319). Such arguments had, of course, the advantage of appearing to defer to a traditional belief in sexual difference, while in fact asserting that such distinctions ought to have very little actual bearing on how society was organised. Some feminists, however, placed more emphasis upon the importance and value of distinctively ‘womanly’ characteristics. Josephine Butler, for example, complained of certain (unnamed) advocates of women’s education who ‘speak of women as if it were a compliment to them, or in any way true, to say that they are like men’. The best kind of education would, in Butler’s view, actively encourage ‘every good quality, every virtue which we regard as feminine’ to ‘develop more freely’ (Butler, 1868, pp. 17–18). The journalist and campaigner for women’s rights, Frances Power Cobbe (1822–1904), also argued that masculine and feminine characteristics were so innate that it was ridiculous to suggest that educating women would erase them. Education was about drawing out one’s powers, therefore, ‘[i]f we draw out a woman’s powers to the very uttermost, we shall only educe her womanliness ... and so make her a perfect woman’ (Cobbe, 1862, p. 8). Neither Butler nor Cobbe concluded from their belief in difference between the sexes that women were in any way inferior to men. But upholding sexual difference continued to have rather more conservative implications elsewhere, even for some women educationalists. Dorothea Beale (1831–1906) began her paper to the Social Science Congress on the education of girls, by asserting that ‘I desire to institute no comparison between the mental abilities of boys and girls, but simply to say what means to be the right means of training, so that they [women] may best perform that subordinate part in the world’ (Beale, 1865, p. 1).

230

Laura Schwartz

Religious arguments were extremely important to these debates since differences between men and women were usually defined as ‘God given’. At the same time, there existed, at least since Mary Wollstonecraft, a feminist tradition of looking to Christianity to claim the ‘sexless soul’, and arguing that men and women were one in the eyes of Christ (Taylor, 2005, p. 412). Earlier in the century, radical Unitarians’ heterodox rejection of original sin, and a belief in the perfectibility of both the male and female soul through virtuous education, led them to argue forcefully for women’s right to knowledge (Gleadle, 1995; Watts, 1998).3 In her influential book The higher education of women (1866) Emily Davies insisted, from an Anglican perspective, that Christianity preached only ‘one moral law’ for men and women, concluding that ‘The theory of education of our English Church recognises no distinction of sex’ (Davies, 1988, pp. 14–15). Josephine Butler, an Anglican like Davies, though of a more evangelical bent, also insisted that the movement for women’s education was supported by Christian teachings. She accused those who argued that educating women would make them unfeminine of committing an ‘infidelity against God’, of doubting the strength of His Creative power and the feminine virtues He had bestowed upon women. Butler also concurred with Davies in proclaiming that Christ favoured the equality of women in order that the sexes might attain greater union (Butler, 1868, pp. 18–19). The women associated with the foundation of Lady Margaret Hall (LMH, est. 1879), St Hugh’s (est. 1886), and St Hilda’s (est. 1893) in Oxford, however, came from a more conservative Anglican tradition. Many leading High Churchmen had been among the most outspoken opponents of women’s education, advocating a traditional interpretation of Scripture that taught that God had created Eve to serve Adam (Burgon, 1884; Burstyn, 1980). Elizabeth Wordsworth (1840–1932), Principal of LMH, Annie Moberly (1846–1937), Principal of St Hugh’s, and Dorothea Beale, founder of St Hilda’s, though of varying outlooks, were all strongly influenced by a broad High Church tradition. Wordsworth’s father the Bishop of Lincoln, for example, was the author of a famous sermon on ‘Christian Womanhood’ which condemned any form of education that encouraged women to compete as men’s equals (Wordsworth, 1884). His daughter, likewise, argued that women should never seek to emulate men, but instead celebrate their womanly characteristics of self-sacrifice and moral superiority (Wordsworth, 1894, pp. 8, 12). And yet her insistence on the God-given nature of sexual difference also led her to argue, like Butler and Cobbe, against those who claimed that education would create unwomanly women: ‘Put women into whatever circumstances you will, they (happily for the world) will always remain women’, she told her students.4 The question for Wordsworth, then, was not whether women should be educated, but how.

An education best suited to women Feminists were divided over what kinds of education were best suited to women and these debates were rooted in wider philosophical and religious differences.

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

231

Yet they also reflected the political alignments and social networks of the various groups of reformers. Emily Davies and Frances Power Cobbe, both active in metropolitan women’s rights circles, were insistent that women receive an identical education to that of men. This included sitting competitive examinations, and Davies’ first campaign was for girls of secondary school age to be allowed to sit for the Cambridge Local Examinations.5 Although such a position, in Davies’s case, derived from the belief that women’s intellects were essentially no different from men’s, thus enabling them to compete directly, it was also a practical move – for Davies held that if women did not strive to achieve the same standard as men, their qualifications would be disregarded (Cobbe, 1862, p. 15; Davies, 1988, pp. 134–135). In 1869 Emily Davies, with the support of Barbara Leigh Smith Bodichon, established Girton College at Cambridge, where students were required to study the same curriculum as men, sit for all the examinations, and complete the degree in the same time allowed for male undergraduates (Bradbrook, 1969; McWilliamsTullberg, 1975; Strachey, 1978; Howarth, 1988). The majority of the North of England Council for the Higher Education of Women, however, was against such a move. Some members, including Josephine Butler’s husband George, opposed it on the grounds of women’s different intellectual capacities and future roles in life, though many others pointed to how outdated the existing university curriculum was, and insisted that women should not seek to emulate this. One of Josephine Butler’s correspondents advised her that ‘It seems to us that instead of claiming equality with men, you would put yourselves into a most unworthy – one might say – slavish position, if you adopted a bad examination, only because it was one which now men passed’ (NECHEW, 1868). Members of NECHEW supported instead the foundation of Newnham College, where students were permitted to follow a self-guided course of study, and instead of Greek and Latin for the degree examinations, they benefited from some of the new subjects then being pioneered at Cambridge. Newnham was thus also a focus for university reformers such as the Cambridge don Henry Sidgwick who helped to found Newnham along with its first Principal and NECHEW member Anne Jemima Clough (1820–1892) (Gardner, 1921; Hamilton, 1936; Phillips, 1979; Sutherland, 1987; 2000). The Oxford women’s colleges followed the same course as Newnham and did not initially compel their students to read for degrees or sit examinations. Although she supported those students who wished to take exams, Elizabeth Wordsworth was especially keen to ensure that rather than have ‘facts ... ruthlessly and unremittingly shovelled into her brain’, a girl’s poetic imagination ought to be nourished. In her view, girls should also have a ‘Wanderjahr’ between school and college during which a more holistic education might be pursued (Wordsworth, 1894, pp. 11, 13). She also regarded the religious aspect of women’s education to be of equal weight to the intellectual. In her view, one of the most important reasons for women to educate themselves was to enable them to become religious teachers, and this applied equally whether they intended to marry or to take on more professional roles within the Church.

232

Laura Schwartz

Women should have the requisite knowledge to read and interpret the Bible accurately, and to defend the writings of the Church Fathers and Anglican Divines against secularising forces (Battiscombe, 1978, pp. 174–175). Dorothea Beale also condemned the idea that women’s education was simply about academic success, and insisted that ‘we should ever remember that moral training is the end, education the means’ (Beale, 1865, p. 13). Their relationship to the Established Church was of great importance to the identity of all the Oxbridge women’s colleges. In Oxford, the initial group of reformers split over whether the women’s college they had come together to found should be non-denominational or affiliated to the Church of England. Those who favoured the former option established Somerville College, while Lady Margaret Hall (followed by St Hugh’s and St Hilda’s) was founded on a ‘definite Church basis’ (Rogers, 1938; Brittain, 1960; Griffin, 1986; Adams, 1996). The Cambridge colleges, though not designated Church institutions, were also concerned with the moral education of their students. Newnham, dominated by the freethinking Clough family, was decidedly nondenominational – though Anne Jemima Clough nevertheless encouraged her students to attend some place of worship on Sundays (Sutherland, 2006, pp. 90–93). Girton was reportedly known as ‘that infidel place’ and was also supported by a number of freethinkers including Barbara Leigh Smith Bodichon (Hirsch, 2000). Yet, although no religious tests were instituted, Girton did hold daily prayers and Sunday services and in 1902 it acquired its own Chapel (Bradbrook, 1969, pp. 3, 62–63). Unlike the University of London, the Oxbridge women’s colleges were residential institutions – a development which had important ramifications for thinking on female education. Residency at Oxbridge – for both male and female undergraduates – was supported by a liberal vision of educating to improve character as well as intellect (Howarth, 1988). The college environment was considered almost, if not as, important as the content of the lectures and tutorials that took place within it. Both Davies and Clough argued that women’s colleges should provide their students with space to develop intellectually, free from the domestic chores and social interruptions that distracted them at home (Davies, 1878, pp. 11–12, 17; Sutherland, 2006, p. 98). Elizabeth Wordsworth, however, was strongly against women’s colleges becoming mere professional institutions, believing that they ought to be kept as small as possible so as to allow for familial intimacy between staff and students. Although LMH and St Hugh’s expanded rapidly in the years following their foundation, they continued to be modelled along the lines of the middle-class home. Annie Moberly, for example, insisted that her college room be treated not as a study but a drawing room, so that, rather than knocking on entering, her students would have to stand around awkwardly, waiting to be noticed (Iremonger, 1956, p. 63). All of the Oxbridge women’s colleges placed severe restrictions on their students’ dress, conduct, movements, and interaction with the opposite sex. Even those reformers with explicitly feminist commitments failed to challenge the extent to which their places of learning reproduced and re-created middle-class femininity.

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

233

Thus, although some of the most radical among them did favour co-education, at least at a primary school level (Malleson, 1874; Wolstenholme, 1869, pp. 325–327; Strachey, 1978, p. 130; Hirsch, 2000, pp. 87–91), most feminists supported single sex education without question.

Conclusion Theories of women’s education in the nineteenth century emerged out of wider discussions on the ‘woman question’, and were shaped by feminists’ re-thinking of gender roles, sexual difference, and the family. Arguments for and against women’s education, and the kind of education they ought to receive, were grounded in debates over sexual difference. While their opponents relied on notions of women’s difference to argue against their receiving an education outside the home, feminists were not united in asserting either women’s intellectual equivalency or equality with men. Some, like Emily Davies and Elizabeth Wolstenholme, did suggest that gendered characteristics were predominantly socially constructed and they therefore championed access to education as the means by which women might free themselves from the debilitating effects of convention. Other feminists, however, such as Josephine Butler and Frances Power Cobbe were more inclined to value ‘feminine’ virtues as the basis for the transformation of society, which the education of women would make possible. Different models of women’s education were thus put forward, and the main area of contention was whether female students ought to compete directly with men by pursuing a ‘male’ course of study, sitting examinations and reading for university degrees. On this question, Girton and Newnham chose different approaches – though the distinction ought not to be over-determined. Support for the first two Cambridge women’s colleges was not mutually exclusive, and their advocates frequently worked together as part of the same reforming networks. Feminist thinking on education, like the Victorian women’s movement at large, reflected and responded to many wider concerns and contemporary political questions. It was imbued with a horror of idleness, and a belief in the value of work, the dignity of economic independence, and individual selfimprovement. And it embraced a liberal vision of education which endorsed institutional socialisation. It was fundamentally determined by the religious controversies of the age and the religious outlooks of its practitioners. The more conservative approach of many of the Oxford women, their ambivalence over demanding women’s formal admission to the university, and their emphasis on teaching ‘feminine’ values of self-sacrifice can therefore more fruitfully be understood in the context of their High Church vision of women’s education. Even the more radical of the educational reformers, however, believed that education also entailed socialisation or a ‘moral’ element, and as a result the women’s colleges both challenged and reproduced dominant ideas of middle-class femininity – without ever rejecting such norms altogether. The feminist campaign for women’s education was a case of ideas and institutions developing in tandem. Though higher education colleges for women

234

Laura Schwartz

reflected the varying visions of their founders, such visions were often themselves the result of pragmatism and compromise. Feminists were responding to the pressing need for professional training and qualifications for middle-class women, and such an imperative encouraged a degree of flexibility in their theorising and a willingness to at least pay lip service to the concerns of their opponents. At the same time, however, all practical efforts to improve the educational opportunities of women had such important implications for their position in society more generally, that more overtly political reverberations could not be avoided. The movement for women’s education was implicated in feminist politics because education during this period was so fundamentally identified with women’s personal, intellectual, emotional, and spiritual emancipation.

Notes 1 By 1913 Wordsworth had come to accept that votes for women were inevitable, though she remained unenthusiastic. 2 A handful of feminist women and radical men were interested in improving workingclass education, establishing the Working Women’s College in London in 1864 staffed by Elizabeth Whitehead Malleson, Clementia Taylor, and Frances Martin, and assisted by John, the husband of women’s rights advocate and London School Board member Alice Westlake; see Levine, 1990; Purvis, 1991. 3 For Non-conformist contributions to secondary education, see Binfield, 1981. 4 E. Wordsworth, Isaiah I–XII (1907–08), Sermon manuscripts, Oxford, St Hugh’s College Archive, XIII.3. 5 Girls were permitted to take these examinations for the first time in 1863.

References Adams, P. (1996) Somerville for women: an Oxford college 1879–1993 (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Battiscombe, G. (1978) Reluctant pioneer: a life of Elizabeth Wordsworth (London, Constable). Beale, D. (1865) The education of girls (Sheffield, National Association for the Promotion of Social Science). Binfield, C. (1981) Belmont’s portias: Victorian nonconformists and middle-class education for girls (Leicester, Friends of Dr William’s Library (Leicester Printers Ltd)). Bodichon, B. L. S. (1857) Women and work (London, Bosworth & Harrison). Bradbrook, M. (1969) ‘That infidel place’: a short history of Girton College 1869–1969 (London, Chatto & Windus). Brittain, V. (1960) The women at Oxford: a fragment of history (London, George G. Harrap). Burgon, J. W. (1884) To educate young women like young men, and with young men – a thing inexpedient and immodest: a sermon preached before the University of Oxford in the chapel of New College on Trinity Sunday (8 June 1884) (Oxford & London, Parker & Co.). Burstyn, J. (1980) Victorian education and the ideal of womanhood (London, Croom Helm). Bush, J. (2005) ‘Special strengths for their own special duties’: women, higher education and gender conservatism in late Victorian Britain, History of Education, 34(4), 387–405.

Feminist thinking on education in Victorian England

235

Butler, J. (1868) The education and employment of women (Liverpool, T. Brakell). Butler, R. G. (1869) Education considered as a profession for women, in: J. Butler (ed.) Woman’s work and woman’s culture (London, Macmillan), 49–77. Caine, B. (1997) English feminism, 1780–1980 (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Cobbe, F. P. (1862) Female education, and how it would be affected by university examinations: a paper read at the Social Science Congress, London, 1862 (3rd edn.) (London, Emily Faithfull). Cott, N. F. (1987) The grounding of modern feminism (New Haven & London, Yale University Press). Davies, E. (1878) Home and the higher education (London, The London Association of Schoolmistresses). Davies, E. (1988, 1st edn. 1866) The higher education of women (London, The Hambledon Press). Delamont, S. (1989) Knowledgeable women: structuralism and the reproduction of elites (London, Routledge). Delap, L. (2005) Feminist and anti-feminist encounters in Edwardian Britain, Historical Research, 78(201), 377–399. Dyhouse, C. (1981) Girls growing up in late Victorian and Edwardian England (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul). Dyhouse, C. (1995) No distinction of sex? Women in British universities, 1870–1939 (London, UCL Press). Fletcher, S. (1980) Feminists and bureaucrats: a study in the development of girls’ education in the nineteenth century (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Gardner, A. (1921) A short history of Newnham College, Cambridge (Cambridge, Bowes & Bowes). Gleadle, K. (1995) The early feminists: radical unitarians and the emergence of the women’s rights movement, 1831–51 (Basingstoke, Macmillan). Glenday, N. & Price, M. (1974) Reluctant revolutionaries: a century of headmistresses, 1874–1974 (London, Pitman Publishing). Griffin, P. (1986) St Hugh’s: One hundred years of women’s education in Oxford (Basingstoke, Macmillan Press). Hamilton, M. A. (1936) Newnham: an informal biography (London, Faber & Faber). Hirsch, P. (2000) Barbara Leigh Smith Bodichon: feminist leader and founder of the first university college for women, in: M. Hilton & P. Hirsch (eds) Practical visionaries: women, education and social progress, 1790–1930 (London, Pearson Education), 84–100. Howarth, J. (1988) Introduction, in: E. Davies (ed.) The higher education of women (London & Ronceverte, Hambledon Press). Howarth, J. & Curthoys, M. (1987) The political economy of women’s higher education in late nineteenth and early twentieth century Britain, Historical Research, 60(142), 208–231. Iremonger, L. (1956) The ghosts of Versailles. Miss Moberly and Miss Jourdain and their adventure: a critical study (London, Faber & Faber). Levine, P. (1987) Victorian feminism, 1850–1900 (London, Hutchinson). Levine, P. (1990) Feminist lives in Victorian England: private roles and public commitment (Oxford, Basil Blackwell). Malleson, M. F. R. (1874) College for men and women with which is incorporated the working women’s college: address upon the opening of the college to men as well as women (London, Kenny & Co).

236

Laura Schwartz

McWilliams-Tullberg, R. (1975) Women at Cambridge: a men’s university though of a mixed type (London, Victor Gollancz). NECHEW (1868) Letters received and read at the meeting of the North of England Council for the Higher Education of Women, Leeds, Wednesday 15 April 1868 (For private circulation) Offen, K. (1988) Defining feminism: a comparative historical approach, Signs, 14(1), 119–157. Pederson, J. S. (1987) The reform of girls’ secondary and higher education in Victorian England: a study of elites and educational change (New York & London, Garland). Phillips, A. (ed.) (1979) A Newnham anthology (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Purvis, J. (1991) A history of women’s education in England (Buckingham, Open University Press). Rogers, A. H. (1938) Degrees by degrees: the story of the admission of Oxford women students to membership of the university (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Sharples (1832, 18 February) The third discourse of the lady of the rotunda, Isis. Strachey, R. (1978, 1st edn. 1928) The cause: a short history of the women’s movement in Great Britain (London, Virago). Sutherland, G. (1987) The movement for the higher education of women: its social and intellectual context in England, c.1840–80, in: P. J. Waller (ed.) Politics and social change in modern Britain: essays presented to A. F. Thompson (Sussex, Harvester), 91–116. Sutherland, G. (1990) The plainest principles of justice: the University of London and the higher education of women, in: F. M. L. Thompson (ed.) The University of London and the world of learning, 1836–1986 (London & Ronceverte, Hambledon Press), 35–56. Sutherland, G. (2000) Anne Jemima Clough & Blanche Athena Clough: creating educational institutions for women, in: P. Hirsch & M. Hilton (eds) Practical visionaries: women, education and social progress, 1790–1930 (London, Pearson Education), 101–114. Sutherland, G. (2006) Faith, duty and the power of the mind: the Cloughs and their circle 1820–1960 (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Taylor, B. (1983) Eve and the new Jerusalem: socialism and feminism in the nineteenth century (London, Virago). Taylor, B. (2005) Mary Wollstonecraft and the feminist imagination (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Tuke, M. J. (1939) A history of Bedford College for women, 1849–1937 (London, Oxford University Press). Watts, R. (1998) Gender, power and the Unitarians in England, 1760–1860 (London & New York, Longman). Wollstonecraft, M. (1989) A vindication of the rights of woman, in: J. Todd & M. Butler (eds) The works of Mary Wollstonecraft (vol. 5) (London, William Pickering), 79–266. Wolstenholme (1869) The education of girls: its present and its future, in: J. Butler (ed.) Woman’s work and woman’s culture (London, Macmillan), 290–330. Wordsworth, C. (1884) Christian womanhood and Christian sovereignty: a sermon (London, Rivingtons). Wordsworth, E. (1894) First principles in women’s education (Oxford, James Parker). Wright, F. (1831) Lecture 1. On the nature of knowledge, in: F. Wright (ed.) Course of popular lectures as delivered by Frances Wright, in New York, Philadelphia, Baltimore, Boston, Cincinnati, St. Louis, Louisville, and other cities, towns and districts of the United States. With three addresses on various public occasions and a reply to the charges against the French reformers of 1789 (4th edn.) (New York, Office of the Free Enquirer, Hall of Science).

16 Idealism and education Andrew Vincent

Introduction Idealist philosophers wrote comparatively little directly on education. Despite this, Idealism, as a more general philosophical movement, including the British, American, German, and Italian kinds, featured a strong interest in education. The comparative paucity of direct reflection can be explained by the fact that the Idealists’ interest in education was integral to their whole philosophy. If one takes a slightly more oblique perspective on education, one can argue that between 1870 and the 1920s (in Britain in particular) there were notable examples of sophisticated educational reflection, as well as, in some cases, direct engagement with educational practices. This article will briefly elucidate the meaning of idealism, then move to a consideration of Idealists’ educational philosophy and their involvement with educational practice. What is Idealism? The first question is: what is Idealism? There are a number of commonplace senses of the term. It can be thought of as corresponding to the conventional sense of ideal, as in perfectionism or utopianism. This sense of idealism might thus be opposed to an ordinary language sense of realism. But the use of idealism in this essay has nothing to do with that sense. It is not referring to ideals or to utopias, but to ideas, and specifically to human consciousness. This is philosophical idealism. Versions of this sense of philosophical idealism are found in ancient Greece, particularly in the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle; but in its current form it was initially influenced largely by the writings of Bishop Berkeley (1685–1753). Berkeley’s subjective idealism also ran alongside some different and much richer variants of idealism, generated in Germany in the writings of, for example, Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) J. G. Fichte (1762– 1814), Friedrich Schelling (1775–1854) and G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831). In Britain (including both Wales and Scotland – we aren’t talking just about Oxford Idealism), it dominated philosophical thinking from the 1870s up to the 1920s. Its key philosophical proponents were figures such as T. H. Green (1836–1882), Edward Caird (1835–1908), Henry Jones (1852–1922), R. B. Haldane

238

Andrew Vincent

(1856–1928), F. H. Bradley (1846–1924), and Bernard Bosanquet (1848– 1923) (Boucher and Vincent 2011). From the 1920s and 1930s – when to a degree it was being abandoned, but by no means refuted, in the academy – Idealism still included such immensely significant figures as R. G. Collingwood (1889–1943) and Michael Oakeshott (1901–1990). It is important to note that Idealism was not one singular movement in Europe or North America. It embodied a wide range of philosophical tendencies, although space does not allow detailed analysis of them to form a substantial part of this essay. There were subtle philosophical divisions between various factions of Idealism, for example, personal idealism and absolute idealism. But if there is one guiding principle of Idealism, in general, it is that reality, all that is and appears, is for and in human consciousness. Thus, the known world cannot be considered independent of a knower. There is no reality, as such, which is antecedent to human consciousness. A natural or material cause could not therefore be antecedent to consciousness. If something is known in any way, it is human consciousness which knows it. There could therefore be no pure natural history of mind. There could be an ‘idea’ that mind has a natural history, but such an idea could not logically be antecedent to the knowing consciousness. To suggest that there is anything, therefore, absolutely outside of consciousness is meaningless verbiage for Idealism.

Idealist philosophical background to education The Idealist conception of education is linked directly to a philosophy of mind. One way to elucidate this is to focus briefly on Hegel. For Hegel, originality and uniqueness in thought do not arise from an intellectual vacuum. The substance of thought has to be assimilated from the past and made one’s own through a process of thoughtful re-enactment. Hegel argued that one could consequently trace in outline the basic thought structures through which the world has actually been configured over human history. The particular individual can therefore progress via the various stages of humanity’s self-apprehension, that is passing in microcosm through the macrocosm of human history and the knowledge that humanity has accrued. Such knowledge becomes, as it were, transparent as it is recapitulated by each generation, particularly via education. According to the British Idealist R. B. Haldane, for example, many misunderstand Hegel, thinking that his work begins with a highly abstract logic and only then moves to human experience. In Haldane’s view Hegel, to the contrary, treats ‘human experience as the source of his quest after what is ultimately real’. Nothing lies outside conscious experience. Consciousness will only perplex us ‘if we insist on making reality stop short at something below consciousness’ (Haldane, 1904, vol I, p. 284). There is no leap from judgement to reality. We should therefore simply refuse to begin from the opposition between consciousness and experience. Reality is the epiphany of consciousness. In this sense one can never escape the circle of thought. Philosophy is, as Haldane put it, quite simply the ‘self-comprehension of mind’ (Haldane, 1904, vol II, p. 148).

Idealism and education 239 Following from this argument, the purpose of the philosophy for Idealism is the same as the purpose of education, namely, making the human mind its own object. The educated individual is one who has assimilated the world conceptually and realises his or her own identity with the most general sense of Mind – that is humanity’s self-apprehension considered as the general structure of human thought. Such an educated individual is at home in the world. It followed for Hegel, for example, that the content of any educational curriculum should be derived from the way the human mind has formed itself over the history of human development through various civilisations. The stages through which Mind has passed provide the formal content of the curriculum. As Hegel comments in the Phenomenology of Spirit: Thus as far as factual information is concerned, we find that what in former ages engaged the attention of men of mature minds, has been reduced to the level of facts, exercises and even games for children; and, in the child’s progress through the school, we shall recognize the history of the cultural development of the world traced, as it were, in a silhouette. (Hegel, 1979, p. 16) Such assimilation is not simply passive, it entails rather an active engagement by the student. Thus, in his second Nuremberg school address, Hegel comments, [I]f learning limited itself to mere receiving, the effect would not be much better that if we wrote sentences of water; for it is not the receiving but the self-activity of comprehension and the power to use it again, that first makes knowledge our possession. (Hegel, 1909, p. 167) In Hegel’s terms knowledge can only come about through a rounded grasp of the sciences of humanity. To think through the detailed material of the various sciences in class re-enacts the active principle of thought itself. A teacher must therefore possess the knowledge themselves thoroughly (within a particular domain) and think it through in front of the class; the pupils must then themselves take on the ‘work of thought’ in order to possess the knowledge as their own. In this process, the rich content of thought can then be assimilated. Hegel’s idea was that his early Philosophical propaedeutic and later Encyclopaedia of the philosophical sciences were premised on the generic formative structures of Mind. The school or early university classes for Hegel are not, though, the place for the singular advancement of knowledge; any such advancement lies farther up the ladder of scholarly learning. The school and university are rather a place to review internally and fully engage with the rich history of human thought. This entails the individual understanding who they are, and developing a sense of at-homeness in the world. A parallel argument can be observed in, for example, T. H. Green’s Prolegomena to ethics. For Green, knowledge of the world and nature does not

240

Andrew Vincent

explain the nature of knowledge. The producer precedes the product. Knowledge of the world, including time and space, exists for the self-conscious human subject, since the concepts of space and time presuppose this subject. Psychological introspection will not tell us about the nature of knowledge, because it also presupposes the conscious subject. There can, therefore, be no experience of the world antecedent to consciousness. Thus, Green maintains that pure sensationalism would be speechless. There may well be an external world, but it could not be external to the conscious subject. Knowledge, as such, in any shape is always mind apprehending itself (Green, 1907). For Green this argument underlined the enormous significance of education in terms of the intellectual and moral development of human beings. These arguments can be illustrated finally in the work of the twentieth century Italian Idealist Giovanni Gentile (1875–1944) – although this expresses a subtly different sense of Idealism. Gentile wrote a number of works on education up to the 1920s, for example, The Reform of education (1923). As Benedetto Croce (1866–1952) noted, it is clear that Gentile saw a close connection between his philosophical writings, such as The theory of mind as pure act, and his understanding of education. Put at its simplest, education was viewed as the process of thought itself, which (as indicated above) is the core of reality for Idealism. Mind is its own creation. All roads converge here for Gentile; nothing is real save mind’s self-creation. Gentile referred to this basic principle as ‘thoughtful thinking’ (pensiero pensante – see Gentile, 1920, pp. 18–19). Nothing therefore has value unless it is resolved within the act of thinking. In this sense there is nothing literally outside of thought. Every act of knowing, speaking or thinking about something apparently external to us, for Gentile, becomes real in the very act of thought. Strictly speaking an outside exists, but only insofar as we think it. Through the activity of thinking and knowing we overcome every form of externality. Gentile’s Idealism is more extreme than Hegel’s, in terms of its stress upon the active role of thought. As Croce comments: As far back as 1900 he [Gentile] published a monograph ... in which he showed that pedagogy in so far as it is philosophical resolves itself without residuum into the philosophy of spirit; for the science of the spirit’s education cannot but be the science of the spirit’s development, - of its dialectics, of its necessity. (Croce, 1923, p. ix) Gentile’s Reform of Education book basically focuses on teachers (in fact it was delivered as a series of lectures to trainee teachers in Trieste). He casts the whole debate about education quite directly onto his philosophic concerns. This has no direct bearing though upon formal training in philosophy; yet, at the same time, it is tied intimately to the philosophical impulse. As Gentile comments, ‘special philosophical training can be effectual only if all education, from its very beginning, wherever that may be, has been philosophic’ (Gentile, 1923, p. 240).

Idealism and education 241 In essence, he contends that all the great philosophical disputes underpin ordinary pedagogic concerns. Consequently all teachers should minimally become aware of, for example, the philosophical implications of naturalism and realism, over and against idealism. Realism makes ‘all reality consist of an external existence’. Naturalism asserts, variously, that ‘nature alone exists’ (Gentile, 1923, p. 73). Idealism asserts, on the contrary, that ‘we discover the impossibility of conceiving a reality which is not the reality of thought itself’ (Gentile, 1923, p. 73). Gentile stresses that all teachers should be aware minimally that reality is ‘this very thought itself by which we think all things’ (Gentile, 1923, p. 74).

The self and education In considering the way education and philosophy share a fundamental commonality, it is important to grasp that Idealists saw the formation of the human self as integral to both. One key idea arises here, namely, self-realization. It is by the critical assimilation of thought that the individual realises herself. Much of Hegel’s argument here is embodied in the German idea of Bildung. Bildung refers to the development of the person from a child (governed by a more instinctive life) towards a rational and ethical stance. The student must gradually sacrifice immediate interests and idiosyncrasies to the systematic demands of social practices and critical thought. The guidance of the individual – particularly towards intellectual concerns – is described by Hegel as a ‘second birth’ (Hegel, 1971, addition p. 126). Each subject in the school and university curriculum expresses consciousness in a certain systematic intellectual shape. These shapes must be critically assimilated and ultimately transcended dialectically. Bildung also indicated for Hegel the growth of the capacity for autonomy within each human being. As Hegel comments, ‘the final purpose of education ... is liberation and the struggle for higher liberation still; education is the absolute transition from an ethical substantiality which is immediate and natural to one which is intellectual and so both infinitely subjective and lofty enough to have attained universality of form’ (Hegel, 1971, p. 125). Individuality is not idiosyncrasy. As Hegel argues, ‘This reshaping of the soul alone is what education means. The more educated a man is, the less is there apparent in his behaviour anything peculiar only to him, anything that is merely contingent’ (Hegel, 1971, addition p. 52). Rational thought becomes habitual and overcomes capriciousness. The final result is the citizen of a civil and ethically sensitive state. There is a broad philosophical theory at work here which relates to the work of both Rousseau and Kant, as well as to Hegel. It can also be observed in the core arguments of British Idealism. Basically all human action is by definition self-realisation. In acting we realise the object we desire. The object is posited by the self as something which will satisfy the desire. The object as such is called a good. The good is located in the realisation of the potentialities of the self. Thus, any action to realise a good, however incomplete that good may be, is a form of self-realisation. ‘Good’ is distinguished by Idealists from ‘true good’ or the ‘real will’. The ‘true good’ is that object which provides the more complete

242

Andrew Vincent

satisfaction. The true good is understood as the realisation of the full potentialities of the self. What we ultimately desire in this context is the self as a more comprehensive universal ethical whole. It follows that the true good can be described as the most complete form of self-realization. For T. H. Green, for example, this true good is equivalent to the common good and this in turn has deep social and political implications. Moral self-realisation is thus willing an object which truly satisfies the self in the most comprehensive ethical manner.

The will and education In the context of self-realization, the will becomes crucially important in both education and philosophy. The will is literally, in Hegel’s terms, ‘thinking translating itself into existence, thinking is the urge to give itself existence’ (Hegel, 1971, p. 4, addition). F. H. Bradley formulates this idea in a similar way. Will is ‘the realization of itself by an idea, an idea ... with which the self here and now is identified’ (Bradley, 1935, pp. 444–445). Bernard Bosanquet gives a crisp rendering of this same idea in an essay entitled ‘The reality of the general will’. For him the individual human mind should be considered as analogous to a machine ‘of which the parts are ideas or groups of ideas, all tending to pass into action’. The will can then be said to consist ‘of those ideas which are guiding attention and action’ (Bosanquet, 1895, p. 322). For Bosanquet, though, certain ideas had a logical and systematic power to govern and focus the contents of the individual mind. Such ideas enabled the individual to grasp and solve a range of problems. Success in coping with problems reinforced the credibility and strength of such ideas and the forms of action which flowed from them. Bosanquet thought that such formative ideas reflected the real necessities of human life. He also maintained that such ideas were largely derived from the tried and tested customary institutions of social and political life itself. They formed ‘the inside which reflect the material action and real conditions that form the outside’ (Bosanquet, 1895, p. 324). The good will, for Bosanquet, was one in which reason and will were united within certain dominant fertile ideas. These ideas ultimately formed the substance of the idea and practice of the general will. The logical sequence of this argument is that each individual will embodies a dominant, reasoned idea. This idea ‘marshals’ and ‘focuses’ the contents of the mind and structures both will and thus actions in concrete ways. Some ideas have a more comprehensive rational capacity to unify the mind. Such ideas are derived ultimately from existing institutional structures of everyday social existence. The general will, in this sense, is analogous to the individual will. The general will consequently embodies those generic creative and dominant ideas of the whole society. In the same manner that the individual marshals the contents of their own consciousness, so the general will represents the marshalling of all the individual wills of civil society as a whole. As Bosanquet put it, the general will is ‘the whole working system of dominant ideas which determines the places and functions of its members’ (Bosanquet, 1895, p. 325). In this reading the

Idealism and education 243 sovereignty of the general will embodies the sovereignty of certain dominant reasonable ideas. Such dominant ideas also figured as the crucial dimension of the good will of each individual. This corresponds again directly to the Idealist theory of citizenship. The good citizen is one who has internalised certain comprehensive dominant ideas – derived from society – within their own self. The good state is the organised body within which such a comprehensive will functions. The above theory also bears very fundamentally on the way individuals act in the world. This in turn has powerful educational implications. Thus, each mode of human experience is wholly dependent on implicit dominant ideas. All human experience bears witness to these organising dominant ideas. Human experience is therefore always through these modes – each implicitly embodying a series of key organising ideas. Such ideas make the experience coherent and functional in the world. Many of these organising ideas often remain inchoate and habitual to those that function within that mode. The education curriculum basically tries to grasp and to communicate the dominant ideas which make the diverse modes of experience cohere in themselves. If the ideas are grasped clearly, and the implicit does becomes explicit, then the individual working in that mode can think and act more effectively and rationally in the world. The educational inference from this argument – broadly – is that all human actions are forms of self-realization and all actions are structured through willing. Willing is dependent upon certain dominant ideas – which assemble the contents of consciousness. It follows that to educate the will by attaining clarity with regard to certain dominant ideas is not only to change the character of the will, but is also to change the consequent actions of individuals. In turn such ideas enunciate psychological and practical changes in the circumstances and everyday life of the individual. The circumstances and environment of an individual are determined by the actions and, as argued, actions are structured by will and thus dominant ideas. Thus to change the will is to change the whole environment of the individual. For Idealism this transformation of the will is perceived to be at the heart of genuine education. Will, not force, is the basis of human development and co-existence. Modes of education It is important to realise that in the Idealist understanding, education functions at a number of levels. Experience, willing, action, cognition, and so forth are (as indicated) all considered educative in terms of the way the person develops and functions within a community. Idealist philosophy is thus as one with the idea of education. We might though, more conventionally, tend to think of education as more closely related to formal institutions such as schools and universities. Whilst not denying this institutional dimension, the Idealists tended to consider it to be multi-faceted. The philosophical background to this is that institutions are never external. They are also, perfectly or imperfectly, the concrete manifestation of ideas and will. To enter into the life of an institution is to become involved with

244

Andrew Vincent

the ideas present within it. Certain institutions, for Idealism, can carry the individual forward, in an educative sense, by affecting will and action. This can be illustrated, in a slightly formulaic manner, by Hegel’s writings. He thinks, for example, of the institution of the family as having a primary educational function. At one level it ensures the mediation of adult sexual desires into an ethical substance (the institution of the family itself) and consequently educates and develops the cognition of young adults. The fact of individual property becoming family property is part of this transformative process. The family also, as importantly, provides a practical and moral basis for the child’s education and ideally ensures that it develops skills necessary to earn its own living. The child’s particular feelings are trained in the family, much of the normative content being unconsciously assimilated via love, trust, and natural feelings. The parent gives the child the matter of their own consciousness, yet the child must begin progressively to take control autonomously of their own life. Ultimately the consciousness of the maturing child supersedes the felt unity of the family. In the school and potentially in the university, ideas and values are more systematically inculcated. In the formal curriculum of the school, the particular character of the child is superseded by the general rationality and rules of the institution. As Hegel puts it ‘the immediacy of the child no longer counts; here it is esteemed only according to its worth ... guided in accordance with universal principles, moulded by instruction according to fixed rules, in general subjected to a universal order’ (Hegel, 1971, p. 61, section 396, addition). For Hegel, the school and university represent universality (in contrast to the particularity of the family). Only when the young adult has a sense of universality can she be free to follow her own interests and seek satisfaction in the social realm – civil society. Civil society looks, at first glance, like another realm of particularity. Initially it is a realm for the satisfaction of individual wants – as in a classic market society. However, the individual in civil society when faced with the arbitrary necessities of making a living has to recast their desires as thought. This raises the individual, at one level, to a formal sense of freedom. The world of necessity places demands on the individual will; this entails rationally giving up youthful ideals. For Hegel, ‘the insight into the rationality of the world, liberates him from mourning over the destruction of his ideals. What is true in these ideals is preserved in the practical activity’ (Hegel, 1971, p. 62, 396, addition). The invisible hand (Adam Smith’s understanding of the market) becomes in Hegel the underlying ‘cunning of reason’ of the social and economic realm. In pursuing my own interests I am forced by necessity to think rationally; I must restrain my interests and become part of a chain of social connections. Ultimately in civil society the individual gradually comes to recognize their dependence on fellow citizens. It is then through participating thoughtfully in the complexity of public institutions that the idea and practice of citizenship develops. This enunciates a more thoughtful understanding of the state. These moments are all profoundly important for Hegel for the all-round education of the human being. The school and the university are just parts of this developmental process.

Idealism and education 245

Brief biography of Idealist educational practice The first Idealist to focus on education was Johann Gottlieb Fichte. Fichte’s Addresses to the German nation makes a strong case for a national system of German education for all citizens. For Fichte, distinctions of class or social status were largely meaningless. Education should be popular, equal, and national. The underlying aim of such education was moral. Education should aim to bring about a moral transformation of society. The education he advocated would be egalitarian and universal. In his own terms it would enable Germany to be moulded into a single national entity and provide deep-rooted motivations to its citizens. His ideas were widely admired by, amongst others, the Prussian minister of Education Baron von Altenstein, who tried to put some of them into practice, particularly the idea of a universalized system of education. Many of the practices of Prussian education – influenced by his writings – became part of the model so much admired over the nineteenth century by such British visitors as Matthew Arnold (1822–1888). Arnold was involved in two Royal Commissions on education in Britain and visited Germany several times for inspiration. The point about Fichte, which was not carried far by Idealists in Britain, was his nationalistic focus. For Fichte, only the Germans as a people can be totally diligent concerning their mental culture. The philosophy of other nations remained inadequate. To think philosophically or poetically in German was to be transfigured and liberated, since one was in immediate contact with one’s nature. Foreigners speaking compound neo-Latinate languages, such as French and English, were cut off from their natures ‘because their life deviated from nature originally and in a matter of the first importance’ (all quotations from Fichte, 1979, 4th Address, 55–84). Despite these nationalistic reflections, the Fichtean model of educational practice – as well as its philosophic and moral underpinnings – served as an inspiration for British Idealist educationalists. Fichte’s shorter works, such as the Vocation of man and the Vocation of the scholar, were particularly admired by British Idealists such as T. H. Green and R. B. Haldane. In summary the important Fichtean ideas were that education should be focused on the all round intellectual and moral development of all citizens. For Fichte this required it to be a central public role of the modern state, that is, to provide universal and equal educational opportunities, in terms of a ladder of learning, for all citizens regardless of their social or financial status. It is necessary, biographically, to correct the popular image of Hegel as the heavy-weight Germanic Professor of Philosophy. From 1795 until 1801 Hegel acted as a private tutor for two families in Berne and then Frankfurt. There was a short spell as a privat-docent in Jena (when he completed his Phenomenology of Spirit), and then the editorship of a Catholic newspaper, the Bamberger Zeitung in 1807. In 1808 his friend Niethammer found him a secure post as Rector of a Gymnasium (or classical school for boys) in Nuremberg. It was here that he wrote his Science of logic (the larger logic). Hegel taught classes in the Gymnasium to boys from the ages of 14 to 19, from 1808 until 1817, when he finally obtained his first secure university post in philosophy at Heidelberg, then

246

Andrew Vincent

moved to Berlin University in 1818, where he worked till his death in 1831. He was thus 45 when he acquired his first full-time salaried university post and he had spent approximately fourteen years instructing children and young adults outside of university. He also drafted his own school curriculum, in the form of a Philosophical propaedeutic, for the Nuremberg Gymnasium. As argued earlier, educational motifs saturate all of Hegel’s writings. Like Fichte he believed in the crucial role of education in intellectually and morally transforming humanity. As he states unequivocally in his Encyclopaedia of the philosophical sciences ‘The Absolute is Mind (Spirit) – this is the supreme definition of the Absolute. To find this definition and to grasp its meaning and burden was ... the ultimate purpose of all education and all philosophy’ (Hegel, 1971, pp. 18–19, section 384). The British Idealist interest in education can be initially illustrated in the ideas and practice of T. H. Green. In 1864 Green was appointed an assistantcommissioner in the Midlands to the Schools Inquiry Commission chaired by Lord Taunton. His main responsibility, until 1866, was to inspect the endowed schools of Warwickshire and Staffordshire and later Buckinghamshire, Leicestershire, and Northamptonshire. The final report of the commission, with Green’s contribution, was published in 1868. The Endowed Schools Act of 1869, however, nowhere lived up to Green’s vision for the Fichtean or Hegelian reconstitution of society through national education (see essays in Green, 1888). After his commission work, Green was elected as a teachers’ representative on the governing body of King Edward’s School in Birmingham. Contrary to many classical liberals, Green and the majority of British Idealists believed intensely in making education universal and compulsory, through the state. Green argued this latter point from the early 1870s and it was finally legislated on by the Liberal government in 1880. Idealists such as Green argued that compulsion did not entail any real encroachment on the liberties of parents. On the contrary, to compel parents to educate their children removed an obstacle to the effective growth of the capacity in the next generation to exercise their rights and freedoms as good citizens. Insofar as compulsion was sensitive to the particular ecclesiastical or other preferences of the parents, there was no interference with the moral duty of the parent. Green argued for a systematic national approach to education which would remove powers from the church and local school boards and establish responsibilities at the level of county school boards, and ultimately the state, for a national educational system. Green also deplored the elitism of universities and their separation from local cities and communities. He argued robustly for extending access to higher education to poorer students and the working classes. With the support of Benjamin Jowett, Balliol Hall – an annex to the main Oxford college – was provided for students with financial difficulties. Green presided over the hall. Green was also a keen supporter of the early University Extension Movement, which began in the 1870s, as well as women’s university education. Green’s authoritative philosophical advocacy had a powerful effect on a number of crucial public figures involved in the structuring of British education in the early twentieth century, certainly up to the 1920s. Key civil servants such as Arthur Acland, R. B. Morant, M. T. Sadler, and

Idealism and education 247 Hubert Llewellyn Smith, among others, were all deeply influenced by Green’s arguments. The most successful British Idealist exponent of education was R. B. Haldane. His most conspicuous work lay in higher education policy (see Vincent, 2007). His first foray was in the Universities in Scotland Bill and the University of London Bill in the 1890s. Haldane, as a senior Liberal politician, became deeply involved with Sidney Webb in the negotiations over the University of London Act. This was to give the University both teaching and examining functions. He was also closely engaged in the establishment of Birkbeck College (University of London) in guiding it through to university status. He remained president of Birkbeck College until his death in 1928. The passing of the University of London Act was followed by a period of fruitful cooperative work with Sidney Webb, and others, in setting up the London School of Economics and Political Science. It is unlikely that it would have seen the light of day so soon without Haldane’s detailed networking assistance (see Logan, 1960). He also became obsessed – like many precursors in the nineteenth century – with the German educational structures, particularly the Technische Hochshule system. This was based upon his visits to one particularly famous institution in Germany in Charlottenburg, and became a theme of many of his speeches. He regularly campaigned on the need for a ‘London Charlottenburg for South Kensington’. Although it did not come to fruition for a number of years, it eventually (again with his direct assistance) was established as the Imperial College of Science and Technology. In the early 1900s, Haldane became deeply involved in the establishment of civic universities across Britain. He engaged in direct advocacy before the Privy Council in 1903 for the Royal Charters for Liverpool and Manchester. He mediated between warring factions over a number of years in virtually all the early key civic university debates of this period. Part of his authority and impact was due to the fact that he chaired two key Royal Commissions, on University and Higher Education development in London (1909–13) and in Wales (1916– 18). He was also a close friend of the deeply influential civil servant, R. B. Morant, Permanent Secretary of the Board of Education. Apart from a wide range of public speeches on this theme, a great deal of his influence was also exercised subtly through behind the scenes manoeuvring, networking, and sophisticated lobbying. As a result of his direct intervention, campaigning, and advocacy, the civic Universities of Liverpool, Birmingham, Leeds, Bristol, Nottingham, Southampton, and Sheffield were all established with their own Charters – these were closely followed by the Welsh Universities and the University of Reading. Haldane became, for a time, the first Vice Chancellor of the new civic University of Bristol. After the First World War, he was again a more restrained, but nonetheless influential, background figure behind the 1918 Fisher Education Act. Herbert Fisher himself was also a profound admirer of the German system – as well as the work of T. H. Green. Haldane was also directly involved in the creation of the British University Grants Committee (UGC) which functioned until the 1980s – the initial idea for the UGC had been

248

Andrew Vincent

aired by a committee Haldane chaired in 1904. In sum, as one scholarly text notes, Haldane’s achievement lay ‘in the foundations of our [the British] whole system of education ... It was Haldane who, patiently over decades, created in the public mind and among politicians a consciousness of the need for quality and balance in education’ (Ashby & Anderson, 1974, p. 173). Another example of such practice was the work of the British Idealist philosopher Henry Jones (see Boucher & Vincent, 1993). Jones was one of the key Commissioners on University Education in Wales, prior to the First World War. He was instrumental in setting up the so-called ‘penny rate scheme’ for Wales, that is, helping (in aim) to abolish university fees, such as to allow ordinary working men and women to enter into university education. It was a scheme subsequently adopted by many counties in England. University education, however, had to be integrated (as Green and Haldane argued) into a comprehensive national policy, making education at all levels free and available universally for all. Jones was a passionate supporter of the federal principle in the University of Wales, and when in Australia he campaigned for the establishment of a new University in Brisbane. He was in harmony with the desire amongst Australian Idealists, such as William Mitchell (1861–1962) in Adelaide and Francis Anderson (1858–1941) in Sydney, to expand the educational system in a similar manner to Britain. As with T. H. Green there was a general belief in the capacity of education as the great social leveller in society, delivering equal opportunities, if not equal outcomes. That is, the role of education was part of the more general ‘enabling role’ of the Idealist conception of the state. Jones, like his mentor Edward Caird, as well as his friend Haldane, was also deeply involved in extra-mural teaching as well as in the Workers’ Educational Association. It is worth noting that virtually all the pre-1920 generation of British Idealists (with the exception of F. H. Bradley) were eager to extend educational opportunities universally, supporting the University Extension Movement, ethical societies, and later the Workers’ Educational Association. This educational belief included a mix of both state and voluntary-based organisations (see Gordon & White, 1979). Many of the Idealist writers, such as Haldane, also advocated the raising of the school leaving age, the national development of secondary schools, positive inducements for students to pass onto higher education or technical institutions, and the extensive development of technical colleges. Many such reforms did not come to fruition till later in the twentieth century. However Haldane, like Green and others, viewed this whole process in terms of advancing the cause of ethical citizenship. The most controversial of the twentieth century Idealists is Giovanni Gentile. The problem for many is that Gentile was Minister of Instruction in Mussolini’s first government between 1922–23. He was not only, with Croce, one of the foremost Italian philosophers at the time, but more significantly for posterity, he was also a committed Fascist (assassinated at the closing stages of that regime). However his ideas on education precede his involvement in Fascism, and relate much more explicitly to his Idealist philosophy. In his official position he instituted a broad-ranging reform of the Italian school system, which, in the words of one

Idealism and education 249 recent commentator was ‘a reform that long remained, and in part still is, the foundation of the Italian school system’ (Turi, 1998, p. 914). Even Croce remarked, we owe it to Gentile that Italian pedagogy has attained in the present day a simplicity and a depth of concepts unknown elsewhere. ... And this ... is due pre-eminently to the work of Gentile. His authority therefore is powerfully felt in schools of all grades. (Croce, 1923, p. ix) Gentile’s reputation was, though, clearly blighted by Fascism, despite the fact that the core of his curriculum reforms survived into the late twentieth century.

British Idealism and education For British Idealism it was clear that education was not isolated from the rest of social policy. The purpose of both social existence and education in general was to enable human capacities and provide opportunities for individual selfrealisation. In this sense, education permeated all aspects of society, and no feature of it (from family to state) could absolve itself of the responsibility to remove the obstacles to the equal cultivation of ethical citizenship. The British Idealists’ idea of education was viewed as an intrinsic part of the philosophical enterprise, linked with a more general understanding of human nature and its potential for development. It was an egalitarian principle oriented to equality of opportunity for all citizens, aiming to establish the groundwork for ethical citizenship. The state had a crucial role to play here. Idealism was impatient of individualistic liberal theories which tried to play down to the role of the state in human affairs. Rather, it was the positive duty of the state to establish a national education system, from primary to university level, which, at many points, would be legally compulsory. Although offering little immediate advice on the technicalities of day-to-day teaching, it offered an overarching ethical vision of education. There were clearly, as indicated, a variety of linked senses of education at work. First, it was premised on a collection of sciences which require communication and instruction in schools and universities. Knowledge was embodied abstractly in all the various disciplines, with the one proviso that in the final analysis all the sciences found their unity and were resolved in a philosophical position. There was, in other words, a systematic connection between all the various sciences or disciplines, which formed a coherent systematic unity of mind. More substantively, Idealists also believed that the whole process of formal education itself was intrinsically philosophic, concerned with the act of thinking and thus the life of mind. This philosophic process was linked to the overall ethical development of the individual person; more significantly it was an essential prerequisite for the advance of genuine citizenship of a modern state. Overall, education was seen to facilitate the absorption of deep organising ethical ideas, enabling individuals not only to take more effective control of their

250

Andrew Vincent

own lives, but also to find common ground with their fellow citizens. The assimilation of civilising capacious ideas meant that individuals could also be freed ‘from the depressing effect of circumstance for which they were not responsible’ (Haldane, 1929, p. 301). For Haldane, higher education in particular, in major civic centres, was viewed as generating a reflective unity of ideas within major cities (see Haldane, 1929, p. 140). This is one intellectual – oft-forgotten – root to the very idea of the ‘civic university’. Universities would not just be centres of research and training, but also rational opinion-formers in local communities, bringing the grand formative, if often implicit, ideas into everyday civic practice. As Haldane argued, in an address to students, ‘nothing is so expansive as the train of thought suggested by an idea that is really great’, in effect, it ‘transforms the whole outlook’. All significant higher level teaching should be guiding individuals to this ‘large outlook’ (Haldane, 1910, pp. 13–14). He thus described universities, in this context, as the brain and intelligence of the educational system, permeating ideas to all other educational institutions. By the end of the nineteenth century, Idealism had taken deep root in British society because it fulfilled a number of social purposes. The consequences of rapid industrialisation and the expansion of world trade caused immense social and personal dislocation and degradation for certain sectors of society. Idealism was not merely a philosophical movement, but primarily a reforming force. It counterbalanced the individualism of classical liberalism, offering a philosophy that emphasised social cohesiveness, social justice, and equality of opportunity. It was a philosophy that emphasised social responsibility through the greatest of all social levellers, access to education for all. Further it was an intensely moralistic philosophy. It condemned everything which impeded self-realisation, that is, the realisation of what is potential in oneself as a moral and reasonable being. The role of the state in all this was to ensure that the obstacles to self-realisation were removed. While most were committed liberals, Idealists also advocated the ‘right’ kind of socialism, which eschewed class antagonism and emphasised social responsibility. The criterion of the extension of state activity always had to be the enabling of citizens to attain greater freedom. Compulsory education did not diminish freedom of choice but actually enhanced the capacity of individuals to develop their talents. British Idealism emphasised both the responsibilities of individuals to seize the opportunities to make themselves more virtuous, and of the owners of private industry to act responsibly by transforming their workshops from schools of vice into schools of virtue. Idealism, in general, was a philosophy that conveyed optimism about human capabilities. It acted as a profound interrogation, critique, and metaphysical counterbalance to the doctrines such as market-based liberalism and utilitarianism. It offered a philosophy that gave an emphasis to social cohesiveness and to the closeness of the relation between individual and collective responsibility. Its highlighting particularly of the importance of active social citizenship subsequently became an important theme in early twentieth-century welfare theory. In this sense, Idealism was a ‘working educational philosophy’ which for a significant moment in British cultural history set the course of moral and political thinking

Idealism and education 251 and delivered a resounding, if nonetheless temporary, refutation of the individualistic ethos.

References Ashby, E. & Anderson, M. (1974) Portrait of Haldane at work on education (London, Macmillan). Bosanquet, B. (1895) Reality of the general will, in: B. Bosanquet (ed.) Aspects of the social problem (London, Macmillan). Boucher, D. & Vincent, A. (1993) A radical Hegelian: the social and political philosophy of Henry Jones (New York, St Martin’s Press). Boucher, D., Vincent, A. (2011) British idealism: a guide for the perplexed (London & New York, Continuum Press). Bradley, F. H. (1935) Collected essays vol. 1 (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Croce, B. (1923) Introduction, in: G. Gentile, The reform of education. Fichte, J. G. [1808] (1979) Addresses to the German nation (trans. R. F. Jones & G. H. Turnbull) (Westport, CT, Greenwood Press). Gentile, G. (1920) The theory of mind as pure act (trans. W. Carr) (London, Macmillan). Gentile, G. (1923) The reform of education (trans. D. Bigongiari, introduction by B. Croce) (London, Benn Brothers). George, M. & Vincent, A. (1982) Development and self-identity: Hegel’s concept of education, Educational Theory, 32, 131–141. Gordon, P. & White, J. (1979) Philosophers as educational reformers: the influence of idealism on British educational thought and practice (London, Routledge). Green, T. H. (1888) The works of T. H. Green vol. 3 (London, Longmans, Green). Green, T. H. (1907) Prolegomena to ethics (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Haldane, R. B. (1904) The Pathway to Reality, vols 1 & 2 (London: John Murray). Haldane, R. B. (1910) Universities and national life: three addresses to students (London, John Murray). Haldane, R. B. (1914) The conduct of life (London, John Murray). Haldane, R. B. (1929) An autobiography (London, Hodder & Stoughton). Hegel, G. W. F. [1807] (1979) The phenomenology of spirit (trans A.V. Miller) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Hegel, G. W. F. (1909) Second school address, in: M. Mackenzie, Hegel’s educational theory and practice (London, Swan Sonnenschein). Hegel, G. W. F. [1817] (1971) Philosophy of mind, Part 3 of the encyclopeadia of the philosophical sciences (trans. W. Wallace) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Hegel, G. W. F. (1986) The philosophical propaedeutic (eds. M. George & A. Vincent, trans. A. V. Miller) (Oxford, Blackwell). Hegel, G. W. F. [1821] (1991) The philosophy of right (trans. T. M. Knox) (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Logan, Sir Douglas (1960) Haldane and the University of London (Haldane Memorial Lecture) (London, University of London). Mackenzie, M. (1909) Hegel’s educational theory and practice (London, Swan Sonnenschein). Turi, G. (1998) Oblivion, remembrance, and criticism, The Journal of Modern History, 70, 913–933. Vincent, A. (2007) German philosophy and British public policy: Richard Burdon Haldane in theory and practice, Journal of the History of Ideas, 68, 157–179.

17 ‘Affection in Education’ Edward Carpenter, John Addington Symonds, and the politics of Greek love Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke In an essay on ‘Affection in Education’ published in the 1899 volume of the International Journal of Ethics, Edward Carpenter defended the utility for personal development of strong same-sex attachments that might ‘sometimes take quite intense and romantic forms’, either between older boys and younger boys in the same school, or between teachers and their pupils. Since ‘it is beginning to be seen that the affections have an immense deal to say in the building up of the brain and the body’, he declared, the ‘evolution and organization’ of the affections was ‘probably going to become an important part of school management’ (Carpenter, 1899, pp. 482–483). Such relationships between schoolboys, Carpenter argued, were beneficial on both sides. ‘The younger boy looks on the other as a hero’, ‘thrills with pleasure at his words of praise or kindness’, and ‘contracts habits’ from him, while the ‘elder one, touched, becomes protector and helper; the unselfish side of his nature is drawn out, and he develops a real affection and tenderness towards the younger’. Similarly affectionate relationships between pupils and their teachers could also be valuable for the former. Carpenter described the case of ‘rather a wild, “naughty” boy’ of eleven or twelve who had ‘given his parents (working-class folk) a good deal of trouble’, but who came to feel ‘the strongest affection’ for his teacher at ‘some sort of night-school or evening class’, with ‘most favorable’ results for his development (p. 484). The ‘unformed mind’, Carpenter remarked, ‘requires an ideal of itself, as it were, to which it can cling or towards which it can grow’; and whether things turned out well ‘depend immensely on the character of the elder one, on the self-restraint and tenderness of which he is capable, and on the ideal of life which he has in his mind’ (p. 485). Having sketched the kinds of relationship he was keen to champion, Carpenter then turned his attention to the actually-existing public schools (in the British sense of that term) of his time. ‘So far from friendship being an institution whose value is recognized and understood’, he wrote, ‘it is at best hardly acknowledged, and is often actually discountenanced and misunderstood’. The ‘disease of premature sexuality seems to have got possession of our centres of education’, such that ‘wretched practices and habits abound’ that ‘cloud and degrade the boys’ conception of what true love or friendship may be’ (p. 486). He described

‘Affection in Education’

253

one ‘well-known school’ as ‘a stew of uncleanness’: ‘There was plenty of incontinence, not much cruelty, no end of dirty conversation, and a great deal of genuine affection, even to heroism, shown among the boys in their relations with one another’. Yet ‘all these things were treated by masters and boys alike as more or less unholy’, and a ‘kiss was by comparison as unclean as the act of fellatio, and no one had any gauge or principle whatever on which to guide the cravings of boyhood’ (pp. 486–487). In such an atmosphere, the ‘big boys in such places become either coarse and licentious or hard and self-righteous’ the ‘small boys’ become the ‘odious little wretches, the favorites, the petted boys, and the “spoons” of the school’, and with the passage of time, the ‘public opinion of the school ceases to believe in the possibility of a healthy friendship; the masters begin to presume (and not without reason) that all affection means sensual practices, and end by doing their best to discourage it’ (p. 487). In the closing pages, Carpenter broached the question of what might be done about such a state of affairs. ‘Masters wage war against incontinence, and are right to do so’, for to ‘prolong the period of continence in a boy’s life is to prolong the period of growth’. Their methods, however – above all ‘grim silence and fury’ – were counter-productive (pp. 490, 487). There was some place for ‘rudimentary teaching on sex’ and ‘lessons of anatomy and physiology’ in the schools, but the main vehicle for moral improvement would have to be the cultivation of ‘very close and tender confidences between the elder and the younger’. The ‘need of attachment’ must ‘be met by full recognition of it, and the granting of it expression within all reasonable limits; by the dissemination of a good ideal of friendship and the enlistment of it on the side of manliness and temperance’. The schools, he hoped, ‘will in time recognize comradeship as a regular institution – considerably more important, say, than “fagging” – an institution having its definite place in the school life’, such that it might ‘inspire its members with the two qualities of heroism and tenderness, which together form the basis of all great character’ (pp. 491–492). When the essay was republished in 1908 in his collection of essays called The intermediate sex, Carpenter here added the thought that the public schools were too large to be suitably reformed, and were in any case ‘hampered by powerful traditions which naturally make them conservative’. Rather, he looked to smaller schools, ‘say of from 50 to 100 boys’, in which the ‘personal influence of the headmaster will be a real force reaching each boy’ (Carpenter, 1908a, pp. 95–96). In closing, he noted that although his ‘remarks in this paper have chiefly had reference to boys’ schools’, they nevertheless broadly applied to girls’ schools as well, ‘where much the same troubles prevail’, the difference being that friendships ‘instead of being repressed are rather encouraged by public opinion’, and the problem being that ‘they are for the most part friendships of a weak and sentimental turn, and not very healthy either in themselves or in the habits they lead to’. ‘Possibly’, Carpenter concluded, ‘the co-education of boys and girls may be of use in making boys less ashamed of their feelings, and girls more healthy in the expression of them’ (Carpenter, 1899, p. 493).

254

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

This would all appear to place Carpenter among the group of adherents to what we might call ‘Socratic pederasty’, a model which is now well established in the discourse of same-sex love in nineteenth-century England. In her 1994 book Hellenism and homosexuality, for example, Linda Dowling – whose analytic framework we employ throughout this paper, even as we call into question some of her particular judgements and interpretations – described the role played by Greek ideals of male friendship and affection in the Oxford University reform movement of the 1850s and 1860s, establishing ‘the grounds on which, after its shorter-term construction as a nineteenth-century sexual pathology (KrafftEbing, Havelock Ellis), “homosexuality” would subsequently emerge as the locus of sexual identity for which, today, such late-Victorian figures as Walter Pater and Oscar Wilde are so often claimed as symbolic precursors’. Victorian liberals saw Britain as in some senses historically equivalent to Classical Athens – though they stressed its ideas of liberty and individualism rather than its love of democracy. And, like Athenian democracy, Athenian pederasty – in the sense of a widespread culture of sexual relationships between older and younger men – was usually elided in the Victorian version. But, according to Dowling, Victorian Hellenism turned out to be a kind of Trojan horse. In the wake of the work of Benjamin Jowett and the other university reformers – who sought to ‘reintegrate Oxford into the national life’, pursuing a vision of a more open university, less socially and religiously exclusive, with higher intellectual standards among both students and college fellows – ‘Pater and Wilde and the Uranian poets could not be denied the means of developing out of this same Hellenism a homosexual counterdiscourse able to justify male love in ideal or transcendental terms’ (Dowling, 1994, pp. xiii, 62–65). The aesthetic conception of same-sex affection these writers disseminated, as Dowling repeatedly observes, was based on Plato’s ‘Socratic eros’, the idea proposed by Socrates – see especially Symposium 209a (Plato, 1999, p. 46) – that men who love youths procreate not bodies but ideas, as the love of beauty and virtue in an individual leads to the love of all beautiful and virtuous people and things, and to an appreciation of the philosophical idea of the beautiful and the good. This eros, for Socrates, originates in sexual desire but completely transcends it, and the Victorian version of this position – at least the public version – was summed up most famously by Oscar Wilde at his trial in 1895. When asked what Lord Alfred Douglas had meant in his poem ‘Two Loves’ by the phrase, ‘The Love that dare not speak its name’ (Douglas, 1894), in what was a precarious legal situation for Wilde in which he faced strong incentives to deny any sexual dimension to his own same-sex affections, he replied in these stirring terms: ‘The Love that dare not speak its name’ in this country is such a great affection of an elder for a younger man as there was between David and Jonathan, such as Plato made the very basis of his philosophy, and such as you find in the sonnets of Michelangelo and Shakespeare. It is that deep, spiritual affection that is as pure as it is perfect ... It is in this century misunderstood, so much

‘Affection in Education’

255

misunderstood that it may be described as the ‘Love that dare not speak its name’, and on account of it I am placed where I am now. It is beautiful, it is fine, it is the noblest form of affection. There is nothing unnatural about it. It is intellectual, and it repeatedly exists between an elder and a younger man, when the elder man has intellect, and the younger man has all the joy, hope and glamour of life before him. That it should be so, the world does not understand. The world mocks at it and sometimes puts one in the pillory for it. (Wilde, 1895) Set against this backdrop, it could appear straightforward to classify Carpenter’s ‘Affection in Education’ as a prime example of an essay defending this kind of Hellenism and applying its insights to the specific question of school reform. And, indeed, the relevant chronology might seem to support such a reading. Although ‘Affection in Education’ was first published in 1899, it was written a few years earlier (Rowbotham, 2009, p. 200), thus placing it squarely in the company of the various essays on love and gender relations that Carpenter had published in 1896 as Love’s coming of age (Carpenter, 1896). He had also originally intended to include in that collection an additional essay on Homogenic love, and its place in a free society, also written around the same time as the others, but in the end this was not included precisely owing to the public scandal surrounding the Wilde trial (Rowbotham, 2009, pp. 194–195). Instead, Homogenic love was privately circulated in pamphlet form and, over a decade later, included in an updated and somewhat censored version in another collection of essays, The intermediate sex (Carpenter, 1894, 1908b). The argument we seek to develop in this essay, however, is that to read Carpenter chiefly as an exponent of Dowling’s ‘counterdiscourse’ within Oxford Hellenism and as some kind of ally of Wilde would be a simplification that would threaten a misunderstanding. Wilde’s ‘Love that dare not speak its name’ was indeed a classic statement of the ideals of this Hellenism, articulating an aristocratic, individualist, philosophical, idealist, and spiritual model of same-sex love, one that rested on a Platonic ideal of chaste affection between an older and a younger man with the goal of intellectual development. But, for its critics – such as John Addington Symonds and, as we will contend, also Edward Carpenter – this was a censored version of Socrates’ eros. It was not as censored perhaps as Jowett’s, which saw marriage between a man and a woman as an appropriate modern analogy (Dowling, 1994, p. 74), but it was still one which did not confront the more explicitly sexual aspects of Platonic love, let alone the historical ones of Greek love. It was also a deeply elitist construction of erotic practice. This new elite concerned was very visible. In 1881 Gilbert and Sullivan’s operetta Patience caricatured its distinctive lifestyle, views and sexuality, including attachments a la Plato, as did W. H. Mallock’s 1877 satire on Oxford life, The new republic (Gilbert, 1881; Mallock, 1882) – and these interventions from more traditional elitists did not prevent Oxford undergraduates adopting the aesthetic lifestyle with gusto, taking Mallock as their primer (Dowling, 1994,

256

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

pp. 111–112). But if it is true, as Dowling says, that Greek studies operated as a ‘homosexual code’ among late Victorian aesthetic liberals (p. xiii), we suggest that it is also true that Greek love operated as an aristocratic code, as one way of clinging on to cultural status and difference in a rapidly homogenising and democratising time. What Carpenter called ‘homogenic love’, by contrast, was principally inspired by John Addington Symonds’ sharp reaction against the Oxford aesthetes, offering a more martial, democratic, physical, and communitarian model of ‘comrade-love’ that would find expression in a sexual relationship between equals and which aimed – at least in Carpenter’s version – at social and political improvement. So, in what follows, we will consider first Symonds, then Carpenter’s Homogenic love, and then we will turn our attention back to ‘Affection in Education’ once again towards the end. John Addington Symonds was born in October 1840 in Bristol, the son of a well-connected doctor, and educated unhappily at Harrow and then at Balliol College, Oxford. As Phyllis Grosskurth says in her biography, he has usually been remembered ‘as a late nineteenth-century aesthete, a minor Pater perhaps’ (Grosskurth, 1964, p. ix). He was a man of many letters, known for his bad poetry and for his good essays. In 1873 he published his Studies of the Greek poets, which included the first serious published discussion in English of homosexuality either Greek or modern. Symonds’ chapter led to his enforced withdrawal from the election for the Oxford Poetry Professorship of 1877, and Symonds himself left England, to live principally thereafter in Switzerland and Venice. Alongside his project on the Greek poets he had written a more extensive essay on Greek homosexuality called ‘A Problem in Greek Ethics’, which he eventually published anonymously in ten copies for private circulation in 1883 (Symonds, 1901, Preface). This work later formed the basis for a section of the work on Sexual inversion that he co-wrote with Havelock Ellis, and which was published after his death. In the meantime, in 1891, he published a second essay on homosexuality, ‘A Problem in Modern Ethics’, this time summarising and criticising more recent explanations and defences. Finally, in 1892, he published an essay on ‘The Dantesque and Platonic Ideals of Love’, a sceptical examination of representations of chaste and idealistic love in Greek philosophy and Italian chivalry. Dowling has claimed him wholeheartedly for her Oxford Hellenist counterdiscourse: This is precisely the context in which such writers as Symonds and Pater would come to assert, in all seriousness, that the Socratic eros was essential to the survival of liberal England. For this erotic bond represented to them a pure form of intellectual procreancy and regeneration, the two men insisting on the truth and genuine Victorian relevance of Plato’s famous teaching in Symposium 209 that at the highest level of masculine love, men who love men are procreating ideas – generating the creative arts, philosophy, ‘wisdom and all her sister virtues,’ especially that kind of wisdom ‘which governs the ordering of society’. (Dowling, 1994, p. 80)

‘Affection in Education’

257

But in making this claim she passes over his later, more nuanced and contrarian work which outlined his disillusion with the ideal of Platonic affection in favour of his earlier idealistic work, including even his undergraduate essays. She quotes his famous recollection in his memoirs that he ‘stumbled upon’ the Phaedrus and the Symposium in his final year at Harrow and therein ‘discovered the true liber amoris at last, the revelation I had been waiting for ... It was just as though the voice of my own soul spoke to me through Plato, as though in some antenatal experience I had lived the life of [a] philosophical Greek lover’ (Grosskurth, 1984, p. 99; Dowling, 1994, p. 67). She notes that when he arrived in Oxford John Conington, the Corpus Professor of Latin, gave him William Johnson’s 1858 collection of poetry Ionica, which contained, as she puts it, an ‘Arcadian world of friendship and chaste affection’ and which, as Symonds recalled, ‘went straight to my heart and inflamed my imagination’ (Dowling, 1994, pp. 86–87, quoting Grosskurth, 1984, p. 109). This does indeed place him, as an undergraduate, right at the heart of Oxford aestheticism and its love of Socratic lovers. But, like most undergraduates, his views changed. As far as the Greeks were concerned, Symonds moved far beyond the views of Pater. He took a much broader and more historicised view of Greek sexuality than their depiction of a pederastic ‘Socratic eros’. Instead of encouraging identification with the Greeks, or advocating the straightforward recreation of Greek culture in Victorian England, he was well aware of the cultural specificity of Greek love. In ‘A Problem in Greek Ethics’, Symonds explained that paiderastia was unknown to Homer (Symonds, 1901, p. 28), but appeared among the Greeks after the heroic age in two forms. In the first, ‘chivalrous and martial form’ – and here Symonds’ description of institutionalised sexual relationships between males in Dorian states, such as Sparta, drew substantially on Karl Müller’s groundbreaking German study of the Dorians, which had been translated into English in 1830 but then politely ignored – an older ‘Inspirer’ handed down heroic traditions to a younger ‘Hearer’, with whom his bond was essentially educational and military rather than sensual or lustful, although it was nonetheless physical – everything except ‘outrage’ (stuprum) was allowed (Müller, 1830, vol. 2, pp. 306–313; Symonds, 1901, pp. 30, 13–14; Dowling, 1994, p. 79). There was then also a sensual and lustful form of ‘boy-love’ which first appeared in Crete – an import perhaps from oriental Phoenicia, but if so, one that quickly acquired Hellenic characteristics, received religious sanction, and spread far and wide (Symonds, 1901, pp. 30, 17–20, 60, 5). Just as Achilles and Patroclus had become – after Homer – the ideal-typical heroic lovers, Ganymede became the focal point for this kind of boy-love (p. 6). These two forms of masculine passion – the noble and the base, the spiritual and the sensual – were the antecedents of ‘that mixed form of paiderastia upon which the Greeks prided themselves’ (p. 8), which drew its ‘military and enthusiastic elements’ from the Dorian immigration into Greece, while its ‘refinements of sensuality and sanctified impurity are referable to contact with Phoenician civilization’, both aspects having been organised and moulded by the Hellenic spirit (p. 18). This state of affairs arose, apparently, because ‘gymnastic exercises

258

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

tended to encourage and confirm the habit of paiderastia’ (pp. 40, 61–62) and the martial mentality made the production of future soldiers the major reason for marriage (pp. 62–63). Nonetheless, the majority of Greek men were still more ‘susceptible’ to women; boy-love ‘distinguished warriors, gymnasts, poets, and philosophers from the common multitude’ (p. 67; see also Dowling, 1994, pp. 29–31). One thing on which Symonds agreed with the other Oxford aesthetes was that Greek love was pederastic, involving relationships between older and younger men. Indeed, he pinpointed male adolescence as the crucial and most attractive stage of life for the Greeks: ‘In the bloom of adolescence the elements of feminine grace, suggested rather than expressed, are combined with virility to produce a perfection which is lacking to the mature and adult excellence of either sex’ (Symonds, 1901, pp. 68–69). Unlike the other Hellenists, however, he contended that it was also physical, and he even contended that the Dorian martial love of Achilles and Patroclus ‘by no means excluded the ordinary sexual feelings’ (p. 3). Symonds, in short, was attempting to understand the Greeks as they were historically, rather than as Plato portrayed them. Not only did Symonds look to history rather than philosophy for his Hellenism, he also came explicitly to reject the philosophical ideal of the Socratic eros (Symonds, 1901, p. 48). He described it as an attempt by Socrates ‘to reform and to ennoble paiderastia’ (Symonds, 1901, p. 50) by modifying the practical educational function of the Dorian martial model into a philosophical one, in which passionate friends sought ‘to advance in knowledge, self-restraint, and intellectual illumination’ (p. 51; also Symonds, 1893, p. 69). But he decided that Socrates failed, and that this transcendental conception, like that of chivalric love, veiled a physical reality that, in the essay on the ‘Dantesque and Platonic Ideals of Love’, he said included ‘social evils of the gravest kind’ (p. 78). Furthermore, the ‘philosophical ideal of paiderastia ... met with little but contempt ... Like his republic, his love existed only in heaven’ (Symonds, 1901, p. 55) ‘There is’, he remarked in both of his treatments of this subject, ‘a deeply rooted mysticism, an impenetrable Soofyism, in the Socratic doctrine of Erôs’ (Symonds, 1893, p. 71; 1901, p. 52). Symonds’ stand against the Socratic eros was not only based on its implausibility and mysticism, but also on its political undesirability. On his account, this version of Greek love could not ‘have anything to do with those connections profitable to the State and useful to society, which involve the procreation and rearing of children, domestic cares, and the commonplace of daily duties’ (Symonds, 1893, p. 76). The more historically realistic version of Greek love, however, could provide such a positive social example: the Greeks gave us the example ‘alone in history ... of a great and highly-developed race not only tolerating homosexual passions, but deeming them of spiritual value, and attempting to utilise them for the benefit of society’ (Symonds, 1901, p. 1). In the laws and customs governing ‘Dorian love’, ‘we discern the intention of promoting a martial spirit in the population, securing a manly education for the young, and binding the male members of the nation together by bonds of mutual affection’ (Symonds, 1893, p. 63). This had practical consequences: ‘Nearly every city had

‘Affection in Education’

259

some tale to tell of emancipation from tyranny, of prudent legislation, or of heroic achievements in war, inspired by the erotic enthusiasm’ (p. 64). As Dowling has noted, the resulting picture was, among other things, a stand against a civic republican intellectual tradition which identified the health of the state with virtue, virility and a warrior ideal, and had long identified love between men with effeminacy and weakness (Dowling, 1994, p. xv). Symonds turned the language of corruption and effeminacy around. For him, Greek love was ‘the very fountain of civic health’ rather than a source of corruption and decay (Symonds, 1893, p. 64; see also Symonds, 1901, pp. 3, 8, 51), just as, he wrote in ‘A Problem in Modern Ethics’, the ‘fighting peoples of the world’, from the Turks to the Tartars, ‘have been distinguished by the frequency among them of what popular prejudice regards as an effeminate vice’ (Symonds, 1896, p. 109). For Symonds, then, there was a political and social point to Greek love, at least in its best and most martial incarnation. He did not, however, pursue this theme further in his account of the problem in modern ethics. Rather, this late work presented suggestions for legal reform, as well as a sympathetic account of the views of the mid-nineteenth century German lawyer and writer Karl-Heinrich Ulrichs for English readers (Weeks, 1990, p. 54). Ulrichs took the view that modern ‘Urnings’ – he took the word from Plato’s distinction between Aphrodite, daughter of Dione, the goddess of earthly love, and Aphrodite Urania, the goddess of heavenly love, who had no mother – were the result of an anomalous development of the embryo in the womb, where although the genitals develop male or female characteristics, a matching differentiation in the part of the brain determining sex drives fails to take place. The result was an anima muliebris virile corpore inclusa – a harmless variation rather than a defect (Weeks, 1990, p. 27). Debate over the innate and acquired versions of ‘inversion’ had been raging on the Continent for some time, and although Ulrichs’ notion of a third or intermediate sex was influential, it had played no real part in the writings of the aesthetes, for whom the love of boys and young men seems to have been understood as a positive choice, and as a behaviour rather than an ingrained preference. For Symonds, as for Ulrichs, a sexual preference for other males was, by contrast, usually innate and inconvertible (Symonds, 1896, pp. 43ff; also p. 11; cf. p. 93; Weeks, 1990, p. 26) – though Symonds also admitted other possible factors, such as forced abstinence from females or ‘wantonness and curious seeking after novel pleasure’ (p. 126), and he suggested that there have been historical epochs when the habit had become institutionalised and endemic in whole nations – such as that of the Dorian Greeks (pp. 63, 109). And just as Symonds had insisted, against the dominant Oxford tradition, on the physicality of Greek love, so he did later of modern love: ‘human nature being what it is, we cannot expect to eliminate all sexual alloy from emotions raised to a high pitch of passionate intensity’ (p. 119). On the other hand, he rejected pederasty as a feature of modern love between men, noting with approval Krafft-Ebing’s opinion that as well as not being predisposed to sodomy, Urnings ‘inasmuch as they always prefer adults, they are in no sense specially dangerous to boys’, although there were some ‘old debauchees or half-idiotic individuals, who are in the habit of

260

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

misusing boys’ (p. 110, paraphrasing Krafft-Ebing, 1889, p. 108; cf. Symonds, 1896, p. 86–7). In summary, then, it appears to us that in his later writings at least, Symonds was doing something quite different from the other exponents of aesthetic Hellenism at Oxford with both Greek and modern love between men. For him, Greek love was physical and practical in a social and political sense, rather than being idealist and philosophical, while modern ‘inversion’ was innate, also physical, but not pederastic. This stance was not only different from that of the Oxford aesthetes; it was intellectually and politically opposed. John Addington Symonds died in 1893, but from 1894 his contrarian stance was developed by his friend and intellectual interlocutor Edward Carpenter. Carpenter was born in 1844 into an upper middle-class Brighton family, educated at Brighton College and Trinity Hall, Cambridge, took holy orders, and became a fellow of Trinity Hall in 1868. He left the church in 1873 and Cambridge the following year, moving to the North of England as a lecturer in the Cambridge University extension scheme, and ending up from 1877 in Sheffield. He became increasingly involved in radical movements, and was devoted to rural life with his longtime companion George Merrill as a vegetarian, market gardener, and sandal-maker. Carpenter is principally remembered for his political writings, which he published in various collections, including Civilization, its cause and cure, and for an epic poem in the tradition of Walt Whitman called Towards democracy. Homosexuality was, however, another constant theme in his work from 1894, when a lecture on what Carpenter called ‘Homogenic Love’ – originally intended, as noted above, to become an essay in the collection Love’s coming of age – was instead turned into a pamphlet printed for private circulation. It is clear from Homogenic love that Carpenter’s understanding of issues surrounding samesex love was in many ways consistent with that of Symonds before him. Modern ‘comradely love’ was not associated with ‘any distinct disease of body or mind’ (Carpenter, 1894, p. 20) and was certainly ‘capable of a healthy and sane expression’ (p. 31); it occurred universally (p. 5); it had a physical side – though this was not as important as the emotional one (pp. 14, 16); and, like the Dorian same-sex relationships from antiquity, it avoided ‘corruption and effeminacy’ (p. 41). Like Symonds, Carpenter was interested in legal changes as well as social ones, protesting in particular against the Labouchère Amendment – or Section 11 of the 1885 Criminal Law Amendment Act – which created the somewhat vaguely-specified criminal offence of ‘gross indecency’, for which Wilde was later to be convicted (p. 49). In some areas Carpenter went further than Symonds had before him. When it came to pederasty, for example, he not only rejected its appropriateness for the modern world, but also seemed to downplay its significance among the ancients as well. One of the reasons he had for rejecting pederastic models was that he sought to present male love as ‘unswerving devotion and life-long union’ (p. 4). Another was that Carpenter was far more interested in transgressing the boundaries of social class than those of age. Homogenic love was a ‘passionate and lasting compulsion [that] may draw members

‘Affection in Education’

261

of the different classes together’ (p. 47) – a view that Symonds had expressed in correspondence with Carpenter, but not one that he ever publicly declared (Schueller & Peters, 1967–9, letter #2079, 21 January 1893, vol. 3, p. 808; also Kaplan, 2005, pp. 16–17). Then there was the nature question. Carpenter agreed with Symonds that the scientific study on the Continent of the previous three decades had established ‘that sexual inversion – that is the leaning of sexual desire to one of the same sex – is in a vast number of cases quite instinctive and congenital, mentally and physically, and therefore twined in the very roots of individual life and practically ineradicable’ (Carpenter, 1894, p. 18). But he added that in born inverts, ‘the person concerned has difficulty in imagining himself affected otherwise than he is; and to him at least the homogenic love appears healthy and natural, and indeed necessary to the concretion of his individuality’ (p. 18). This last phrase suggests that sexual inclination was for Carpenter a constitutive part of personal identity, something that Symonds never quite said, and something which would have been meaningless to Dowling’s transcendental Oxford Hellenists, for whom the act or the relationship was the thing, not the permanent inclination. It may even have been objectionable to Wilde, too, if we accept Jonathan Dollimore’s argument that Wilde deliberately portrayed the subject as dispersed, disruptive, and decentered, as part of a reaction against the repressive ordering of sexuality and the bourgeois ideology of the unified subject (Dollimore, 1987, pp. 56–61). Carpenter hardly merits a mention in Dowling’s book, perhaps because he was a Cambridge man, or perhaps because his views did not fit comfortably into her version of homosexual counterdiscourse. The only attention he does receive, in a footnote, is somewhat misleading. ‘Matriculating at Cambridge’, Dowling writes, ‘Carpenter developed into a homosexual apologist along the earnest, enthusiastic and activist lines characteristic of that university, although he was no less dependent on the ideal of the Socratic eros so central to the Oxford writers treated here’ (Dowling, 1994, p. 79 n. 5). Dowling supports her point by quoting a passage from Homogenic love, that ‘just as the ordinary sex-love has a special function in the propagation of the race, so the other love should have its special function in social and heroic work, and in the generation – not of bodily children – but of those children of the mind, the philosophical conceptions and ideals which transform our lives and those of society’ (Carpenter, 1894, pp. 42–43). But her interpretation of this passage ignores Carpenter’s first claim here, that the ‘other’ sex-love should have a special function ‘in social and heroic work’, and over-emphasises the transcendentalism of the second part, that this other love will generate children of the mind rather than the body. Carpenter was not propounding an intellectual individualist creed, but rather emphasising the general social benefits of homosexuality. Although the concept of the ‘generation of ideas’ as opposed to bodies is taken (perhaps indirectly) from Socrates’ speech in the Symposium about the generation of the beautiful and good through pederastic love, Carpenter’s version of this concept was much more political and active than transcendental and intellectual. The resemblance to the Hellenists’ ideal of boy-love is purely at the level of vocabulary; Carpenter’s heart was elsewhere.

262

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

And this social and political interpretation of this passage is congruent with the rest of his writing on homosexuality. Like Symonds, Carpenter listed examples of Greek love in the service of the state (p. 5; Symonds, 1901, p. 11–12), but his views of such service in the modern world were more radical than those of Symonds, and more focused than Walt Whitman’s romantic vision of democratic comradeship (Weeks, 1990, p. 49).1 He explained that homogenic love was essential for ‘the State’, since those involved in male–female relationships could not neglect the home to perform other social duties, neither could a single person, who lacked the happiness of an affectionate tie. So it is difficult to believe that anything except that kind of comrade-union which satisfies and invigorates the two lovers and yet leaves them free from the responsibilities and impedimenta of family life can supply the force and liberate the energies required for social and mental activities of the most necessary kind. (Carpenter, 1894, p. 44) His illustration was Greek: if ‘the love of Harmodius had been for a wife and children at home, he would probably not have cared, and it would hardly have been his business, to slay the tyrant’ (p. 44). In this the Greeks were a much better example than the Romans, ‘whose materialistic spirit could only with difficulty seize the finer inspiration of the homogenic love, and which in such writers as Catullus and Martial could only for the most part give expression to its grosser side’ (p. 8). This paper is chiefly concerned with Carpenter’s essays from the 1890s, but this theme – the social benefits of homosexuality – was one that he continued to expound over the course of his writing career, and a later work from 1914, Intermediate types among primitive folk – a fascinating and extremely odd study of the origins of homosexuality among early humans and its subsequent practice among the Greeks and the Japanese – dated them all the way back to pre-history. There he suggested that ‘intermediate types’ were responsible for the evolution of the human race out of their caves: for in a world of male hunters and female gatherers or homemakers there was no impetus towards social development, but equally also no obvious social function for those who did not fit comfortably into the categories of male and female. These types had to find new activities and roles for themselves, and they did so as warriors, sages and priests, artists and potters, and so on – in the process inventing rational thought, religion, art, and so on (Carpenter, 1914, esp. pp. 10–12). In the modern world, intermediates could usefully adopt similarly socially useful work such as teaching, and could act as communicators and reconcilers between men and women (Weeks, 1990, p. 75). Indeed, Carpenter inverted the case that Symonds had made against the Socratic eros: where Symonds had argued that that version of Greek love was not useful to society because it did not involve procreation and domestic functions, Carpenter made the lack of procreation and domesticity a social virtue in his own

‘Affection in Education’

263

theorisation of homogenic love. Homosexual relationships held out the promise of new forms of solidarity, which Carpenter explicitly contrasted with the connections that had to be maintained between marriage, materialism, and commerce (Carpenter, 1894, p. 45). Let us return, at last, to ‘Affection in Education’. It is clear that some of the themes of Dowling’s transcendental or aesthetic Oxford Hellenism are on display in this essay, and that we are closer to the world of what we might call Socratic pederasty here than in, for example, Homogenic love. The relationships Carpenter advocates are not between equals in terms of age, there is an explicitly pedagogical or developmental aspect to them, and some of the language is redolent of the transcendentalism of the earlier Hellenists: ‘I believe affection, attachment ... springs up normally in the youthful mind’, Carpenter wrote, ‘in a quite diffused, ideal, emotional form – a kind of longing and amazement as at something divine – with no definite thought or distinct consciousness of sex in it’ (Carpenter, 1899, p. 488). Plato was mentioned briefly twice in the essay, furthermore: once in one of the letters Carpenter quoted, where his correspondent (‘an elderly man who has had large experience as a teacher’) noted that ‘Plato fully understood’ the importance of affection, and ‘aimed at giving what to his countrymen was more or less sensual, a noble and exalted direction’ (p. 485); and again in a note that referred to an episode at the end of Plato’s dialogue Lysis (p. 488n). At times it is tempting to think that Carpenter, having rejected Socratic eros for the innate homosexuals described in Homogenic love, was now recommending a version of this model of same-sex affection as being appropriate for the development of heterosexual boys in England’s schools – for, as Carpenter noted, ‘At that age love to the other sex has hardly declared itself, and indeed is not exactly what is wanted’ (p. 485). Yet despite these debts to the Platonic, aesthetic tradition, the weight of Carpenter’s argument here too rested with the kinds of concerns that were evident in Homogenic love, and which in turn could be traced back to the writings of Symonds. Although Carpenter was nervous about premature sexual activity, there was no Socratic flight from the physical expression of affection. Carpenter suggested that the ‘natural expression’ of a boy’s affection was ‘in caress or embrace’ (p. 493), and one of the correspondents he quoted approvingly in the essay asserted that the right kind of ‘rapport’ between a teacher and a pupil was ‘not only of a merely intellectual nature’, but involved ‘a certain physical element’ (p. 485). And although Carpenter may have concentrated his discussion on the public schools, which only educated a small minority of the population, his concern was directed far more towards what he described as ‘the peculiar character of the middle-class man of today, his undeveloped affectional nature and something of brutishness and woodenness’ rather than with anything to do with the development of young aristocrats – indeed, he noted with approval ‘the rapid rise which is taking place, in scope and social status, of the state day-schools’ (p. 489n) – and we earlier mentioned one of the letters from which Carpenter drew in his essay, concerning the ‘naughty’ workingclass boy.

264

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

Most importantly of all in this essay, far from a project of fashioning exemplary individuals, Carpenter’s interest continued to lie in practical, institutional reform. Carpenter’s was a political – civic, national, perhaps even martial – agenda. ‘In almost all human societies except, curiously, the modern nations’, he wrote, ‘there have been institutions for the initiation of the youth of either sex in these matters’, initiations that ‘have generally been associated ... with inculcation of the ideals of manhood and womanhood, courage, hardihood, and the duties of the citizen or the soldier’ (p. 489). The Greeks were praised for their recognition that friendship was ‘a national institution of great importance’ and, as with Symonds before him, there was particular mention of Müller’s scholarship on the ancient Dorians (p. 485). In Crete and in Sparta, the institution of male friendship between an elder and a younger man ‘was entered into in quite a formal and public way, with the understanding and consent of relatives’, and ‘they fought thenceforward side by side in battle’ (pp. 485–486). The task for the schools of Carpenter’s day was to develop functionally equivalent institutions and practices within and across schools in order to facilitate the proper emergence and prevent the abuse of affection in education. David Halperin, John. J. Winkler, and Froma I. Zeitlin have remarked that in the Greek world, ‘Sexuality ... is not so much a subject in and of itself – a unitary category of analysis – as it is one of the languages for defining, describing, interpreting, and (hence) transacting all manner of other business’ (Halperin et al., 1990, p. 4). We have already argued for this much later period that the Hellenising, pederastic, intellectual version of homosexuality, fetishised in particular at Oxford, was a way of clinging on to elite status and traditions in a rapidly changing world, a way of maintaining difference and superiority at the dawning of a democratic age – rather as we believe it often was in Athens itself (see also Quinn, 2007a, 2007b). For Symonds, to some extent, but especially for Carpenter in the 1890s, homosexuality was a way of engaging with that new world, a rejection of aristocratic self-fashionings in favour of a democratic, more inclusive, reading and use of transgressive sexuality. These writers constructed homosexuality as a means to democracy rather than as a way of avoiding it. Halperin has written that we will understand Greek pederasty better ‘if we do not view it as an isolated, and therefore “queer” institution but if we regard it, rather, as merely one strand in a larger and more intricate web of erotic and social practices in ancient Greece, ranging from heroic comradeship to commercial sex’ (Halperin, 1990, p. ix). We believe that the same can be said for late Victorian Britain. Nor is it simply the case that attention paid to the disagreements among the advocates of same-sex love helps us to illuminate Carpenter’s project in works such as Homogenic love or ‘Affection in Education’. Such attention also opens up a pathway towards a new history of fin de siècle socialisms, for as well as being two of the most eloquent apologists for love between men, Oscar Wilde and Edward Carpenter were also two of the most imaginative (and, we might add, still insufficiently appreciated) socialist thinkers of their age, and the same issues that separated them when it came to thinking about same-sex love showed up in their other political writings as well. Wilde’s affection for the individual

‘Affection in Education’

265

intellectual benefits of the Socratic eros fitted well the view expressed in the opening lines of The soul of man under socialism that the ‘chief advantage’ of socialism would be to ‘relieve us from that sordid necessity of living for others’ in a world where the ‘majority of people spoil their lives by an unhealthy and exaggerated altruism’ (Wilde, 2001, p. 127). Carpenter’s socialism, by contrast, was one in which love taught citizens to be unselfish and anti-egoistic, rejecting individualism along with commercialism, materialism, modern industrial practices, and so on, in favour of a semi-anarchic, moralising vision of rural utopianism (see, e.g., Carpenter, 1897). Different versions of homosexuality could buttress different versions of socialism; to talk about sex – as ever – was also to be talking about politics.

Note 1 Carpenter’s debts to Whitman are complex, and we have no space to explore them here. For a variety of approaches to the question, see Carpenter, 1906, 1924; Sedgwick, 1985, pp. 203–217; Robertson, 2008, ch. 4; Rowbotham, 2009, pp. 38–41, 43–45, 50–57, 72–73; Bevir, 2011, pp. 247ff.

References Bevir, M. (2011) The making of British socialism (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Carpenter, E. (1894) Homogenic love, and its place in a free society (Manchester, Labour Press Society). Carpenter, E. (1896) Love’s coming of age: a series of papers on the relations of the sexes (Manchester, The Labour Press). Carpenter, E. (1897) Transitions to freedom, in: E. Carpenter (ed.) Forecasts of the coming century (Manchester, The Labour Press), 174–192. Carpenter, E. (1899) Affection in education, International Journal of Ethics, 9(4), 482–494. Carpenter, E. (1906) Days with Walt Whitman: with some notes on his life and work (London, George Allen). Carpenter, E. (1908a) Affection in education, in: The intermediate sex: a study of some transitional types of men and women (London, George Allen & Unwin), 83–106. Carpenter, E. (1908b) The homogenic attachment, in: The intermediate sex: a study of some transitional types of men and women (London, George Allen & Unwin), 39–82. Carpenter, E. (1914) Intermediate types among primitive folk: a study in social evolution (London, George Allen & Co). Carpenter, E. (1924) Some friends of Walt Whitman: a study in sex-psychology (London, J. E. Francis). Dollimore, J. (1987) Different desires: subjectivity and transgression in Wilde and Gide, Textual Practice, 1(1), 48–47. Douglas, Lord Alfred (1894) Two loves, reprinted in C. White (ed.) (1999) Nineteenthcentury writings on homosexuality: a sourcebook (London, Routledge), 54–56. Dowling, L. (1994) Hellenism and homosexuality in Victorian Oxford (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). Gilbert, W. S. (1881) Bunthorne’s recitative and song, from Patience; or Bunthorne’s Bride, reprinted in C. White (ed). (1999) Nineteenth-century writings on homosexuality: a sourcebook (London, Routledge), 16–18.

266

Josephine Crawley Quinn and Christopher Brooke

Grosskurth, P. (1964) John Addington Symonds: a biography (London, Longmans). Grosskurth, P. (ed.) (1984) The memoirs of John Addington Symonds (London, Hutchinson). Halperin, D. (1990) One hundred years of homosexuality: and other essays on Greek love (New York, Routledge). Halperin, D., Winkler, J. J. & Zeitlin, F. I. (eds) (1990) Before sexuality: the construction of erotic experience in the ancient Greek world (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Kaplan, M. B. (2005) Sodom on the Thames: sex, love, and scandal in Wilde Times (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). von Krafft-Ebing, R. (1889) Psychopathia sexualis (Stuttgart, Enke). Mallock, W. H. (1882) The new republic; or, culture, faith, and philosophy in an English country house (new edn.) (London, Chatto & Windus). Müller, C. O. (1830) The history and antiquities of the Doric Race (trans. H. Tufnell & G. C. Lewis) (Oxford, S. Collingwood), 2 vols. Plato (1999) The symposium (trans. C. Gill,) (London, Penguin). Quinn, J. C. (2007a) Herms, Kouroi and the political anatomy of Athens, Greece & Rome, 54 (1), 82–105. Quinn, J. C. (2007b) A response to Briggs and Vickers, in: G. Rousseau (ed.) Children and sexuality: the Greeks to the Great War (Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan), 70–74. Robertson, M. (2008) Worshipping Walt: the Whitman disciples (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Rowbotham, S. (2009) Edward Carpenter: a life of liberty and love (London, Verso). Schueller, H. M. & Peters, R. L. (eds) (1967–9) The letters of John Addington Symonds (Detroit, Wayne State University Press), 3 vols. Sedgwick, K. E. (1985) Between men: English literature and male homosocial desire (New York, Columbia University Press). Symonds, J. A. (1893) The Dantesque and Platonic ideals of love, in: In the key of blue and other prose essays (London, Elkin Mathews & John Lane), 55–86. Symonds, J. A. (1896) A problem in modern ethics: being an inquiry into the phenomenon of sexual inversion (London). Symonds, J. A. (1901) A problem in Greek ethics: being an inquiry into the phenomenon of sexual inversion (London). Weeks, J. (1990) Coming out: homosexual politics in Britain, from the nineteenth century to the present (rev. edn.) (London, Quartet Books). White, C. (ed.) (1999) Nineteenth-century writings on homosexuality: a sourcebook (London, Routledge). Wilde, O. (1895) Second trial, fourth day, cross-examination by Gill, reprinted in C. White (ed.) (1999) Nineteenth-century writings on homosexuality: a sourcebook (London, Routledge), 57–58. Wilde, O. (2001) The soul of man under socialism, in: L. Dowling (ed.) The soul of man under socialism and selected critical prose (London, Penguin).

18 John Dewey Saviour of American education or worse than Hitler? Richard Pring

Introduction John Dewey (1859–1952) was born in Burlington, Vermont. Aged sixteen he attended the University of Vermont where he read Darwin’s The origin of species (1859), although it was not on the college curriculum. Its evolutionary theory, especially as developed by T. H. Huxley (1825–1895) in his Elements of physiology, profoundly influenced his ‘distinctive philosophical interest’ and thereby his educational theory. Indeed, in later reflections on his life, Dewey wrote: There was derived from that study a sense of interdependence and interrelated unity that gave form to intellectual stirrings that had previously been inchoate, and created a type or model of a view of things to which material in any field ought to conform ... I was led to derive a picture of it, derived from the study of Huxley’s treatment. (quoted in Ryan, 1997, pp. 53/54) Graduating from Vermont in 1879, Dewey taught (not very well) for three years in two schools and then entered Johns Hopkins University to study philosophy. There he was influenced by C. S. Peirce (1839–1914), the ‘founding father of pragmatism’, and by the pervading influence of Hegelian idealism, and thereby the Oxford idealist F. H. Bradley (1846–1924). In 1884, Dewey was appointed to the University of Michigan. His reading there of the Oxford idealist philosopher, T. H. Green (1836–1882), who had argued strongly for the role of philosophy in helping to understand the problems of social life, influenced Dewey’s conviction of the centrality of such social life in the transformation of experience – and thus of the link between educational aims and the development of community. Hence, Dewey was deeply influenced by evolutionary theory, by the philosophy of pragmatism, and by Hegelian idealism. These came together in his arguments for the essential unity but evolving nature of all experience, for the active pursuit of that unity through inquiry and problem-solving, for the key place of community in the enrichment of that experience, for the reduction (following such enquiry) of the notion of ‘truth’

268

Richard Pring

to that of ‘warranted assertion’, and for the gradual transformation of such ‘warranted assertions’ through further enquiry and the abolition of ‘dualisms’ – in particular, between ‘the spectating mind’ and ‘the spectated material world’, and between knowledge and action, which had bedevilled traditional education. The child’s experience, inquiry arising from that experience, integration of thought and action, and nurturing of community should be central to educational thinking and practice, not peripheral as usually is the case. In 1894 Dewey was appointed to the University of Chicago. His arrival was welcomed by William James: Chicago has a School of Thought! – a school of thought, which it is safe to predict, will figure in literature as the School of Chicago for twenty-five years to come. Some universities have plenty of thought to show, but no school; others have plenty of school, but no thought. The University of Chicago, by its Decennial Publications, shows real thought and a real school. Professor John Dewey and at least ten of his disciples, have collectively put into the world a statement, homogeneous in spite of so many cooperating minds, of a view of the world, both theoretical and practical, which is so simple, massive and positive that, in spite of the fact that many parts of it yet need to be worked out, it deserves the title of a new system of philosophy. (James, 1904, p. 172) That ‘new system of philosophy’ is what Dewey spent the next forty years developing and expounding. But the ‘School of Thought’, which endured for much more than the predicted quarter of a century, finally neglected the integration of theory and practice integral to Dewey’s philosophy. For Dewey, theory had to be an illumination of intelligent practice. That integration of theory and practice became, instead, the academic study of education, placed in the School of Social Sciences. The department of education was closed in 1997. Therefore, to all Departments or Schools of Education: ‘Beware Chicago!’ Once theory loses touch with practice, then why have a Department or School of Education?1 In 1904 Dewey moved to Columbia University, New York City, where he remained for the rest of his academic life, and where he produced the major synthesis of his educational thinking Democracy and education. The title is significant because the creation of democratic communities was a principal aim of education. But his writings were many, as his ideas evolved or needed defence against his critics.

Saviour or Hitler? John Dewey was, and still is, a controversial figure in the history of education. That is reflected graphically in the title of this paper. It is taken from the account of Dewey by Nel Noddings; not only has he:

John Dewey 269 been hailed as the saviour of American education by those who welcome greater involvement of students in their own planning and activity [but also] he has been called ‘worse than Hitler’ by some who felt that he infected schools with epistemological and moral relativism, and substituted socialisation for true education. (Noddings, 2005)

Dewey, the saviour There are two reasons why Dewey might have merited the title of ‘saviour’. The first lies in his criticism of what he referred to as ‘traditional education’ and the substitution of his own ‘pedagogical creed’ in its place. Traditional education was characterised by the ‘transmission of knowledge’ – from the mouth of the teacher into the ear of the learner without regard to the interests and experiences of those learners with which that knowledge, in order to be meaningful, had to connect. What should be a lively transformation of the learner’s understanding of experience became for many little more than ‘inert ideas’. The popularity of this critical account of traditional education was reflected in the growth of what was called ‘progressive education’, often attributed to the influence of Dewey. A key person was a colleague of Dewey at Columbia University, W. H. Kilpatrick (1871–1965) who, in 1918, published The project method. To avoid the dead hand of ‘the transmission of knowledge’, the curriculum should be built around the active pursuit of practical and interdisciplinary projects. These projects would, if carefully chosen, provide both the interest to motivate the young learner and the acquisition of the different kinds of knowledge needed to pursue this interest. The classic tome of curriculum theory (Smith, Stanley & Shores, 1957) lists the ‘interests’, according to developmental stages, around which the curriculum might be integrated. One must, however, be careful of too close an association of Dewey with this interpretation of his ideas. The ‘pursuit of interests’, whether through projects or otherwise, requires a closer philosophical examination of what is meant by ‘interest’ which Dewey, though not all his supporters, provided (see Dewey, 1916, ch. 10; also, Wilson, 1971). The second reason why he might have merited the title of saviour is that education, as he conceived it, had to address the social conditions of the time. Those social conditions were of an increasingly multiethnic and diverse community as immigrants from all over the world entered the United States. Here was an educational task of some magnitude as they and those already within the United States had to come together as a community, forming like interests and concerns despite religious, ethnic, and cultural differences. Education should serve not only individual advancement but community enrichment and harmony. This should not be interpreted as a mere instrumental use of education. It reflected a deeper philosophical understanding of education as essentially democratic. Democracy for Dewey meant, not a particular organisation of political power, but a way of life, which reflected the essential social nature of persons and the personal development through the creation of, and participation in, the

270

Richard Pring

community – a capacity and propensity which needed to be nurtured in school. That positive view and influence of Dewey is reflected in a once major American educational text book – The social foundations of education, (Stanley et al., 1955; see, particularly, pp. 287–332). Dewey: worse than Hitler On the other hand, the source of Dewey’s popularity was also paradoxically the source, too, of the condemnations which he then, and subsequently, received. Economic difficulties within the United States were in part attributed to the failures of the educational system, in particular the adoption of the very approaches to education which others had hailed as a saving grace. Young people were leaving school without the skills, knowledge, and motivation to proceed into higher education or employment, and ‘progressive education’ was to blame. And that blame was directed at the so-called ‘progressive approaches’ associated with Dewey and his disciples. The criticisms, however, went deeper than that. Dewey’s emphasis on respect for differences of background and experience, and on individual inquiry, was rooted in a pragmatic philosophy of truth and knowledge which challenged the prevailing understanding of a liberal education. One antagonist, the president of Chicago University, R. M. Hutchins, had a clear view of the foundations of education: Education implies teaching. Teaching implies knowledge. Knowledge is truth. The truth is everywhere the same. Hence education should be everywhere the same. (Hutchins, 1936, p. 66, quoted in Ryan, 1997, p. 279) This is a far cry from the idea of knowledge being ‘warranted assertion’ or from truth being associated with the resolution (tentative and temporary maybe) of problems faced. Therefore, one either loved Dewey or hated him, although, as with educational disagreements generally, the arguments were polarised without too much close attention to what Dewey actually said. Dewey was himself a fulsome critic of much that fell under the title of ‘progressive education’. In Experience and education, responding to his critics in 1938, he steered a middle way between the traditionalists and the progressives, condemning equally both of these warring opposites. But such an understanding of his position itself reflects the way educational thinking is so easily translated into slogans. As Scheffler argues in The language of education, The example of John Dewey’s educational influence is instructive. His systematic, careful, and qualified statements soon were translated into striking segments serving as slogans for the new progressive tendencies in American education. Dewey himself criticised the uses to which some of his ideas were put. (Scheffler, 1960, p. 37)

John Dewey 271

Crossing the Atlantic Britain was not immune from Dewey’s influence. He was identified by the historian Brian Simon as one of the influences upon the primary school ‘revolution’ which emerged in the 1930s, and which became part of the ‘ideological orthodoxy’ behind the Plowden Report of 1967 (Simon, 1991, p. 362), and was reflected in the publications of the New Education Fellowship and its journal New Era to which Dewey contributed. The Plowden Report into primary education was seen to advocate ‘child-centred’ approaches, and many schools, including secondary ones, promoted a project-based curriculum out of which knowledge and thinking skills would flourish – well illustrated by Charity James’ Curriculum Laboratory at the University of London’s Goldsmiths College (see James, 1968). The organisation of the curriculum would be based on the learner’s particular enquiries, questions, and understandings, rather than on the end products of others’ enquiries, which were reflected in the different branches of learning and encapsulated in the traditional subjects of the curriculum (Goldsmiths College Curriculum Laboratory, 1969, p. 6). As in the United States, concern about standards in education came to be focused on the influence of what was seen to be the ‘child-centred’ ethos of the Plowden years, and Dewey was seen as the presiding culprit. For example, the philosopher, Anthony O’Hear, while a member of the Council for the Accreditation of Education, proposed that it is highly plausible to see the egalitarianism which stems from the writings of John Dewey as the proximate cause of our educational decline. (O’Hear, 1991a, p. 28) O’Hear’s pamphlet about Dewey, published by the Centre for Policy Studies, was entitled Father of child-centredness (O’Hear, 1991b). Indeed, when the present author arrived in Oxford in 1989 and was seated at dinner next to Keith Joseph who had been Secretary of State for Education under Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher, he was accused of being responsible for all the problems in our school – because he had introduced teachers to John Dewey.2 Much more recently, he was asked by a present Cabinet Minister whether he did not think that John Dewey was the cause of all our educational problems. More recently still, however, when a former Secretary of State for Education (an historian by reputation) was asked why the Conservatives were so against John Dewey, he simply replied, ‘Who is John Dewey?’ Perhaps, then, the perceived influence of Dewey himself is waning, though not, evidently, what he was purported to stand for. In a recent interview, the present Secretary of State for Education blamed the decline in social mobility as having more to do with ‘progressive teaching methods and softer subjects in state schools – a move away from traditional subjects rigorously taught’ (The Guardian, 25.5.12). The conflict between Hutchins and Dewey continues, though without reference to the original protagonists.

272

Richard Pring

What were the reasons behind such assumptions? The Plowden Report seemed to have inherited the view, fairly common in previous decades amongst influential educationists, that growth of the inner potentials of the child was the aim of education, and that the guiding principle of the educational process was to identify and nurture those interests which led to further growth. As with Dewey, the ‘mortal sin’ was to bore children, to deaden those very forces which would lead to further growth and to the expansion of the interests of the child. The teacher’s task was, at least in part, to remove the barriers to the growth of personality, including building on the natural curiosity to understand and to know. The Report urged schools ‘deliberately to devise the right environment for children to allow them to be themselves and to develop in the way and at the pace appropriate to them’ (Plowden Report, 1967, para. 507). This, of course, would be different for different children – a far cry from Hutchins’ ‘education should everywhere be the same’. That required the identification of those interests which had the potential for such growth – not an easy task, as the Plowden Report admitted: We are still far from knowing how best to identify in an individual child the first flicker of a new intellectual or emotional awareness, the first readiness to embrace new sets of concepts or to enter into new relations. (Plowden, 1967, para. 9) On the whole, however, the critics failed to make an important distinction between the oft-prevailing understanding of growth in the biological sense and growth through social interaction. In a book referred to by the education historian, W. H. Armitage, as ‘the manifesto of the English progressives’ (see Dearden, 1972, p. 66), Edmund Holmes displayed the biological analogies often behind thinking of education as growth when he asserted that the ‘perfect manhood which is present in embryo in the new-born infant, just as the oak-tree is present in embryo in the acorn, will struggle unceasingly to evolve itself’. (Holmes, 1911, p. 241) The metaphor of the oak-tree, or of plants, was not untypical amongst the ‘education as growth’ theorists, such as Friedrich Froebel (1782–1852), who were suspected by the critics to lie behind Plowden. It would be (and was) mistaken to identify Dewey with such a view, despite his constant reference to education as ‘growth’ (for example, Dewey, 1916, ch. 4). He completely rejected the biological metaphor. Rather, he argued for growth as emerging from social interaction, initially with those in immediate social contact, then with the wider community in which one lived, and later with the community accessed through formal education in which one is challenged by what others have said and done, including ‘the wisdom of the race’ as that is embodied in science, history, and so on. Growth occurs through interaction

John Dewey 273 between the active enquiries of the learner and the social and cultural environment in which those enquiries are pursued. The task of the teacher is to help in making the connections. Behind Dewey’s understanding of the individual learner’s ‘growth’ are significant and controversial issues in philosophy – in particular, in the theory of knowledge and in ethics (that is, in how one determines what is worth learning). Before, however, such philosophical matters are approached, it would be useful to set out Dewey’s ‘manifesto’ for education which was underpinned by such philosophical positions.

‘My pedagogic creed’ Dewey wrote prodigiously for half a century, but in no way did he deviate from his core beliefs set out in a sort of manifesto in 1897, My pedagogic creed. This was based on criticism of what he saw to be defects of ‘traditional education’. The criticisms might be summarised as follows. Traditional education: • • • • •

was disconnected from the experiences that the students brought from their homes and their communities; was disconnected from the practical and manual activity through which they were engaged with the physical world; ignored the interests that motivated young people to learn; treated knowledge as something purely symbolic and formal – organised in textbooks, ‘stuck on’ without connections to existing ways of understanding; maintained discipline through external authority rather than through the active engagement of young people in activities and enquiries.

In contrast to this, the school should be an extension of the home and the community – building on the knowledge and experience already gained, and expanding and deepening it with a view to feeding back to those communities greater understanding and an intelligent contribution to community life. Second, in being such an extension of home and community, the school should value practical and manual activity through which one understands the material world and the necessities for everyday survival. ‘Knowing how’ is as demanding as ‘knowing that’, and the former might be said logically to precede the latter. Third, the interests of the learner are to be respected in their own right, not simply harnessed by the teacher to help motivate the learners to be interested in something which, in itself, they find uninteresting. The interests themselves need to be educated. Fourth, the division of public knowledge into subject compartments must be seen, not as valuable in itself; rather, they are the cultural resources created by others which are useful in finding solutions to the problems one faces and to the enquiries one is pursuing. To transmit them as ‘bodies of knowledge’, disconnected from the enquiries to which they are a response, is not simply bad psychology of learning. It is a misunderstanding of the nature of knowledge and

274

Richard Pring

its logical organisation. Finally, external authority is necessary only because the activity of the learners has not been disciplined by the intrinsic interest in the activities or enquiries to be pursued. In an ideal educational setting, externally imposed discipline should be unnecessary. In practice, such will rarely be completely achieved. But it needs to be the educational ideal constantly striven for. These educational ideas were put into practice in his own experimental school at the University of Chicago.

Philosophical foundations Dewey was much influenced by the evolutionary theory of Charles Darwin (1809–1882) and the idealism of G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831). Following the former, he rejected the notion of human beings as constituted of mind and body (the dualism of Descartes). Rather, evolutionary theory pointed to the continuity between primitive organisms, the animal world, and the human species, in which the organism adapts to the environment in increasingly sophisticated ways, gradually through sensory and then reflective and self-conscious capacities. The criticism of Cartesian dualism is vouched for by the doctrine of biological development which shows that man is continuous with nature, not an alien entering into her processes from without. (Dewey, 1916, p. 285) Hence, the further dualism – between thought and action – is also dismissed. Human beings are not ‘thinkers’ and then ‘doers’. They are active and adaptive organisms, and thinking is but coping with problems arising from the barriers to adaptation and action. The meaning therefore of a belief is the guidance it gives to action and to the overcoming of a problem. The influence of idealism, particularly through the work of T. H. Green, reinforced this through its emphasis upon the essential unity of experience. That idealism rejected both the atomisation of experience and thus the atomisation of the so-called knowledge of that experience. Reality was a construction or an interpretation of the human mind, and that mind could not isolate one area of ‘constructed reality’ from another. To understand anything fully would be to see its connections with the whole. The distinction between contingent and necessary connections between ideas was ultimately unsustainable. Furthermore, coming to see things as a whole (never completely accomplished) evolved through yet further experience and through the interaction between different sets of ideas, different arguments, different protagonists. Ideas are always in a state of evolution. Pragmatism, as that is usually attributed to C. S. Peirce, tallied with much of this. Again, a human being is not a mind in a body, a thinking part set aside from the physically active part, contemplating a ‘true account’ of the physical world. Rather, a human being is an organism whose life is one of actively adapting to

John Dewey 275 the environment in terms of how that environment is conceived and how it has affected the capacities of the organism to adapt. Language embodies a way of conceiving the world in which one is constantly adapting, but the meaning of the words and of the propositions in which they occur is the practical effect which they have. So long as ‘they work’, the beliefs that they reflect are ‘warranted’. As soon as they do not have the desired effect, the beliefs become problematic, in need of refining and involving a reorganisation of how one sees practically the environment within which one is acting and adapting to meet one’s goals. In order to get at the meaning of a theory, one might ask what practically follows from it. Such a criterion would see off much educational theory. If nothing follows practically from the statement ‘all children are curious’ or if no observed practice would lead to its rejection, then it is meaningless. Pragmatism is and was a radical shift in philosophy from an empirical tradition in which truth lies in the correspondence between statements and reality and in which bodies of such statements in theories of various kinds reflect a reality independent of them. Pragmatism may be a philosophical position which many would reject. But in doing so would they necessarily have to reject the educational theory, and its implications, of John Dewey?

Key educational ideas In answering that question, one needs to draw attention to the following key ideas in Dewey’s educational writings. Transformation of experience In his major work on education, Dewey defines education as the reconstruction or reorganisation of experience which adds to the meaning of experience, and which increases ability to direct the course of subsequent experience. (Dewey, 1916, p. 70) Experience is an awareness. But such awareness is tinged with feelings; it is an awareness of something; it is shaped by its association with previous experiences; it is ‘organised’ by conceptual schema which we have inherited from others and which are embodied in the language we learn from childhood. Such experiences therefore come not raw – as sense data unspoilt by the perceiving subject (as the empiricists argued) – but ‘theory-laden’. To experience something is to see it from a particular point of view, linked to a broader set of understandings and emotions, having a history arising from the unique circumstances of each person. Such experiences determine how one sees and interprets further experience. They open up possibilities for further experiences, and they cut out others. A child slipping on the ice will come to see the ice in a different way and that will

276

Richard Pring

affect the meaning he or she attaches to ice and its possibilities. Each person, therefore, is constantly re-interpreting the world of things and people in the light of the experiences they have had, affecting what they want to do and not to do, closing off some experiences, and opening up others. These re-organisations are often not explicit. They are internalised. Dewey spoke of both the educational possibilities of some experiences and the mis-education of others. A mis-educational experience is one that deadens the mind – for example, the ‘inert ideas’ typical of much ‘traditional education’. A pupil may learn the right performances for an examination on Macbeth, but, if that experience is shrouded in boredom, then the result is a determination never to read Shakespeare again. That experience of Shakespeare was mis-educational. One might put this in another way by talking about the meaning of an experience. For Dewey, ‘meaning’ of something is what it does for you, how it affects your action or reaction. The distinction, which we normally assume between ‘the meaning’ of a belief or a proposition, objectively speaking, and the meaning of it in the sense of its particular connotation which is derived from the person’s experience, is blurred. Doubts about the pragmatist foundations of Dewey’s educational thinking should not detract from the arguments he made concerning the centrality of experience and its gradual transformation through further experience. To ignore the significance of the experiences which the learners bring from home and community is to leave them, at a deeper level, largely unaffected by their formal learning. The academic work which in no way connects with what shapes their beliefs, or ignites their emotions, or excites their imagination, is sloughed off as of little significance. The good teacher in Dewey’s scheme of things is one who makes the connections between the child’s interests and experience and the ‘wisdom of the race’ which we have inherited. Where such a connection is made, the learner will be able to find greater depth in what has been experienced, to see how it might be enriched or found wanting, and to appreciate its being subjected to criticism or to further elucidation. It is this connection which needs to be explained further. Reconciling experience and inquiry with ‘objective knowledge’ Inquiry is the process that takes place when the person, pursuing an activity, faces a problem that is not easy to resolve. It is as though one’s previous experiences and the ways of organising them are not up to the job. One tries to solve the problem with further experience. It is what Dewey referred to as a ‘forked road situation’. One makes a choice (formulates a hypothesis) and takes a particular route (tests the hypothesis). If that reaches a dead end (if the hypothesis is falsified), then one tries another route (having reformulated the hypothesis). And so on ad infinitum. Therefore, as is argued in Experience and education (1938, p. 25), there is ‘an organic connection between education and personal experience’. Education is part of that ‘search for meaning – that ‘trying to make sense’ as one seeks to solve a problem through inquiry. The resolution of the problem

John Dewey 277 is a ‘warranted assertion’. One is warranted to trust it until further experience shows that it is no longer warranted. Dewey argues that the growth of knowledge (as that is written down in books and shared by other inquirers in science or in history, for example) is but ‘warranted assertion’, tentatively held. But such assertions have withstood a great deal of testing by others’ experiences in similar contexts. Hence, in facing similar problems people should take seriously what has been tentatively agreed in publicly accessible inquiries. It is the job of the teacher to make the connection between these inherited traditions of inquiry (‘the wisdom of the race’) and the inquiries of the learners as they endeavour to make sense of their experiences. Thus, the child and the curriculum are simply two limits which define a single process. Just as two points define a straight line, so the present standpoint of the child and the facts and truths of studies define instruction. It is a continuous reconstruction, moving from the child’s present experience out into that represented by the organised bodies of truth that we call studies. (Dewey, 1902, pp. 126–127) This is the basis of Dewey’s criticism of formal education. It treats knowledge, in its various forms, as bodies of knowledge to be handed on as such, objective, intrinsically worthwhile, without any connection, logical or contingent, to the personal understandings, the search for meaning, or the attempts to make sense of the learners. No connection is made between the inquiries as they are frozen in the textbooks and the inquiries of the young learner. It is also the basis of Dewey’s criticism of the ‘progressives’, that is, those who see growth to arise simply from the pursuit of interests, the enlargement of experience, disconnected from the results of others’ inquiries as these are embodied in the traditional disciplines or so-called bodies of knowledge. In bridging this gap between the way of thinking of the child and the developed thinking we have inherited from others (between what David Hamlyn [1967] referred to as the psychological and the logical aspects of learning), Dewey uses the following analogy: We may compare the difference between the logical and the psychological to the difference between the notes which an explorer makes in the new country, blazing a trail and finding his way along as best he may, and the finished map that is constructed after the country has been thoroughly explored. (1902, p. 136) The maps of knowledge (created by the ‘explorers’ within science, history, anthropology, etc.) put together the combined ways of organising experiences for particular purposes. Their value lies in their practical use. The maps put to the aid of the traveller the wisdom gained from previous travels. It is the job of the teacher to make the links – to ‘psychologise’ the logical framework of received knowledge as embodied in the inherited maps of inquiry.

278

Richard Pring

Dewey worked through examples. He illustrates the connection between the logical and the psychological through the growth of mathematical thinking. The abstractions of mathematical formulas have grown out of the child’s present crude impulses in counting, measuring, and arranging things in rhythmic series. (1902, p. 134) It is possible and important to reconnect if the abstractions are to be understood and if they are to be put at the service of the ‘impulses’ (the interests, the activities) of the learner. This connection between the ‘logical and the psychological’ might be illustrated through Bruner’s ‘Man: a Course of Study’ (MACOS), an American inquiry-based curriculum project within social studies, highly popular in Britain before being killed off by the National Curriculum in 1988. It posed the questions: ‘What is human about human beings? How did they get that way? How can they be made more so?’ Students, in seeking answers to these questions, engaged in various forms of inquiry – role playing as anthropologists, simulating problems of survival, answering questions about child-rearing. In doing so, however, they drew upon the inquiries, where they felt it appropriate, of anthropologists, sociologists, linguists, historians, theologians, artisans. Their inquiries were both deeply personal (these questions, carefully posed, touched a chord with the concerns of the young people) and yet systematically informed by traditions of inquiry (Bruner, 1966). Here, as in Dewey, ‘traditional learning’ is valuable as a cultural resource, well attested by the systematic inquiries of others, to be drawn upon by the learners as they engage in deliberations about what is of deep concern in their own lives and inquiries. Social nature of growth – community and school The gradual transformation of experiences takes place through the social interactions, first within the family, later within the wider community. Hence, the importance attached by Dewey to the ‘centrality of social life’ and to the development of community (as opposed to an aggregate of individuals). Once, most people lived in small, fairly self-sufficient rural communities, where they would learn the economic skills and the social values for a flourishing life. But, roughly speaking, [schools] come into existence when social traditions are so complex that a considerable part of the social store is committed to writing and transmitted through written symbols ... As soon as a community depends to any considerable extent upon what lies beyond its own territory and its own immediate generation, it must rely upon the set agency of schools to ensure adequate transmission of all its resources ... Hence, a special mode of intercourse is instituted, the school, to care for such matters. (Dewey, 1916, p. 19)

John Dewey 279 The school provided an enrichment of community in two ways. First, the greater the diversity of the social group, the greater would be the enrichment and possible transformation of the meaning attached to social experiences, especially beyond the rural communities. Received assumptions and ways of seeing the world are more likely to be challenged. Other points of view have to be reconciled with one’s own. One’s experiential grasp of reality must be challenged in wider interaction with others of different experiences. Second, the school put the young people in touch with the wider community, which ‘lies beyond [their] own territory and own immediate generation’. Purposive education or schooling should present such an environment that this interaction will effect acquisition of those meanings which are so important that they become, in turn, instruments of further learning. (Dewey, 1916, p. 19) Dewey argued for the common school, because a diverse school population would be enabled, with direction and support from the teacher, not simply to tolerate the different views and backgrounds of the other learners, but to be challenged and informed by them. Diversity of background was to be seen as an asset rather than barrier to learning. School would not only nurture the sense of community amidst diversity, but also provide the basis, the shared understandings, necessary for the development of future communities. Men live in a community in virtue of the things which they have in common. What they must have in common in order to form a community or society are aims, beliefs aspirations, knowledge – a common understanding. (Dewey, 1916, p. 14) The aim of education: growth within democratic communities This learning to live actively within a community was not a mere additional perk in a good education. The major work in which Dewey developed the educational philosophy arising from the pragmatic theory of meaning and knowledge was Democracy and education. This book seems initially to have little to say about democracy in its procedural sense. There is nothing there about ‘one person one vote’ or the ‘universal franchise’. But for Dewey these were the technical aspects of democracy, not what it really meant. Democracy for him was inseparable from the empowerment of all to live fulfilled lives, to be enabled through learning and experiences to make valuable contributions to communal life as earlier described, and to have all barriers removed which prevented them from doing so. Education of all within a community of shared understandings which enabled all to learn from each other was the condition for true democracy. As he argued, Democracy has many meanings, but if it has a moral meaning, it is to be found in resolving that the supreme test of all institutions and industrial

280

Richard Pring arrangements shall be the contribution they make to the all-round growth of every member of society. (Dewey, 1920, p. 186)

The whole of Dewey’s philosophy, therefore, and thereby his educational theory, was profoundly political – not in the sense of propagating a particular political doctrine or arrangement (for example, one person, one vote), but in the sense of arguing for a form of life, central to the growth of knowledge through inquiry, through social interaction, and through critical reflection on experience. In this way, all would be able to learn from each other, to respect each other and to participate in the deliberations and decision-making which affected all. The teacher-centred vision of education It is particularly essential, at the present time when the teacher is seen as ‘delivering’ the curriculum written elsewhere, to see by contrast the exalted role which Dewey attributed to the teacher in My pedagogic creed. I believe that the teacher is the true prophet and the usherer in of the kingdom of God. (Dewey, 1985, p. 30) The reason for this exalted view of teaching is that teaching lies in that bridging of the gap between the enquiries of others (the ‘logical aspects’ of the understandings we have inherited) and the modes of understanding and experiences of the learners (the ‘psychological aspect’). That requires on the part of the teacher not only the pedagogical skills to bridge that gap, but also a profound love and knowledge of the different modes of inquiry. These are our inheritance and the teacher is both the guardian of them and ‘the prophet’, pronouncing their importance and relevance to the next generation. The failure to recognise this by the public school system: in such a way that every teacher has some regular and representative way in which he or she can register judgement upon matters of educational importance, with assurance that this judgement will somehow affect the school system, [means that] the assertion that the system is not, from the internal standpoint, democratic, seems to be justified. (Dewey, article in The Elementary School Teacher, 1903).

The relevance of John Dewey to educational policy and practice As was reflected in the response from the former Secretary of State for Education, it would seem that, in Britain, Dewey has left no legacy. Who has read John Dewey? Or who, indeed, amongst the present cohort of teachers has even heard

John Dewey 281 of him? Those preparing to be teachers or those in receipt of professional development receive little or no introduction to the history of educational ideas or to the philosophical questions underpinning them. Less and less influence is attributed to him for the so-called ‘poor standards’ in our schools. The ‘Plowden era’ is a fading memory. That is a pity because in England and Wales, as in the United States, we are witnessing a revolution in educational language, aims, and provision of which Dewey’s philosophical and educational writings offer a trenchant critique. There is an ‘Atlantic Bridge’, indeed, by which ideas cross the ocean with remarkable rapidity. Diane Ravitch summarises the revolution in the United States, following President Bush’s No Child Left Behind, thus: NCLB introduced a new definition of school reform ... In this new era, school reform was characterised as accountability, high-stakes testing, datadriven decision-making, choice, charter schools, privatisation, deregulation, merit pay and competition between schools. Whatever could not be measured did not count. (Ravitch, 2010, p. 217) One consequence of this is that, As it elevated the concept of school choice, the Department of Education destroyed the concept of neighbourhood schools ... Neighbourhoods were once knitted together by a familiar local high school that serves all the children of the community, a school with distinctive traditions and teams and history. (Ravitch, 2010, p. 83) The present author shows how Ravitch’s trenchant critique is equally relevant to England and Wales – as also is the response that Dewey would give in the light of the ideas summarised above (Pring, 2012). First, local community responsibility for education has been gradually eroded over a long period, but it has quickened under present policies with the creation of ‘free schools’ (based on the model of the US Charter Schools) and ‘academies’, under direct contract to the Secretary of State. Gone is local accountability of the education within the community. Furthermore, the creation of greater choice within a more market driven system has polarised rich and poor, ethnic groups and social classes. There is a severance between the aims of education as a personal good and those aims as a public service for the creation of common experiences, common culture, common understandings which were at the heart of Dewey’s notion of democracy – and indeed of that of R. H. Tawney (1880–1962) (Tawney, 1938). Second, the new language of education, adopted from performance management, bears little relation to that of Dewey’s ‘transformation of experience’ – respecting, as a starting point, the experiences and ways of understanding which the learners bring with them into school. There is little room in such performance

282

Richard Pring

management for the ‘exploration of ideas’, the ‘tentative inquiring’, the ‘struggle to understand’, the ‘targets’ imposed by Government, the ‘performance indicators’ by which learners and teachers and schools are tested, the ‘audits’ by which schools are classified and failed. There is a need to ask, as Dewey constantly asked, what are the aims of education in the light of what we mean by saying we help all young people to develop their humanity within the wider society. Third, the Hutchins/Dewey disagreement remains with us still. What is the nature of the school subjects which shape the curriculum? Dewey’s critique of the curriculum as ‘the transmission of knowledge’ (and of the dualism between thinking and doing, theory and practice) is as relevant today as it was then – the transmission of inert ideas, failing to illuminate the experiences and interests of young people and leading to disengagement of so many. Finally, Dewey’s extolling of the teachers as ‘the true prophet and the usherer in of the kingdom of God’ may seem over the top, but it is in sharp and refreshing contrast with the teacher as the deliverer of the curriculum, in the creation of which he or she has had little or no position. For Dewey, a healthy education requires a profound respect for the teacher. The dictation, in theory at least, of the subject-matter to be taught, to the teacher who is to engage in the actual work of instruction ... [which] meant nothing more than the deliberate restriction of intelligence, the imprisonment of the spirit. (Dewey, 1903) Rather should The public school system [be] organised in such a way that every teacher has some regular and representative way in which he or she can register judgment upon matters of educational importance, with assurance that this judgment will somehow affect the school system[?] (Dewey, 1903) There is a revolution in both the content and the provision of education in the United States and Britain – an underlying disdain for the practical, a deregulation of educational provision, a transfer of responsibility from public to private and for-profit companies, an emphasis on competition at the expense of partnership, a deprofessionalisation of teachers, a reduction of worth-while learning to what is measurable. Those who wish to question such a revolution may find support in the very different vision of education of John Dewey.

Notes 1 It is important to distinguish between ‘School’ in the sense of an informal collection of like-minded thinkers, ‘School’ as a formally constituted university department, and ‘school’ as a place where young people go. Here ‘School’ refers to the first, although

John Dewey 283 such like-minded interests would seem to have developed into ‘School’ in the second sense (the one which in recent years, has closed), and not to the third sense, or the Lab School, which Dewey helped create. 2 After several lengthy discussions, I can report that Lord Joseph no longer holds these views.

References Bruner, J. (1966) Man: a course of study, in: Towards a theory of instruction (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). Dearden, R. (1972) Education and the development of reason, (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul). Dewey, J. (1903) Democracy in education, The elementary school teacher, 4, 193–203. Dewey, J. (1916) Democracy and education (New York, The Free Press). Dewey, J. (1920) Reconstruction in philosophy (Boston, Beacon Press). Dewey, J. (1938) Experience and education (New York, Macmillan). Dewey, J. [1897] (1966) My pedagogic creed, in: Selected educational writings (ed. F. W.Garforth) (London: Heinemann). Dewey, J. [1902] (1966) The child and the curriculum, in: Selected educational writings (ed. F. W.Garforth) (London: Heinemann). Goldsmiths College Curriculum Laboratory (1969), Report no. 6 (London, University of London). Hamlyn, D. (1967) The logical and the psychological aspects of learning, in: Peters, R. S. (ed.) The concept of education (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul). Holmes, E. (1911) What is and what might have been (London, Constable). Huxley, T. H. (1886) Elements of physiology and hygiene (New York, Appleton). James, C. (1968) Young lives at stake (London, Collins). James, W. (2004) The Chicago school, in: J. M. Capps, D. Capps (eds) James and Dewey on belief and experience (Urbana, University of Illinois Press). Killpatrick, W. H. (1918) The project method, Teachers College Record, 19, 319–334. Noddings, N. (2005) Philosophy of education (2nd ed.) (Boulder, Westview Press). O’Hear, A. (1991a) Education and democracy: the posturing of the left establishment (London, Claridge Press). O’Hear, A. (1991b) Father of child-centredness: John Dewey and the ideology of modern education (London, Centre for Policy Studies). Plowden Report [Central Advisory Council for Education (England)] (1967) Children and their primary schools (London, HMSO). Pring, R. (2012) The life and death of secondary education for all: dream or reality? (London, Routledge). Ravitch, D. (2010) The death and life of the great American school system (New York, Basic Books). Ryan, A. (1997) John Dewey and the high tide of American liberalism (New York, Norton). Scheffler, I. (1960) The language of education (Springfield, IL, Charles C. Thomas). Simon, B. (1991) Education and the social order, 1940–1990 (London, Lawrence & Wishart). Smith, B. O., Stanley, W. O., & Shores, J. H. (1957) Fundamentals of curriculum development (New York, Harcourt, Brace & World). Stanley, W. O., Smith, B. O., Benne, K. D., Anderson, A. W. (1955) Social foundations of education (New York, Holt, Rinehart & Winston).

284

Richard Pring

Stenhouse, L. (1967) Culture and education (London, Nelson). Stenhouse, L. (1975) Introduction to curriculum research and development (London, Heinemann). Tawney, R. H. (1938) Equality (London, George Allen & Unwin). Wilson, P. (1967) In defence of bingo, British Journal of Educational Studies, 15, 5–27. Wilson, P. (1971) Interest and discipline in education (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul).

Index

Abelard, Peter 56 abolitionism, anti-slavery 122, 124, 196, 200, 204 academy 43, 134 affection 10, 15, 19, 94, 133, 135, 138, 152, 155, 182, 184, 186, 252–6, 257–8, 262–4 Aikin, John 196 allegory, allegorical method 39, 40, 54 Analytic Review, The 145–6 aristocracy 28, 34, 211, 256, 263, 264 Aristotle 4, 6, 7, 8, 15, 21–39, 46, 47, 68, 83, 87–8, 237 Arnold, Matthew 220, 245 art 23, 33, 34, 46, 49, 54–6, 57–8, 60, 62, 63, 67, 70–1, 94, 121, 131, 132–3, 168, 184, 196; fine art, creative art 7, 19, 29, 32, 40, 124, 161, 163, 165, 189, 202, 220, 256, 262; liberal arts, see: liberal studies etc; see also: techne asceticism 47, 52 associationism, association of ideas 132–3, 135, 141, 150, 195, 196, 198, 275; see also: pedagogical method Athanasius 52 Augustine, St. 53–6, 58, 62, 63, 64, 68, 81, 124 authority 49, 73, 76, 87–8, 90, 94, 107, 109, 111–2, 116, 117–8, 122, 123–7, 147, 149, 155, 162, 169–70, 174, 180, 182, 212, 218, 273; government authority over education 70; sovereign authority 85, 95–6 autonomy 2, 3, 22, 27, 31–3, 113, 115–6, 118, 125–6, 151, 163, 165, 167, 170, 171, 173, 220, 241, 244; see also: freedom, independence

Bacon, Francis 86 Bain, Alexander 219, 222 Barbauld, Anna 196, 204 Beale, Dorothea 226, 229, 230, 232 Bell, Andrew, see: monitorial system Bell-Lancaster system, see: monitorial system Bentham, Jeremy 212, 216, 222 Berkeley, Bishop George 237 Beyme, Karl Friedrich 168 Biber, George Edward 210, 218, 221 Bildung 160, 161, 162, 163, 173, 212, 241 Bodichon, Barbara 227–8, 231, 232 body 7, 11, 13, 18, 24, 47, 60, 63, 105, 148, 149–50, 164, 195, 198, 252, 260, 261, 274; see also physical education Bosanquet, Bernard 238, 242 Bradley, F.H. 238, 242, 248, 267 Bramhall, John 93 Bruner, Jerome 278 Budé, Guillaume 66, 67, 73 Butler, Josephine 224–5, 228, 229, 230, 231, 233 Calvin, John 79, 113, 129 Campe, Joachim Heinrich 162 Carpenter, Mary 197 Carpenter, Edward 2, 252–4, 255–6, 260–5 Carpenter, Lant 197, 198 Cassiodorus 52, 62 Cleanthes 38, 40, 48 character, character development 2, 12, 29–30, 69–70, 74, 77, 108, 130, 140, 150, 167, 173, 179–88, 191, 195, 204, 211, 212, 213, 214, 222, 232, 233, 244, 252, 253, 263; see also: environmentalism, ethology

286

Index

childhood, children 2, 3, 10, 13–4, 27, 28, 31–4, 46, 75–6, 77–80, 88, 95–6, 100, 103–4, 104–12, 113, 119, 125–6, 132–3, 136, 149, 154–5, 157, 179, 182, 183–5, 188–91, 195, 196, 198, 203, 205, 214–6, 217, 219, 228, 239, 241, 244, 246, 258, 261–2, 268, 271–2, 275, 276–8; early childhood learning 69–70, 72–4, 137–8, 152 Chrysippus 38, 40–4, 48, 49 Cicero 7, 12, 38–40, 43, 52, 57, 58–9, 67, 88 citizenship, citizens 2, 10, 28–30, 32, 33, 44, 46, 60, 69, 75–6, 80, 89, 90, 93, 96–7, 109–12, 113, 115–7, 119, 125, 126, 127, 130, 133, 134, 137, 140, 155, 156, 167, 173, 178, 195, 204, 210, 214, 217, 220, 241, 243–4, 245–6, 249–50, 264, 265 class 28, 45, 76, 157, 181, 182, 187–8, 191, 196, 201, 202, 205, 211, 216, 220, 228, 232, 245, 250, 260–1, 281; middle class 28, 157, 165, 166–7, 172, 173, 200, 227–8, 233–4, 263; working class 179, 180, 197, 200, 202, 205, 209, 210, 228, 234, 246, 252 Cleomedes 39, 42, 49 Cobbe, Frances Power 228, 229, 230–1, 233 Cobbett, William 202 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor 211, 222 Collingwood, R.G. 238 Comenius, Jan 86, 89 commerce, commercial society 29, 129–31, 131–3, 134–8, 139–42, 156, 163, 169, 173, 185, 194, 196, 263, 264, 265 common good, common interest 27–8, 49, 60, 117, 121, 124, 125, 169, 190, 242 commonwealth 76–7, 84–6, 88–9, 90, 91, 93, 95–6, 99, 110, 111, 147, 178, 192 community, communitarianism 27–8, 32, 59–61, 167, 173, 179, 181–3, 184–9, 191, 192, 200, 243, 245, 250, 256, 267–8, 269–70, 272, 273, 278–81 competition 72, 162, 171–2, 181–3, 191, 225, 231, 281, 282 Comte, Auguste 204, 212, 214, 221 Condorcet, Marquis de, Nicolas de Caritat 166 Conington, John 257

consensus, concord 85, 90, 92, 96–7, 140; see also: harmony, peace consent 27, 32, 85, 95–6, 122–3, 264 consequential argument, consequentialism 9, 18, 70, 91–2, 95, 106, 107, 154, 165, 179–80, 184, 186, 215, 244, 250, 258 contemplation 26, 32, 33, 47–8, 54–5, 59, 62, 132, 134, 137, 167, 274 contextualism 35 cooperative movement, cooperation 32, 121, 164, 179, 181, 183, 198, 200 Cornutus 38–42, 43 corporal punishment, see: punishment corruption 27, 61, 70, 74, 77, 84, 120, 129, 132, 133, 135–6, 137, 138–40, 141, 149, 151, 152, 155–6, 163, 186–7, 200–1, 259, 260 cosmopolitanism 116, 119, 121, 160, 165, 167, 171 counter-reformation 79 Cousin, Victor 218, 221 crime 77, 123, 180, 181 Croce, Benedetto 240, 248–9 curriculum 139, 162, 183–4, 191, 195, 197, 210, 211, 215, 220, 231, 239, 241, 243, 244, 246, 249, 267, 269, 271, 277, 278, 280, 282 Daily News, The 201, 204, 205 Darwin, Charles 267, 274 Davies, Emily 225, 228, 229, 230, 231, 232 deism 147, 148, 152, 154, 184; see also: theology democracy, demos 7, 16, 29, 32, 76, 84, 88–9, 113, 180, 182, 195, 202, 204, 211, 214, 220, 254, 256, 260, 262, 264, 268, 269, 279, 281 Dewey, John 2, 209, 267–284 Descartes, Rene 274; see also: dualism dialectic 17, 22, 55, 57–9, 62, 67–8, 240–1 Diogenes Laertius 40, 42, 44, 46, 47 Disraeli, Benjamin 209 dissent, rational dissent, dissenting academies 85, 92, 98, 145, 194–7, 202, 205 domestic life, home 13, 108, 155, 196, 197, 203, 226, 227, 232, 233, 262, 273, 276; see also: education, domestic Dowling, Linda 255, 256, 257, 258, 259, 263

Index dualism 150, 268, 274, 282 Dunne, Joseph 33, 35 Dunning, Thomas 202 Dury, John 86 educated individual 29, 95, 124, 149, 161, 164, 178, 194, 203–4, 212, 217, 227, 228, 239, 241 education; christian 52–3, 54–5, 56, 63, 66–8, 78, 87, 89, 121, 147, 184, 218, 221, 230; of citizens, civic education 63, 84–6, 90, 91–2, 93–4, 96, 111, 115–9, 121, 124–6, 127, 134, 140, 196, 250, 264; domestic 125, 148, 154–5, 182, 199, 203, 262; elite 38, 76, 86, 93, 99, 225, 264; ethical, moral 8, 11, 21–2, 25–6, 29, 31, 35, 43, 45, 47, 53, 56, 58–9, 68, 69, 72–4, 76, 77–8, 79, 80, 84, 87, 98, 112, 115–6, 117, 119, 122–3, 124–5, 126, 129–30, 133, 135, 136, 138, 140, 148, 149, 150, 152, 156, 161–2, 164–6, 169, 172–3, 174, 185, 189, 191, 195, 197–9, 203–4, 209–10, 213–4, 215, 220, 227, 230, 232–3, 280, 242, 244–6, 249, 250, 253, 265, 279; literary, literature 38, 40, 41, 43, 67, 68, 73, 80, 162, 196, 197, 201, 203, 216, 220; musical, music 29, 41, 55, 189, 202; national 148, 153, 154, 169, 171, 185, 195, 197, 202, 204–5, 210, 214, 245–6, 248–9, 254; of people, of common people 84–6, 88, 92, 94, 96, 99, 104–7, 140, 195, 198–9, 200–1, 204; philosophical 163, 169, 220, 240–1, 249; physical 165, 183, 189, 191, 195, 197, 198; public 4, 21, 24, 27, 28, 30, 31, 32, 59, 69, 75, 83, 85, 87, 89, 92, 96, 99, 108, 111–2, 125, 126, 194, 204, 205, 216, 218, 244, 264; religious 28, 68, 75, 76, 94, 98, 111, 136–7, 168, 173, 184, 197, 211, 218, 231; of rulers 59–60, 61, 201; sex education 190, 224, 244, 253, 264; of women and girls 4, 73, 149–50, 152, 183–4, 188, 191, 197, 203, 219, 222, 224–33, 234, 253; of young children, see early childhood education; see also: socialisation educational history 6, 53, 171, 268, 281 educational theory 1, 6, 18, 35, 53, 57, 66, 69, 103, 104, 112, 125, 126, 129–30, 131–4, 135, 137, 148, 151,

287

157, 184, 185, 214–5, 221, 230, 267–8, 269, 275, 280, 282; innatism 104, 123, 152, 186, 195, 229, 259–60; environment, environmentalism 76, 179–80, 182, 195, 198, 205, 243, 272–5, 279; pragmatism 267, 270, 274–6, 279 educational philosophy 1, 3–4, 21–2, 30–2, 34, 66, 79, 83, 115, 150, 169, 195–7, 198, 237, 239, 241–3, 249–50, 267, 269, 270, 273, 279, 280–1 egotism, egocentrism, see: self interest, self absorbtion elenchos, see: socratic method Ellis, Havelock 254, 256 eloquence 52, 57–8, 62 Emerson, Roger 130 emotion 25, 31, 136, 143, 149, 150, 151, 155, 157, 189, 191, 213, 217, 220, 234, 259, 260, 272, 275–6 English Woman’s Journal, The 225, 227 enlightenment 85, 97, 100, 115, 129–30, 131, 134, 136, 138–40, 162–3, 164 environment, see: educational theory Epictetus 38, 39, 43, 44–6, 48–9, 50, 148 epicureans, epicureanism 41, 45 episteme, epistemology 3, 5, 21–3, 53, 61, 62, 131, 132, 141, 160, 164, 165, 269 equality, egalitarianism 3, 27, 73, 75, 149, 155, 161, 163–5, 169–70, 181, 187, 191, 198, 209, 230, 231, 245, 249, 271 eros, erotic love, desire 7, 11, 12, 13–8, 19, 190, 254–7, 278–9, 261, 262, 264–5 Erasmus, Desiderius 2, 66–74, 78, 79–80, 81 erudition 43 ethics 3, 7–9, 11, 21–2, 26, 31–2, 35, 39, 41–8, 49, 54, 55, 58–9, 60, 63, 68, 79, 117, 130, 134, 146, 148, 149, 153, 156, 167, 171–2, 197, 215, 241–2, 244, 248, 249, 259, 273 ethology 213–5 Eudaimonia, see: human flourishing evil 17, 47, 74, 78, 89, 91, 95, 104–6, 110, 122, 147–8, 153–4, 183, 199–200, 228, 258 examinations 15–6, 170, 201, 218, 221, 226, 231–3, 234, 247, 276 experience 12, 15–7, 22, 25–6, 31, 70, 90, 92, 148, 153, 162, 182, 194–5, 199, 238, 240, 243, 257, 267–8, 269, 270, 273, 274, 275–7, 278–80, 281–2

288

Index

family 19, 85, 95–7, 104, 108–10, 112, 120, 146, 169, 171, 181, 188, 198, 203, 227, 233, 244, 249, 262, 278; see also schools - home schools, parenting, domestic life feminism, feminists 3, 146, 155, 157, 204, 221, 224–234 Ferguson, Adam 130, 138–9, 140, 141 Fichte, Johann 2, 161, 163–70, 171–2, 173, 174, 237, 245–6 flourishing, see: human flourishing Fordyce, David 130, 134–6, 138, 141 Fourier, Charles 178, 185–90, 191–2 Fox, William Johnson 197, 199 free thinking 88, 98, 172, 194–5, 197, 199, 205, 232; see also dissent freedom, free man 27, 33, 41, 46, 48, 61–2, 71, 76, 96, 109, 111, 113, 116–7, 118, 120–1, 125–6, 133, 160, 161, 164–9, 172–3, 186, 188, 189, 191, 196, 199, 202, 224, 227, 229, 232, 244, 246, 250, 262; free will 87, 122–4, 148, 164, 212; liberation 67, 78, 99–100, 186–8, 191, 241, 244, 245, 262; friendship 2, 13, 15–7, 19, 27, 30, 34, 131, 155, 181, 186, 252–4, 257, 258, 264; see also affection Froebel, Friedrich 197, 272 Fronto 38 general will 115–6, 116–126, 127, 242–3 gender 73, 79, 150, 157, 201, 205, 225, 233, 255 Gentile, Giovanni 240–1, 248–9 gerontocracy 182 Gilbert of Poitiers 56 girls, see education, schools, good, human good 7–8, 11, 15–16, 22–3, 26, 27, 29, 31, 33, 34, 42, 44–5, 46–7, 49, 53, 72–4, 77–8, 86, 89–91, 94, 104–7, 110, 115, 119, 120, 122–3, 124, 125, 131–3, 135, 136, 147–8, 154, 169, 171, 183, 188, 194, 227, 229, 241–2, 243, 254, 261, 281; see also: common good Goethe, Johann Wolfgang 212 government, governments 3, 4, 24, 27, 29, 30, 31–2, 67, 86, 88, 96, 104, 107, 109–12, 136, 140, 147, 156, 163, 168, 180, 182, 197, 202, 205, 210–1, 214, 218, 225, 246, 248, 282 Grace 59, 108, 204, 258

Graces, Three 40 grammar 38, 39, 41, 55, 57, 58, 68 Green, T.H. 237, 239–40, 242, 245, 246–7, 248, 267, 274 Grosskurth, P 256–7 habit, habitus 22, 24, 25, 28, 31, 47, 57, 61, 73–4, 88, 92, 95, 105, 106–8, 152, 179, 180, 182, 184–5, 198, 199, 241, 243, 252–3, 258, 259; see also: socialisation, practice Haldane, R.B. 237, 238, 245, 247–8, 250 Hall, C. 201 Halperin, D. 264 happiness 7, 9, 21, 22–3, 31, 33, 47, 58, 60, 76, 110, 121, 133, 138, 140, 155, 164, 181, 186, 195, 196, 215, 262; see also: human flourishing harmony 16–7, 18, 60, 61, 62, 164, 165, 166, 182, 186, 187–90, 269 Hartley, David 195, 197, 198, 199, 205 Hartlib, Samuel 86 Hays, Mary 196 Hegel, G.W.F 117–8, 125, 237, 238–40, 241, 242, 244, 245–6, 267, 274 Hellenism 38, 254–5, 256–8, 260, 261, 263, 264 Herder, Johann 162–3, 165, 171 Hierocles 39, 43 history of education, see: educational history Hobbes, Thomas 2, 4, 83–102, 121, 122, 131, 145, 146, 147–8 Home, Henry, Lord Kames 130, 136–8 Homer 39, 41, 49, 98, 257 homosexuality 254, 256, 258, 260, 261–3, 264, 265 Howell, James 86 Hugh of St Victor 52–3, 53–6, 57–9, 60, 62–3 Hullah, John Pike 202 human flourishing 26–7 humanism 66–9, 74, 78–9, 80, 130 human nature 22, 28, 29, 44, 59, 71, 73, 100, 105, 113, 115, 163, 178, 179–80, 186–7, 188, 214–5, 249, 259 Humboldt, Wilhelm 160–1, 163, 170, 173 Hume, David 130, 140, 141, 145, 147–8 Hutcheson, Francis 131, 140, 141, 165 Hutchins, R.M. 270, 271, 272, 282 Huxley, T.H. 220, 267

Index idealism 163, 221, 237–250 incentives 2, 91, 107, 139, 153, 254 independence 30, 32, 117, 121, 122, 123, 126, 161, 189, 202, 203, 212, 213, 219, 233; see also: autonomy, freedom inequality, social inequality, see: equality Infant School Society, The 192 innatism, innate ideas, see: educational theory institutions 2, 4, 27, 28, 33, 34, 74, 76, 77–8, 80, 115, 120, 124, 129–30, 131, 139, 140, 148, 153, 154, 167, 171, 180, 185, 187, 194, 203, 210, 211, 218, 226, 228, 232, 233, 242, 243–4, 248, 250, 252, 253, 257, 259, 264, 280 instrumentalism 2, 29, 33, 168, 248, 269 interest 16, 30, 41, 42, 57, 58, 59, 63, 78, 90, 93, 104, 105, 106, 110, 113, 121, 136, 147, 181, 182, 184, 189, 190, 196, 215, 224, 228, 241, 244, 269, 272, 273–4, 276, 277, 278, 282, 283; see also: self interest; public and private interests inversion, see: gender; see also: homosexuality Iselin, Isaak 165 James, William 268 John of Salisbury 52, 56–59, 64 Johnson, Joseph 146 Jowett, Benjamin 246, 254, 255 justice, injustice 3, 7, 8, 17, 30, 98, 108, 123, 134, 136, 138, 148, 150, 250 justification 2, 9, 13, 31, 55, 61, 91, 107, 110, 111, 112–3, 139, 183, 210, 227, 254, 280 Kames, see home, Henry Kant, Immanuel 160, 163, 165, 171, 237, 241; Kantianism, neo-Kantianism 31, 115– 116, 163, 164–5, 169, 170, 171 Kilpatrick, W.H. 269 kingship, see: monarchy Kingsley, Charles 226 knowledge 3, 6, 8, 10, 12, 13, 14, 22–4, 29, 34, 35, 40, 41–2, 43, 44, 45, 46, 48, 53, 54–5, 57–60, 61, 62, 66, 68, 69, 70, 72, 87, 91, 93, 94, 107, 112, 113, 116, 118, 126, 133, 137, 139, 140, 146, 160, 161, 162, 163, 168, 171, 173, 182, 184, 191, 195, 196, 200, 201, 202, 203, 204, 212, 215,

289

218, 224, 225, 230, 232, 238, 239–40, 249, 258, 268, 269, 270–1, 273, 274, 277, 279–80, 282; moral knowledge, of virtue 8, 9, 22–3, 72, 107, 126, 147, 153, 154 Kristjansson, K 32, 35 labour 9, 29, 60, 68, 104, 131, 139, 157, 160, 164, 165–6, 179, 182, 187, 191, 202, 227–8, Ladies Educational Associations 226 Lancaster, Joseph, Lancastrians, see: Monitorial system language, 18, 25, 27, 40, 68, 70, 71, 85, 87, 108, 121, 132, 164, 171, 179, 186, 187, 203, 216, 219, 227, 245, 259, 263, 264, 275, 281; ordinary language 238 La Vopa, A. 167 law of nature, natural law 91, 98, 109, 120, 147, 166 legislation, legislator 21, 22, 23, 24, 32, 93, 109, 115, 116–8, 119–20, 124, 125, 179, 204, 212, 246, 259 leisure 28–9, 46, 75, 200 liberal studies, liberal education, liberal arts 11, 16, 19, 29, 31, 41, 42, 45, 52, 53, 54, 55, 60, 70, 75, 130, 131, 139, 194, 196, 200, 211, 219, 221, 232, 233, 246, 270 liberalism 31, 91, 97, 113, 129, 140, 157, 172, 194, 196, 197, 205, 211, 214, 221, 225, 246, 247, 249, 250, 254, 256 liberation, see: freedom literacy, literacy rates 72, 86, 200, 210 literature, see: education - literary Locke, John 2, 3, 4, 5, 103–113, 120, 121, 126, 141, 148–9, 151, 154, 157 logic 6, 9, 16, 17, 24, 39, 42, 43–4, 46, 49, 52, 55, 57, 59, 62, 67, 69, 81, 216, 238, 242, 246, 273, 277, 278, 280 love (philia) 10, 11, 13–7, 18, 19, 107, 108, 116, 120, 181, 186, 195, 217, 244, 252, 256; love of learning etc 56, 105, 108, 133, 280; see also: eros, friendship Lowe, Robert 202 Lucan 39 Luther, Martin 79 Macaulay, Catharine 146–7, 147–8, 149, 150–1, 155, 156 MacIntyre, A 32

290

Index

MacLure, William 182 Manilius 39, 42 Marcet, Jane 199, 205 Marcus Aurelius 38–9, 44–5, 48–9 marriage 146, 150, 151, 153, 181, 213, 228, 255, 258, 263 Martineau, Harriet 194–206 Macé, Jean 192 Makarenko, Anton 192 Marx, Karl 178, 190 Maurice, F.D. 226 Mechanics Institutes, The 197, 200, 202, 228 Melancthon, Philipp 79 meritocracy 147, 162, 170, 211–2 militarism, military service, military training 24, 29, 75, 111, 124, 168, 169, 170, 184, 257 Mill, James 212 Mill, John Stuart 2, 5, 209–222 Milton, John 86, 87, 89, 198 modern, modernity 6, 7, 9, 10, 11, 66, 79, 80, 98, 100, 112, 121, 124, 126, 127, 129, 130, 131, 134–6, 137–8, 139, 141, 147, 160–3, 167, 171, 178, 181, 188, 195, 201, 245, 249, 256, 259–60, 262, 264, 265 monarchy 83, 88–9, 103, 127, 147, 149, 155 monitorial system 183, 202, 216, 222 Montessori, Maria 4, 5 Monthly Repository, The 199, 218 morality, see: ethics More, Thomas 2, 66, 67, 69, 72–3, 74–8, 80, 81 More, Margaret 72 Muller, Carl 257, 264 music, see: education Musonius Rufus 38, 39, 44, 45–6, 46–8, 49, 50 Myth, Mythology 40, 228 National Association for the Promotion of Social Science 202, 204 nationalism 171, 245 natural law, see: law of nature necessity, necessitarianism 23, 76, 118, 122, 126, 134, 148, 198, 212, 240, 244, 265, 273 Nederman, C 57, 58, 60, 63, 64 Nero, Emperor 186–7 New Lanark 179, 180, 181, 182–3, 184 Nightingale, Florence 201, 203

Noddings, Nel 268–9 norms of conduct 2, 25, 42, 141, 150, 153, 184, 195, 233, 244 North of England Council for the Higher Education of Women 225, 231 Northcote-Trevelyan Committee 211 Oakeshott, Michael 238 obedience 84, 87, 89–90, 91, 95–6, 99, 100, 107, 109 obligation 10, 48, 89, 98, 109, 110, 122, 123, 134, 136, 148 original sin, see: Sin Owen, Robert 178, 179–85, 186, 191, 192, 212, 213, 222, 227 parenting, parents 2, 10, 14, 27, 70, 78, 95–6, 103–4, 105, 106–12, 113, 152, 153, 154, 155, 170, 183, 184, 188, 189, 198, 213, 217, 219, 227, 244, 246 Panaetius 38, 40 parliament 86, 87, 89, 145, 202, 204, 209, 210, 212, 221 passion, see: emotion Pater, Walter 254, 256, 257 patriarchy, paternal authority 103, 109, 112, 123, 182 patriotism 145, 149, 168, 171 peace 27, 85, 89, 90–1, 94, 95, 96–7, 99, 117, 167, 169, 201 pedagogy 1, 49, 57, 61, 62, 79, 108, 240, 249 pedagogical method; associationism, association of ideas 132–3, 135, 141, 150, 195–6, 198, 275; commentary 43; dialectic 17, 22, 57, 58, 59, 62, 67–8, 240, 241; demonstration, proof 44, 47, 84, 92, 93, 94, 199–200; enjoyment 70–1, 196, 200, 203; experiment 194, 195, 196, 197; games, play 71, 72, 75–6, 79, 108, 148, 183, 184, 190, 239; manipulation, subterfuge 84, 99, 135, 140, 146, 155; rote learning, memory 87, 185, 203, 222; story telling 152, 199; see also: teaching pederasty 254, 257–8, 259–60, 261, 263, 264 Peirce, C.S. 267, 274 Pestalozzi, Johann 4, 5, 182, 183, 188, 197, 203 philia, see: love, friendship philosophical method 6, 7, 15, 17, 39, 41, 55, 57–8, 75, 79, 87–8, 150, 195, 220,

Index 237–8, 245; see also: allegory; consequentialism; contextualism; dialectic; idealism; socratic method; philosophy; divisions of 3, 9, 21–2, 31–2, 35, 38, 39, 42–6, 54–5, 67–8, 104, 141, 147, 153, 164, 186, 197, 215; Purposes of 1, 2–3, 8, 9, 16–7, 23, 38, 41, 46–9, 76, 80, 84, 116, 140, 169, 215, 239–40, 241, 246, 261, 267 phronesis 22–3, 26, 32–3, 35 Phronesis Praxis Perspective (PPP), see: dunne physical education, see: education, physical physics 39, 40, 41, 42–46, 49, 54, 122, 214 piety 7–8, 9–11, 40, 68, 69, 78 Plato 4, 7–8, 9, 11, 13, 14, 17–8, 21, 23, 27, 38, 41, 43, 46–7, 48, 83, 115, 116, 126, 134, 176, 220, 237, 254–9, 263; Crito 10; Charmides 7, 11–13; Euthyphro 8, 10, 15, 16, 116; Gorgias 7, 16–7; Republic 9, 10, 17, 18, 27, 41, 116, 134, 178; Symposium 13, 18, 254, 256, 257, 261 Plowden Report 271–2, 281 Plutarch 40, 42 poetry 29, 39, 40–1, 189, 196, 212, 217, 219, 220, 231, 245, 256, 258 Polis 23, 24, 27, 115, 118; see also: state political science 23–4, 26, 32, 59; aristotelian 21–3 political stability, see: stability political theory 24, 59, 66, 98, 129, 148, 153, 156, 157, 220 polity, political community 3–4, 21, 28, 24, 27, 156 Pope, Alexander 147 Posidonius 39, 40, 47 power, 1–2, 3, 4, 11–12, 15, 59, 63, 67, 74, 91, 93, 98, 103, 106, 109, 111, 113, 116, 118, 122, 123, 127, 147, 156, 167, 194, 196, 198, 202, 229, 239, 242; political power 1, 3, 4, 61, 103, 109–10, 157, 161, 168, 181, 269, 279; spiritual, religious, power 99, 230, 246; of prince, of king, of sovereign 49, 60, 83–4, 85, 89, 90, 95–6, 97 practice 6, 18, 22, 23, 25, 28, 31, 32, 33–4, 35, 39, 40, 42, 43, 44, 46–7, 55, 57–8, 59, 61, 66, 67, 68, 69, 70, 72, 74, 75, 77, 78–9, 80, 83, 97, 105, 111, 115, 132, 185, 195, 201, 211, 225, 237, 241, 242, 244, 245, 246, 248,

291

250, 252, 253, 255, 262, 264–5, 268, 274, 275, 280–2; see also: habit, socialisation pragmatism 57–8, 234, 267, 270, 274, 275–6, 279 pride 78, 107, 138, 165, 190 Priestley, Joseph 195–6, 198, 200, 205 privacy, private 1, 3, 30, 55, 71, 75–6, 84, 89, 90, 107, 115, 120, 121, 124, 125, 126, 135, 135, 153, 154, 182, 187, 255–6, 282 progress, progressivism 22, 25, 30, 43, 45, 48, 129–30, 147, 161, 163, 165–8, 171, 173, 189, 191, 195, 197, 199, 200, 201, 205, 214, 215, 222, 227, 238, 239, 244, 269, 270, 271, 272, 277 property 89, 104, 108, 111, 125, 137, 151, 162, 182, 187, 197, 244 public, public concern, public life 1, 2, 3, 4, 10, 21, 24, 27, 28, 29, 30, 32, 49, 59, 69, 73, 75, 76, 83, 85, 87, 89, 90–1, 92, 93, 96, 98, 99, 108, 111–2, 115, 119, 121, 125, 126, 129, 133, 135, 136, 151, 153, 157, 160, 162, 163, 166, 167, 170, 179, 181, 187, 194, 197, 201, 203, 204, 211–2, 216, 218, 221, 226, 227, 229, 244, 245, 246, 247, 248, 253, 264, 273, 277, 281, 282; see also: schools, public punishment 2, 71, 77, 91, 92–3, 95, 98, 99, 106–7, 111, 113, 123, 148, 150, 156, 162, 179, 184, 188, 197, 203 pupil 40, 47, 72, 169, 185, 212, 216, 218, 239, 276; see also: teacher-pupil relationship Quadrivium 41, 54 Quarterly Review, The 200, 205 rationality, rationalism, reason 3, 18, 22, 24–5, 27, 31–2, 34, 44, 46–8, 57, 59, 74, 76, 81, 90–3, 95, 97, 98, 105, 106, 118–20, 120, 124, 125, 147–8, 149, 152, 154, 156, 157, 171, 244; see also: Justification Rawls, John 1–3, 5, 91, 98 reading 29, 38, 43, 48, 53, 54, 56, 57, 58, 88, 183, 233; see also: signs reality, realism, realisation 47, 56, 118, 121, 125, 127, 129, 152, 153, 156, 178, 188, 192, 200, 219, 228, 237, 238–9, 240, 241–3, 249, 250, 258, 274, 275, 279

292

Index

reformation 67, 78–9 Reid, Thomas 131 religion, religious practice 3, 7, 9, 28, 68, 75–6, 79, 80, 88, 90, 94, 110–2, 124, 136, 140, 141, 146–7, 148, 151, 153, 157, 168, 171, 173, 179, 180, 181, 184, 185, 194–7, 227, 230, 232, 233, 254, 257, 262, 269; see also: Education, religious renaissance 21, 22, 63, 66, 67–9, 79 republic, republicanism 38, 60, 86, 87–9, 90, 100, 117, 120–1, 127, 130, 132–4, 149, 155–7, 169, 258–9 rhetoric 38–40, 55, 57, 58, 67–70, 79, 99, 151, 209 rights X, 60, 85, 88, 91, 99, 146, 149, 153, 155, 156, 196, 197, 204, 205, 217, 223–6, 231, 246; to Education 85, 102–13, 153, 156, 217, 224; to Punish 111; to Resist 112, 146; to Work 153, 156 Robertson, J. 162 Roman Empire, Roman imperial era 161, 38–49 Rorem, P. 55 Rousseau, John-Jacques 115–27, 134, 136–8, 148–51, 153, 154, 163, 165, 166, 169, 241 sacred 53–6, 60, 62, 151 Savigny, Friedrich Carl 161 scepticism 9, 59, 61, 162 Schelling, Friedrich 163 Schleiermacher, Daniel Friedrich 160–73 scholastics, scholasticism 1, 4, 52, 62, 67, 68, 79, 87, 88 schools; boarding schools 108, 153, 155; cathedral schools 52; common school 27, 28, 32, 279; free schools 86, 281; French écoles speciales 171; girls’ schools 225, 226, 253; home school 72, 73; Infant Schools, écoles maternelles 192; national schools 185, 210; public schools (English)108, 112, 216, 218, 226, 252, 253, 263, 280, 282; private schools 153; secondary schools 225, 231, 248 science 22–3, 24, 41, 59, 85, 90–2, 129, 130, 140, 161, 163–5, 167, 168, 172, 173, 189, 195–7, 199, 201, 202, 204, 213–5, 220, 240, 272, 277; see also: Episteme, Social Science secular 52–6, 60–2, 94

self; self-interest 10, 15, 147, 156, 249; self-cultivation, self-improvement 45, 160–73; self-love 14, 15, 43, 117, 118, 124, 135; self-realisation 188, 250; self-understanding, self-knowledge 12, 14, 15, 53 Seneca 4, 38–43, 45, 46, 48, 88, 186 sex 149, 150, 154, 155, 183, 184, 188, 190, 191, 224, 229, 230, 232, 233, 252–5, 258–61, 263–5 sexual difference 149, 151, 226–8, 230, 233; see also: Gender Shaftesbury 131 Sidgwick, Henry 231 sin 53, 73, 74, 79, 89, 194, 227, 230, 272 signs, meaning 54, 184; see also: interpretation Smith, Adam 130, 131, 134, 138–40, 244 social obligation, see: obligation social relationships, society, social structure 43, 51, 72, 73, 107, 155, 167 socialisation 1–3, 122, 152, 173, 214 socialism 180, 181, 183, 192, 265 social science 129, 130, 204, 214, 219; see also: ‘Ethology’ Society for the Diffusion of Useful Knowledge, The 202 Socrates 1, 4, 6–10; see also: eros, pederasty socratic method 6, 8, 10, 15 Somerville, Mary 203, 205, 225 soul 7, 9, 11–18, 47, 56, 61, 124 Soulsby, Lucy 225 sovereignty 4, 85, 88, 91 Spalding, Joachim 164 spiritualism 179, stability 2–3, 91, 97, 115, 212 state power 60, 103, 104, 111, 112, 153, 167, 168, 171; see also: sovereignty, polis, power Steffens, Halle Henrik 163 Stoics, stoicism 38–50, 147–148 student life, student culture 17, 167; see also: universities subsistence 187 suffrage 202, 210, 224; plural voting 210; votes for women 210, 234 Sweeney, E 54, 56 Symonds, John Addington 1, 255–264 sympathy 134, 147, 184

Index Taunton Commission 210, 218, 225 Taylor, Harriet 212, 213 Taylor, J 54, 62 teacher 17, 22, 43, 44, 48, 52, 69, 71–4, 92, 115, 124, 184, 191, 239, 241, 272–273, 280, 282; teacher-pupil relationship 4, 46, 212–213, 252, 263 teaching; as catechism 94; as coaching 25; as imprinting 94, 96–97; as preaching 58, 87, 93; see also: pedagogy, padagogical method, education temperance 7–8, 47, 180, 253 theology 39–40, 68, 71, 126, 155–156; see also: deism, piety theory 6, 42, 46–47, 104, 126, 129–141, 151, 267, 268, 269, 275; and practice 33, 46–47, 185, 268, 275, 282; see also: practice Tocqueville, Alexis de 214 Tory 145 trades unions, trades unionism 179, 202 Trivium 41, 55–58, 62 truth 2, 21, 24, 40, 59 105; christian truth 54, 68, 75 Turnbull, George 130, 131–133 tyranny, tyrant 60, 62 unitarianism 194–197 universal basic income 187–188; see also: equality universe 40, 42, 45, 186 university, universities 3, 62, 66, 83, 85–87, 139, 160–163, 168–172, 219, 220, 246–248, 254 utilitarianism 197, 215, 250 Utopianism 74–78, 105, 178–192, 237 Valla, Lorenzo 67 Veyne, P 42 vices, human vices 25, 61, 73, 76, 107, 131, 153; of rulers 250, 259; see also: pride Vives, Juan Luis 66, 67 virtue 7–9, 24–26, 76–80, 132, 135–136, 147, 153; citizen virtue 28, 30, 86, 90; human virtues 7–8, 26, 30, 41; of rulers 61–62, 259; see also: wisdom Vlastos, G 15

293

Wallis, John 83 war 14, 84, 163, 184, 247, 248, 259; English civil wars 86, 87, 90, 98 Ward, Mary 225 Ward, Seth 83–84, 87, 88 warrior ideal 259 weakness, human weakness 47, 55, 58, 147, 150, 192, 259 Webster, John 83, 87 Whigs 145, 149 Whitman, Walt 260, 262 Wilde, Oscar 254–255, 260, 261, 264 Wilderspin, Samuel 192 Wilkins, John 83, 87, 88 will 14, 15, 115–127, 148, 156, 164, 242–244; will of God 117, 148; see also: free will, general will William of Conches 56 Winkler, J. 264 Winstanley, Gerrard 87 wisdom 7–16, 25–26, 41, 47, 52–61, 150, 153, 167, 195, 199, 276, 277 Wollstonecraft, Mary 1, 2, 4, 145–157, 196, 204, 230 Wolstenholme, Elizabeth 224, 227, 228, 229, 233 Wordsworth, Elizabeth 225, 230, 231, 232 work, see: labour women 72–73, 145, 146, 150–151, 154, 195–205, 210, 213, 219, 224–234, 246, 248; see also: girls work 29, 46, 76, 156, 183, 187–190, 225, 227–229, 249, 262 worship, see: religious practice Xenophon 8, 13, Zeno 38, 40, 44, 48 Zeus 44; Zeus’s city 44; see also: universe Zeitlin, F. 264 Zwingli, Ulrich 79