Human Wisdom of St. Thomas - Breviary of Philosophy from Works of St. Thomas Aquinas

Josef Pieper has attached no commentary to the texts brought together in this breviary of the philosophy of St. Thomas,

262 78 7MB

English Pages [121] Year 1948

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD FILE

Polecaj historie

Human Wisdom of St. Thomas - Breviary of Philosophy from Works of St. Thomas Aquinas

Table of contents :
The order of the parts of the universe to each other exists in virtue of the order of the whole universe to god -- The creature is vanity in so far as it comes from nothingness, but not in so far as it is an image of god -- There can be good without evil, but there cannot be evil without good -- Intellectual nature have a greater affinity to the whole than other beings -- Our intellect in understanding is extended to infinity -- Morality presupposes nature -- Reason is man's nature. Hence whatever is contrary to reason is contrary to human nature -- The desire of the last end is not amoung those things over which we have mastery -- The happienes of the active life lies in the action of prudence by which man rules himself and others -- Moral virtue does not exclude the passion -- Through virtue man is ordered to the utmost limit of his capacity -- Pleasure prfects operation just as beauty perfects youth -- Grace and virtue imitate the order of nature which is instituted by the divine wisdom -- The theologian considers human actions in so far as through them man is ordered to beatitude -- Each being naturally loves god more than itself -- Things are more in god than god is in things -- This is the final human knowledge of god: toknow that we do not know god - - KEY TO THE ABBREVIATIONS IN THE INDEX OF REFERENCES - - INDEX OF REFERENCES

Citation preview

The Human Wisdom of St. Thomas A Breviary of Philosophy from the works of ST. THOMAS AQUINAS

Arranged by

JOSEF PIEPER Translated by DROSTAN MacLAREN, O.P.

SHEED & WARD New York 1948

Copyright 1948 by Sheed & Ward, Inc.

NIHIL OBSTAT: FR, MARCUS BROCKLEHURST, O.P,, S,T,L, FR, ALBERTUS M. BRINCAT, O.P,, PHIL. BACC, IMPRIMI POTEST: FR, ANTONINUS MAGUIRE, O.P. VICARIUS PROVINCIALIS PROVINCIAE ANGLIAE LONDINI, DIE 17A MAIi, 1947,

PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA BY THE HADDON CRAFTSMEN, INC., SCRANTON, PA.

To

Dr. Franz Schranz

with affection and gratitude

CONTENTS PREFACE .................................. ........

I.

II.

III. IV. V. VI. VII.

VIII.

IX.

lX

The order of the parts of the universe to each other exists in virtue of the order of the whole universe to God ................................ The creature is vanity in so far as it comes from nothingness, but not in so far as it 1s an image of God ........................................ 6 There can be good without evil; but there cannot be evil without good........................... 9 Intellectual natures have a greater affinity to the � than other beings ......................... 19 s>ur .intellect in understanding is extended to 1nfin1ty........................................ 24 Morality presupposes nature ..................... 36 Reason is man's nature. Hence whatever is con­ trary to reason is contrary to human nature ........ 42 The desire of the last end is not among those things over which we have mastery......... . ............ 46 The happiness of the active life lies in the action of prudence by which man rules himself and others. 49 vii

CONTENTS X. XI.

XII.

XIII.

XIV.

xv. XVI. XVII.

Moral virtue does not exclude the passions........ 55 Through virtue man is ordered to the utmost limit of his capacity ................................. 58 Pleasure perfects operation just as beauty perfects youth ......................... . --:-:-:-':'. ......... 60 Grace and virtue imitate the order of nature which is instituted by the divine wisdom ............... 63 The theologian considers human actions in so far as through them man is ordered to beatitude ...... 75 Each being naturally loves God more than itself .. 78 Things are more jE_ God than God is in things .... . 87 This is the final human knowledge of God: to know that we do not know God ............. ......... . . 99

KEY TO THE ABBREVIATIONS IN THE INDEX OF REFERENCES .............................105 INDEX OF REFERENCES ............................105

VIII

PREFACE These remarks are not intended of the necessity of using his

mind

to relieve the reader

to get at the

meaning

of the texts brought together in this Breviary.

contrary,

it

all

the

seems desirable that the reader should

encounter these passages from the works of

Aquinas

On

on

his

own

Thomas

and, so to speak, left alone

without the aid of an introduction or commentary.

It

be hoped that such an encounter will of itself introduce the reader to the form and design of the is

to

whole work of the “Universal Doctor” of Christendom. The Editor does not wish this book to be read straight through from beginning to end at one sitting, but rather that one or more of these texts, or even a whole section, should be absorbed thoughtfully again and again; in this way the reader will kindle his own thinking, and by gradually making the thought of St. Thomas his own, he will gain some degree of familiarity with the philosophical attitude with which each and every one of these words has been uttered. I therefore deliberately refrain from even the briefest interpretation of my own of the basic thought of St. Thomas Aquinas contained in this synthesis. In spite of this, I must not omit to point out that this book, which is intended to be a Breviary of “Philosophy,” contains nothing which is Theology in the strict sense of the term. (That can be left over for IX

PREFACE a second, similar, self-contained collection of texts.)

must be remembered that this philosophy has sprung from the soil of a great theology in which alone was it able to flourish. Also it can scarcely remain hidden from anyone who follows the thought Nevertheless,

it

attentively that the reflections here gathered together

lead to the gateway of

word

of our Breviary

the eagle; blessed

which

human

like

Theology and

is

The

Faith.

that concerning the

beyond

all

human power

last

owl and

is

a heart

an eagle, flying upwards over the mists of with deeply penetrating eye into

frailty, gazes

the light of unchangeable truth.

“Order and Mystery”: this title needs a word of explanation. It has become almost a commonplace that ordo represents a basic category of mediaeval

thought,

and

especially

of

the system

of

Thomas

Aquinas.

Ordo: represents the clear and

up

intelligible building

of reality, as well as the doctrine

which

reality; it represents the satisfaction

reflects that

enjoyed by our

and penetrating the pattern of life which can be trodden and followed by our thought. And in fact nobody who minds

in surveying

life;

represents ways of

it

has absorbed into himself even a

little

Theologica” will be able completely to

of the

“Summa

resist the cold,

enchantment which the reason in its search for enlightenment encounters in an explanation of the

logical

universe constructed with such architectural power. Nevertheless, anyone

who

does not see this world,

apparently explained with the utmost clarity of reason.

PREFACE surrounded on all its borders by pathless mystery does not do justice to Thomas Aquinas. In the opinion of Thomas, not only does mystery put a limit to the penetrability of reality, but ordo itself is interwoven and crossed by mystery. And it is not only mystery in

theological

the

sense,

likewise

flowing

through every part of the whole world, which opposes itself to the grasp of our ordering thought and our attempts at rational mastery. No, the boundary between order and mystery passes through this world itself;

the effort of

human thought, says Thomas, has down the essence of a single

not been able to track gnat.

One aim

of our Breviary

double aspect of the work of and the mystery.

to demonstrate this

is

St.

Thomas: the order

Anticipating a probable objection by

critics, I

myself

wish to say quite frankly that the choice of the texts has been determined entirely by the personal feelings

remark may also be allowed work I had in mind especially my friends, and I included only such texts

of the chooser; so a personal here.

During

own

circle of

as I

this

should like to bring to their notice. This

order that the real character of

made

visible to

them

objective point of view

St.

did in

Thomas might be

in this way. Yet after

may

I

all,

the

balance the subjective to

a certain extent.

This Thomist Breviary has, I suppose, scarcely been harmed by the fact that the work of selection and translation has been done during my years of service in the XI

PREFACE army, and had to progress in a not very academic atmosphere. In such changing conditions of life, what has already for the tialities

become first

time,

familiar

is

encountered afresh,

as if

and with previously unknown poten-

of understanding. In this

way not

a few tract-

which I thought I knew very well, at this second meeting have entirely surprised me. It is now my hope that the character of Thomas Aquinas as revealed in this Breviary, may dawn on the reader also, whether already acquainted with it or not, with that morning power of radiation which is usual at a first meeting. ates,

JOSEF PIEPER

xii

The least insight that one can obtain into sublime things

is

more

desirable

than the most certain knowledge of

lower things

(I,

i,

5 ad

1).

I The order of the parts of the universe to each other exists in virtue of the order of the whole universe to God. (1) ( 2) Everything eternal 1s necessary. (3) Just as God himself is One, so he also produces unity; not only because each being is one in itself, but also because all things in a certain sense are one perfect unity. (4) The more unity a thing has, the more perfect is its goodness and power. (5) The higher a nature is, the more closely related to it is what emanates from it. (6) Everything imperfect strives after perfection. (7) The source of every imperfect thing lies neces­ sarily in one perfect being. (8) The beginning of everything is directed towards its perfection. This is clear in those things

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

which are done by nature, as well as in those things which are made by art. Thus every beginning of perfection is ordered to the complete perfection, which is realized in the last (9)

end.

The

higher the rank a thing holds in the uni-

verse, the

more

it

ought to participate in that

order in which the goodness of the universe consists.

(10)

(11)

The more

power and the greater degree of goodness it possesses, the more universal is its striving after goodness and the more it seeks out and accomplishes good in that which is distant from it.

The

perfect a thing

is

in

sign of perfection in lower beings

is

that

they are able to produce things like themselves.

(12)

What comes from God

is

well ordered.

the order of things consists in are led to

(13)

God

that they

each one by the others.

The complete mands

this,

Now

perfection of the universe de-

that there should be created natures

which return

to

God, not only according

to the

likeness of their being, but also through their actions.

This can only be through the acts of and the will, because God himself

the reason

s

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF has no other

way

Hence, for the it

ST.

THOMAS

of acting towards himself.

final perfection of the universe,

was necessary that there should be intellectual

beings.

(14)

Although a thing which adheres firmly to God better, yet a thing which can either adhere to God or not is also good. Hence that world in which both these kinds of beings are found is better than one in which there is only one kind. is

(15)

Although a being subject to decay would be if it were incorruptible, yet a world composed of both permanent and transitory beings is better than one in which there of higher degree

are only incorruptible beings.

(16)

Although

spiritual substance

is

better than cor-

poreal substance, nevertheless a world in which there were only spiritual beings

would not be

better but rather less perfect.

(17)

All

movement

is

derived from something un-

moved.

(18)

Everything changeable

moved is

is

reduced to a

first

un-

being; hence each particular knowledge

also derived

from some completely certain

knowledge, which

is

3

not subject to error.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (ig)

ST.

THOMAS

The

order of divine providence demands that there should be coincidence and chance in things.

(20)

(21)

The perfection of the whole of corporeal nature depends in a certain sense on the perfection of man. The is

lowest

member

of a higher class of beings

always found in contact with the highest

member

of a lower class.

of animal

life

Thus

the lowest type

scarcely exceeds the life of plants;

which have no movement have only the sense of touch and stick to the earth just like plants. Hence the blessed Denis says, The Divine Wisdom joins the last of the higher kind with the first of the lower kind. In the genus of corporeal things we can therefore take something supreme, namely the human body, which is united in harmonious equilibrium. It touches the lowest member of a higher class, namely the human soul which, from its mode of understanding, can be perceived to hold for example, oysters

the lowest position in the class of intellectual

Hence

comes to pass that the intellectual soul is said to be like the horizon or boundary line between corporeal and incorporeal substance, since it is itself an incorporeal substance and yet is the form of the body. beings.

it

4

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (ss)

Intellect

universe.

must

is .

.

the .

first

end of the universe good of the intellect. Hence truth must be

last

necessarily be the is

THOMAS

author and mover of the

Hence the

This, however,

ST.

truth.

the last end of the whole universe.

II

The

creature

vanity in

is

comes from nothingness, but not in so far as it is an image of God. (23) so far as

(24)

Even though created beings will never sink

(25)

The

creature

it

pass away, they

back into nothingness. darkness in so far as

is

out of nothing. But inasmuch as origin from God,

and (26)

it

(27)

The

image

the cause of a tendency to notitself,

in

has developed out of nothing.

is distant from that which namely God, the nearer it is to nothingness. But the nearer a being stands to God, the further away it is from nothingness.

is

(28)

it

its

him.

being. Rather the creature has this of so far as

comes has

participates in his

this leads to likeness to

God cannot be

it

it

further a being

Being of

itself,

The movement creature this

is

proper to the nature of a

not a tendency towards nothingness:

movement

has a fixed direction towards 6

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

good and the tendency towards nothingness only a defect in

(29)

is

it.

Since free will comes from nothingness,

it is its

peculiar property not to be naturally confirmed in good.

(30)

The

property of being pliant to evil belongs

to the will in virtue of

ness

(31)

and not because

The

it

its

origin from nothing-

comes from God.

intellectual creature cannot naturally

relieved of the possibilities of sinning; since

has arisen out of nothingness,

it

be it

can be capable

of defect.

(32)

not a convincing argument to say

It is clearly

that

what

is

derived from nothing tends of

and thus the potency

to nothingness

being resides in created by

God

itself

to not-

created things. For beings

all

can only be said to tend towards

nothing in the same way

as they

have also taken

from nothing. This, however, happens only through the power of the agent. their origin

Hence

the potency to not-being does not dwell

but God has the power either to them being or to allow the inflow of being them to dry up.

in creatures,

give into

(33)

Even

that

which

is

stable in things 7

would sink

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

back into nothingness, since it arises from nothing, were it not held up by the hand of the governor of all things.

(34)

The

potency to not-being of spiritual creatures

dwells

more

in God,

who can withdraw

the

influx of his power, than in the nature of those

creatures themselves.

(35)

God were

reduce a being to nothingness, he would not do it by an action, but because he If

would

to

cease to act.

8

Ill

There can be good without

be

(37)

Every creature participates in goodness in the

same degree

(38)

(39)

but there cannot without good. (36)

evil;

evil

as

it

participates in being.

and

Everything that

is,

good

it exists.

in so far as

Being

itself is like

in whatever

goodness.

way

it is, is

Good and Being

are convertible ideas.

(40)

Good and

true and being are one and the same

thing in reality, but in the

mind they

are dis-

tinguished from each other.

(41)

Good and

the inclination to good follow from

the very nature of a being; hence, so long as the nature remains, the inclination to good cannot be removed, not even from the damned.

(42)

No

(43)

Evil consists entirely in not-being.

essence

is

in itself evil. Evil has

9

no

essence.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (44)

Nothing can be

ST.

called evil in so far as

being, but only in so far as

part of

(45)

it is

it

is

it

has

deprived of

being.

Evil actions are good and far as

(46)

its

THOMAS

come from God

in so

a question of the being they possess.

All that belongs to being and action in a sinful

comes from God as first cause. But the deformity in it goes back to free will as its cause, just as the progress made by one who limps is reduced to the power of movement as its first act

cause, while all the obliquity in such a gait arises

(47)

from the crookedness of

There

God

his limbs.

is

nothing unseemly in the thought that

acts

with adulterers in their natural action,

for the nature of adulterers their will.

What

is

not

evil,

only

worked by the power of from their will but from

is

their seed springs not their nature.

Hence

it is

not unfitting that

should co-operate in that action and give

God it its

final perfection.

(48)

In the demons one

aware of both their nature, which is from God, and the deformity of their sin, which is not from God. Thus it is not is

absolutely true to say that

we must add beings.

But

—only

it is

God

is

in the demons:

in so far as they are real

absolutely true to say that 10

God

1

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF is

in things,

if

we mean

ST.

THOMAS

things whose nature

is

not deformed.

(49)

demons are intellectual substances, way have a natural urge to any whatsoever. Hence they cannot naturally

Since the

they can in no evil

be

(50)

evil.

Evil itself

which

is

not a positive thing, but that in is something positive, in so away only a part of the good.

evil adheres

far as evil takes

In the same way, blindness

is not anything but he who happens to be blind is something positive.

positive,

(51)

Just as perfection

word good,

so the

is comprehended under the word evil means nothing but

the loss of perfection.

(52)

some particular thing being but good arises only from a whole and

Evil arises through lacking,

integral cause.

(53)

A single and solitary defect is sufficient to make something bad. But for a thing to be absolutely good a single, particular goodness is not sufficient; for this the entire fulness of goodness

is

demanded. (54)

Every being

is

perfect in so far as 1

it

has real

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

existence but imperfect in so far as

and thus deprived

potential,

(55)

Good so

is

of real existence.

what all things desire, well by the Philosopher.

as

is

.

in their

own way

.

.

was

But

things

all

This

desire real, actual being.

evident from the fact that

all

said

first

things by their

very nature fight against corruption.

(56)

only

it is

Hence

real, actual

being makes up the idea of the good.

The good

fulfills

not only the idea of being

perfect but also that of causing perfection.

(57) -

Although everything being, yet being

created thing. creature

(58)

is

is

is

good in so

not

Hence

it

itself

far as

it

has

the essence of a

does not follow that a

good in virtue of

its

own

essence.

Everything naturally desires unity just as

it

also desires goodness.

(59)

There

is

no

desire

which

is

not directed towards

a good.

(60)

(61)

Nobody can

strive after evil for its

own

sake.

Sin does not occur in the will without some

ignorance in the intellect. For unless

it is

we

will nothing

good, either real or apparent. 12

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (62)

It is

THOMAS

ST.

impossible that any evil should be striven

by the natural

precisely as evil, either

after

appetite, or the sensitive, or the intellectual,

which (63)

We

is

the will.

do not

strive

towards evil by tending

towards anything but by turning away from something. Just as a thing reason of

thing

is

called

is

good by

participation in goodness, so a

its

by reason of

called evil

its

turning away

from good. (64)

Evil in things

lies

outside any purpose:

it

occurs

without the intention of the agent.

(65)

(66)

Even

aimed at in sin is something evil in reality and opposed to the rational nature, nevertheless it is apprehended as a good and according to nature. Evil

that

if

is

is

never loved except under the aspect of

good; that in

which

is

to say, in so far as

some particular

respect,

it is

but

is

truly a

good

conceived as

absolutely good.

(67)

To

will evil

is

neither freedom nor a part of

freedom.

(68)

Pain at the

loss of

something good shows the

goodness of the nature.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (69)

Hatred would never overcome the sake of a

(70)

ST.

The

still

THOMAS love, except for

greater love.

rational, intellectual nature

is

related to

good and evil in a way which distinguishes it above all other beings. For every other creature is naturally ordered to some particular, partial

On

good.

the other hand, only the intellectual

nature apprehends the universal idea of good itself

through

moved by is

fault

(71)

and is good in its

intellectual knowledge,

the desire of the will to the

universality. evil

its

Hence, among rational creatures,

divided in a particular way, namely, into

and punishment.

In the sphere of free-will every evil

is

either

punishment or fault. Fault comes nearer than punishment to the idea of evil. (72)

Punishment

who

is

is opposed to the good of the one punished and deprived of some good.

Fault stands in opposition to the good of the

order towards God, and thus

it is

directly op-

posed to the divine goodness.

(73)

Judgment must not be passed on

things accord-

ing to the opinion of the wicked, but according to that of the good, just as in matters of taste,

judgment must not be according

to the opinion

of the sick, but according to that of the healthy. 14

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF Hence punishment

is

ST.

THOMAS

not to be regarded as the

greater evil, because the wicked are of

it;

To

more

afraid

must rather be held as the greater

because the good are more afraid of

evil,

(74)

but

fault

it.

the order of the universe there also belongs

the order of justice,

ment should be

which demands that punishon everyone who sins.

inflicted

God is the author of the evil punishment, but not of the evil which

In this respect,

which is

(75)

is

fault.

It is

thus determined in the order of divine

one is subject in punishment to the power of him by whose suggestion one has con-

justice: that

sented to

(76)

sin.

must be avoided in every way; hence it is in no way permitted to do evil so that from it some good may arise. But good need not be done in every way; hence some good must Evil

sometimes be omitted in order that great may be avoided.

(77)

Just as good

is

naturally prior to evil, which

signifies a lack of

soul,

good, so the affections of the

whose object

to those affections

which therefore

evils

is

good, are naturally prior

whose object is evil, and from the former. Hence

arise 15

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

hatred and sadness have their cause in some love, desire or pleasure.

(78)

Good

is

the cause of evil in so far as

a cause at

all.

For

it

must be

Evil

(80)

Every is

is

can have

realised that evil

cannot have a cause, proper to

(79)

it

itself.

not caused except by good. evil

is

based on some good.

based on the good rooted in

.

.

.

Moral

human

evil

nature;

which springs from the nature and is the privation of being, is based on matter which is good, like being which only exists potentially. evil

(81)

Everything everything

(82)

evil

is

false in

Evil produces

no

rooted in some good, and

some

truth.

except in virtue of some

effect

good.

(83)

Evil does not fight against good except in virtue of good. For in itself

and (84)

is

the source of

However much

it is

no

evil

powerless and weak,

activity.

is

multiplied,

able completely to swallow

(85) Stronger than the evil in wickedness

in goodness. 16

it

is

never

up good. is

the good

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (86)

Good can be

(87)

Though

ST.

THOMAS

form than evil. For there is some good in which no evil is mixed, but there is nothing so very evil that no good is mixed in it. realised in purer

evil always lessens

good, yet

able completely to destroy

it.

it is

never

Just as in this

way some good always remains, so there cannot be anything completely and wholly evil. (88)

There can be no supreme evil in the same way is a supreme good, which is essentially

as there

good.

(89)

In the world nothing

and completely (90)

is

found which

is

wholly

evil.

In every sinful action there remains something good.

(91)

Nothing is so very evil that it cannot have some appearance of good; and by reason of such goodness

(92) It

is

it is

able to

move

the desire.

impossible for the good of our nature to be

destroyed completely by

sin.

is not impossible that an evil should be ordered to good by some good; but it is impossible that anything should be ordered to evil by some good.

(93) It

17

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (94)

(95)

(97)

THOMAS

were completely excluded from reality, it would mean that much good would also be taken away. Divine providence does not imply the complete removal of evil from reality, but rather the ordering to some good of the evil which arises. If evil

Many good

things

would disappear

not allow some evil to

(96)

ST.

If

God had

if

God

did

exist.

taken away from the world every-

thing which

man

the universe

would remain imperfect.

has

made an

occasion of sin,

were taken away from some parts of the universe, then much of its perfection would disappear, for its beauty arises from the orderly union of good and evil, while evil springs from the waning away of good. Nevertheless, by the foresight of the governor of the universe, good follows from evil just as the song receives its sweetness from the interval of silence. If evil

18

IV Intellectual natures have

a greater affinity to the

whole than other beings. (99)

(98)

In the universe only the intellectual nature is its own account, all others on account

sought on of

( 1

00)

it.

The highest step

in the

tion of creatures

which matter tends

Man (101)

It

is

whole process of genera-

the

is

human

as its

therefore the

soul,

towards

ultimate form.

end of

all

.

.

.

generation.

follows that spiritual things are called great

according to their fullness of being. For Augustine says that,

no (102)

size, to

among

be greater

is

those things

which have

the same as to be better.

Intellectual natures have a greater affinity to

the whole than other beings; for every intellectual being

in so far as

is

by the power of

manner all things, comprehend all being

in a certain

it is

able to its

understanding. Every other

nature possesses only an imperfect participation in being. 19

— THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (1

03)

The and

( 1

04)

The

desire of

man

to

is

ST.

THOMAS

know something whole

perfect.

soul

is

given to

man

in the place of all the

forms, so that in a certain sense

man might

be

all things.

(105)

The

natural perfection of each single being

which

is

in the state of potentiality consists in

can be made actual. But the in the state of potentiality with

the fact that intellect

is

it

regard to things which can be known. Before is

made

perfect that

it

actual

when

imperfect; but

is

it

it is

it

is

it

made

carried over into the act, so

arrives at the

knowledge of

things.

Hence

some philosophers, directing their attention to the natural perfection of man, have said that the final happiness of that in his soul

is

man

consists in this

reflected the order of the

Man’s beatitude consists in whole universe. the knowledge of God but not in the knowledge of created things. Hence one is not more blessed because of the knowledge of creatures, but only because of the knowledge of God. Nevertheless, this very knowledge of created things belongs .

.

.

to the natural perfection of the soul.

(106)

It is said that

the soul

things, because

In this

way

it is

it is

is

in a certain sense all

created to

know

all things.

possible for the perfection of 20

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

the whole universe to have

its

THOMAS existence in one

Hence, according to philosophers, which the soul can attain is that in it is reflected the whole order of the universe and its causes. This also, they say, is the last end of man, which in our opinion will be attained in the vision of God. What is single being.

the ultimate perfection to

there that they will not see,

who (107)

him

(Gregory the Great)

acts.

man

is not only a soul but a and body. But Plato was able to assert that man is a soul which makes use of the body, because he attributed sense percep-

It is clear that

compound

of soul

tion to the soul as proper to

(109)

will see

Only the intellectual creature is able to comprehend the direction by which it is directed to its

own (108)

sees all things?

who

In so far as the soul

is

it.

the form of the body,

it

has not got an existence apart from the exist-

ence of the body;

through

(110)

it is

rather united to the body

this existence.

Union with

the

body belongs

to the essence of

the soul.

(ill)

Since the soul

is

only a part of

human

nature.

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF it

in

(112)

does not possess

its

ST.

THOMAS

natural perfection except

union with the body.

Hence our body itself

is

transitory because

perfectly subject to the soul; for

completely subject to the soul,

would overflow

to

it

not

it is

were

it

immortality

from the immortality of

the soul.

(113)

It is clear that

the better a

body

is

prepared,

the better will be the soul allotted to

Since

among men

.

.

.

some who possess them also will be endowed with a greater power there are

a better-disposed body, allotted a soul

it.

to

of understanding.

(114)

Since the body with which the intellectual soul is

united must be prepared in the best way,

is

necessary for the sensitive nature to possess

it

the finest possible organ of the sense of touch.

Hence

it is

said that

among

all sensitive

beings

we have

the most reliable sense of touch,

also that

it is

and on account of the delicacy of this sense that one man is more fitted than another for the work of the intellect (Aristotle)

(115)

All the other senses are based

on the sense

of

Among all beings which have sense perception, man has the most delicate sense of touch. And among men, those who possess touch.

.

.

.

.

.

.

22

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF more

the

THOMAS

ST.

refined sense of touch have the best

intelligence.

(116)

Since tion

man

possesses intellect

and bodily

and sense percep-

strength, so, according to the

plan of divine providence, these are

(117)

all

har-

monized in him, in the likeness of which is found in the universe.

that order

The human

abundance on the

soul possesses such an

of various powers because

dwells

it

borders of spiritual and material being; in

it

therefore the powers of both kinds of being

meet together. (118)

Natural things learn nothing and forget nothing.

...

We

do not forget nor do we learn

natural things.

(119)

In

man

there

is

not only

memory but

also retro-

spection.

(120)

A

devil

knows the nature

better than

(121)

In us there

man is

of

human

thought

does.

not only the pleasure which

we

share with the beasts, but also the pleasure

which we share with the

23

angels.

V Our

in

intellect

standing

under-

extended to

is

infinity. (122)

(123)

(124)

Desire of the knowledge of truth nature.

In

active nature the intellect

its

naturally capable of

peculiar to

is

human

therefore

is

knowing everything

that

exists.

(125)

Wonder

(126)

Our

is

intellect in

to infinity.

(127)

the desire for knowledge.

knowing anything

This ordering of the

infinity

would be vain and

were no

infinite object of

An

is

extended

intellect to

senseless if there

knowledge.

ever-so-imperfect knowledge of most sub-

still implies high perfection for the Hence, although the human reason is unable perfectly to comprehend what lies be-

lime things soul.

yond

its limits,

perfection for perceives

(128)

it

by

nevertheless

it

acquires

itself if it, at least

in

much

some way.

faith.

The greatest kindness one can render to any man consists in leading him from error to truth. 24

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (129)

The

distinction

more

restricted,

ST.

THOMAS

between intelligent beings and those which have no knowledge lies in the fact that the latter have nothing but their own form, while intelligent beings have the forms of other things also, since the image of the thing known is in the knower. Hence it is clear that the nature of non-intelligent beings is narrower and while that of intelligent beings

has greater breadth and power of comprehension. is

( 1

30)

in

Hence the Philosopher says a certain manner all things.

The most

perfect types of beings, such as intel-

lectual beings, to their

that the soul

own

make

the most complete return

essences. In

knowing something

outside themselves, they step outside themselves in a certain sense; in so far as they

know

that

they know, they already begin to return to

midway knower and the thing known. But that return is completely achieved when they know their own essences. Hence every being which knows its own essence is said to make themselves, for the act of knowledge

is

between the

the most perfect return to

(131)

To

return to

its

own

its

essence.

essence

is

nothing other

than having independent being resting in

(132)

The

itself.

proper object of the human intellect when united with the body is natures actually existing in corporeal matter. 25

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (133)

(134)

THOMAS

ST.

Our natural knowledge can extend as far as it can be led by the hand through material things. Since the senses are the

knowledge,

we

pass

it

first

source of our

follows that all things

judgment are some way.

upon which

necessarily related to the

senses in

(135)

Although the soul creatures are, yet of

its

own

more

is

it

like

than other

from which and from which

nature, so as to distinguish

other natures, except by

way

it

of creatures

can be known by the senses, our knowledge takes its origin.

(136)

God

cannot arrive at knowledge

Although by Revelation we are elevated to the knowledge of things which would otherwise remain unknown to us, yet we are never raised so far as to know them in any way other than through things which can be known by the senses.

(137)

The

senses are not deceived concerning their

proper object.

(138)

Truth

is

faculties,

in both the reason

and the

but not in the same way.

sense-

It is in

the

reason as the result of the act of knowledge,

and

at the

same time

as

26

known by

the reason.

.

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF known by

It is is

reflected

act

on

but also

the reason because the reason

of their act.

own

its

act,

knowing not only its ... In the

relation to reality.

its

sense-faculties,

THOMAS

ST.

however, truth .

.

But

.

it

is

only the result

is

not in the sense-

known by the senses. Though the sense-faculties make true judgments on things, yet they do not know the truth by which they make true judgments. For though the senses know that they perceive things, yet they do not know their own nature, and consequently the faculties as

nature of their truth remain

(139)

No

sense organ

tion.

that

The

To

its

is

aware of

eye neither sees

it sees.

and of (140)

act, its relation to reality

unknown by

But the

act of

judge one’s

and

its

the senses.

itself

intellect

or of

its

opera-

nor does aware of

itself, is

it

see

itself

knowing.

own judgment:

this

can only

reflects on its own and knows the relation between that upon which it judges and that by which it judges. Hence the root of all freedom lies in the reason.

be done by the reason, which

act

(141)

The

object of the natural appetite

case this thing in so far as

it is

object of the sensitive appetite

thing in so far as

it

is

is

in every

this thing. is

The

always this

agreeable and brings

pleasure; for example, water not in so far as 27

it

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF is

THOMAS

ST.

water, but precisely as pleasing to the taste.

But the proper object of the

will

perception

is

the good

is

way

taken as such. In the same

itself,

sense

distinguished from intellectual

knowledge: the apprehension of this coloured thing is proper to the senses, but the intellect

knows the very nature (142)

The

truth of the

of colour

human

itself.

intellect receives

its

and measurement from the essences of things. For the truth or falsity of an opinion depends on whether a thing is or is not. direction

(142a)

The most things;

perfect kind of order

from them

found in derived the order of our

is

is

knowledge.

(143)

The human

measured by things so not true on its own ac-

intellect

is

that man’s thought is count but is called true in virtue of its conformity with things. The divine intellect, on the other hand, is the measure of things, .

.

.

since things are true to the extent in

which they

represent the divine intellect.

(144)

Created things are midway between God’s knowledge and our knowledge, for we receive our knowledge from things which are caused by God’s knowledge. Hence just as things which can be known are prior to our knowledge and •

28

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

its measure, so is God’s knowledge the measure of created things and prior to them.

are

(145)

The word

has naturally

the reality

who as in

(146)

it

expresses than with the person

speaks, even its

Nobody

more conformity with

though

it

dwells in the speaker

subject.

perceives himself to

know

except from

the fact that he knows some object, because knowledge of some object is prior to knowledge of oneself as knowing. Hence the soul expressly attains to the perception of itself only through that which it knows or perceives. Our mind is unable to know itself in such a way that it immediately apprehends itself, but it arrives at knowledge of itself by the fact that it perceives .

.

.

other things.

(147)

It is all

necessary to say that the

human

soul

knows

things in the eternal ideas as all our knowl-

from participation in them. The is nothing else than a kind of participated image of the uncreated light in which the eternal ideas are con-

edge

arises

intellectual light dwelling in us

tained.

(148)

Just as in that part of the soul adapted to active operation, the

first

intuitive awareness of prin-

ciples never errs, so insight into the first prin29

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

knowledge never errs in that part of the which is disposed to speculative reasoning.

ciples of

soul

(149)

A

twofold relationship

One

is

found between the

when the real thing is manner of the soul and not in its own mode: the other is when the soul is related to the real thing existing in its own mode of being. Thus a thing is the object of the soul in a double way. One way is in so far as soul

and

itself in

reality.

the thing soul,

is

the soul in the

disposed or adapted to be in the

is

not according to

its

own mode

of being,

but in the manner of the soul; that is to say, in a spiritual way. This is the idea of intelligibility in so far as it is knowable. In the other way, a real thing is the object of the soul inasmuch as the soul is inclined to it and ordered to it according to the mode of real being existing in itself. This is the idea of desirability in so far as it is desirable.

(150)

Knowledge the thing

takes place in the degree in

known

is

place inasmuch as the lover real object of his love.

a nobler

but,

way

which

in the knower, but love takes is

united with the

Higher things

exist in

in themselves than in lower things

on the other hand, lower things

exist in a

nobler way in higher things than in themselves.

Hence knowledge

of lower things

is

more

valu-

able than love of them, but love of higher 30

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF and above

things,

all

THOMAS

ST.

love of God,

is

more

valuable than knowledge.

(151)

Love of God is better than knowledge of him; on the other hand, knowledge of corporeal things

better than love of them. Nevertheless,

is

considered in

the intellect

itself,

is

nobler than

the will.

(152)

Knowledge is perfected by the thing known becoming one with the knower in its image. Love, however, causes the very thing

which

itself

loved to become one with the lover

is

in a certain sense.

Hence

love has

more

unitive

power than knowledge. (153)

Union belongs desire

is

as to itself

(1

54)

to love in so far as the loving

related in affection to the thing loved

or something belonging to

Intellectual activity

made perfect in

is

ligible things are in the intellect its

own proper mode

lect

is

of being.

not injured but

is

The

action of the will,

sists

in

thing loved.

blemish when

Hence it

is

that intel-

according to

Hence

the intel-

made perfect by things. on the other hand, con-

movement towards

that in love the soul

itself.

the thing

itself,

so

fused together with the

the

soul

receives

some

clings to things in an inordi-

nate way. 31

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (155)

There

the following distinction between the

is

intellect

THOMAS

ST.

and the

Knowledge

will.

known The will,

the fact that the thing

way

in the knower.

is

is

caused by

in a certain

however, does

not act in the same way, but contrariwise, according as the will

is

related to the actual

thing desired, in so far as the one who wills seeks something in which he finds satisfaction. For this reason good and evil, which are concerned with the will, are in things; but truth and error, which are concerned with the intellect, are in the mind which knows.

(156)

Love

is

said to transform the lover into the

loved because by love the lover the thing loved.

is

But knowledge

moved towards creates likeness

in so far as an image of the thing

known

arises

in the knower.

(157)

Truth and goodness include one another. The is something good; otherwise it would not worth desiring; and the good is true; otherbe wise it would not be intelligible. truth

(158)

Since goodness and truth are convertible in reality, it follows that the

mind

as true just as truth

good is

is

known by

the

desired by the will

as good.

(159)

Truth

is

the good of the intellect; for this 32

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF reason every intellect

knows

(160)

(161)

The

is

ST.

called

THOMAS good because

it

truth.

will

would never

knowledge unless comprehended knowl-

desire

the intellect

first

edge

itself as

something good.

The

good, considered as true,

reason before

of all

is

related to the

related to the will as some-

it is

thing worth desiring.

(162)

The

intellect

is

in itself prior to the will, be-

cause the object of the will

known, yet the movement.

(163)

will

Every act of the will the will lect, for

is

will

receiving it

is

a good which

is

arises

from an

act of the

prior to a particular act of the intel-

the will tends towards the final act of

the intellect, which

The

is

prior in action and in

Nevertheless, one particular act of

intellect.

(164)

is

is

its

is

beatitude.

not a supreme rule but

is

a rule

direction from elsewhere, because

directed by the reason and intellect, not

only in us but also in God. In us intellect and will are really distinct,

and hence the

will

and

the rectitude of the will are also not the same,

but in

God

intellect

33

and

will are the

same in

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF reality,

with his will

that

man

it

when one

itself.

to will perfectly

perfection of goodness

the good, but not

would seem

directly in this

itself;

namely,

imperfectly and ineffectively

wills

than that of truth.

It

itself;

in

does not always obey

what he wished

The

is

some way always wills which he wishes to will. In one sense,

however,

(167)

of his will

In a certain sense the will always obeys namely, so that

(166)

THOMAS

and hence the rectitude

also identical

(165)

ST.

.

all

.

effectively.

more widespread

is

All beings strive after

know

that

life,

.

and

the truth.

God cannot be

loved

one cannot love what Augustine says. But we

for

one does not know, as do not know God directly in

we

this life:

see

him through a glass darkly (i Cor. 13.12). Hence we do not love him directly. To this we must reply: Although one cannot love what one



does not know, yet the order of knowledge need

not necessarily be the same as that of love.

Love

is

the term or end of knowledge; hence

can begin at once where knowledge namely, in the thing itself which is it

ceases,

known

through another thing. (168)

The

intellect

for all the

knows not only

powers of the 34

soul.

for itself,

The

but also

will wills not



THE HUMAN WISDOM OF only for

itself,

ST.

but also for

THOMAS the powers of

all

the soul.

(169)

Man

wills

(170)

The

proper object of love

good (171)

is

good by natural

necessity.

is

the good.

.

.

The

.

the proper cause of love.

Everything that

whatever

acts,

it

may

be, per-

forms every action from some kind of love.

(172)

Just as natural

movement and

rest spring

from

the form of a thing, so every affection of the soul

has

(173)

its

Love

origin in love.

is

the

first

movement

of the will

and every

faculty of desire.

(174)

In us love receives

(175)

The

first

of the '*

its

order from virtue.

act of the will does not exist in virtue

command

of the reason, but in virtue of

some higher

a natural instinct or

35

cause.

VI Morality presupposes nature. (176)

(177)

Natural love resides not only in the powers of the vegetative soul but also in all the powers of

the soul and in every part of the body, and universally in all things.

(178)

The

first

source to which every act of the will

is reduced man.

(179)

is

that

which

is

Just as natural knowledge

willed naturally by

is

always true, so

natural love always good, since

it

is

is

nothing

other than a natural urge implanted by the

author of nature. Hence, to say that a natural inclination

is

wrong

to offer

is

an insult to the

creator of nature.

(180)

In the same

way

as

the will

nature, everything that

and foundation

in

is

is

founded on

desired has

something which

is

its

origin

naturally

desired.

(181)

The

right order of things

the order of nature,

for

is

in

harmony with

natural things are

ordered to their end without any error. 36

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (182)

(183)

The

to nature.

what the reason

It is certain that

much

so that

can be

is

naturally

is

true in the highest degree; so

it is

not even possible to think

it

false.

Since the will is

which are

principles of reason are those

endowed with

(185)

THOMAS

Reason imitates nature.

conformed

(184)

ST.

is

naturally good,

always good. As

man

wills his

its

natural act

own

happiness

naturally, the natural act of the will

stood to be

life

and beatitude.

If

we

is

under-

are refer-

ring to moral good, then the will considered in

itself

is

neither good nor bad, but

potency to good and

(186)

is

in

evil.

In the sphere of intellectual knowledge and voluntary action, what

and from

it all

else

edge of naturally

is

is

natural comes

derived.

known

first

From

first,

the knowl-

principles

is

de-

rived the knowledge of that which follows from

them, and from the fact that one wills the end naturally perceived is derived the choice of the

means leading

(187)

to the end.

Action conformable to art and reason must be uniform with that which is according to nature

and

instituted

by the divine reason. 37

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (188)

A

ST.

THOMAS

natural desire cannot possibly be vain and

senseless.

(189)

(190)

Nature is presupposed by all the virtues, those bestowed gratuitously by God as well as those which are acquired.

To become reason

is

like nature

by consenting

to the

the property of those virtues dwelling

in the appetite.

(191)

Just as the order of right reason takes

from man,

so the order of nature

is

its

origin

from God

himself.

(192)

Natural inclinations dwell in things by the action of God,

who moves all

things.

Hence

it is

impossible that the natural tendency of any kind of being should be directed to something which is evil in itself. But the natural urge to carnal intercourse resides in It is therefore

perfect animals.

impossible that carnal intercourse

should be evil in

(193)

all

itself.

Even in the state of innocence there would have been generation of offspring for the multiplication of the

human

race; otherwise

would have been necessary in order a good should arise from it. 38

man’s sin

that so great

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (194)

ST.

THOMAS

may say: If the Word has assumed body, why then did the Evangelist make

Perhaps you a living

no mention the flesh,

of the spiritual soul but only of

when he

says.

The Word was made

flesh}

To

firstly

in order to manifest the reality of the In-

this I

answer: the Evangelist did this

who

carnation against the Manichees,

Word

did not take on real flesh

.

.

not fitting that the word of the good

on

take

flesh,

.

said the

since

it is

God should

which they themselves called

a

creature of the devil. (195)

Since that which

is

according to nature

is

or-

dered by the divine reason, which ought to be

whatever

trary to

human

reason, hence sin and evil done by human judgment conthe order which is commonly found

imitated by is

is

in natural things.

(196)

Everything that opposes a natural inclination is

sinful because

it

is

contrary to the law of

nature.

opposed

(197)

Sin

(198)

Since sin

is

is

to the natural inclination.

contrary to nature ... to seek the

satisfaction of a natural desire

nothing inordinate (199)

The

is

added

to

virtues perfect us so that

is

not sinful

we

follow our

natural inclinations in a fitting manner. .89

if

it.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (200)

The

natural inclination

THOMAS

ST. is

the beginning of

virtue.

(201)

Although the virtues in

their perfect state

do

not have their origin in nature, yet they cause

an inclination to that which nature, that

is

to say, that

according to

is

which

is

according

to the order of reason.

(202)

The

submission of the lower powers of the soul

comes from nature, but they are not actually and continually subject by their nature. to reason

(203)

The

natural inclination to the good of virtue

indeed a beginning of virtue, but fect virtue. tion, the

The more

horse

blind, the

is

forward, the

some object

is

not per-

perfect such an inclina-

more dangerous can

united to right reason

it is

.

.

.

it

be,

just as

if it is

when

more impetuously

not

a racing it

dashes

more violently does it collide with and the more grievously is it in-

jured.

(204)

There can be a natural a single virtue

inclination to the acts of

but not

to the acts of all the

by which the same time

virtues, because the natural readiness

a

man

is

inclined to one virtue at

causes an inclination to the contrary of another virtue.

He who happens

disposition to fortitude, 40

to

have a natural pre-

which

is

manifested in

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

the prosecution of a difficult end, to meekness,

which

is less

disposed

consists in mastering the

passions of the irascible powers.

(205)

Every sin

man

is

based on a natural desire. Since

naturally desires likeness to God, in so far

an image of the divine goodness, hence Augustine says, when speaking to God: The soul commits adultery when it turns aside from Thee and in sinning seeks outside Thee those things which it can find pure and clear only when it returns to Thee. as all naturally desired

goodness

is





41

VII

Reason

is

man’s nature.

Hence whatever

is

con-

trary to reason is contrary to

(207)

(208)

What

is

ing to

human

ordered according to reason

The good this:

human nature.

is

accord-

nature.

man, precisely

of

(206)

as

man,

consists in

that the reason should be perfect in the

knowledge of

truth,

and

that the subordinate

be regulated in accordance with the rule of reason. For man’s human nature belongs to him from the fact that he has affections should

the

(209)

power

The

rule

of reason.

-of

the

human

will

is

twofold.

One

is

immediate and homogeneous, namely, the human reason. The other is the supreme rule, namely, the eternal law, which is, so to speak, God’s reason.

(210)

The human will can only be protected from when the reason is preserved from ignorance

sin

and

error.

42

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (211)

ST.

THOMAS

Moral virtue perfects the appetitive faculty of directing it towards the good of the

man by reason.

(212)

Human

nature in the

strict sense consists in

being according to the reason. Hence a man is when he acts in accord-

said to contain himself

ance with reason.

(213)

The more

necessary something

is,

the

more

it

needs the preservation of the order of reason in

(214)

it.

Moral virtue

is

nothing other than a participa-

tion of the appetite in right reason.

(215)

The

perfection of virtue

is

achieved not by

nature but by the reason.

(2

1

6)

(217)

(218)

(219)

The reason which knows evil is not opposed good but rather shares in the idea of good. The

root cause of

human good

is

to

the reason.

Human good is the end of the moral virtues; but the good of the human soul is to be in accordance with reason. The

reason

activity.

is

the primary source of

Those sources 43

of

human

all

human

action which

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

are also found elsewhere, in

some way obey the

reason.

(220)

Every movement of the appetite conformed to true knowledge is good in itself; but every movement conformed to false knowledge is in itself

(221)

The

bad and

sinful.

spiritual beauty of the soul consists in the

fact that the

man

conduct and action of

accordance with and

fitted

to

the

is

in

spiritual

clearness of the reason.

(222)

Considered in

from the reason it is

(223)

itself is

the will which departs

always bad, no matter whether

right or wrong.

Although a man is not superior to himself, yet by whose command he has knowledge, is superior to him; thus man is bound by his the one,

own conscience. (224)

When

the reason proposes something to us as

God’s command, despise the

as despising

(225)

Conscience because

then, even

command

it is

if it is

of the reason

in error, to is

the same

God’s command.

be the law of our minds the verdict of the reason, deduced

is

said to

from the law of nature. 44

(226)

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF ST. THOMAS Man himself does not create the law;

but

through his knowledge, by which he perceives the law created by someone else, he is bound to obey the law.

(227)

To compare

the obligation of conscience with

the obligation is

due

to the

command of a superior

the same as comparing the obligation of a

divine

command with

perior’s

the obligation of a su-

command. Since

a divine

command

binds even against the order of a superior and in a higher way, the obligation of conscience

is

thus higher than the obligation of a superior’s

command, and if it

conflicts

the conscience will bind even

with the

45

command

of a superior.

VIII

The

desire of the last

end

is not among those things over which we have mas-

tery. (228)

(229)

Wherever there is

(230)

intellectual knowledge, there

also free will.

He who action,

(231)

is

The

acts against his will has

nature of free will

choose

evil;

quence of

We

is

of

will.

not the ability to

but the choice of

evil

is

a conse-

free will, in so far as the latter resides

in a created nature

(232)

no freedom

but he can truly have free

which

is

capable of defect.

are masters of our actions inasmuch as

we

are able to choose this or that. Choice, however, is

not concerned with the end, but only with

means leading to the end. Hence desire of end is not among those things over which we have mastery. the

the last

(233)

The

will necessarily desires

its last

end

so that

unable not to desire it; but it does not necessarily desire any of the means leading to it

is

the end. 46

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (234)

Anything towards which we not subject to free

(235)

THOMAS

strive naturally

is

will.

Every appetitive nature must necessarily desire peace, since

it

always strives to arrive peacefully

and without hindrance its

(236)

ST.

at that towards

which

desire goes out.

Whoever

strives

towards good, by

fact also desires beauty. ... It

that

is

is

this

very

the same desire

directed towards goodness, beauty and

peace.

(237)

The end

is

last in

execution but

first

in the in-

tention of the reason.

(238)

Man

necessarily desires everything

on account

of the last end.

(239)

Man in

is

when he is good when he is good in his

not called simply good

some part

entirety;

only, but

but the

latter

comes about through

the goodness of the will.

(240)

A good man is not one who has a good but one who has a good will.

(241)

A

(242)

good will makes a

The man who

man

absolutely good.

has a good will

a good man. 47

intellect

is

called simply

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (243)

ST.

THOMAS

Rightness of intention alone does not

make

the

will completely good.

(244)

From

the fact that one wills the end, the reason

determines on the means leading to the end.

(245)

Whenever at the

a colour

is

seen, light

same time; but one can

is

perceived

see light

without

perceiving colour.* In the same way, whenever the

means to an end are willed, the end is willed same time; but the converse does not

at the

hold good. The theory of light which St. Thomas inherited from now known to be quite erroneous. What he means by the

Aristotle

is

words, “one can see light without perceiving colour,** is that though the “diaphanous** is not visible in itself as colours are, i.e., air, ether, or atmosphere yet it may be said to be seen in the same sense as we say we see darkness.





48

IX

The

happiness of the ac-

tive life lies in the action

by which man rules himself and others.

of prudence

(246)

(247)

Three things are necessary for the salvation of man: to know what he ought to believe, to know what he ought to desire, and to know what he ought

(248)

The that

(249)

to do.

will

directed to the end, but choice to

is

which leads

to the end.

A man

does not take counsel with himself over the end, but only over the means leading to the end.

(250) (25 0

To

order

is

The name

the task of the wise man.

of wise

served only for

man

simply in

itself is re-

him whose

consideration directed to the end of the universe, which

is is

also the source of all things.

(252)

Even though knowledge 49

of universals

is

first

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF in certainty, yet

it

ST.

THOMAS

does not have

first

place in

the sphere of operation; that belongs rather to

knowledge of

particulars, since action

is

con-

cerned with particular things.

(253)

It is not the task of prudence to concern itself with the most sublime things, which are con-

sidered by wisdom. Prudence rules the things

which are ordered to wisdom, namely the means by which men ought to arrive at wisdom. In this way prudence is the servant of wisdom. (254)

Prudence considers the ways by which we rive at beatitude: but

wisdom considers

ar-

the very

object of beatitude.

(255)

Man

already possesses some share in true beati-

tude according to the measure in which he studies wisdom.

(256)

By wisdom itself one is kingdom (Wisd. 6.21).

(257)

Moral virtue presupposes knowledge.

(258)

led to the everlasting

Since practical knowledge belongs to prudence, it is

more natural

to

man

than pure speculative

knowledge.

(259)

Human

virtue

is

perfection in a 50

human

way.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF ST. THOMAS Man is not able to comprehend the truth

of

things with certainty in a simple intuition, especially

those

things

which are related

to

action and contingent.

(260)

The

happiness of the contemplative

life

lies

but the perfect consideration of the highest truth; but the happiness of the active life lies in the act of prudence, through in nothing else

which man rules himself and

(261)

The more

others.

contemplation excels the active

life,

the more service seems to be done for God by one who has to put up with a loss of his beloved contemplation in order to serve the salvation of his neighbour for God’s sake.

(262)

A precious pearl is more valuable than bread; but in the case of hunger bread would be preferred to

(263)

it.

He who is dying of hunger must be fed rather than taught, since for one in need it is better to

inherit

wealth than to be a philosopher

although the latter in tainly of higher value. (Aristotle),

(264)

To

itself is cer-

be called from the contemplative to the active life is not a loss but a gain. 51

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (265)

ST.

THOMAS

All the virtues of the appetitive part of man,

which are called the moral

virtues, in so far as

they are virtues are caused by prudence.

(266)

When

things are lower than the one

them, then to

what

is

know them

is

who knows

superior to willing

directed towards them, because then

things are in a higher in themselves



thing else

in

is

way

in the intellect than

since everything that it

in the

manner

is

in some-

of that thing

which it is. But when things are higher than the one who knows them, then the will ascends in

higher than the

mind

is

Thus

able to reach.

it

comes about that in the sphere of moral action, which is lower than man himself, an intellectual virtue gives their form to the moral virtues as prudence to the other moral virtues. In the sphere of the theological virtues, however, which are directed towards God, charity, which is a virtue of the will, gives its form to faith, which



is

(267)

an intellectual virtue.

To

prudence belongs the execution of

all pre-

cepts about the acts of justice contained in the law.

(268)

The

act of the

unless reason

(sensitive) is

desire

is

imperfect

perfected by prudence,

matter what disposition to good the appetitive faculty. 52

may

no

dwell in

Without prudence,

there-

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

cannot be discipline, or moderation,

fore, there

or any moral virtue.

(269)

Prudence is wisdom wisdom absolutely in to

human

good, but

in

human

itself.

man

is

affairs,

Prudence

is

but not directed

not the highest good

in the sphere of existing beings.

(270)

(271)

(272)

All moral virtue must be prudent. All sins are opposed to prudence, just as virtues are ruled

by prudence.

Prudence helps

all

in

(273)

them

all

the other virtues and acts

all.

In general,

man

can receive counsel from an-

other regarding that which in the very act

judgment

itself,

is

to

be done; but,

the preservation of his

in undisturbed rectitude against the

influence of the passions arises only from the

unerring rule of prudence, without which there can be no virtue.

(274)

In matters of prudence nobody

is

self-sufficient

in all things.

(275)

Those who need another,

if

know how

to

be guided by the advice of

they are in a state of grace, at least to advise themselves 53

by the

fact that

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

they seek the advice o£ someone else and are able to distinguish good and bad counsel.

(276)

human

In

activity a special

£ound wherever there domination and ordering. is

(277)

is

kind o£ prudence a special kind o£

A man

cannot be

domain

o£ a single virtue unless

sufficiently

prudent in the he is prudent

in all things.

(278)

When man

acts

against

against prudence, without

any virtue he acts which there cannot

be any moral virtue.

(279)

Prudence

by intemperance. Hence the vices opposed to prudence arise mostly from impurity. .

.

is

£rustrated chiefly

.

54

X Moral virtue does not

ex-

clude the passions. (280)

(281)

The

passions are in themselves neither

good

nor bad, since in man good and evil are determined according to the reason. Hence the passions, considered in themselves, can as well as evil,

with the reason or be contrary to (282)

What

is

be good

according as they can correspond

good

is

it.

determined for every being

according to the condition of

its

nature.

Hence

good human action is accompanied by passion and the service of the body. (283)

human

Since

soul, of

human

is made up of body and an intellectual and a sensitive part, good demands that man should sur-

nature

render himself in his totality to virtue; that is to say, both in his intellectual and sensitive

and with

part,

virtue

it

is

his body.

Hence, for

human

necessary that the desire for just

vengeance should reside not only in the rational part of the soul but also in the sensitive part

and

in the body,

moved

and that the body should be

to serve virtue. 55

— THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (284)

Hence

it is

ST.

THOMAS

true that to act from passion lessens

both praise and blame, but

to act

with passion

can increase both.

(285)

It is

not contrary to the idea of virtue that the

deliberation of the reason should be suspended in the carrying out of that

which has already

been considered by the reason. (286)

He who

is

angry or afraid

is

not praised or

blamed, but only he who, while in

this state,

behaves either properly or not.

(287)

There

are four basic passions of the soul-

Sadness, Joy,

(288)

Fear.

Like nature, passion also drives to

(289)

Hope and

itself

violently

one determined thing.

Of

all

the passions, sadness causes the most

injury to the soul.

(290)

Every virtue by which a passion

is

ordered

also gives order to the body.

(291)

Anger,

even

it is

if it

true, in

some way upsets the reason,

follows a rational judgment, but

it

helps the promptitude of action.

(292)

Anger, like

all

other movements of the sensitive 56

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF appetite, a'

man

is

ST.

THOMAS

useful from the fact that

does more

readily

when angry

what reason com-

mands.* Otherwise the sensitive appetite in man would be in vain, whereas it remains true that nature makes nothing in vain.

(293)

Since hatred wills evil to another precisely as evil, it is not satisfied with any degree of evil, since

what

is

desired for

its

own

sake

is

desired without any limit, as the Philosopher says.

.

.

.

Anger, however, wills

evil

only under

the aspect of just vengeance; hence evil inflicted exceeds the

the opinion of the one

measure of

who

is

when

the

justice in

angry, then he

becomes merciful. (294)

Despair, like hope, presupposes desire. Neither

hope nor despair is directed towards anything which does not move our desire. (295)

Fear

is

never without hope in a happy result,

which cannot in

whom

exist in

any way in the damned,

there can therefore be no fear.

(296)

All fear arises from the love of something.

(297)

Fear makes

Though anger coming nevertheless

it is

men more after a

useful because

it

deliberative than hope.

rational

judgment upsets the reason,

gives greater

promptitude in carrying

out the commands of the reason. Coming before a judgment, however, anger is bad, as it makes a true judgment almost impossible.

57

XI Through

virtue

ordered

man

utmost

the

to

is

limit of his capacity. (298)

(299)

Sin consists in the loss of order in the soul, just as sickness consists in disorder of the

(300)

Inordinate love of

(301)

All sin arises from some ignorance.

(302)

Inordinate fear

miser fears the

man (303)

is

self is

body.

the cause of all sin.

included in every

loss of

sin;

the

money, the intemperate

the loss of pleasure.

Spiritual sins contain a greater malice than

those of the flesh.

(304)

He who

from that in which

sins turns aside

the idea of the last end

is

truly found; but, as

a matter of fact, he does not cease to intend the last

end, which, however, he seeks wrongly in

other things.

(305)

The good

for everything

according to

its

is

form; evil

what is

is

that

not correspond to the order of

its

fitting to

it

which does form.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (306)

Sin

is

Virtue cause

THOMAS

nothing other than falling away from the

good which (307)

ST.

is

it

is

fitting to one’s nature.

called the limit of potentiality

.

.

.

be-

causes an inclination to the highest act

which a faculty can perform. (308)

The

nature of virtue demands that

look

up

to the last end.

59

it

should

XII Pleasure

opera-

perfects

tion just as beauty perfects youth. (309)

(310)

way

All things desire pleasure in the same

as

they desire goodness; but they strive towards pleasure on account of good and not e converso. It

does not thereby follow that pleasure

good or that

is

the

good in itself; but every pleasure does spring from some good, and some pleasure springs from that which is the highest good and good in itself. greatest

(311)

it

is

The fact that children and animals seek pleasure does not show that they are altogether wicked:

them the natural impulse acts from God, who moves them to act according to that imin

pulse.

(312)

Pleasure as the

is

a kind of perfection of operation,

Philosopher has

made

clear;

it

perfects

operation just as beauty perfects youth.

(313)

The way

good in the same towards the enjoyment of good,

desire strives towards as

which

it

strives

is

pleasure.

Thus 60

as the desire

is

moved

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

through striving towards good, so through striving towards pleasure. to action

(314)

The more

perfect action causes

more

also

perfect

pleasure.

(315)

In so far as

it is

loved, everything

becomes a

source of pleasure.

(316)

uniform in that it means the resting in some good, and in this respect it can be a rule and measure of action. He whose will comes to rest in an actual good is himself good, while he whose will comes to rest in evil is All pleasure

himself

(317)

Good

is

evil.

is

aspired to and pleasure

the same reason: this reason

is

is

desired for

nothing other

than the satisfaction of the appetite in good.

(318)

The

idea of joy

is

distinguished from that of

pleasure. Pleasure arises

from a

real

union with

some good

thing. Joy, however, does not re-

quire

the

this;

mere

satisfaction of the will

is

sufficient for the idea of joy.

(319)

Pleasure

is

not good in the highest degree from

the fact that

it

is

pleasure, but because

perfect rest in a sublime good. 61

it

is

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (380)

ST.

THOMAS

Pleasure which springs from contemplation is opposed by no sadness; nor is sadness joined except in an accidental way. to it



(321)

There is a double goodness common to pleasure and sadness; true judgment on good and evil as well as the due order of the will which accepts good and rejects evil. Thus it is clear that in pain and sadness there is some good the lessening of which can make them less good themselves. But in every pleasure there is not something evil through whose removal the pleasure itself can become better. Hence it is in fact possible that some pleasure can be the highest good of man but sadness cannot be .

the greatest

human

.

.

evil.

62

XIII

Grace and virtue imitate the order of nature which is instituted by the divine wisdom. (322) (323)

The thing

act of the intellect

known being

accomplished by the

is

in the knower; thus the

determined

excellence of the intellectual act

is

according to the degree of the

intellect.

act of the will, is

and

The

of every appetitive faculty,

perfected in the inclination of the one

desires to the actual thing desired, as to

its

who end;

hence the dignity of the act of the appetite is determined in accordance with the actual thing which is the object of this act. A thing inferior to the soul

in

itself,

manner

is

in the soul in a nobler

for every thing of that in

which

than the soul, however, itself,

what

way than

is

in another in the

it

is.

is

A

thing higher

in a nobler

way

in

than in the soul. Hence, with regard to is

inferior to us,

love, for

knowledge

is

nobler than

which reason the Philosopher places

the intellectual virtues higher than the moral

But with regard to what is above us, especially God, love is higher than knowledge. Hence charity excels faith. virtues.

63

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (324)

The

discipline

which

(325)

.

.

and moderation of the miser,

restrain the desire for intemperance beit

may

cost

Although charity

is

not necessary to

know

rather

(326)

THOMAS

money, are not true virtue. There can be no true virtue without charity.

cause .

ST.

As

it is

it is

necessary for salvation,

more

generally

good

it is

that one has charity;

useful not to know.

to love a friend in so far as

he

is

a

bad to love an enemy in so far as he is an enemy; but it is good to love an enemy m so far as he is a creature of God. To love a friend as a friend, and an enemy as an enemy, would be a contradiction; but it is no contradiction to love both friend and enemy in so far as both are creatures of God. friend, so

(327)

To

it is

love an

enemy

friend, since if

we

it

is

higher than to love only a

shows greater love of God. But

consider both acts in themselves,

better to love a friend than an enemy, better to love

God

than a friend.

involved in loving an

The

and

it

is

it is

difficulty

enemy does not determine

the nature of merit,

except inasmuch as

it

which overHence, if love were so perfect that it would completely overcome the difficulty, it would be still more meritorious. manifests the perfection of love

comes

this difficulty.

64

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (328)

THOMAS

In the idea of merit and virtue the good

more valuable than that

(329)

ST.

also meritorious:

is difficult is

is

the effort. Hence, not all

must the same

but

it

be difficult in such a way that time good in a higher way.

it is

The

good more than

nature of virtue

lies

in

at

in difficulty.

(330)

The

divine law so orders

men

to each other

one preserves his order. This means have peace with each other, for peace between men, as Augustine says, is nothing that each

men

that

other than the (331)

The

harmony

of order.

idea of peace includes the idea of concord

and adds something further. Wherever there is peace, there is also concord; but wherever concord rules, there

understood

is

at all in its

cord implies one

many

not always peace,

proper sense.

common

peace

if .

intention

.

.

is

Con-

among

people; but peace, in addition to this

common

purpose, also implies a unity of desire

opposed by a twomen with themselves and the dissension between one another. Only the second kind of dissension

in each individual. Peace fold

dissension;

is

the dissension of

opposes concord. (331a)

To is

be

the

at

peace befits love; but to

work

of ordering wisdom. 65

make peace

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (332)

A

ST.

THOMAS

father naturally loves his son

more than

brothers love each other, although the son does

not love his father as

much

as

he

is

loved by

him.

(333)

The

love with

which one loves oneself includes and child more than the love

the love of wife of father.

(334)

The common good is

the noblest

among human human

goods; but the divine goodness surpasses

good.

(335)

Man

cannot possibly be good unless he stands

in the right relation to the

(336)

(337)

(338)

The

common

good.

higher virtues are in a closer relation to

the

common

are

more

the

common

The good

good. But justice and fortitude

closely related than

temperance to

good.

whole is higher than the particular good of an individual, if both are understood as springing from the same source. But the good of a single grace is higher than the natural good of the whole universe. of the

Just as the right use of power in ruling over

many people

is

a

good 66

in the highest degree,

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF SO

is its

THOMAS

ST.

misuse in the highest degree

power can be turned into good or (339)

God’s power

is

use his power in the case of

hence he can only good way. But this is not so

man. Hence

man

(340)

it is

not sufficient for

should become like to

in power, unless he

goodness

Thus

his goodness;

in a

beatitude that

evil.

evil.

becomes

like to

God

him

in

also.

Every law is ordered to the common salvation of mankind, and it is in virtue of this quality that it possesses the nature and binding force of law. In so far as it fails in this, it has no power of obligation.

(341)

Among

the virtues only justice includes the

idea of duty; hence moral virtue

by law in the degree in which

is

determinable

it is

related to

justice.

(342)

The

task of the

human lawgiver is to rule To God alone, who is the

external actions only.

divine lawgiver,

(343)

belongs

interior

movements

Human

law

justice; if it

it

sets

the

ruling

of

the

of the will.

up no

precepts except about

prescribes the acts of other virtues,

does so only in so far as these assume the

nature of justice. 67

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (344)

(345)

Justice without

(346)

is

THOMAS

mercy cannot be perfect

Justice without

out justice

ST.

mercy

cruelty;

is

virtue.

mercy with-

the mother of laxity.

Mercy does not cancel out justice; it is rather, in a manner of speaking, the plenitude of justice.

(347)

The

old and the wise,

who

think that evil can

happen to themselves, likewise the feeble and the fearful are more merciful. Those, on also

the contrary,

and

who

think themselves to be happy,

so strong that

no

evil

can happen to them,

Thus weakness

are not so easily merciful.

is

always a foundation of mercy.*

(348)

Among

all

the moral virtues the activity of

right reason appears tice.

The wrong

most apparent in

(349)

more

use of the reason

The good of the reason

The

is

therefore

sins against justice.

lies

object and in justice as

(350)

particularly in jus-

in truth as

its

proper

its

proper

effect.

praise of fortitude in a certain sense de-

pends on justice. Hence Ambrose says. Fortitude without justice is the matter from which evil arises. * This applies only to man. God’s mercy always

68

arises

from

his love.

(351)

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF ST. THOMAS To suffer death is not to be praised for its own sake but only because of

(352)

its

order to some good.

Those who do brave deeds

for

the sake of

worldly glory are not truly brave. (353)

It

can happen that a

man may

fear death less

than he ought. (354)

Fortitude appears to excel

Virtue

among

the virtues.

concerned with things difficult and is concerned with difficulty;

is

good. But fortitude

hence

it is

we must

the greatest of the virtues.

is

The

difficulty.

The

greatness of a

therefore to be measured according to

the idea of

(355)

this

reply: the idea of virtue consists in

good rather than virtue

To

good rather than that of

difficulty.

who

are rightly

acts of fortitude in battle are

ordered to

boldest people are those

related to divine things.

(356)

The

and peace; for it would be wage war only for its own sake. victory

(357)

Fortitude has two acts



to attack

foolish to

and

to hold

one’s ground.

(358)

The most to

it

special act of fortitude,

than attacking,

to stand

immovable

is

more peculiar

to sustain, that

is

to say

69

in the face of danger.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (359)

ST.

THOMAS

Endurance truly implies a suffering attitude of the body, but it also implies an act of the soul which with all its strength perseveres in good; it follows from this that the soul does not yield to bodily passion already attacking

(360)

Endurance

is

more

difficult

than attacking, and

this for three reasons. Firstly,

to

mean

that

one stands

while one

assailant,

endurance seems

fast against a

who

it.

stronger

attacks goes forward

with superior strength; but

it is

more

difficult

weaker opponent. Secondly, endurance perceives danger already present, while for the one who attacks it is still in the future; but it is more difficult to be unmoved by the present than by the future. Thirdly, endurance implies duration in time, while one can attack with a sudden impulse; but it is more difficult to remain unmoved for a long time than to fly at some difficult object with a sudden movement. to fight against a stronger than a

(361)

A brave man

(362)

Patience tial

is

is

also patient.

included in fortitude, for the essen-

is also possessed by the namely not being upset by threatening Fortitude, however, adds something furnamely to attack the threatening evil when

quality of patience

brave, evil.

ther,

necessary.

70

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (363)

ST.

THOMAS

A man

is called patient not because he shuns but because he endures a present evil in an honourable fashion; that is to say, he is not made unduly sad by it.

evil

(364)

Among lays

the virtues temperance in particular

claim to a special beauty, and ugliness

most apparent in

(365)

There

is

especially

(366)

sins of

is

intemperance.

something shameful about all sin, but about the sin of intemperance.

Intemperance

is

most opposed to the purity and

beauty of man.

(367)

Right reason makes one exercise abstinence in a fitting way, namely, with cheerfulness of mind, and for a fitting end, namely, for the glory of God and not for the glorification of oneself.

(368)

All worldly things can be reduced to three:

honour, wealth and happiness.

(369)

Abstinence from things which bring pleasure fitting for those

who have undertaken

of contemplation and the passing

on of

the

is

life

spiritual

good to others in a kind of spiritual generation, but it is not fitting to those whose task it is to do bodily work and serve physical generation. 71

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (370)

If a

man

ST.

THOMAS from wine

deliberately abstains

to

such an extent that he does serious harm to his nature, he will not be free from blame.

(371)

(372)

Recreation

The

is

necessary to lead a

result of impurity

is

a

human

life.

harmful duplicity

of mind.

(373)

The

virtue of chastity prepares

man

best for

contemplation.

(374)

He who

gives

way

blame than he who is

(375)

less

to anger

is less

worthy of

yields to desire, for the latter

deprived of reason.

Sons imitate their fathers more in sins of anger than in sins of desire.

(376)

Meekness above

all

makes men masters of them-

selves.

(377)

(378)

Pride extinguishes

all

the virtues and destroys

all

the powers of the soul, since

to

them

The

its

rule extends

all.

skilful doctor puts

up with

his patient

by a lesser illness in order that he may recover from a serious disorder; in the same way the gravity of sins of pride is shown being

afflicted

72

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF by the

fact that

God

allows

other sins in order to heal

(379)

Many

ST.

THOMAS

man

to fall into

him from

pride.

people take pride even in their humility.

(380)

In a certain sense humility is man’s readiness to approach spiritual and divine things.

(381)

Humility makes

(382)

Humility prepares the way for wisdom.

(383)

Two

man

capable of knowing God.

things can be considered in

man; what

is

God and what is of man. ... In view of this every man must submit what is of man in himBut self to what is of God in his neighbour. humility does not demand that a man should submit what is of God in himself to that which seems to be of God in another. ... In the same way humility does not demand that a man of

.

should submit what is

(384)

(385)

of

man

of himself to that

.

which

in another.

Pusillanimity can also spring from pride.

To

act deceitfully

but a proud

(386)

is

.

The

man

is

is

a sign of pusillanimity:

open and frank in

ambitious are easily 73

made

all things.

jealous. In like

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF manner

ST.

THOMAS

the faint-hearted are jealous, as they

consider everything to be important, and whatever good

falls to

someone

be an unfair advantage.

74

else,

they believe to

XIV The theologian considers human actions in so far as through them man is ordered to beatitude. (387) (388)

The

(389)

A man is called a wayfarer because he is striving

last

end of human

life is

towards beatitude; but he

hensor”

(390)

when he

is

beatitude.

called a “compre-

has already reached beatitude.

Striving towards beatitude

is

the same as striv-

ing towards the satisfaction of the will.

(391)

Happiness is a good proper to human beings. Animals can only be called happy by a misuse of language.

(392)

Even though money

merely useful, yet it has a certain resemblance to happiness because it is

possesses the character of universality, since all

things obey

(393)

money

(Eccles. 10.19).*

In perfect beatitude the whole

man

is

made

For the miser, one who makes money the last end of human life, all things may be said to obey money. St. Thomas is here referring to the *

sin of avarice.

75

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

which means that perfection overflows from the higher to the lower part of his nature.

perfect,

In the imperfect beatitude of the present

life,

on the other hand, we proceed contrariwise from the perfection of the lower part to that of the higher part.

(394)

What

most desired and willed by the inis the supreme perfection of that nature; which perfection is its own beatiis

tellectual nature

tude.

(395)

(396)

The

rational creature naturally desires beati-

tude.

Hence

Perfect

cannot wish not to be happy.

beatitude belongs naturally to

alone, as in tical.

it

him being and

For the creature, however, beatitude

not a natural possession but

(397)

God

God

beatitude are iden-

is

is its last

beatitude by his essence.

.

.

.

is

end.

Men, how-

ever, only participate in beatitude; as Boethuis says,

they are called “gods” by reason of some

participation.

(398)

Virtuous action

is

to

be praised because

it

is

by which he

is

directed towards beatitude.

(399)

Virtues perfect

man

led to beatitude. 76

in actions

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (400)

Whatever

is

willed

is

ST.

THOMAS

in every case directed

towards beatitude, which

itself is

not desired on

account of something else and in which the

movement (401)

The

last

of the desire comes to rest.

end and beatitude

perfect operation.

77

of

man

is

his

most

XV Each being naturally loves

God more than itself. (402) (403)

(404)

Each single being is perfect in the measure in which it reaches up to its own origin. In tending towards

its

own

perfection, every-

thing tends towards God, for the perfections of all things are images of the divine being.

(405)

The

highest perfection of

in the

(406)

mind

of

Since the soul

is

man

human

life consists

being open to God.

created directly by God,

not be completely happy unless

it

it

sees

will

God

directly.

(407)

Every rational being knows God implicitly in every act of knowledge. For, just as nothing has the nature of desirability except through likeness

to

the

first

goodness, so nothing

knowable except through first

(408)

The

its

its is

likeness to the

truth.

natural desire for knowledge cannot be

satisfied in

us until

we know 78

the

first

cause,

and

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

any kind of way but in its essence. God, however, is the first cause. Hence the last end of the creature endowed with a spiritual that not in

intellect

(409)

The

God

to see

in his essence.

happiness and beatitude of any in-

final

tellectual

(410)

is

being

is

Purity makes the eye the vision of

God

know God.

to

fit

for clear vision; so also

promised

is

to the

pure of

heart.

(411)

The

creature

is

darkness compared with the

Hence created derived from the power of

excellence of the divine light.

knowledge, which created being,

(412)

is

is

called evening knowledge.

Created things in themselves do not lead away from God but towards him; for the invisible things of

God

are clearly seen, being understood

made (Rom.

1.20)

the fact that they lead us away from

God

by the things that are

from the

Hence

fault of those

it is

who

use

said: creatures are

to the feet of the

them

made

.

But

arises

foolishly.

into a snare

unwise (Wisd. 14.11). But

even in the fact that creatures lead us away from God in this way, there is evidence that they have their being from God, for they would not be able to lead the unwise away from God 79

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

except by enticing them by the good which they possess

(413)

It is

from God.

quite clearly a false opinion to say that,

with regard to the truth of

faith, it

is

completely

what one thinks about created things, provided one has the right opinion about God; an error about creatures reacts in a false knowledge of God. indifferent

(414)

The end and soul

is

ultimate perfection of the

to transcend the

human

whole order of created

things through knowledge and love, and to ad-

vance to the

(415)

first

cause,

which

is

God.

The end which the intellectual creature reaches by its own activity is the complete actualisation of the intellect in relation to all intelligible

things lying within tellect

(415a) Although the a

little

edge

it

its

becomes most

capacity; in this the in-

like to

human

God.

intellect

can

know only

about divine things, yet in that knowlfinds

its

desire, love

and happiness more

completely than in the most perfect knowledge it

(416)

can have of lower things.

All beings naturally strive towards explicitly

but implicitly. 80

God

—not

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (417)

Although the soul intellect

yet the

is

THOMAS

ST.

God through

led to

the

more than through the love of the will, movement of love reaches him more

perfectly than the intellect does.

(418)

Man

God through

love

than through his reason, because in love

man

approaches nearer to

does not act himself, but

(419)

in a

is

God

speaking drawn nearer by

manner

of

himself.

Nothing lies midway between our intellect and God, either by way of efficient causality since our minds are directly created and sanctified by God or by way of some object causing beatitude since the soul is beatified by enjoying God



— —

himself.

(420)

Love, which

even in

is

an

act of the appetitive faculty,

this life tends

from him passes on

God and

primarily to

to other things; according

to this, charity loves

God

directly but other

things through the mediation of God. In knowledge, however, the converse

know God through through

effects

is

true, since

we

other things, either as cause

or

by way of eminence or

negation.

(421)

It

can well happen that one

charity loves one created thing

another equally with 81

God and

who

is

not in

more than God,

another

less

than

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF God. But

it

is

ST.

THOMAS

impossible for one to love a

creature equally with

God and

at

the same

time love nothing more than God, because the last

end of the human

will

must

necessarily be

one single thing. (442)

(423)

worth loving in so far as it worth loving since his goodness is infinite. But no creature can love infinitely, since no finite power can be infinitely in act. Hence God alone can love himself in the most perfect way, since his power of loving Since everything

God

is

is

good,

is

as great as his goodness,

The

we

infinitely

why we

reason

cause

is

are called wayfarers

are striving towards God,

is

be-

who is our we advance

end and beatitude. In this life by coming nearer to God, not with bodily steps but through the affection of the heart. This approach, however, is made by charity because by it the mind is united with God. last

(424)

Man

is

(425)

The

love of

things:

united with

it

God through

his will.

God has the power of uniting reduces human affections from many Love

on the other hand, divides up human affections and diversifies to one.

.

.

.

of

self,

them.

(426)

Since every creature according to 82

its

nature

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF naturally belongs to God,

man

angel and

themselves, in

its

THOMAS

ST. it

follows that both

naturally love

God more

than

and before themselves. Everything naturally loves God more than

own way

itself.

(427)

Hope

leads to love in so far as the

getting of

(428)

God

some good from God for his

of

sake.

All things, in so far as they have being, are like to God, who manner.

(429)

own

hope

leads to the love

It

is

being in the

evident that

is

God, who

is

which they become

being

itself,

while

things only participate in being. last

and highest

things naturally strive

all

after being, according to like to

first

end towards which God.

all

all

other

Hence

things

strive

the is

likeness to

(430)

All things, in so far as they have being, aim at likeness to

(431)

God, who

is

being

itself.

Being is itself a likeness of the divine goodness. Hence, in so far as a thing longs for being, it desires likeness to God, and longs for God himself implicitly.

(432)

The

last

which

all

end

is

the

first

perfection 83

is

principle of being, in

preserved,

and towards

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF whose likeness their perfection,

all

THOMAS

ST.

things strive according to

some

in relation to being only,

others in relation to living being,

and others in and beati-

relation to living being, intelligence tude.

(433)

Everything which strives after tion tends towards likeness to

He who

its

own

perfec-

God.

{434)

something under some aspect of good, has a will conformed to the divine will.

(435)

All creatures participate in the divine goodness,

wills

with the result that they pour forth to others the goodness which they themselves possess. For

it

belongs to the nature of goodness to communicate itself to others.

(436)

An

good through action is implanted in every creature which comes from the hand of God. But the creature becomes more like to God by the realisation of each single inclination to

good.

(437)

Since God’s essence and operation are identical, the highest assimilation of man to in

some

action.

Hence

is

made

like to

God

beatitude,

in the

God is realised by which man

most complete way

and which is the end of human in an action. 84

life,

consists

(438)

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF ST. THOMAS When man omits to do what is in his power and only waits for God’s help, he appears to tempt

God.

(439)

Since the creature endeavours to be like to

God through many maining

who (440)

is

to

it

is

things, the last thing re-

to seek the likeness to

God,

the cause of other things.

Although there

is

some

likeness to

God

in all

creatures, only in the intellectual creature this likeness

creatures

(440a)

Our

it is

by way of image ... in other by way of vestige or footprint.

likeness to

God

is

our neighbour, which

(441)

is

prior to our likeness to is

based on the former.

Creatures do not reflect their exemplar in a perfect manner.

many there

and

Hence they can

reflect it in

many

images. But

ways, and there are is

only one perfect way of representation,

so there can only be

one Son, who

is

the

perfect image of the Father.

(442)

There

is

only one perfect uncreated image.

The

first exemplar, the divine essence, cannot be represented perfectly by a single creature but must be represented by many created

things.

85

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (443)

One

result of the vision of

fixed,

all else

when known

because

can be

the spirit

comes

the is

God

is

the

first

immutintellect

cause in which

reached, the quest of

an end.

to

THOMAS

and the will. The

ability of the intellect is

ST.

The

mutability of

the will also ceases, because nothing further

remains to be desired contains in is

(444)

(445)

itself

when

the last end,

which

the plenitude of goodness,

reached.

The

nearer a thing

to

is

God, who

is

completely

changeable and more en-

immovable, the during it is.

less

The emanation

of creatures

from God would

be imperfect unless they returned to him in equal measure.

(446)

Wood

burning in a

nature of also

(447)

made

fire;

fire

participates in the

thus in a certain sense

man

is

a participator in the divine nature.

Since the enjoyment of God, deservedly, due to his excellence, surpasses the

creatures,

it

follows

that

this

enters into

Lord (Matt.

it.

all

man but rather Enter into the joy of thy

perfect joy does not enter into

man

power of

complete and

25.21)

86

XVI Things are more in

God

than

is

in

God

things.

(448)

(449)

God

himself

said of

(450)

is

own

his

which can be

being,

no other being.

Since the proper

name

of

God

nature identical with his being

is is

He who

is,

a

proper to him

alone.

(451)

Since God’s being cannot be as

if

contained

pure being, it is not limited in any determined mode of perfection of being but contains in itself the whole of being. in a receptacle, but

(452)

is

All things in the whole world are

moved

to

by something else, except the first agent, whose action is such that he is in no way moved to act by anything else. In him nature and will act

are identical.

(453)

Time

has a before and after, aeon in

no before and

itself

has

though they can be joined

after,

87

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF to

(454)

ST.

THOMAS

but eternity has no before and tolerate such things.*

it,

does

it

The

higher a being

is,

the simpler

after,

nor

Hence

it is.

which possess the highest degree of must also possess the highest degree of

the beings nobility

simplicity.

(455)

God

(456)

Even though

is

the

first

exemplar of

all things.

all things, in so far as

they exist,

they do not all do one and the same way, but in different ways and in different degrees. Thus the divine essence is the proper exemplar and idea of a particular creature in so far as it can be reflected by this determined creature in this determined

reflect the divine essence, yet

so in

way.

(457)

From

the one

first

truth there result

human mind, just produces many images

as

human

in a

face

many

the one

truths in the

broken

mirror.

(458)

God, and what is in God, are not directed to any end but are the end.

aeviternity, or aeon is used by St. Thomas and the Scholastics the measure of the duration of spiritual substances such as angels. It comes midway between time and eternity, and may be conceived as the measure of the duration of a thing which is unchangeable in itself, but whose operations involve change.

*

Aevum,

to

mean

88

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (459)

God, who

ST.

THOMAS

acts first of all beings,

does not gain

anything for himself by his action, but com-

municates and gives out something to others. Hence things are not ordered to God as end in order to

add something

to

him, but so that

may reach the end, each in through him who is himself the they

(460)

God

loves those

their love

rather

(461)

The in

who

its

own

end.

love him, but not as

if

were the reason why he loves them;

it is

the contrary.

divine love causes the good which

some

way,

thing; but

it is

it

loves

not always so with human

love.

(462)

Since

God

is

outside the whole created order

and every creature contrary

is

is

ordered to him, but the

not true, so

it is

clear that there

a real relation of creatures to God.

There

is is,

however, no real relation of God to creatures, but only a rational one, in so far as creatures are referred to him.

(463)

(464)

We

can in truth open our hearts to God, but not without God’s help.

The word perfection, if taken in its literal sense, cannot be applied to God, for nothing is made 89

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF perfect

(factum)

(465)

except what

(per-fectum)

created

is

.

We know and judge all things in the light of the first is

truth, for the light of

our

intellect,

either natural or a gift of grace,

other than an imprint of the

(466)

THOMAS

ST.

Just as a doctor

is

first

is

which

nothing

truth.

said to cause health

though

he only acts exteriorly, while nature alone is active from within, so man is said to teach truth though he only announces it exteriorly while

God (467)

teaches interiorly.

When man

teaches he only exercises an external

activity like a doctor

when he

the interior nature

is

heals;

but just

as

the principal cause of

healing, so also the interior light of the

mind

is

the principal cause of knowledge. These, however,

(468)

We

both come from God.

acquire our interior knowledge by the fact

that things impress their likeness

on our

souls.

But in God’s knowledge the contrary is true; from his mind forms flow out to all creatures. Hence, just as knowledge in us is a sealing of our souls through things, so, on the other hand, forms are nothing other than a sealing of things through God’s knowledge.

(469)

Human rational

knowledge 90

is

in a certain sense

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF caused by things; telligible

hence

things are

THOMAS

ST. it

follows

that

the measure of

knowledge. That reality

is

in-

human

of this nature

is

a

judgment of the reason, but the contrary is not true. God’s mind is by its knowledge the cause of things. Hence his knowledge must necessarily be the measure of things, just as the rules of art measure the works of art, each of which is perfect in the degree in which it true

obeys these rules.

(470)

Even if the human intellect did not exist, things would still be called true by reason of their If, however, both were thought to be no more, which is

order to the divine intellect. intellects

impossible, the idea of truth could not exist in

(471)

any way.

The knowledge

of

God

is

compared

to created

things as art to works of art. Hence, just as art

not only knows but also creates what

is

artis-

while it only knows but does not what deviates from the rules of art, so God’s knowledge both knows and creates all good things, while it only knows sin and evil, which are deviations from his eternal law, but tically correct,

create

does not cause them.

(472)

God’s purpose or in those

is

who

not frustrated in those

attain salvation. 91

who

sin

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (473)

ST.

THOMAS

There remains one reason for the angels’ joy, men repent and when they sin, namely that the order of divine providence is both when

fulfilled.

(474)

J’^st as

a pottery vase could expect to be put to

good use by the

potter, so

man must hope

to

expect right guidance from God.

(475)

mercy that it what is more,

It is a feature of

to others and,

is

poured forth it

should

this

belongs

that

comfort the poverty of others. But

in the highest degree to the superior. Hence,

mercy belongs properly to God, and it is said that his omnipotence is here most clearly shown. (476)

God’s omnipotence

most manifest in clemency and mercy, for the supreme power of God is most clearly evident in the fact that he forgives sins freely. He who is bound by the law is

of a higher authority

is

not free to leave sins

unpunished.

(477)

Divine justice always presupposes divine mercy

upon which

it is

based.

Nothing

is

due

to the

creature except with regard to something real

already existing in latter

is

due

it

beforehand; and

to the creature, again

regard to something prior. Since

ceed to

infinity,

we must 92

it

if is

we cannot

this

with pro-

necessarily arrive at

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

something which depends only on the goodness of the divine will, which is man’s last aim and end.

(478)

(479)

(480)

(481)

Nothing is due to anyone except in virtue of something which has been given to him gratuitously by God. Things are

been created in the beginning of time, not as if the beginning of time were the measure of creation, but because heaven and earth have been created together with time.

God

said to have

has created

all

men

for beatitude.

human law is between men, so the purpose of the divine law is to establish friendship between men and God. Just as the primary purpose of

to cause friendship

(482)

(483)

The eternal law is compared to the order human reason as art to a work of art. God by

his

of the

power does touch created things in

moving them, but he himself is not touched, for the natural power of no creature is able to penetrate to God.

(484)

Irrational

creatures 93

neither

participate

in

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF human

THOMAS

ST.

reason nor do they obey

it,

yet they

participate in the divine reason by obeying

(485)

Wherever God his

is,

there he

undivided power he

is is

totally.

in

it.

Through

contact with

everything.

(486)

Even natural love, which dwells in all things, arises from some knowledge; this knowledge, however, does not belong to things themselves

but to the founder of creation.

(487)

It is

true that God,

who

is

the

first

cause, does

not enter into the essences of created things; yet created being can only be understood as

having arisen from the divine being.

(488)

though they do not give being to other things except in so far as the power of God acts in It is clear that all inferior beings,

are active,

them.

(489)

God must be in all The fact

way.

.

things

(490)

.

is

.

things in the most intimate that he acts directly in all

a sign of the almighty

power of God.

Everything which acts must be said to act through the power of God. It is God himself

who

is

the cause of the activity of all things. 94

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (491)

Though proper

created

things

effects, yet it is

ST.

THOMAS

produce

their

not superfluous that

should also produce the same

own God

because

effects,

the creature produces nothing except through

power of God. Nor is it superfluous that the effects which God can produce by himself should also be produced by other causes. This comes not from any insufficiency in the divine power, but from the immensity of God’s goodness, through which he has wished to communicate his likeness to things not only by giving them existence but also in making them the



the causes of other things. In this double the image of

Here

also

is

God

is

common

way

to all creatures.

manifested the beauty of the order

in creation.

(492)

All creatures are nothing other than an objective expression is

(493)

and representation of what

contained in the concept of the divine Word.

Knowledge and will mean that the thing known in the knower and the thing willed is in the wilier. Thus, according to knowledge and will, things are more in God than God is in is

things.

(494)

We

know that everything done by God dwells in him as known, so it follows that all created things are in him as in the divine life. Also .

95

.

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

the natures of inanimate things are alive in God’s mind, in which they have divine existence.

(495)

Since is

is

the universal cause of

God

is

is

being,

all

thus necessary that wherever being

God (496)

God

is

found,

also there present.

the cause of all action in so far as he

grants the

power

which he preserves

of acting,

and brings into act, and in so far as it power that every other power

his

When we realise

that

God

is

his

is

through

is

active.

own power and

that he dwells in every being, not as part of

essence but as holding that

it

God

it

in being,

it

its

follows

himself must act directly in every

agent; this, however, does not exclude the action of the will

(497)

The

and of nature.

natural

necessity

which are determined action of

God

directing

indwelling in to a single

them

end

things is

the

to their end, just

by which an arrow is determined is an action of the archer and not of the arrow. But there is a difference; what creatures receive from God is their nature, but what man impresses on as the necessity

to fly to a certain target

natural things, in addition to their nature,

is

the compulsion of force. Hence, just as the

necessary compulsion in the flight of the arrow

shows the aim of the archer, so the natural 96

THE tIUMAN WISDOM OF

ST.

THOMAS

necessity in creatures manifests the direction of

divine providence.

(498)

(499)

God moves all things in their own manner. Hence some things participate in the divine movement in a necessary way, but the rational creature is moved freely. It

is

not contrary to the idea of nature that

moved by God

natural things should be first

mover, since nature

is

as

a kind of instrument

used by God. In the same way there is nothing contradictory in the idea of voluntary action arising from God, in by God.

(500)

so far as the will

is

moved

God’s providence cares for all things in their Voluntary action, and mastery

own manner

.

.

.

man and to compulsion is opdoes not compel man to act

over that action, are peculiar to spiritual creatures.

Hence God

posed.

To

this

rightly.

(501)

God’s action

as first cause

action

needed

is

also

as

is

but natural

perfect,

second cause.

God

could

do what nature does without the help of nature, but it is his will to act through the medium of nature so that order may be preserved in things. 97

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (502)

God our

(503)

THOMAS

does not justify us without any action on

part.

Divine providence does not destroy the nature of things but preserves

(504)

ST.

The

gifts of

it.

grace are joined to nature in such

way that they do not destroy but perfect Hence the light of faith, which flows into

a

it.

us

through grace, does not extinguish the light of natural knowledge which is our natural inheritance.

(505)

Grace does not destroy nature but presupposes and perfects it.

XVII This is the final human knowledge of God: to know that we do not know God. (506)

(507)

Although uncreated truth exceeds truth, yet there

is

which are less known better by us.

(509)

God

created

nothing to prevent created

known

truth from being better

(508)

all

to us.

in themselves are

Things

known

one in reality but multiple according our minds; we know him in as many ways created things represent him.

The

is

necessity of calling

evident. Since

to as

God by many names is know God naturally

we cannot

except from his

effects,

so

it

is

necessary to

designate his perfection by different names, just as different perfections are

things.

hend

If,

found in created

however, we were able to compre-

his essence in itself

and give him a name

proper to his essence, then we would express him in a single name. This is promised to those

who

will see

God

in his essence. In that day 99

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF there shall be one Lord,

THOMAS

ST.

and

his

name

shall be

one. (Zach.14.9).

(510)

Created things are not sufficient to represent the creator.

Hence we cannot

possibly arrive at

perfect knowledge of the creator

from creatures;

in addition, because of the weakness of our intellect

we cannot even know

all

that created

things manifest of God.

(511)

God

can in no way be said to be like creatures;

but creatures can truly be called

like to

God

in a certain sense.

(512)

No human

affections in the strict sense

actually be in

God

also,

can

with the exception of

joy and love.

(513)

Even though yet

never arrives

it

due God.

is

(514)

to

it

may be very like God, the stage when something

a creature

in the

at

way

we know

God

due

to

From

his effects

he

the cause of other things, and that he

is

excels everything else

him; that

is

edge in this

(515)

that things are

Th^

that

which he

exists, that

leaves far

below

the final perfection of our knowllife.

truths of faith,

which can only be known

100

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF completely by those

can be

known by

who see the human

the

which are not

similitudes,

THOMAS

ST.

essence of God,

reason only in

sufficiently clear to

give comprehensive knowledge of that truth as if

by a demonstration or

as

understood in

if

human

useful for the

itself.

Nevertheless,

mind

to exercise itself in such enquiries, inade-

quate

as

it is

they are, provided there

is

no presump-

tuous claim to complete understanding and demonstration.

A

little

knowledge of the most it is poor and in-

sublime things, even though sufficient, is a

(5 1 6)

source of the highest joy.

The human mind proceeds to the knowledge of God in three ways, although it does not arrive at

knowledge of what he

is

but only that he

Firstly: in so far as his creative action is

more

perfectly. Secondly: in so far as

cause of higher excellence

he above as

(517)

is

all

more

is

the

show forth

intellect,

his

Thirdly: in so far

known more and more as being those things we see in his effects.

The human its

distinctly.

known

he

these bear his

effects, for since

likeness in a higher way, they

is.

far

which naturally acquires

knowledge from material

things,

is

not able

of itself to arrive at the point of seeing the

divine substance in

itself,

since

elevated incomparably above

and even above

all

all

other beings. 101

the latter

is

material things

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (518)

Our

cannot

mode

own mode

know them

of existence

To know God know

(520)

THOMAS

intellect speaks of divine things,

cording to their

(519)

ST.

of existence



not



ac-

for

it

but according to the so found in created things.

in a created likeness

is

not to

the essence of God.

Whatever

is

comprehended by

a finite being

is

itself finite.

(521)

The

way

investigation of divine things in such a

one were able to comprehend them completely is presumptuous and is forbidden.

as if

(522)

(523)

It is

impossible to predicate anything of

and of other beings in the same

sense.

The

the will of

reason cannot track

down

God

God

except with regard to what he must will with absolute necessity; but his will in relation to creatures

(524)

God

is

there

is

is

not of such a kind.

not called incomprehensible because something in him which cannot be seen,

but because he

is

not seen as perfectly as he

can be seen.

(525)

God may

is

honoured by

say or

because

we

know nothing about him, but

be-

102

silence, not

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF cause

we know

that

we

ST.

THOMAS

are unable to compre-

hend him.

(526)

(527)

Neither Christian nor pagan knows the nature of

God

In

we cannot know perfectly what God but we can know what he is not, and in this

is,

as

he

is

in himself.

this life

consists the perfection of

our knowledge

as

way-

farers in this world. Likewise, in this life

we

cannot love God perfectly so that we are permanently turned towards him in act, but only imperfectly so that our minds are never turned towards what

(528)

(529)

The

contrary to him.

its immensity exceeds form every which can be grasped by our minds. Hence we cannot comprehend it by knowing what it is, but only have a slight knowledge of it in knowing what it is not.

We he

(530)

is

divine substance in

only

is

know God

above

all

that

truly

men

when we

believe that

can think about God.

end of our knowledge God is ultimately known as unknown, because then the mind knows God most perfectly when it knows that his essence is above all that can be It is said that at the

known

in this life of wayfaring. 103

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (531)

Even though

ST.

THOMAS

the eye of the owl does not see

the sun, nevertheless the eye of the eagle gazes at

it.

104

Key

to the Abbreviations in the

Index of References

In the following index of references, the references to the Summa Theologica are represented only by num-

For example,

bers.

II-II, 123, 2

II part, question 123, article 2

for the

means the II Part of the .The same holds good

commentary on the Books

Peter Lombard. For example,

of the Sentences of

3, d. 33, 2, 5,

3rd. Book, dist. 33, question 2, article 5. works are abbreviated as follows: C.G.

=

Comp,

Summa theol.



means the

The

other

contra Gentiles.

Compendium

theologiae.

=

Questiones disputatae de veritate. Pot. :z= Questiones disputatae de potentia Dei. Mal. rr Questiones disputatae de malo. Car. zr Questiones disputatae de caritate. Corr. frat. Questiones disputatae de corr. fraterna. De spe = Questiones disputatae de spe. Virt. comm. Questiones disputatae de virtutibus in communi. Virt. card, zi: Questiones disputatae de virtutibus cardinalibus. Spir. creat. Questiones disputatae de spiritualibus creaturis. An. zz Questiones disputatae de anima. Quol. zz: Questiones quodlibetales. Ver.





De perfectione vitae spiritualis. De natura verbi intellectus. Un. int. zz De unitate intellectus contra Averoistas. Comm. in An. zz Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima. In Met. — Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle. In Job. zz Commentary on the Gospel of St. John. In Matth. zz Commentary on the Gospel of St. Matthew. In Trin. = Commentary on Boethius on the Trinity. In div. nom. zz Commentary on Pseudo-Dionysius on the Divine Names. Praec. car. zz De duobus praeceptis caritatis. Perf. vit. spir. zz

Nat. verb, zz

Index of References (1)

Pot. 7. 9.

(3)

Pot. 3, 16

(2)

C.G.

(4)

C.G.

1,

83.

105

1,

ad

102.

1.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

(5)

C.G.

(51)

Comp,

(6)

I-II, i6, 4.

(52)

(7)

C.G.

1,

(53)

MI, MI,

(8)

MI.

1, 6.

(54)

3, go.

(55)

C.G. C.G.

3, 24.

(56)

Ver. 21, 3 ad

2, 6.

(57)

11.

4,

C.G. (10) C.G. (11) C.G. (9)

28.

theol.

I,

ad

3.

19, 7

20, 2.

I, 6,

1,

28.

G

37-

ad

3

(12)

I-II,

111,

(58)

I-II, 36, 3-

(13)

C.G.

2, 46.

(59)

I-II, 8, 1.

(14)

(60)

MI,

78,

(15)

Ver. 24, 1 ad 16. Ver. 5, 3 ad 3.

(61)

C.G.

4, 92.

(16)

C.G.

(62)

I,

(17)

I,

(63)

Pot. 3, 6

(18)

Ver. 16,

(64)

C.G.

(65) (66)

MI, MI,

(67)

Ver. 22,

6.

(68)

I-II, 35»

1

(69)

I-II, 29, 3

1.

3, 136.

84,

ad

1

(19)

C.G.

(20)

Comp,

3.

2.

3, 74.

C.G. (22) C.G. (23) Car.

theol. I, 148.

2, 68.

(21)

1.

1, 1

ad ad

11.

(24)

I, 65,

(25)

Ver. 18, 2 ad

(26)

I,

1

1.

(27)

104, 3 ad C.G. 2, 30.

(28)

Pot. 5,

(29)

1

5.

1.

ad 16. 8 ad 14. 6 ad 3.

(30)

Ver. 24, Ver. 22,

(31)

2, d. 23,

(32)

C.G.

(33)

I.

103.

»

(34)

I,

104,

1

(35)

I,

(36)

I,

104, 3 109, 1

(37)

Ver. 20, 4.

(38)

C.G.

(39)

Ver. 21,

(40)

MI,

(41)

Ver. 16, 3 ad

(42)

C.G.

(43)

Pot- 3- >6

(44)

I. 5.

2, 30.

27,

(72)

MI,

(73)

Mai.

(74)

1.

(75)

1,

49 63

Corr Mai. Mai.

1.

3.

(81)

1.

Mai. (83) C.G. (84) C.G. (85) C.G.

79, 1, ,

,

.

3.

29, 5. 5.

3, 7.

48, 6.

ad 4. 5 ad 10.

2.

8.

frat. 1

ad

1

ad

10.

3» 11*

ad

12,

2.

ad

1

3, 12; cf. I, 48, 4. 3» 71-

(86)

Ver. 16, 2

(87)

1.

(88)

Comp,

(89)

»

(sed contra)

3-

theol.

(9«)

Ver. 22, 6 ad

(46)

(92)

Mai.

(47)

C.G.

(93)

Ver. 5, 4 ad

(94)

Comp,

(95)

1,

48 2 ad

3.

(96)

1,

92

ad

3.

(48)

I, 8, 1

(49)

I.

(50)

Mai.

ad

4.

63, 41, 1.

106

10.

3» 9-

(90)

2, 89.

4.

5.

1, 3-

3,

3 ad 2. Ver. 8, 4 ad 5. Pot. 3, 6 ad 20.

(45)

3.

3. 2.

1

103, 7 ad Ver. 24, 10

ad

1.

ad ad



17 , 4

49

3.

ad

1

10,

^82)

3, 7.

14.

1, 4*

(79)



ad

4 ad

6,

Mai.

C.G. (80) C.G.

2.

2.

3» 4*

I, 48;, 5»

(78)

ad ad ad ad

ad

1

t

(70)

(77)

2.

2.

19^ 9-

(7»)

(76)

1.

114.

I,

2,

1

117.

ad

11.

6.

12. 6.

theol.

,

,

I,

1.

I,

142.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

(142a) II-II, 26,

ad 2. ad 3.

1

(102)

C.G. C.G. C.G. C.G. C.G. C.G.

(147)

I,

(103)

I-II, 32, 2.

(148) (149)

(106)

Comm, in An. 3, 8, lect. 13. Ver. 20, 3; Ver. 20, 3 ad 5. Ver. 2, 2.

Ver. 16, 1 (sed contra). Ver. 22, 10.

(107)

C.G.

(108)

I,

75, 4.

(109)

I,

76, 7

(110)

Un.

(111)

Spir. creat. 2

ad

(112)

Ver. 13, 3 ad

2.

(113)

I,

(97) (98) (99) (100)

(101)

(104) (105)

(114)

3, 71. 3,

112.

(143)

I-II, 93,

3,

112.

(144)

I, 14,

3,

22.

(145)

1,

43. 112.

(146)

Nat. verb. Ver. 10, 8.

3,

3, 113.

ad

3.

int.

An. C.G.

(117)

(118)

1, 77, 2. Virt. comm.

(1 19)

An.

(120)

Mai.

13.

I-II, 31,

(124)

C.G. Mai. C.G.

(125)

MI,

(123)

9.

ad 4 ad

16, 8

59.

32, 8.

(128)

C.G. 1, 43. C.G. 1, 5. In div. nom.

(129)

I,

(126) (127)

(130)

Ver.

1, 9.

Ver.

2, 2

(132)

I,

84, 7.

(133)

I,

12,

(135) (136)

ad

2.

12.

Ver. 12, 3 ad Ver. 18, 2 ad

In Trin.

2.

7.

6, 3.

85, 6.

(137)

I,

(138)

Ver.

O39) C.G.

9.

1,

2, 66.

(141)

Ver. 24, Ver. 25,

(142)

De

(140)

4, 4.

14, 1.

(131)

(134)

spe

I-II, 28,

I-II, 26, 2

(154)

I-II, 86,

(155)

C.G.

1

ad ad ad

1

1

3. 2. 2.

cf.

16,

I,

1;

C.G. C.G.

107

71.

1,

3, 26.

(161)

I-II, 19, 3

ad

(162)

Car.

ad

12.

(163)

(166)

I-II, 4, 4 ad 2. Ver. 23, 6. Ver. 24, 10 ad 15. Ver. 21, 3.

(167)

II-II, 27, 4, obj.

(168)

I-II,

(169)

Ver. 25,

(170)

I-II, 27, 1.

3,

5 ad

I-II, 28, 6.

De

(173)

I,

(174)

I-II, 55,

(175) (176)

I-II, 17, 5 Corr. frat.

(177)

I-II, 26,

(178)

Car.

(179)

I,

(180)

Ver. 22,

spe

60,

(181)

C.G.

(182)

I,

(183)

II-II,

3.

1. 1

1

ad 4. ad 3. 1, ad ad 3.

1. 1

ad

3.

5.

3, 26.

60, 5.

I-II,

1

1.

(171)

20,

1,

2.

(172)

(186)

7.

ad 13. ad 2. ad 3. 1

59, 2

I,

(159)

(184)

1.

6,

79* 11

C.G. (185) Mai.

2.

ad

3.

77;

1,

Mai.

(158)

(165)

3.

9, 1. 3,

(152)

(164)

7.

43.

1,

ad

(153)

(160)

3, 81.

(121)

108, 6 82, 3.

(156)

8.

(122)

I,

I,

26, 3.

76, 5.

(116)

3.

84, 5.

(151)

^57)

1.

8 ad

(150)

5.

85, 7.

(115)

1

154, 12. 1, 7.

2, 3

17,

ad

9 ad

2.

2.

5.

ad

1.

Ver.

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF

THOMAS

ST.

(187)

II-II, 50, 4.

(231)

Ver. 24, 3 ad

(188)

C.G.

(232)

I,

(189)

Ver. 16, 2 ad

(233)

Ver. 22,

(190)

I-II, 58,

(234)

1,

(191)

II-II, 154, 12,

(192)

C.G.

(193)

I,

(194)

In Joh.

(195)

II-II,

(196)

II-II, 133, 1; II-II, 142, 1.

(>97)

I,

(>98)

Quol.

3, 22.

(»99) (200)

II-II,

108, 2.

2, 79.

5.

ad

1

3.

ad

1,

3, 126. 1-

982

1, 7.

130,

1.

63, 9.

4 ad

I-II, 58,

(201)

I-II, 71, 2

(202)

Virt.

(203)

I-II, 58,

(204)

Virt.

3.

ad

comm.

4 ad

comm.

Mai. (206) Mai.

ad

17.

3.

ad

8

10.

2.

8,

(205)

1.

8,

ad

14, 2

8.

82,

ad

1

2.

3.

6.

83, 2.

(235)

II-II, 2g, 2.

(236)

Ver. 22,

1

(237)

I-II,

18,

7

(238)

MI,

1,

(239)

Virt.

(240)

I, 5,

(241)

Virt.

comm.

(242)

Mai.

1,

(243)

I-II,

(244)

I-II, 90,

(245)

I-II,

(246)

Virt.

(247)

Praec. car.

ad ad

12. 2.

6.

comm. 4 ad

ad

7

9 ad 16.

5.

ad 2. ad 3. 8, 3 ad 2. comm. 5 ad 19, 8 1

(248)

C.G.

(249)

I-II, 14, 2.

(250)

(251)

C.G. C.G.

(252)

I-II, 77, 2

1,

88.

1.

1,

II-II,

145, 3.

(208)

Virt.

comm.

(209)

I-II, 71, 6.

(253)

I-II, 66,

5 ad

1.

(210)

C.G.

(254)

I-II, 66,

5 ad

2.

(211)

I-II, 59, 4.

(255)

(212)

II-II, 155,

(256)

C.G. C.G.

(213)

II-II, 153, 3.

(257)

I-II, 56, 2

ad

2.

(214)

Virt.

(258)

Ver. 18, 7 ad

7.

(259)

II-II, 51,

(215)

157» 2Virt. comm. 8.

(260)

Virt.

(216)

C.G.

1,

(261)

Perf.

I-II,

66,

70.

4,

ad

1

comm.

2.

12

ad

16;

IMI,

71*

comm. 4

8.

(princ)

(207)

9.

2.

3.

1.

1,

1,

2.

1,

2.

ad

1.

ad

1

comm.

2.

5 ad

spir.

vit.

8.

23.

(262)

Quol.

3.

(263)

II-II, 32, 3.

(218)

IMI,

(264)

IMI,

(219)

MI,

(265)

Virt.

(220)

II-II,

(266)

Car. 3 ad 13.

(221)

II-II, 145, 2.

(267)

II-II, 56, 2

(222)

(268)

Ver. 14,

(223)

i-n, 19, 5. Ver. 17, 3 ad

3.

(269)

II-II, 47, 2

(224)

I-II,

5 ad

2.

(270)

Virt.

comm.

12

ad

(225)

1.

(271)

II-II,

119, 3

ad

3;

(227)

Ver. 17, 1 ad Ver. 17, 3 ad Ver. 17, 5.

(228)

I,

82,

(229)



59» 3-

(230)

Mai.

(217)

ad

(226)

1;

Virt.

47> 6. 58, 2. 20,

19,

1

6,

1.

ad 1

2

1.

3.

ad

22.

108

ad

1,

14.

182,

ad

1

comm.

3.

6.

ad

3.

ad

1.

6.

3.

(272)

II-II, 47, 5

(273)

Virt.

(274)

II-II, 49, 3

(275)

n-ii, 47,

ad

2.

comm. 6 ad ad 3. 14 ad 2.

2.

23. II-II, 55,

..

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF (276)

IMI,

(277)

Virt. card. 2

(278)

I-II, 73,

1.

50,

II -II, 153,

(280)

I-II, 59, 2

(281)

I-II,

(282)

I-II, 59, 5

(sed contra)

1.

59,

Mai.

(284)

Ver. 26, 7

(285)

II-II, 158,

(286)

II-II, 125,

(287)

Ver. 26, 5. C.G. I, 89.

ad 1. 1 ad 2. I ad 1.

I-II, 37, 4.

(290)

Virt.

comm. 12,

Mai. II-II,

I-II, 35, 5.

(321)

I-II, 39,

(322)

II-II, 31, 3.

(323)

II-II, 23,

(324)

II-II, 23, 7.

4 ad

6 ad

9.

Ver. 10, 10 ad 7. Car. 8 ad 11, ad 12.

(327)

Car. 8 ad 17.

(328)

II-II, 27, 8

(329)

II-II, 123, 12

(330)

C.G.

ad

ad 4. ad 2. 6 ad 1. 4 ad 3. 4 ad 2.

(293)

I-II, 46, I-II, 40,

(295)

I-II, 67,

(296)

I-II, 43,

(297)

I-II, 44, 2

(298)

Virt.

comm.

(299)

Mai.

7, 1.

(300) (301) (302)

II-II,

(303)

I-II, 73, 5.

(304)

I-II, 1, 7

(305)

MI,

(306)

I-II, 109, 2

(307)

Virt.

ad

ad

ad

2.

(336)

II-II, 141, 8.

(337)

I-II.

ad

113. 9

4 ad (339) I-II. 2. 4 ad (340) 1-11,96,6. (338)

3.

11

96, 3

(335)

(334)

(sed contra)

1

I,

I-II, 2,

I-II,

100, 9.

I-II, 77, 4.

I-II.

100, 2.

C.G.

(344)

I-II. 65, 4-

(345)

In Matth.

(346)

I,

(347)

II-II. 30. 2.

(348)

II-II, 55, 8.

15.

4, 70.

125, 2.

ad

1.

18, 5.

ad

2.

comm. 9 ad

15;

Virt.

card. 3.

21, 3

(349)

II-II.

124,

(350)

II-II,

123, 12

(35O

II-II,

II-II, 123, 4.

(352)

C.G.

(353)

II-II, 126,

(312) (313)

C.G. Mai.

1

3.

ad

2.

90.

1,

10, 3.

8 ad

(314)

I-II, 32,

(315)

I-II, 31, 6.

(316)

I-II, 34,

(317)

I-II, 2,

3.

4 ad

6 ad

2.

1; I-II,

34, 2

ad

3-

(318)

C.G.

(319)

I-II, 34,

t,

90.

3 ad

(354)

II-II,

(355)

I-II, 45. 3 -

109

ad ad

3.

3.

1.

123, 12

ad

(356)

C.G.

(357)

II-II, 128, 1.

(358)

II-II, 123, 6.

(359)

II-II, 123,

6 ad

(360)

II-II, 123,

6 ad

(361)

I-II, 66,

(362)

Virt. card,

(363)

II-II, 136, II-II,

3.

1.

1.

(309)

6 ad

1.

2.

(308)

I-II, 34,

2.

5, 1.

ad

124. 3 II-II, 131, 1

90.

3.

2.

5 ad

I-II. 99.

(342)

(440a) II-II, 26, 2

I,

1.

4 ad

(399) (400)

1,

ad

C.G. 3 21. (440) I2 93 6.

62, 4.

C.G. (401) C.G.

3.

4.

(437)

1

3. 2.

106, 4.

ad 2. 3 ad 3-

13, 3

1,

ad

(430) (431)

2.

ad

1

3.

,

(384)

36,

20.

60 5; I, 60, 5 ad (427) De spe 3. (428) C.G. 1, 80. (429) C.G. 32 19(426)

ad

10.

,

(383)

1

4.

(421)

(425)

In Matth. 11. (382) Mai. 8. 3 ad 8.

(381)

8 ad

103.

I,

62,

8

.

,

10,

2

1

3 ad

1

5*

ad

ad

1.

3. 1.

I,

2.

13,

11.

1.

.

THE HUMAN WISDOM OF ( (

454 ) 455 )

(456) (

457 )

(458) (

C.G. I.

18.

1,

(494)

44. 3 -

Quol. Quol. Pot.

18, 4; I, 18,

C.G.

(496)

Pot. 3, 7.

(497)

I,

(498)

Quol.

(499)

I-II, 6,

1

(500)

C.G. 3

14^*

(501) (502)

Pot. 3, 7 ad 16. I-II, 111, 2 ad 2.

ad

2

1.



Ver. 27, 2 ad

(461)

C.G.

(462)

I. 13.

1.

150.

3,

(464)

7 Ver. 24, 15 ad 2. Ver. 2, 3 ad 13.

(465)

I,

(466)

Ver. 11,

(467)

I,

(468)

Ver.

-

ad

88, 3

117,

ad 7. ad 1. ad 6.

1

1

1,

»

I-II,

In Trin.

(505)

Ver. 14, 10 ad 9;

10, 4. 2, 3.

ad

2

I, 2,

Pot. 7, 5 ad 14. Ver. 10, 12 ad 6.

4 ad

C.G.

1,

61.

(508)

I,

(470)

Ver.

1,

2.

(509)

C.G.

Ver. 5, 2 ad 11. Ver. 2, 11 ad 1.

Quol.

5, 2.

(510)

(472)

I,

63, 7

(511)

(473)

I.

113,

ad 2. 7 ad 3.

474 ) Comp, theol.

(475)

II-II, 30, 4.

(476)

I,

25, 3

477 )

I,

21, 4.

(478)

I,

25, 3

I,

46, 3

(

(

479 )

(480)

(481)

ad ad ad

Ver. 23, i-n, 99,

2, 4.

13,

1,

(512)

C.G.

1,

91.

(513)

Ver.

2,

11.

3.

3.

(518)

h

39» 2.

2.

(519)

I,

12,

2.

(520)

I-II, 4, 3

(521)

In Trin. 2, C.G. 1, 32.

1.

4 ad

(484)

(523)

I,

46, 2.

C.G.

(524)

I,

12, 7

(486)

I-II, 27, 2

(525)

In Trin.

(487)

Pot.

(526)

I,

(488)

C.G.

3, 66.

(489)

I, 8,

1; I, 8, 1

C.G. (491) C.G. C.G. ( 498 ) (490)

(

493 )

I, 8,

(

3, 68.

ad 3. 5 ad 1.

ad

3.

528 )

Car. 10,

(528)

C.G.

1,

1.

ad

ad

1. 1

ad

2.

2.

ad 6. ad 5. ad 2 (contra) 2, 1

14;

I,

3

(prooem-

C.G. 1, 5; Ver. 8, 1 ad In Trin. 1, 2 ad 1. (531) In Joh. prologus. (529)

4 ^*

ad

2;

2.

ium)

3, 70.

3

13, 10

(527)

3, 67.



ad

3.

C.G. 3, 49. (5 « 5 ) C.G. 1, 8. (516) In Trin. 1, (517) C.G. 4»

I-II, 71, 2

3,

8

(514)

(485)

(483)

1,

31.

ad 4. I, 105, 2 ad 1. I-II, 93, 5 ad 2.

(482)

I,

1.

(507)

(471)

2.

ad 3. ad 2. ad 3.

(503)

(506)

i

7

(504)

1

1

2,

1.

103,

(469)

(

4 ad

3, 68.

10, 7.

(460)

(463)

I,

THOMAS

ST.

4, 1.

1,

459 ) C.G.

(495)

.

(530)

3.

111

8.